ArticlePDF Available

When is mindreading accurate? A commentary on Shannon Spaulding’s How We Understand Others: Philosophy and Social Cognition

Authors:

Abstract

In How We Understand Others: Philosophy and Social Cognition, Shannon Spaulding develops a novel account of mindreading with pessimistic implications for mindreading accuracy: according to Spaulding, mistakes in mentalizing are much more common than traditional theories of mindreading commonly assume. In this commentary, I push against Spaulding’s pessimism from two directions. First, I argue that a number of the heuristic mindreading strategies that Spaulding views as especially prone to error might actually be quite reliable in practice. Second, I argue that current methods for measuring mindreading performance are not well-suited for the task of determining whether our mental-state attributions are generally accurate. I conclude that any claims about the accuracy or inaccuracy of mindreading are currently unjustified.
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cphp20
Philosophical Psychology
ISSN: 0951-5089 (Print) 1465-394X (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cphp20
When is mindreading accurate? A commentary on
Shannon Spaulding’s How We Understand Others:
Philosophy and Social Cognition
Evan Westra
To cite this article: Evan Westra (2020): When is mindreading accurate? A commentary on
Shannon Spaulding’s How�We�Understand�Others:�Philosophy�and�Social�Cognition, Philosophical
Psychology
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2020.1765326
Published online: 13 May 2020.
Submit your article to this journal
View related articles
View Crossmark data
When is mindreading accurate? A commentary on
Shannon SpauldingsHow We Understand Others:
Philosophy and Social Cognition
Evan Westra
Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada
ABSTRACT
In How We Understand Others: Philosophy and Social
Cognition, Shannon Spaulding develops a novel account of
mindreading with pessimistic implications for mindreading
accuracy: according to Spaulding, mistakes in mentalizing are
much more common than traditional theories of mindread-
ing commonly assume. In this commentary, I push against
Spauldings pessimism from two directions. First, I argue that
a number of the heuristic mindreading strategies that
Spaulding views as especially prone to error might actually
be quite reliable in practice. Second, I argue that current
methods for measuring mindreading performance are not
well-suited for the task of determining whether our mental-
state attributions are generally accurate. I conclude that any
claims about the accuracy or inaccuracy of mindreading are
currently unjustied.
ARTICLE HISTORY
Received 5 July 2019
Accepted 8 August 2019
1. Introduction
Mindreading or theory of mind is the ability to predict and explain the
behavior of other agents in terms of their mental states. A very common
view among philosophers and cognitive scientists is that mindreading is an
essential part of ordinary human social cognition. According to this idea,
our basic abilities to understand why other people act as they do, to predict
what they will do next, and to plan our social interactions all involve
reasoning about peoples beliefs, desires, intentions, and other mental states.
Without this ability, the behaviors of others would appear to us as bizarre
and unpredictable, and even basic forms of social coordination that we take
for granted would become very dicult for us. Indeed, our advanced mind-
reading capacities are thought to be a key part of the explanation for why we
human beings have greatly surpassed our great ape cousins in the domains
of culture, language, and large-scale cooperation (Baron-Cohen, 1997;
Scott-Phillips, 2014; Tomasello, 2014). Mindreading, in other words, is
CONTACT Evan Westra evan.westra@utoronto.ca Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto,
Toronto, Canada
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY
https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2020.1765326
© 2020 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group
our primary means for gaining the knowledge we need to succeed in the
social world.
In How We Understand Others: Philosophy and Social Cognition,
Shannon Spaulding is ambivalent about this view of mindreading
(Spaulding, 2018). On the one hand, she endorses the idea that mindreading
is a pervasive and important feature of social cognition she dubs this the
broad scope of mindreading claim(Spaulding, 2018,p.9)and forcefully
rejects attempts by other philosophers to undermine it. In this sense, her
book can be read as consistent with the mainstream view in the mind-
reading literature. On the other hand, however, she argues that her fellow
mainstream mindreading theorists have too often taken it for granted that
mental-state attribution is generally accurate a habit that she attributes to
excessive emphasis on measures like the false-belief task and the tacit
assumption that accurate belief-attribution ought to be the primary expla-
nandum of mindreading theories (Spaulding, 2018, p. 43). In contrast,
Spaulding maintains, our mental-state attributions regularly misrepresent
the real mental states of others; indeed, Spaulding thinks that accuracy is
often not even our primary goal when we reason about the minds of others.
This pessimism about the accuracy of mindreading is a dominant theme
throughout the book, as well as in Spauldings earlier work (Spaulding, 2016,
2017). Drawing on a wide range of empirical ndings from social psychol-
ogy (which have received surprisingly little attention from mindreading
theorists until now), Spaulding paints a picture of mindreading as
a complex, messy process that takes on dierent forms in dierent social
contexts and is regularly distorted by a variety of unreliable heuristics and
biases. This culminates in an argument for a version of the Model Theory of
mindreading (Godfrey-Smith, 2005; Maibom, 2003), which takes the het-
erogeneity and context-sensitivity of mindreading as its primary explanan-
dum, rather than its putative accuracy. Thus, while Spaulding agrees with
the received view that mental-state attribution is a central and pervasive part
of everyday social cognition, she pushes back against the idea that mind-
reading is a reliable source of social knowledge.
Spaulding also argues that this pessimism about theory of mind has
consequences for debates in mainstream philosophy. For example, she
argues that our unreliable mindreading abilities should aect how we
deliberate in contexts of apparent peer disagreement. The problem of peer
disagreement refers to contexts in which two agents who are epistemic peers
nd themselves in possession of the same evidence and yet nevertheless
come to dierent conclusions regarding a particular question; each agent is
then faced with the question of whether she should remain steadfast in her
position (Kelly, 2011) or if she should treat her epistemic peers position as
evidence that she should conciliate and decrease condence in her own
position (Christensen, 2007). To the extent that the problem of peer
2E. WESTRA
disagreement has any bearing upon how we should deliberate in real-world
scenarios (and is not a mere idealization), it presupposes that we are usually
able to recognize when we are in the company of an epistemic peer.
Spaulding suggests, however, that this assumption is not tenable in light of
her arguments about the unreliability of mindreading: not only do we
regularly overestimate our own epistemic status, we also display a wide
range of biases when it comes to judging the knowledge and competence of
others. If this is right, then most perceived cases of peer disagreement are
probably not cases of peer disagreement at all because we are not normally
able to recognize whether another person is an epistemic peer. Because most
of the biases relevant to evaluations of potential epistemic peers tend to
inate how we view our own knowledge and competence relative to others,
Spaulding thinks that our default policy in contexts of apparent peer
disagreement should be to decrease our condence in our own judgments
(Spaulding, 2018, pp. 8188).
