ArticlePDF Available
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=uabn20
A JOB Neuroscience
ISSN: 2150-7740 (Print) 2150-7759 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/uabn20
Ethical Contexts for the Future of Neuroethics
John R. Shook & James Giordano
To cite this article: John R. Shook & James Giordano (2019) Ethical Contexts for the Future of
Neuroethics, AJOB Neuroscience, 10:3, 134-136, DOI: 10.1080/21507740.2019.1632969
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2019.1632969
Published online: 22 Jul 2019.
Submit your article to this journal
Article views: 20
View related articles
View Crossmark data
with ones parents. While the Chinese do not reject
Brandts values, the relative weight they assign to these
values may differ substantially.
It is arguable whether or not the Chinese value sys-
tem is adaptive. But even if it were, it may nevertheless
provide a critical challenge to what may be an over-
emphasis on individual rights and autonomy. Garret
Hardin, in discussing the so-called tragedy of the
commons,observed that
Every new enclosure of the commons involves the
infringement of somebodys personal liberty cries of
rightsand freedomfill the air. But what does
freedommean? When men mutually agreed to pass laws
against robbing, mankind became more free, not less so.
Individuals locked into the logic of the commons are free
only to bring on universal ruin. (Hardin 1968, 1248)
Sometimes personal liberty and self-driven choice
have to be regulated in order to provide freedom.
Those, like myself, who were enculturated in the West
may not understand Hardins point as deeply, on a
visceral level, as the average Chinese citizen.
Consequently, we may be less well off if we fail to
take on board her perspective.
I end with another of Hardins observations:
The morality of an act is a function of the state of the
system at the time it is performed. Using the commons as a
cesspool does not harm the general public under frontier
conditions, because there is no public; the same behavior in
a metropolis is unbearable. (Hardin 1968, 1245)
We are living in a world that is increasingly inter-
connected, where an increasing subset of resources can
no longer be treated as a commons. Food gathering
and land for waste disposal are but a few of the
examples of resources that must be tightly regulated
and controlled in order to ensure global well-being.
Given the state of the world and the size of popula-
tions, among other things, it is an open question
whether or not Chinas framework of values is the
best (even if imperfect) moral alternative under current
conditions. That being said, the point of this brief com-
mentary is not to articulate and defend the Chinese
framework of values. It is simply to make room on
the table for non-Western voices and, perhaps, to more
effectively heed Kellmeyer and colleaguescall for
greater perspectival diversity.
REFERENCES
Brandt, R. 1979. A theory of the good and the right. Oxford, UK:
Oxford University Press.
Bruckner, D. 2009. In defense of adaptive preferences.
Philosophical Studies 142(3): 307324. doi: 10.1007/s11098-007-
9188-7.
Griffiths, M. 2019. How many stars is a smile worth? The
social cost of emotional labourThe Guardian, 3 February 2019.
https://www.theguardian.com/media/2019/feb/04/how-
many-stars-is-a-smile-worth-the-social-cost-of-emotional-labour.
Hardin, G. 1968. The tragedy of the commons. Science 162(3859):
12431248.
Kellmeyer, P., J. Chandler, L. Cabrera, A. Carter, K. Kreitmair,
A. Weiss, and J. Illes, for the Emerging Issues Task Force,
International Neuroethics Society. 2019. Neuroethics at 15: The
current and future environment for neuroethics. AJOB
Neuroscience 10(3): 104110.
Nussbaum, M. 2001. Five adaptive preferences and womens
options. Economics and Philosophy 17(1): 6788. doi: 10.1017/
S0266267101000153.
