ArticlePublisher preview available

Conwy Lloyd Morgan, Methodology, and the Origins of Comparative Psychology

Authors:
To read the full-text of this research, you can request a copy directly from the author.

Abstract

The British biologist, philosopher, and psychologist Conwy Lloyd Morgan is widely regarded as one of the founders of comparative psychology. He is especially well known for his eponymous canon, which aimed to provide a rule for the interpretation of mind from behavior. Emphasizing the importance of the context in which Morgan was working—one in which casual observations of animal behavior could be found in Nature magazine every week and psychology itself was fighting for scientific legitimacy—I provide an account of Morgan’s vision for the comparative psychologist qua professional psychologist. To this end, I explore the important connection between Morgan and the evolutionary theorist, philosopher, and psychologist Herbert Spencer. It is from Spencer, I contend, that Morgan inherited a number of his key epistemological and methodological concerns about the nascent science of comparative psychology. This extends all the way to the canon, which only works as intended when paired with a Spencerian understanding of mental evolution as a progressive linear sequence. Far from being an incidental residue of a pre-Darwinian time, hierarchy was intentionally built into the very core of Morgan’s scientific comparative psychology.
Vol.:(0123456789)
Journal of the History of Biology (2019) 52:433–461
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-019-09577-2
1 3
ORIGINAL RESEARCH
Conwy Lloyd Morgan, Methodology, andtheOrigins
ofComparative Psychology
EvanArnet1
Published online: 17 July 2019
© Springer Nature B.V. 2019
Abstract
The British biologist, philosopher, and psychologist Conwy Lloyd Morgan is widely
regarded as one of the founders of comparative psychology. He is especially well
known for his eponymous canon, which aimed to provide a rule for the interpreta-
tion of mind from behavior. Emphasizing the importance of the context in which
Morgan was working—one in which casual observations of animal behavior could
be found in Nature magazine every week and psychology itself was fighting for sci-
entific legitimacy—I provide an account of Morgan’s vision for the comparative
psychologist qua professional psychologist. To this end, I explore the important con-
nection between Morgan and the evolutionary theorist, philosopher, and psycholo-
gist Herbert Spencer. It is from Spencer, I contend, that Morgan inherited a number
of his key epistemological and methodological concerns about the nascent science
of comparative psychology. This extends all the way to the canon, which only works
as intended when paired with a Spencerian understanding of mental evolution as a
progressive linear sequence. Far from being an incidental residue of a pre-Darwin-
ian time, hierarchy was intentionally built into the very core of Morgan’s scientific
comparative psychology.
Keywords Morgan’s canon· Spencer· Weismann· Comparative psychology
Introduction
Conwy Lloyd Morgan was a British geologist, psychologist, biologist, philoso-
pher, and comparative psychologist who is largely famous for a single sentence:
his “canon” of interpretation. Initially presented in a lecture by Lloyd Morgan in
England in 1892 (see the report by Dixon 1892), the canon achieved wide circula-
tion after its publication in Morgan’s Introduction to Comparative Psychology. As
* Evan Arnet
earnet@indiana.edu
1 Indiana University Bloomington, 308 Morrison Hall, 1165 E 3rd St, Bloomington, IN47405,
USA
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
... We begin across the Atlantic in late nineteenth-century Britain. Conwy Lloyd Morgan was a psychologist and philosopher whose 1894 text, Introduction to Comparative Psychology, arguably inaugurated Anglo-American comparative psychology as an experimental discipline (Boakes 1984;Wilson 2002;Arnet 2019a;Dewsbury 1984). Following Herbert Spencer, George Romanes, and others, Morgan had a general theory of learning, not necessarily in the sense that animal behavior was not impacted by the environment, but in the sense that there were a small number of core underlying learning faculties, corresponding to instinct, intelligence, and reason. ...
... Following Herbert Spencer, George Romanes, and others, Morgan had a general theory of learning, not necessarily in the sense that animal behavior was not impacted by the environment, but in the sense that there were a small number of core underlying learning faculties, corresponding to instinct, intelligence, and reason. These he took to be hierarchically arranged in accordance with a progressive theory of mental evolution (Clatterbuck 2016;Arnet 2019a). From this perspective, it is sensible to hypothesize that all non-human animals can learn in fundamentally the same way. ...
... The second is a new laboratory experimentalism (Capshew 1992). The third is a deflationary tendency toward the animal mind (Dewsbury 2000;Arnet 2019a). To be clear, though, comparative psychology was not monolithic. ...
Chapter
Full-text available
Following maze research in animal behavior studies through the twentieth century, I explore “control” as an extended historical process involving the successive stabilization or removal of bits and scraps of the world to arrive at the pure form of a phenomenon of interest. Early behaviorist investigation of maze learning aimed to strip environmental cues from maze design to study context-free learning. Exemplifying this tendency is the famous 1907 “Kerplunk” experiment of Watson and Carr, in which they concluded that rats could ultimately learn a maze as one long bodily response unspooling in a successive series of actions, rather than basing their movement through the maze on external sensory stimuli. Supporting this context-free research program was a conceptual understanding of learning as something singular and general. With later, more ecological, accounts of animal behavior, however, it was argued that these early control practices had nullified the rich interrelation between organism and environment that makes advanced learning possible. The result was a deflated and distorted understanding of animal learning. Researchers had, in short, controlled away the phenomenon. This case highlights the tension between the object of inquiry and the object of control, and illustrates how novelty emerges in reinterpreting as central to the phenomenon of interest that which was previously merely interference.
Article