Like Spaulding, I think that the question of accuracy has largely been
taken for granted in the mindreading literature, and I agree that she has
identied an extremely important issue in the study of theory of mind.
However, I am not convinced that the empirical considerations she raises
support pessimistic conclusions about the overall reliability of mindreading.
In the rst part of this commentary, I will argue that several of the ecient,
heuristic mental-state attribution strategies that Spaulding views as unreli-
able might actually produce fairly accurate mental-state attributions most of
the time. I will go on to suggest that the trade-othat we make when we
alternate between deliberate and ecient modes of mindreading would be
better described in terms of precision rather than accuracy. In the second
half of the paper, I will turn to a question that arises from these debates
about the reliability of mindreading: how exactly could we measure the
accuracy of mental-state attribution anyway? After surveying several dier-
ent methodologies, I conclude that we dont currently possess any reliable
means for determining whether a particular act of mental-state attribution is
accurate. A consequence of this conclusion is that any empirical claim about
the accuracy of mindreading is probably unjustied. This creates problems
for Spauldings pessimistic take on mindreading, but also for the optimists
about mindreading whom she criticizes.
2. Mindreading for accuracy versus mindreading for eciency
A central part of Spauldings critique of traditional theories of mindreading
like the theory-theory and the simulation theory is that they all tacitly
assume that the process of mental-state attribution is uniform and consis-
tent across mindreaders, targets, and social contexts. When explaining how
mindreading works in, for example, the controlled experimental conditions
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY 3
of the false belief task, this is excusable, but in real-world scenarios,
Spaulding argues, the mindreading process is inuenced by a myriad of
factors that aect what information it takes in and how that information is
processed. As a result, mental-state attribution can end up functioning very
dierently in dierent kinds of social contexts, and dierent individuals in
the same context may well arrive at divergent mental-state attributions. This
variability is a key component of Spauldings case for pessimism about the
accuracy of mindreading: dierent people in the same situations with the
same evidence can nevertheless arrive at vastly divergent psychological
interpretations of a particular individuals actions (Spaulding, 2017,
2018, p. 36).
One factor that can inuence the cognitive strategies and resources that
we employ while mindreading is our social goals. Sometimes, we are very
motivated to make correct mental-state attributions and behavioral pre-
dictions about others (say, when interviewing a potential nanny for ones
child). In these cases, where mindreading aims at accuracy,Spaulding
suggests that we tend to engage in conscious, deliberative forms of reason-
ing that are cognitively taxing and liable to break down under a cognitive
load (Spaulding, 2018, p. 45). At other times, a personsactualmental
states are not particularly relevant to our plans (e.g., we do not need to
know what a cashier at a grocery store is really thinking in order to buy
eggs and milk). In these cases, we do not engage in eortful forms of
reasoning about mental states. Instead, we employ fast and ecient mind-
reading strategies that require less cognitive eort but are more prone to
error. Thus, whether or not we care about getting our mental-state attri-
butions right can dramatically aect how mindreading functions in a given
situation.
The particular type of mindreading strategy we employ when we are
motivated by eciency may depend upon how we have socially categorized
the mindreading target (Spaulding, 2018, pp. 4546). If we see the target as
similar to us in some respect (e.g., as part of our in-group), we are more
likely to employ a mental-state attribution heuristic called egocentric projec-
tion. Egocentric projection occurs when a mindreader assumes that her
target shares her mental states or otherwise uses her own mental states as
an initial anchor from which she can subsequently adjust (Ames, 2004a;
Epley et al., 2004). The downsides of this heuristic are revealed whenever the
target is not actually that similar to the mindreader. In these cases, the
mindreader may infer that certain propositions are common knowledge
when they are actually not, or she may mistakenly come to believe that
certain goals are shared when they are not. Even when a mindreader does
recognize that a target is not entirely similar to herself, using her own
mental states as an anchor may nevertheless lead her to underestimate the
gap between her targets beliefs and her own.
4E. WESTRA
On the other hand, if a mindreader sees her target as dierent from
herself, she may instead draw on stereotypes about the targets perceived
social category (Ames, 2004b). As Spaulding notes, we tend to automatically
categorize people upon rst encountering them. These categorizations acti-
vate stereotypes associated with a particular group, which often include
beliefs about mental states and traits that members of that group are likely
to share. For example, categorizing a person as a mothermight lead to the
expectation that she cares more about family than work, while categorizing
someone as a millennialmight lead to the expectation that she is entitled,
self-absorbed, and overly fond of avocado toast. Because these stereotypical
beliefs are stored in an ecient format, they become readily accessible
whenever we are faced with the task of predicting and interpreting
a targets behavior. This can lead to biased interpretations and predictions
of a targets actions, such that the same behavior might be interpreted one
way when it comes from a mother, another way when it comes from
a millennial, and so on.
Spauldings insight that a mindreaders goals and social categorizations
can aect how mentalizing functions is a good one. It is not clear, however,
that the modes of mindreading that aim for eciency rather than accuracy
are, in fact, unreliable. Consider rst egocentric projection: as noted, this
strategy will fail when it turns out that we have overestimated the similarity
between ourselves and our target. However, when it comes to the vast
majority of our everyday beliefs, we are often quite similar to the people
around us (Heal, 1996). Consider, for instance, the belief that the Allies won
World War II, the belief that dark clouds mean rain, or the belief that today
is Tuesday. Because these beliefs are so mundane, I do not need to engage in
deliberative reasoning in order to attribute them to the people around me,
nor do I need any particular reasons for these attributions beyond my
evidence for holding those beliefs in the rst place. In projecting these
beliefs of mine onto others, there is vanishingly little chance of error. The
chance of error further decreases when one takes into account the fact that
people naturally sort themselves into groups of like-minded individuals, for
instance, when we go to philosophy conferences, spend time with our
friends, or cluster together online in political echo chambers. In these
familiar social contexts, we can reliably expect a wide range of facts to be
common knowledge and tailor our mental-state inferences accordingly. For
these reasons, the default assumption that our beliefs tend to be shared
(which is eectively a true-belief default) is built into a variety of dierent
accounts of mindreading not as a bug, but as a feature (Heal, 1996; Leslie
et al., 2004). Thus, while egocentric projection may occasionally lead to
striking errors (Epley et al., 2004), there is good reason to think of it as an
ecologically rational heuristic rather than as a bias (Goldstein & Gigerenzer,
2005).