Ethical Contexts for the Future of
Neuroethics
John R. Shook, University at Buffalo
James Giordano, Georgetown University Medical Center
The state-of-the-fieldassessment titled Neuroethics at
15: The Current and Future Environment for
Neuroethics(Kellmeyer et al., for the Emerging Issues
Task Force, International Neuroethics Society 2019) high-
lights a variety of issues of an ethical character. This
assessments selectivity and relative constraint, within
the practical bounds of a short essay, could not be
avoided. Any number of possible and potentially antici-
patable social, legal, and moral concerns may come to
mind, and in light of this, its choice of representative
problems is both timely and helpful. The implications for
human welfare, and humanity itself, from advances in
brain sciences, neurotechnologies, and translational tech-
niques can be safely predicted to be deep and far-
Address correspondence to John R. Shook, Philosophy, University at Buffalo, 135 Park Hall, Buffalo, NY, USA. E-mail:
jshook@pragmatism.org
AJOB Neuroscience
134 ajob Neuroscience JulySeptember, Volume 10, Number 3, 2019
reaching; thus, the academic and applied activities of
neuroethics areand will continue to bedynamic and
increasing at an accelerating pace and widening scope.
In our view, an overlooked matter should be raised
and never allowed to fall into neglect, namely, the status
of ethics. We are not complaining that ethical worries are
omitted from this reportfar from it. Warnings about
potential violations of important moral values and
appeals to selected ethical ideals are presented in abun-
dance. But we would like to point out that an impartial
observer of current neuroethics could justifiably think
that the ethical environmentfor neuroethics, now and
for the foreseeable future, is hospitable to both Western
moral absolutism and tolerant moral relativism. If
viewed through a certain lens, the report might lend cre-
dence to the stage-setting roles played by these contrary
ethical standpoints. It gives due obeisance to underlying
valuessuch as human dignity, well-being, justice, per-
sonal autonomy, and personal privacy. Yet these values
only attain their full ethical meaning and paramount sta-
tus within particular nations as a consequence of ethical
deliberations upon events of the past 80 years (i.e., the
improbities and atrocities brought to light by the
Nuremberg DoctorsTrial) relative to Western philo-
sophical precepts of the last three centuries. Do these
deserve universal prioritization and overriding prece-
dence, among all the values and ideals promulgated by
ethical cultures around the world? One might regard
that question to be philosophically important without
imagining that neuroethics has anything at all do with
its answer. We disagree.
What then does neuroethics have to do with ethics?
Perhaps ethics can only be a significant part of the
demanding environment for neuroethics, requiring its
dutiful compliance. However, with respect to any tech-
nology-based endeavor in general, the iterative modifica-
tion and adaptation of the environment and the
organisms in it (including Homo sapiens) has become a
thoroughly human enterprise. Thus, the possibility that
ethics will be adjusted by neuroethics cannot be ruled
out in advance. We urge the view that this prospect is
not only possible, but inevitable. The grounds for this
view lie in neuroethics and its defining purpose.
At its core, neuroethics is an interdisciplinary field
for deliberations about (1) scientific investigations into
neurocognitive processes, particularly those involved
with capacities for sociality and morality, and (2) ethical,
legal, and social issues generated by brain research and
its varied applications. At first glance, a close relation-
ship between these tasks seems straightforward. The first
assignment is about the science of morality,while
the second addresses the morality of science.
Commonalities at this core of neuroethics are obvious:
science and morality (Farah 2012; Illes and Bird 2006;
Levy 2011). However, the objectives of science and ethics
are dissimilar, and the science of morality and the ethics
of science may not be compatible. Perhaps ethics has no
need of science while morality gets misunderstood by
science, according to the sorts of long-standing objections
raised by philosophy and theology. Ethical supervision
of science and technology with ethics has less opposition,
although proponents of fast progress often complain
about conservative restraints, and conservative propo-
nents frequently complain about hasty and liberal
engagements of science and technology.