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY 5
It is also not obvious that stereotype-based mindreading is particularly
unreliable. Certainly, one can nd many examples of inaccurate stereotypes
that lead to mindreading errors and perpetuate harmful social inequalities
and structural injustices. To cite just one example that Spaulding provides,
many people falsely believe that people with disabilities tend to have a lower
than average quality of life, which could, in turn, lead to a number of
misleading mental-state inferences (Spaulding, 2018, p. 47). However,
stereotypes are not false by denition. As a cognitive structure, stereotypes
are just an ecient way of storing and retrieving semantic information
associated with dierent social categories (Amodio, 2014). The truth or
falsity of a given stereotype thus depends upon the content that it encodes,
not on the mere fact that it is a stereotype.
1
For example, consider the stereotype that most American academics are
politically liberal, which happens to be true (Duarte et al., 2014). If one were
to rely upon this stereotype when anticipating an American academics
beliefs about a divisive political issue such as gun control or abortion, one
would probably arrive at the correct answer most of the time. This example
is not unique: there is a large, though controversial (see, e.g., Bian &
Cimpian, 2017) empirical literature showing that many of our demographic
stereotypes are surprisingly accurate when compared to real-world statistics
(Jussim, 2012; Jussim et al., 2015). Relying upon any of these stereotypes
during mental-state attribution would therefore seem like a fairly safe bet,
provided one does not have any additional individuating information about
the mindreading target (Crawford et al., 2011).
This is not to deny that the stereotype-based errors that Spaulding cites
occur, nor that they are not morally worrisome: they are certainly both.
Even when they are true, relying upon stereotypes can be morally proble-
matic, both because doing so perpetuates the underlying social injustices
that make them true, and because treating a person as a mere instance of
a kind seems to reect a failure to respect that person as a unique individual.
However, when we are trying to understand the relationship between
stereotyping and mindreading, and trying to understand the role of stereo-
types in social cognition more generally, we should nevertheless be careful
not to treat cases of error as representative. The ubiquity of stereotyping in
social cognition does not imply the ubiquity of erroneous stereotyping.
Focusing on these cases obscures the fact that stereotype-based mindreading
often works quite well.
The fact that mindreading processes that aim for eciencymay actually
be quite reliable problematizes Spauldings analysis of modes of mindread-
ing that aim for accuracy.It is certainly true that we are sometimes
motivated to engage in conscious, deliberative forms of mindreading that
are more eortful than stereotyping and projection, but it is not clear that
this eort buys increased accuracy. To better characterize the function of
6E. WESTRA
this mode of mindreading, we must distinguish between accuracy and
precision. To illustrate, consider the contrast between the following two
predictions:
(1) It will rain in July.
(2) It will rain in the morning on July 3.
If it rains in the morning on July 3, then it will be the case that both
predictions were accurate. However, the two predictions nevertheless
dier in terms of their precision. The rst prediction is relatively easy to
make, but it is also quite imprecise: it doesnt tell us when in July it will
rain. This limits its utility because it does not help us make specicplans,
such as deciding on which day we should have a barbecue or an outdoor
wedding. In contrast, the second prediction is very precise and would
support highly specic plans. Making it with any condence would, how-
ever, require more cognitive eort, and it would have a higher chance of
being wrong.
I suspect that the dierence between ecient and deliberative forms of
mindreading involve a similar trade-obetween cognitive eort and preci-
sion. While heuristics like egocentric projection and stereotyping may lead
to reliably accurate mental-state attributions, they are also relatively impre-
cise. This might be ne as long as our plans do not depend upon having
a very precise representation of a persons mental states for instance, when
we are interacting with a cashier at the checkout counter or chatting with
a stranger while waiting for a bus. Relying upon egocentric projection or
stereotyping in these contexts may lead us to construct informationally
sparse models of other agents that fail to capture many details about their
actual attitudes. In many cases, however, a persons specic mental states do
matter to us, and it is worthwhile for us to engage in explicit perspective-
taking in order to understand what they are thinking say, during a serious
conversation with a romantic partner or when a therapist attempts to
understand her patientssuering. By consciously reasoning about
a persons mental states and imagining what their experiences are like, we
buy ourselves an added degree of precision that can be crucial when
negotiating signicant interpersonal relationships or coordinating on com-
plex plans (Westra, 2018,2019b).
In short, while our goals and social categorizations might inuence the
kind of mindreading strategy we adopt, this does not give us reason to be
worried about the overall accuracy of mindreading. Ecient mindreading
strategies may trade oon precision, but they can nevertheless function as
ecologically rational and reliable heuristics. They need not be viewed as
biasesin an epistemically pejorative sense, even though they do result in
morally problematic judgments some of the time.
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY 7
3. How do we measure accurate mental-state attribution?
Spauldings case for inaccuracy in mindreading is not limited to stereotyp-
ing and egocentric projection, however. In her book, she cites a long list of
domain-general biases discovered by social psychologists, such as naïve
realism (Pronin et al., 2002), self-serving and group-serving attribution
biases (Miller & Ross, 1975; Pettigrew, 1979), and the Dunning-Krueger
eect (Kruger & Dunning, 1999), and she describes how these might
negatively impact the accuracy of mental-state attribution for example,
by distorting our appraisals of othersknowledge and competence relative to
our own (Spaulding, 2018, pp. 8185). These, she might argue, are genuine
biases, and they seem much less amenable to an explanation in terms of
ecological rationality. Should not the existence of such a wide range of biases
cause us to be pessimistic about the accuracy of mindreading and other
social judgments?
2
Such pessimism would be too hasty, however. The mere fact that these
biases are likely to lead to mindreading errors does not tell us much about
the overall frequency of those errors relative to accurate mental-state attri-
butions. Even the fact that a large number of these biases exists does not tell
us about their overall eects on mindreading. Consider an analogous argu-
ment, in which I try to argue that human vision is unreliable by listing o
the dozens of optical illusions to which we are prone. This kind of argument
would be unconvincing because we know that these kinds of illusions
comprise only a minority of our perceptual experiences and that our visual
capacities are generally reliable despite them. Likewise, the fact that we are
prone to systematic patterns of error in certain contexts is consistent with
the claim that overall, mindreading is reliable and trustworthy (Westra,
2019a). Thus, in order to make this claim that mindreading is, overall,
accurate it does not suce to provide a list of all the biases that might
cause mindreading errors. What is really needed is a way of measuring the
accuracy of mental-state attribution in its own right.