Suspicions about agendas underlying neuroethics
grow on all sides. Is theorizing about morality to be
liberated by empirical science from philosophical and
theological conjecture? Scientific discoveries are revealing
significant facts about genetic, neurologic, and cognitive
processes of life, despite objections claiming that essences
of identity, mind, and soul are beyond the scope and
competence of science. While metaphysically anachronis-
tic, such protests are perennially devoted to important
values about human life, such as psychological and
moral norms. Living in a responsible and right manner
was never a matter waiting for sciences ethical instruc-
tion. What new agenda is actually served by regarding
humans only in terms of weights and measures? The
reduction of good judgment and moral rightness to brain
processes and behavioral consequences is the goal of
materialistic utilitarianism. Letting utilitarian criteria
supervise brain-related investigations and inventions
would allow rapid adoptions of technoscience in the
name of individual benefit and social betterment. Useful
innovation is about satisfying wants and needs from that
standpoint, and their reality and potency cannot be
denied. Human drives and desires have neurobiological
and psychological grounds that are more evident to sci-
entific view than changing perspectives of personal
rights or social justice. If the agenda is to comprehend
the person and the mind through understanding the
brain, will anything valuable be overlooked? Perhaps,
but what we believe cannotnor should notbe over-
looked is the way that assigning the study of morality to
neuroscience cannot guarantee that applications of
neuroscience will be ethical (Giordano and
Benedikter 2012).
A confusing scene of contentious agendas is not a
promising inauguration of a reputable academic field.
Critiques from many directions are questioning whether
neuroethics is a credible intellectual resource, or even a
coherent academic area (Conrad and De Vries 2011;
Vidal and Piperberg 2017). Dividing neuroethics into
independent areas of study, or distributing tasks of neu-
roethics among other disciplines might alleviate critical
worries. But we disagree that those concerns have hege-
monic cogency. The broad purview assigned to the field
of neuroethics provides ample room for discussions and
deliberations about humanitys technoscientific and eth-
ical future, keeping them in dialogue and dialectic rather
than discord. Neuroethics is needed now because ethical
implications for society raised by neuroscience and neu-
rotechnology cannot be an issue considered separately
from scientific implications of self-understanding as per-
sons bearing moral worth and dignity. No other field
Neuroethics at 15
JulySeptember, Volume 10, Number 3, 2019 ajob Neuroscience 135
among the humanities and social sciences, whether trad-
itionally disciplinary or newly interdisciplinary, is
designed to explore that convergence.
Neuroethics cannot avoid entanglements with mor-
ality, as intellectual progress implies a co-developing
relationship with the environing problematic conditions,
including ethics itself, which demand neuroethical
deliberation(s). The future ethical environment for neu-
roethics will be interestingly differentin no small part
due to the transformative work of neuroethics. The
assessment under discussion, Neuroethics at 15,
seems open to that likelihood. It acknowledges how
ethical values, including fundamental ideals, are not as
static as moral absolutists imagine: The ways in which
these values are understood and applied shift over
time(104). However, that observation by itself affords
insufficient guidance to the contemporary field of neu-
roethics, which in its currency and authenticity need
not or should not solely rely on ancient Greek, trad-
itional African, or medieval Chinese ideas about such
values. The way that neuroethics is largely aligned at
present with some other society and century does not
signal that ethics is safely aloof from the mire of rela-
tivism. Relativism is also on display in devout respect
shown for values that happen to be revered in (for
example) the America of late modernity. Why couldnt
neuroethics be guided toward respecting a different
sets of values from other contemporary cultures?
Absolutism is not achieved merely by proclaiming a
preference that the values of ones own society prevail
over values of other societies.
Ethical values shift and blend over time, exposing
both ethical absolutism and relativism as inadequate the-
ories. Short-term flexibility and long-term fluidity is a
sign of moral progress, not degeneration. Accordingly,
we commend this reports hopes for international con-
sensus and universal ethical standards, as long as those
inclusive ends are not pursued by hegemonic means
(Lanzilao et al. 2013; Lombera and Illes 2009). Still,
unavoidable questions will remain: What does neuro-
ethics have to do with that perennial philosophical quest
for a universal ethics? How should neuroethics conduct
its advisory work in the meantime? Perhaps neuroethics
could help advance consensus on global ethical princi-
ples, or neuroethics may have some special expertise for
discerning humanity-wide ethical rules irrespective of
culture or geopolitics (Shook and Giordano 2014). The
ethical environment for neuroethics will not acquire fur-
ther clarity until the full implications of neuroscience
and neuroethics for understanding morality
become clearer.
What does seem clear to us at present is this:
Interdisciplinary undertakings for embracing both sci-
ence and ethics through mutual dialogue and coordi-
nated deliberations are not efforts to be delayed or
dismissed. As we all look to survey the complex environ-
ment for neuroethics, we should agree that this relatively
new field is timely, necessary, and necessarily flexible.
REFERENCES
Conrad, E., and R. De Vries. 2011. Field of dreams: A social
history of neuroethics. In Advances in Medical Sociology 13:
299324.
Farah, M. 2012. Neuroethics: The ethical, legal, and societal
impact of neuroscience. Annual Review of Psychology 63: 571591.
doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.093008.100438.
Giordano, J., and R. Benedikter. 2012. An earlyand
necessaryflight of the Owl of Minerva: Neuroscience,
neurotechnology, human socio-cultural boundaries, and the
importance of neuroethics. Journal of Evolution and Technology
22(1): 1425.
Illes, J., and S. Bird. 2006. Neuroethics: A modern context for
ethics in neuroscience. Trends in Neurosciences 29(9): 511517.
doi:10.1016/j.tins.2006.07.002.
Kellmeyer, P., J. Chandler, L. Cabrera, A. Carter, K. Kreitmair,
A. Weiss, and J. Illes, for the Emerging Issues Task Force,
International Neuroethics Society. 2019. Neuroethics at 15: The
current and future environment for neuroethics. AJOB
Neuroscience 10(3): 104110.
Lanzilao, E., J. Shook, R. Benedikter, and J. Giordano. 2013.
Advancing neuroscience on the 21st century world stage: The
need for and proposed structure of An internationally
relevant neuroethics. Ethics in Biology, Engineering and
Medicine: An International Journal 4(3): 211229. doi:10.1615/
EthicsBiologyEngMed.2014010710.
Levy, N. 2011. Neuroethics: A new way of doing ethics. AJOB
Neuroscience 2(2): 39. doi:10.1080/21507740.2011.557683.
Lombera, S., and J. Illes. 2009. The international dimensions of
neuroethics. Developing World Bioethics 9(2): 5764. doi:10.1111/
j.1471-8847.2008.00235.x.
Shook, J. R., and J. Giordano. 2014. A principled and
cosmopolitan neuroethics: Considerations for international
relevance. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 9(1): 1.
doi:10.1186/1747-5341-9-1.
Vidal, F., and M. Piperberg. 2017. Born free: The theory
and practice of neuroethical exceptionalism. In Debates about
neuroethics: Perspectives on its development, focus, and future,
eds. E. Racine and J. Aspler, 6781. New York, NY:
Springer.
AJOB Neuroscience
136 ajob Neuroscience JulySeptember, Volume 10, Number 3, 2019
... If neuroscience technology enhances the brain, it will lead to important legal and ethical issues, requiring governance to achieve appropriate outcomes and address ethical concerns. This complex and challenging process must flexibly respond to society by using social institutions [6]. South Korea enacted the Brain Research Promotion Act (BRPA) in 1998, recognizing the importance of neuroscience. ...
Article
Full-text available
In 1998, Korea implemented the Brain Research Promotion Act (BRPA), a law to revamp the field of neuroscience at the national level. However, despite numerous revisions including the definition and classification of neuroscience and the national plans for the training and education systems, the governance for neuroethics has not been integrated into the Act. The ethical issues raised by neuroscience and neurotechnology remain unchallenged, especially given the focus on the industrial purpose of the technology. In the current study, we analyzed the BRPA revision process by using Kingdon's Multiple Streams Framework to determine the problems faced by the process. We propose a new strategy, including neuroethics governance and a national committee, to promote interdisciplinary neuroscience research and strengthen neuroethics in Korea.