Problematically, many of the most commonly used mindreading para-
digms are not actually concerned with measuring accuracy at all. For
example, developmental theory-of-mind paradigms such as the false-
belief task (Wimmer & Perner, 1983) and the theory-of-mind scale
(Wellman & Liu, 2004) only purport to measure whether a participant
possesses certain mental-state concepts. In tasks like these, young children
are asked to make basic action predictions based on what ctional char-
acterswant,think,orknowinaparticularscenario;succeedinginthese
tasks requires children to understand that other agents can have mental
states that dier from their own (e.g., that a character with a false belief
might search for an object in a location the child knows to be incorrect).
In order to isolate conceptual competence from extraneous performance
8E. WESTRA
factors, these paradigms are intentionally designed to be as simple as
possible and do not reect the complexities of real-world social
interactions.
3
Of course, possessing mental-state concepts is a necessary
condition for accurate mental-state attribution: one cannot correctly
attribute beliefs unless one knows what beliefs are. However, beyond
establishing a basic prerequisite for accuracy, these tasks do not tell us
anything about the broader reliability of mindreading.
Tasks that are used to measure more advanced mindreading abilities in
adults are likewise unsuited for measuring accuracy. The reading-the-mind-
in-the-eyes test (RMET) (Baron-Cohen et al., 2001), for example, measures
how well people are able to apply various emotion words to specic facial
expressions. Participants in this task view a series of images depicting the
eyes and part of the face of a model and must choose which emotion word
among four options best describes the models current psychological state.
To succeed in the task, they must be able to make ne-grained discrimina-
tions between dierent facial expressions and also express those discrimina-
tions using sophisticated psychological vocabulary.
4
Again, this ability
might be relevant to the accuracy of mindreading, since it reects partici-
pantsability to individuate dierent types of psychological states according
to their observable correlates. However, being able to classify a face accord-
ing to the type of emotion it displays sets the bar for accuracy fairly low:
recognizing that a person appears to be pensive is not nearly as hard as
judging what they are being pensive about that is, the particular content of
the emotional state in question. Even in terms of emotional categorization,
the decontextualized nature of the RMET leaves much to be desired, since
facts about the context in which a face occurs (e.g., bodily posture) can
radically change whether it is interpreted as expressing positive or negative
emotions (Aviezer et al., 2017,2012). It is thus not clear that performance on
the RMET says much at all about the accuracy of mental-state attribution.
In contrast, recursive mindreading tasks (e.g., Stiller & Dunbar, 2007)do
involve the attributions of particular contents, but not as the result of any
sort of inference. Rather, these tasks measure participantsability to keep
track of mental states of characters from a story when this information is
presented in a complex, multiply embedded format (e.g., Bill knows that
John thinks that Sally doesnt know that Jenny thinks shes nice.). Here, the
correct mental-state information is simply given to participants in
a narrative format; the only way to be inaccurate in this task is to forget
the correct answer (hence, why Stiller & Dunbar, 2007 also found
a signicant correlation between recursive mentalizing and short-term
memory). Of course, maintaining relevant information in ones memory is
sure to be relevant to any kind of complex problem-solving, including
problems that involve mentalizing. Thus, this task also measures something
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY 9
that is relevant to accurate mindreading. It is, however, certainly not a test of
mindreading accuracy as such.
The closest we have come to nding a way to measure the accuracy of
mental-state attribution comes from the literature on empathic accuracy
(Hodges et al., 2014; Ickes et al., 1990). In these studies, experimenters
videotape a target individual as she is being interviewed or while she is
having a conversation. Afterward, the experimenters show the tape to the
target and ask her to indicate what she was thinking at dierent points in
time. The same video is then shown to another participant. At dierent
points during the video, this participant is asked to guess what the target is
thinking. Afterward, independent coders rate how similar the judges
guesses are to the targets self-reports.
5
This use of self-reported mental states as an accuracy criterion is proble-
matic for several reasons. First, it assumes that we have reliable introspective
access to our own thoughts. The problem with this is that there is a large
body of evidence from both neurotypical and clinical cases showing that we
are prone to confabulate about both our prior decision-making and our
occurrent conscious experiences (Johansson et al., 2005; Nisbett & Wilson,
1977; Roser & Gazzaniga, 2004; Schwitzgebel, 2002). This research suggests
that when targets review their recorded interviews and indicate what they
were thinking at the time, they may simply be generating plausible mental-
state attributions about themselves after the fact. This ties into a further
problem: according to theories of introspection like Peter Carruthersinter-
pretive sensory access account, introspection is just a form of mindreading
that is directed at the self (Carruthers, 2009,2011). If this theory or some-
thing like it is correct, then the criterion which empathic accuracy research-
ers have for accurate third-party mindreading presupposes the accuracy of
adierent kind of mindreading. Finally, the mental-state attributions that
these studies evaluate are explicit, verbal, and conscious. Yet, most mind-
reading theories hold that this kind of reasoning about other minds con-
stitutes just a small part of our overall theory of mind and that most
mentalizing is implicit, unconscious, and non-verbal. If this is right, then
it may be that we make many accurate mental-state attributions that we are
unable to put into words.
Despite these objections to the empathic accuracy approach, it is admit-
tedly dicult to come up with a criterion for accurate mental-state attribu-
tion that does not rely upon introspection. One possibility might be to
employ advanced neuroimaging methods such as multivariate pattern ana-
lysis to decode the content of a persons occurrent mental states and then
use this as an accuracy criterion for third-party mental-state attribution (c.f.,
Ritchie et al., 2019 for some of the limitations of this technique). Barring the
signicant technological and methodological advances that this would
require, introspective accuracy criteria are probably the best that we can
10 E. WESTRA
expect to achieve. If the above-mentioned concerns about introspection are
warranted, then this bodes ill for the measurement of accuracy in
mindreading.
This is shocking, considering how often mindreading theorists appeal to
the adaptive signicance of mindreading and its importance in social learn-
ing. Contrary to Spauldings pessimistic view, however, the problem with
this assumption is not that we are less accurate than these theorists would
have us believe. It is, rather, that we are not in an epistemic position to know
whether mindreading is accurate one way or the other. In other words,
claims about the accuracy and inaccuracy of mindreading are both equally
unjustied. If this is right, then mindreading theorists cannot claim to oer
advice to philosophers who are worried about peer disagreement or about
any other philosophical issue that presupposes the accuracy of our mental-
state attributions. It could be that Spaulding is, in fact, correct that we
should not trust our judgments about who our epistemic peers are.