Article
Full-text available
Importance Establishing a formal definition for neurological device abandonment has the potential to reduce or to prevent the occurrence of this abandonment. Objective To perform a systematic review of the literature and develop an expert consensus definition for neurological device abandonment. Evidence Review After a Royal Society Summit on Neural Interfaces (September 13-14, 2023), a systematic English language review using PubMed was undertaken to investigate extant definitions of neurological device abandonment. Articles were reviewed for relevance to neurological device abandonment in the setting of deep brain, vagal nerve, and spinal cord stimulation. This review was followed by the convening of an expert consensus group of physicians, scientists, ethicists, and stakeholders. The group summarized findings, added subject matter experience, and applied relevant ethics concepts to propose a current operational definition of neurological device abandonment. Data collection, study, and consensus development were done between September 13, 2023, and February 1, 2024. Findings The PubMed search revealed 734 total articles, and after review, 7 articles were found to address neurological device abandonment. The expert consensus group addressed findings as germane to neurological device abandonment and added personal experience and additional relevant peer-reviewed articles, addressed stakeholders’ respective responsibilities, and operationally defined abandonment in the context of implantable neurotechnological devices. The group further addressed whether clinical trial failure or shelving of devices would constitute or be associated with abandonment as defined. Referential to these domains and dimensions, the group proposed a standardized definition for abandonment of active implantable neurotechnological devices. Conclusions and Relevance This study’s consensus statement suggests that the definition for neurological device abandonment should entail failure to provide fundamental aspects of patient consent; fulfill reasonable responsibility for medical, technical, or financial support prior to the end of the device’s labeled lifetime; and address any or all immediate needs that may result in safety concerns or device ineffectiveness and that the definition of abandonment associated with the failure of a research trial should be contingent on specific circumstances.
Chapter
The lack of reliable therapies for regeneration or repair of the injured central nervous system, coupled with the promise of iPSC-derived neurons in basic and preclinical studies, has led to rapid expansion of research and development into this area (Boer, 2010; Meloni, Mallet, Faucon-Biguet, 2011). Alongside the promise of iPSC-derived treatments are uncertainties that remain with regard to safety, effectiveness, efficiency, and quality. The field of regenerative neurological therapeutics is entering into early phase clinical trials to assess and establish safety and efficacy of therapies that are not only palliative, but also potentially curative (see Wu et al., 2018). Scientific and regulatory communities must now face questions about the ethical, legal, and social implications (ELSI), as well as the potential social value and utility of these approaches. This article provides an introduction to these ELSI issues and a framework to assist in addressing the issues raised.
Article
В фокусе обзора находятся основные идеи, представленные в последних дискуссиях по нейроэтике. Анализ источников позволяет конкретизировать центральный круг проблем, являющихся предметом интереса нейроэтики, выделить возможные подходы к решению этих проблем и специфицировать дальнейшие перспективы развития нейроэтики. .
Article
Full-text available
Neuroethics research and scholarship intersect with dynamic academic disciplines in science, engineering, and the humanities. On the occasion of the 15th anniversary of the formation of the International Neuroethics Society, we identify current and future topics for neuroethics and discuss the many social and political challenges that emerge from the converging dynamics of neurotechnologies and artificial intelligence. We also highlight the need for a global, transdisciplinary, and integrated community of researchers to address the challenges that are precipitated by this rapid sociotechnological transformation.
Article
Full-text available
Neuroethics applies cognitive neuroscience for prescribing alterations to conceptions of self and society, and for prescriptively judging the ethical applications of neurotechnologies. Plentiful normative premises are available to ground such prescriptivity, however prescriptive neuroethics may remain fragmented by social conventions, cultural ideologies, and ethical theories. Herein we offer that an objectively principled neuroethics for international relevance requires a new meta-ethics: understanding how morality works, and how humans manage and improve morality, as objectively based on the brain and social sciences. This new meta-ethics will simultaneously equip neuroethics for evaluating and revising older cultural ideologies and ethical theories, and direct neuroethics towards scientifically valid views of encultured humans intelligently managing moralities. Bypassing absolutism, cultural essentialisms, and unrealistic ethical philosophies, neuroethics arrives at a small set of principles about proper human flourishing that are more culturally inclusive and cosmopolitan in spirit. This cosmopolitanism in turn suggests augmentations to traditional medical ethics in the form of four principled guidelines for international consideration: Self-creativity, Non-obsolescence, Empowerment, and Citizenship. neuroscience, prescriptive neuroethics, principled neuroethics, cultural pluralism, meta-ethics, cosmopolitanism, medical ethics.