Alternatively, it could be that strategies like egocentric projection and
stereotyping actually make mindreading more reliable, as I argued above.
Without any way to empirically test such claims, however, neither position
enjoys any direct evidential support.
4. Conclusion
In this commentary, I have focused on one theme that emerges in Spaulding
(2018): the accuracy of mindreading. I have oered some pushback against
Spauldings arguments about the inaccuracy of mindreading, and then
I took a step back to point out what I think is a bigger problem regarding
accuracy. In spite of these points of disagreement, I am largely sympathetic
to Spauldings overall project. Theories of mindreading ought to take into
account the role that dierent motivational and social factors play in the way
that mindreading functions, and Spauldings model theory provides
a promising framework for talking about these eects. Moreover, by taking
up the issue of accuracy, Spaulding has advanced the conversation about
mindreading beyond questions about its internal and conceptual under-
pinnings to questions about how our mental-state attributions actually
reect the way the world is. With this commentary, I hope to have built
upon Spauldings advances by highlighting the complexity of this issue, and
I hope to have shown that it is worthy of further philosophical attention.
Notes
1. Spaulding is sensitive to this point. In particular, she is careful to distinguish between
stereotypes that encode false statistical generalizations and stereotypes that encode
generics (Leslie, 2014). For example, most mosquitos carry West Nileexpresses
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY 11
a false statistical generalization, but the generic mosquitos carry West Nileexpresses
a true proposition. Spaulding allows that the stereotypes that inuence mindreading
may be either statistical or generic in their form, and that generic stereotypes some-
times encode true propositions.
2. Spaulding (2018) also argues that sometimes our goals in mindreading are not to
attribute accurate mental states at all but, rather, to shape or regulate the mental
states of our mindreading targets (McGeer, 2007; Zawidzki, 2013). For example, one
might try to encourage a person to sample a new kind of cuisine by convincing
them that they like to try new things. Ostensibly, this mental-state attribution need
not be true in order for it to achieve its goal. However, this goal is entirely
consistent with and indeed might actually depend upon accurate mindreading.
In order for subtle acts of regulative mental-state attribution like this to be eective,
however, they will most likely require other accurate mental-state attributions. For
example, in order for the aforementioned strategy to work, I must rst be able to
predict that the false mental-state attribution would have a particular eect on the
targets actual mental states (say, by activating the persons desire to like up other
peoples expectations of her). If this part of my prediction is wrong, then the whole
regulative strategy would fail. Thus, the fact that we sometimes mindread for
regulative purposes does not undercut the basic claim that mindreading typically
aims at accuracy.
3. Indeed, a common critique of these kinds of tasks is that they involve extraneous
performance demands that obscure conceptual competence (Helming et al., 2016;
Leslie et al., 2005; Westra & Carruthers, 2017).
4. It is also worth noting that performance on the reading-the-mind-in-the-eyes task is
strongly aected by participant race, ethnicity, and education (Dodell-Feder et al.,
2020), which raises further questions about its reliability as a tool to measure mind-
reading competence.
5. Using this method, Lewis and colleagues have found that having stronger stereotypes
can, at least in certain circumstances, lead to more accurate mindreading (Lewis et al.,
2012)a point that is consistent with the argument about stereotyping from the
previous section. However, as I go on to argue, we should be very cautious about how
much authority we give to this nding.
Disclosure statement
No potential conict of interest was reported by the author.
Funding
This work was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of
Canada [PDF 756-2018-0012].
References
Ames, D. R. (2004a). Inside the mind readers tool kit: Projection and stereotyping in mental
state inference. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,87(3), 340353. https://doi.
org/10.1037/0022-3514.87.3.340
12 E. WESTRA
Ames, D. R. (2004b). Strategies for social inference: A similarity contingency model of
projection and stereotyping in attribute prevalence estimates. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology,87(5), 573585. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.87.5.573
Amodio, D. M. (2014). The neuroscience of prejudice and stereotyping. Nature Reviews:
Neuroscience,15(10), 670682. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn3800
Aviezer, H., Ensenberg, N., & Hassin, R. R. (2017). The inherently contextualized nature of
facial emotion perception. Current Opinion in Psychology,17,4754. https://doi.org/10.
1016/j.copsyc.2017.06.006
Aviezer, H., Trope, Y., & Todorov, A. (2012). Body cues, not facial expressions, discriminate
between intense positive and negative emotions. Science,338(6111), 12251229. https://
doi.org/10.1126/science.1224313
Baron-Cohen, S. (1997). Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of mind. MIT Press.
https://books.google.com/books?hl=en&id=MDbcNu9zYZAC&pgis=1
Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Hill, J., Raste, Y., & Plumb, I. (2001). The Reading the
mind in the eyes test revised version: A study with normal adults, and adults with
asperger syndrome or high-functioning autism. Journal of Child Psychology and
Psychiatry,42 (2), 241251. https://docs.autismresearchcentre.com/papers/2001_
BCetal_adulteyes.pdf
Bian, L., & Cimpian, A. (2017). Are stereotypes accurate? A perspective from the cognitive
science of concepts. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,40,e3.https://doi.org/10.1017/
s0140525x15002307
Carruthers, P. (2009). How we know our own minds: The relationship between mind-
reading and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,32(2), 121138. https://doi.
org/10.1017/S0140525X09000545
Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind: An integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford
University Press.
Christensen, D. (2007). Epistemology of disagreement: The good news. Philosophical
Review,116(2), 187217. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2006-035
Crawford, J. T., Jussim, L., Madon, S., Cain, T. R., & Stevens, S. T. (2011). The use of
stereotypes and individuating information in political person perception. Personality &
Social Psychology Bulletin,37(4), 529542. https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167211399473
Dodell-Feder, D., Ressler, K. J., & Germine, L. T. (2020). Social cognition or social class and
culture? on the interpretation of dierences in social cognitive performance. Psychological
Medicine.https://doi.org/10.1017/S003329171800404X
Duarte, J. L., Crawford, J. T., Stern, C., Haidt, J., Jussim, L., & Tetlock, P. E. (2014). Political
diversity will improve social psychological science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,38,
154. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X14000430
Epley, N., Keysar, B., Van Boven, L., & Gilovich, T. (2004). Perspective taking as egocentric
anchoring and adjustment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,87(3), 327.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.87.3.327
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2005). Folk psychology as a model. PhilosophersImprint,5(6), 116.
https://doi.org/10.3366/jqs.2011.0012
Goldstein, D. G., & Gigerenzer, G. (2005). Models of ecological rationality: The recognition
heuristic. Psychological Review,109(1), 7590. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295x.109.1.75
Heal, J. (1996). Simulation, theory, and content. In P. Carruthers & P. K. Smith (Eds.),
Theories of theories of mind (pp. 7589). Cambridge University Press.
Helming, K. A., Strickland, B., & Jacob, P. (2016). Solving the puzzle about early
belief-ascription. Mind & Language,31(4), 438469. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12114
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY 13
Hodges, S. D., Lewis, K. L., & Ickes, W. (2014). The matter of other minds: Empathic
accuracy and the factors that inuence it. APA Handbook of Personality and Social
Psychology, Volume 3: Interpersonal Relations. https://doi.org/10.1037/14344-012
Ickes, W., Stinson, L., Bissonnette, V., & Garcia, S. (1990). Naturalistic social cognition:
Empathic accuracy in mixed-sex dyads. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,59
(4), 730742. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/fd94/e2ae60224a
be60759a790083a922fc58b442.pdf
Johansson, P., Hall, L., Sikström, S., & Olsson, A. (2005). Failure to detect mismatches
between intention and outcome in a simple decision task. Science,310(5745), 116119.
https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1111709
Jussim, L. (2012). Social perception and social reality: why accuracy dominates bias and self-
fullling prophecy. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/
9780195366600.001.0001
Jussim, L., Crawford, J. T., & Rubinstein, R. S. (2015). Stereotype (In)accuracy in perceptions
of groups and individuals. Current Directions in Psychological Science,24(6), 490497.
https://doi.org/10.1177/0963721415605257
Kelly, T. (2011). Peer disagreement and higher-order evidence. In A. I. Goldman &
D. Whitcomb (Eds.), Social epistemology: essential readings (pp. 183217). Oxford
University Press.
Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: How diculties in recogniz-
ing ones own incompetence lead to inated self-assessments. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology,77(6), 1121. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.77.6.1121
Leslie, A. M., Friedman, O., & German, T. P. (2004). Core mechanisms in theory of mind.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences,8(12), 528533. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2004.10.001
Leslie, A. M., German, T. P., & Polizzi, P. (2005). Belief-desire reasoning as a process of
selection. Cognitive Psychology,50(1), 4585. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogpsych.2004.06.
002
Leslie, S.-J. (2014). Carving up the social world with generics. In J. Knobe, T. Lombrozo, &
S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford studies in experimental philosophy: Volume one (pp. 208232).
Oxford University Press.
Lewis, K. L., Hodges, S. D., Laurent, S. M., Srivastava, S., & Biancarosa, G. (2012). Reading
between the minds: The use of stereotypes in empathic accuracy. Psychological Science,23
(9), 10401046. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797612439719
Maibom, H. (2003). The mindreader and the scientist. Mind & Language,18(3), 296315.
https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0017.00229
McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In D. D. Hutto &
M. Ratclie (Eds.), Folk psychology re-assessed (pp. 137156). Springer.
Miller, D. T., & Ross, M. (1975). Self-serving biases in the attribution of causality: Fact or
ction? Psychological Bulletin,82(2), 213. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0076486
Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on
mental processes. Psychological Review,84(3), 231259. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-
295X.84.3.231
Pettigrew, T. F. (1979). The ultimate attribution error: Extending Allports cognitive analysis
of prejudice. Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin,5(4), 461476. https://doi.org/10.
1177/014616727900500407
Pronin, E., Lin, D. Y., & Ross, L. (2002). The bias blind spot: Perceptions of bias in self versus
others. Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin,28(3), 369381. https://doi.org/10.1177/
0146167202286008
14 E. WESTRA
Ritchie, J. B., Kaplan, D. M., & Klein, C. (2019). Decoding the brain: Neural representation
and the limits of multivariate pattern analysis in cognitive neuroscience. The British
Journal for the Philosophy of Science,00,127. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axx023
Roser, M., & Gazzaniga, M. S. (2004). Automatic brains, interpretive minds. Current
Directions in Psychological Science,13(2), 5659. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0963-7214.
2004.00274.x
Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). How well do we know our own conscious experience? The case of
visual imagery. Journal of Consciousness Studies,9(56), 3553. http://faculty.ucr.edu/~
eschwitz
Scott-Phillips, T. (2014). Speaking our minds: Why human communication is dierent, and
how language evolved to make it special (Vol. 3). Palgrave Macmillan. https://books.
google.com/books?hl=en&id=B0yjBQAAQBAJ&pgis=1
Spaulding, S. (2016). Mind misreading. Philosophical Issues, 26.
Spaulding, S. (2017). Do you see what I see? How social dierences inuence mindreading.
Synthese,122. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1404-1
Spaulding, S. (2018). How we understand others: Philosophy and social cognition. Routledge.
https://doi.10.4324/9781315396064
Stiller, J., & Dunbar, R. I. M. (2007). Perspective-taking and memory capacity predict social
network size. Social Networks,29(1), 93104. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socnet.2006.04.001
Tomasello, M. (2014). A natural history of human thinking. Harvard University Press.
https://books.google.com/books?hl=en&id=ksYXAgAAQBAJ&pgis=1
Wellman, H. M., & Liu, D. (2004). Scaling of theory-of-mind tasks. Child Development,75
(2), 523541. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8624.2004.00691.x
Westra, E. (2018). Character and theory of mind: An integrative approach. Philosophical
Studies,175(5), 12171241. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0908-3
Westra, E. (2019a). Getting to know you: Accuracy and error in judgments of character.
Mind & Language.https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12258
Westra, E. (2019b). Stereotypes, theory of mind, and the actionprediction hierarchy.
Synthese,196(7), 126. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1575-9
Westra, E., & Carruthers, P. (2017). Pragmatic development explains the theory-of-mind
scale. Cognition,158, 165176. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2016.10.021
Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining
function of wrong beliefs in young childrens understanding of deception. Cognition,13
(1), 103128. https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(83)90004-5
Zawidzki, T. W. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social
cognition. MIT Press.