Article
Full-text available
Neuroscience, with its promise to peer into the brain and explain the sources of human behavior and human consciousness, has captured the scientific, clinical, and public imaginations. Among those in the thrall of neuroscience are a group of ethicists who are carving out a new subspecialty within the field of bioethics: neuroethics. Neuroethics has taken as its task the policing of neuroscience. By virtue of its very existence, neuroethics presents a threat to its parent field bioethics. In its struggle to maintain authority as the guardian of neuroscience, neuroethics must respond to criticisms from bioethicists who see no need for the subspecialty. We describe the social history of neuroethics and use that history to consider several issues of concern to social scientists, including the social contexts that generate ethical questions and shape the way those questions are framed and answered; strategies used by neuroethicists to secure a place in an occupational structure that includes life scientists and other ethics experts; and the impact of the field of neuroethics on both the work of neuroscience and public perceptions of the value and danger of the science of the brain.
Chapter
Since it first appeared in the public eye in the early 2000s, neuroethics has acquired all the sociological features that define a discipline, such as international societies, university chairs, journals, and academic programs. An important element of its rapid development as a discipline was the claim that it should be autonomous from the field that could claim to be its “parent discipline,” namely, bioethics. This position gave rise to debate. Theoretical questions of the debate may remain open; on the ground, however, neuroethics won. It was born and has remained free. This chapter examines the ultimate foundation of neuroethics’ claim to autonomy, namely (in Adina Roskies’ words), the “peculiar relationship between our brains and our selves,” and how it functions in the discipline’s theory and practice.
Article
An adaptive preference is a preference that is regimented in response to an agent’s set of feasible options. The fabled fox in the sour grapes story undergoes an adaptive preference change. I consider adaptive preferences more broadly, to include adaptive preference formation as well. I argue that many adaptive preferences that other philosophers have cast out as irrational sour-grapes-like preferences are actually fully rational preferences worthy of pursuit. I offer a means of distinguishing rational and worthy adaptive preferences from irrational and unworthy ones. The distinction is based on the agent’s own appraisal of the adaptive preference.
Article
The aim of this article is to argue, by example, for neuroethics as a new way of doing ethics. Rather than simply giving us a new subject matter-the ethical issues arising from neuroscience-to attend to, neuroethics offers us the opportunity to refine the tools we use. Ethicists often need to appeal to the intuitions provoked by consideration of cases to evaluate the permissibility of types of actions; data from the sciences of the mind give us reason to believe that some of these intuitions are less reliable than others. I focus on the doctrine of double effect to illustrate my case, arguing that experimental results suggest that appeal to it might be question-begging. The doctrine of double effect is supposed to show that there is a moral difference between effects that are brought about intentionally and those that are merely foreseen; I argue that the data suggest that we regard some effects as merely foreseen only because we regard bringing them about as permissible. Appeal to the doctrine of double effect therefore cannot establish that there are such moral differences.
Article
"Technology is not the answer to the population problem. Rather, what is needed is 'mutual coercion mutually agreed upon'--everyone voluntarily giving up the freedom to breed without limit. If we all have an equal right to many 'commons' provided by nature and by the activities of modern governments, then by breeding freely we behave as do herders sharing a common pasture. Each herder acts rationally by adding yet one more beast to his/her herd, because each gains all the profit from that addition, while bearing only a fraction of its costs in overgrazing, which are shared by all the users. The logic of the system compels all herders to increase their herds without limit, with the 'tragic,' i.e. 'inevitable,' 'inescapable' result: ruin the commons. Appealing to individual conscience to exercise restraint in the use of social-welfare or natural commons is likewise self-defeating: the conscientious will restrict use (reproduction), the heedless will continue using (reproducing), and gradually but inevitably the selfish will out-compete the responsible. Temperance can be best accomplished through administrative law, and a 'great challenge...is to invent the corrective feedbacks..to keep custodians honest.'"