PHILOSOPHICAL PSYCHOLOGY 15
... As Westra explains, there is actually evidence for the opposite claim. For instance, psychologists have observed notable consistency between what people think of themselves and what close associates think of them with respect to character traits that are morally loaded, such as honesty-humility on the HEXACO model (Ashton and Lee 2010;Lee et al. 2009; Lee and Ashton 2017) and guilt-proneness (Cohen et al. 2013;Westra 2020b). And people tend to converge when assessing others moral trait profiles (Helzer et al. 2014, Westra 2020b. ...
... For instance, psychologists have observed notable consistency between what people think of themselves and what close associates think of them with respect to character traits that are morally loaded, such as honesty-humility on the HEXACO model (Ashton and Lee 2010;Lee et al. 2009; Lee and Ashton 2017) and guilt-proneness (Cohen et al. 2013;Westra 2020b). And people tend to converge when assessing others moral trait profiles (Helzer et al. 2014, Westra 2020b. With this in mind, I take it we can set to the side the objection that empirical evidence could still undermine the force the Moorean-style argument. ...
Article
Full-text available
Character realism is the view that many people have and act from character. This short paper attempts to articulate and draw attention to the underappreciated connection between our commonplaces about good friendship and character realism. The main argument simply shows that character realism is very probable given ordinary intuitions and observations about good friendship and some platitudes about actual valuing attitudes and practices. For according to our commonplaces, good friendship minimally involves valuing another person non-instrumentally; many people enjoy good friendships; and the valuing of another person requires that the person exhibit some sort of stable identity over time in virtue of which we value them. But if we are more certain about these claims about good friendship than we are about our interpretations of recent psychological studies about character, and these claims entail the truth of Character Realism, then perhaps we need not worry so much about the purported empirical challenges to Character Realism.
... To our knowledge, there is as yet no systematic treatment of how groups can be the target of mind-reading. As noted by Spaulding (2018a), failures of mindreading are an understudied area in general (for the view that there is not much to study, see Westra, 2020), and what little exists on that topic deals with the central case of individuals ascribing mental states to other individuals. There is some work on how membership of a group may affect mindreading (Spaulding, 2018b;Tullmann, 2019), which is a related but different question. ...
Article
Full-text available
There is not as much resistance to COVID-19 mitigation as there seems, but there are structural features that make resistance seem worse than it is. Here, we describe two ways that the problem seeming to be worse than it is can make it worse. First, visible hesitation to implement COVID-19 responses signals to the wider society that mitigation measures may not succeed, which undermines people’s conditional willingness to join in on those efforts. Second, our evaluations of others’ willingness to implement these measures are informed by our attempts to mind-read them. Yet attempts to mind-read groups often mislead us, because groups invariably act from diverse motives, whereas mind-reading works best when identifying relatively stable and consistent motivations. This means that a small minority of people refusing to implement measures can have an outsized prominence that prompts mind-reading to diagnose widespread hesitation. These two factors form a feedback loop with each other: we see some people’s hesitation, which prompts us to mind-read other people as being more uncertain about the responses than they actually are, which undermines our confidence in the responses, which in turn encourages others to mind-read this hesitation, which further undermines confidence.
... A first point to note about this is that it is unclear to what extent the reliability of mindreading (or any of the alternative strategies) can be assessed. Westra (2020) argues that we currently do not have any good means of determining the reliability of mindreading. The reason for this is that reliability of mindreading is often assessed through comparison with self-report. ...
Conference Paper
Full-text available
How do we manage to understand the minds of others and usefully interact with them? In the last decade, the debate on these issues has developed from unitary to pluralist approaches. According to the latter, we make use of multiple socio-cognitive strategies when predicting, interpretating, and reacting to the behavior of others. This means a departure from the view of mindreading as the main strategy underlying social cognition. In this paper, we address the question of the controversial status of mindreading within such a pluralist framework. Contrary to many other accounts, we ascribe mindreading an equal status in a pluralist framework. Mindreading is required for a variety of central situations in life and importantly underlies the way in which we understand other people. Mindreading is also no less reliable than alternative strategies; reliability is not so much a matter of different competing socio-cognitive strategies, but rather of their complementary use.
Book
The cognitive ability to think about other people's psychological states is known as `mindreading'. This Element critiques assumptions that have been formative in shaping philosophical theories of mindreading: that mindreading is ubiquitous, underpinning the vast majority of our social interactions; and that its primary goal is to provide predictions and explanations of other people's behaviour. It begins with an overview of key positions and empirical literature in the debate. It then introduces and motivates the pluralist turn in this literature, which challenges the core assumptions of the traditional views. The second part of the Element uses case studies to further motivate the pluralist framework, and to advocate the pluralist approach as the best way to progress our understanding of social cognitive phenomena.
Article
Full-text available
In recent years, theories of social understanding have moved away from arguing that just one epistemic strategy, such as theory-based inference or simulation constitutes our ability of social understanding. Empirical observations speak against any monistic view and have given rise to pluralistic accounts arguing that humans rely on a large variety of epistemic strategies in social understanding. We agree with this promising pluralist approach, but highlight two open questions: what is the residual role of mindreading, i.e. the indirect attribution of mental states to others within this framework, and how do different strategies of social understanding relate to each other? In a first step, we aim to clarify the arguments that might be considered in evaluating the role that epistemic strategies play in a pluralistic framework. On this basis, we argue that mindreading constitutes a core epiststrategy in human social life that opens new central spheres of social understanding. In a second step, we provide an account of the relation between different epistemic strategies which integrates and demarks the important role of mindreading for social understanding.
Article
Full-text available
Theory of mind, also known as mindreading, refers to our ability to attribute mental states to agents in order to make sense of and interact with other agents. Recently, theorists in this literature have advanced a broad conception of mindreading. In particular, psychologists and philosophers have examined how we attribute knowledge, intention, mentalistically loaded stereotypes, and personality traits to others. Moreover, the diversity of our goals in a social interaction—precision, efficiency, self/in‐group protection—generates diversity in the mindreading processes we employ. Finally, the products of mindreading are varied, as well. We produce different sorts of mindreading explanations depending on our epistemic goals and the situational context. In this article, I piece together these different strands of research to present a broad conception of mindreading that is complex, messy, and interesting. This article is categorized under: Philosophy > Knowledge and Belief Philosophy > Psychological Capacities
Article
Full-text available
One view of heuristics is that they are imperfect versions of optimal statistical procedures considered too complicated for ordinary minds to carry out. In contrast, the authors consider heuristics to be adaptive strategies that evolved in tandem with fundamental psychological mechanisms. The recognition heuristic, arguably the most frugal of all heuristics, makes inferences from patterns of missing knowledge. This heuristic exploits a fundamental adaptation of many organisms: the vast, sensitive, and reliable capacity for recognition. The authors specify the conditions under which the recognition heuristic is successful and when it leads to the counterintuitive less-is-more effect in which less knowledge is better than more for making accurate inferences.
Article
Full-text available
People tend to hold overly favorable views of their abilities in many social and intellectual domains. The authors suggest that this overestimation occurs, in part, because people who are unskilled in these domains suffer a dual burden: Not only do these people reach erroneous conclusions and make unfortunate choices, but their incompetence robs them of the metacognitive ability to realize it. Across 4 studies, the authors found that participants scoring in the bottom quartile on tests of humor, grammar, and logic grossly overestimated their test performance and ability. Although their test scores put them in the 12th percentile, they estimated themselves to be in the 62nd. Several analyses linked this miscalibration to deficits in metacognitive skill, or the capacity to distinguish accuracy from error. Paradoxically, improving the skills of participants, and thus increasing their metacognitive competence, helped them recognize the limitations of their abilities.
Article
Full-text available
Character judgments play an important role in our everyday lives. However, decades of empirical research on trait attribution suggest that the cognitive processes that generate these judgments are prone to a number of biases and cognitive distortions. This gives rise to a skeptical worry about the epistemic foundations of everyday characterological beliefs that has deeply disturbing and alienating consequences. In this paper, I argue that these skeptical worries are misplaced: under the appropriate informational conditions, our everyday character-trait judgments are in fact quite trustworthy. I then propose a mindreading-based model of the socio-cognitive processes underlying trait attribution that explains both why these judgments are initially unreliable, and how they eventually become more accurate.
Article
Full-text available
Both mindreading and stereotyping are forms of social cognition that play a pervasive role in our everyday lives, yet too little attention has been paid to the question of how these two processes are related. This paper offers a theory of the influence of stereotyping on mental-state attribution that draws on hierarchical, predictive coding accounts of action prediction. It is argued that the key to understanding the relation between stereotyping and mindreading lies in the fact that stereotypes centrally involve character-trait attributions, which play a systematic role in the action-prediction hierarchy. On this view, when we apply a stereotype to an individual, we rapidly attribute to her a cluster of generic character traits on the basis of her perceived social group membership. These traits are then used to make inferences about that individual's likely beliefs and desires, which in turn inform inferences about her behavior.
Chapter
Theories of Theories of Mind brings together contributions by a distinguished international team of philosophers, psychologists, and primatologists, who between them address such questions as: what is it to understand the thoughts, feelings, and intentions of other people? How does such an understanding develop in the normal child? Why, unusually, does it fail to develop? And is any such mentalistic understanding shared by members of other species? The volume's four parts together offer a state of the art survey of the major topics in the theory-theory/simulationism debate within philosophy of mind, developmental psychology, the aetiology of autism and primatology. The volume will be of great interest to researchers and students in all areas interested in the 'theory of mind' debate.
Book
A proposal that human social cognition would not have evolved without mechanisms and practices that shape minds in ways that make them easier to interpret. In this novel account of distinctively human social cognition, Tadeusz Zawidzki argues that the key distinction between human and nonhuman social cognition consists in our complex, diverse, and flexible capacities to shape each other's minds in ways that make them easier to interpret. Zawidzki proposes that such "mindshaping"—which takes the form of capacities and practices such as sophisticated imitation, pedagogy, conformity to norms, and narrative self-constitution—is the most important component of human social cognition. Without it, he argues, none of the other components of what he terms the "human sociocognitive syndrome," including sophisticated language, cooperation, and sophisticated "mindreading," would be possible. Challenging the dominant view that sophisticated mindreading—especially propositional attitude attribution—is the key evolutionary innovation behind distinctively human social cognition, Zawidzki contends that the capacity to attribute such mental states depends on the evolution of mindshaping practices. Propositional attitude attribution, he argues, is likely to be unreliable unless most of us are shaped to have similar kinds of propositional attitudes in similar circumstances. Motivations to mindshape, selected to make sophisticated cooperation possible, combine with low-level mindreading abilities that we share with nonhuman species to make it easier for humans to interpret and anticipate each other's behavior. Eventually, this led, in human prehistory, to the capacity to attribute full-blown propositional attitudes accurately—a capacity that is parasitic, in phylogeny and today, on prior capacities to shape minds. Bringing together findings from developmental psychology, comparative psychology, evolutionary psychology, and philosophy of psychology, Zawidzki offers a strikingly original framework for understanding human social cognition. Bradford Books imprint
Article
Background The ability to understand others’ mental states carries profound consequences for mental and physical health, making efforts at validly and reliably assessing mental state understanding (MSU) of utmost importance. However, the most widely used and current NIMH-recommended task for assessing MSU – the Reading the Mind in the Eyes Task (RMET) – suffers from potential assessment issues, including reliance on a participant's vocabulary/intelligence and the use of culturally biased stimuli. Here, we evaluate the impact of demographic and sociocultural factors (age, gender, education, ethnicity, race) on the RMET and other social and non-social cognitive tasks in an effort to determine the extent to which the RMET may be unduly influenced by participant characteristics. Methods In total, 40 248 international, native-/primarily English-speaking participants between the ages of 10 and 70 completed one of five measures on TestMyBrain.org: RMET, a shortened version of RMET, a multiracial emotion identification task, an emotion discrimination task, and a non-social/non-verbal processing speed task (digit symbol matching). Results Contrary to other tasks, performance on the RMET increased across the lifespan. Education, race, and ethnicity explained more variance in RMET performance than the other tasks, and differences between levels of education, race, and ethnicity were more pronounced for the RMET than the other tasks such that more highly educated, non-Hispanic, and White/Caucasian individuals performed best. Conclusions These data suggest that the RMET may be unduly influenced by social class and culture, posing a serious challenge to assessing MSU in clinical populations given shared variance between social status and psychiatric illness.
Article
According to mainstream views of emotion perception, facial expressions are powerful signals conveying specific emotional states. This approach, which endorsed the use of stereotypical-posed faces as stimuli, has typically ignored the role of context in emotion perception. We argue that this methodological tradition is flawed. Real-life facial expressions are often highly ambiguous, heavily relying on contextual information. We review recent work suggesting that context is an inherent part of real-life emotion perception, often leading to radical categorical changes. Contextual effects are not an obscurity at the fringe of facial emotion perception, rather, they are part of emotion perception itself.