In this article, I explore how researchers’ metaphysical commitments can be conducive—or unconducive—to progress in animal cognition research. The methodological dictum known as Morgan's Canon exhorts comparative psychologists to countenance the least mentalistic fair interpretation of animal actions. This exhortation has frequently been misread as a blanket condemnation of mentalistic interpretations of animal behaviors that could be interpreted behavioristically. But Morgan meant to demand only that researchers refrain from accepting default interpretations of (apparent) actions until other fair interpretations have been duly considered. The Canon backfired largely because of Morgan's background metaphysical commitment to a univocal, hierarchical, and anthropocentric account of cognitive architecture. I make the case that, going forward, comparative psychologists would do well to pair judicious use of Morgan's Canon with an openness to the existence of non‐humanlike animal minds comprising phenomena belonging to distinct cognitive and folk psychological ontologies. And I argue that this case gives us pragmatic reason to reconcile deep—e.g., psychofunctionalist—and superficial—e.g., dispositionalist—approaches to the metaphysics of belief.
Article
Full-text available
Attribution — the explanation of an observed change in terms of multiple causal factors — is the cornerstone of climate-change science. For anthropogenic climate change (ACC), the central causal factor is evidently ACC itself, and one of the primary tools used to reveal ACC is aggregation, or grouping together, of data, e.g. global mean surface temperature. Whilst this approach has served climate-change science well, the landscape is changing rapidly. First, there is an increasing focus on regional or local aspects of climate change, and on singular or unprecedented events, which require varying degrees of disaggregation. Relatedly, climate change is increasingly apparent in observations at the local scale, which is challenging the primacy of climate model simulations. Finally, the explosion of climate data is leading to more phenomena-laden methodologies such as machine learning. All this demands a re-think of how attribution is performed and causal explanations are constructed. Here we use Lloyd’s ‘Logic of Research Questions’ framework to show how the way in which the attribution question is framed can strongly constrain its possible and responsive answers. To address the Research Question “What was the effect of ACC on X?” (RQ1), scientists generally consider the question “What were the causal factors leading to X, and was ACC among them?”. If the causal factors include only external forcing and internal variability (RQ2), then answering RQ2 also answers RQ1. However, this unconditional attribution is not always possible. In such cases, allowing the causal factors to include elements of the climate system itself (RQ3) — the conditional, storyline approach — is shown to allow for a wider range of possible and responsive answers than RQ2, including that of singular causation. This flexibility is important when uncertainties are high. As a result, the conditional RQ3 mitigates against the sort of epistemic injustice that can arise from the unconditional RQ2.
Article
Full-text available
The article aims to make a contribution to the contemporary debate on emergence by focusing on Conwy Lloyd Morgan’s and George Herbert Mead’s theories of emergence. Both authors, in fact, first elaborated a theory that tried to synthesize the biological, the psycho-physiological and the social dimensions of emergent processes. Since Morgan’s emergentism and Mead’s processual ontology were conditioned by the reflections that the two thinkers had developed over the years and traces back their roots to the early 1890s, the article will be developed as follows. A brief description of Morgan’s conception of organic and mental evolution as elaborated in the 1890s and summarised in his Lowell Lectures will be outlined. Then Mead’s early writings on psychophysics and comparative psychology, pointing out a similarity between Mead and Morgan’s ideas on organic and mental evolution at that time will be introduced. Finally, their theories of emergence from the 1920s, pointing out more interesting similarities and dissimilarities will be examined.
Article
Full-text available
In the nineteenth century, farmers, doctors, and the wider public shared a family of questions and anxieties concerning heredity. Questions over whether injuries, mutilations, and bad habits could be transmitted to offspring had existed for centuries, but found renewed urgency in the popular and practical scientific press from the 1820s onwards. Sometimes referred to as “Lamarckism” or “the inheritance of acquired characteristics,” the potential for transmitting both desirable and disastrous traits to offspring was one of the most pressing scientific questions of the nineteenth century. As I argue in this paper, Carpenter’s religious commitments to abolition and the temperance movement shaped his understanding of heredity. But this also committed him to a body of evidence for the inheritance of acquired characteristics that was coming under criticism for being untrustworthy. Carpenter used his popular treatises on physiology to promote these older, familiar ideas about heredity because they provided vital means of arguing for the unity of mankind and the hereditary dangers of intemperance. While early nineteenth century physiology has been seen by some historians as a challenge to religious authority, given its potentially materialist accounts of the body and the actions of the soul, this paper demonstrates how the missionary and institutional activities of the Unitarian church were ideologically supported by Carpenter’s publications.
Book
Charles Darwin (1809–1882) first published this work in 1868 in two volumes. The book began as an expansion of the first two chapters of On the Origin of Species: 'Variation under Domestication' and 'Variation under Nature', and it developed into one of his largest works; Darwin referred to it as his 'big book'. Volume 1 deals with the variations introduced into species as a result of domestication, through changes in climate, diet, breeding and an absence of predators. He began with an examination of dogs and cats, comparing them with their wild counterparts, and moved on to investigate horses and asses; pigs, cattle, sheep, and goats; domestic rabbits; domestic pigeons; fowl; and finally cultivated plants. The work is a masterpiece of nineteenth-century scientific investigation; it is a key text in the development of Darwin's own thought and of the wider discipline of evolutionary biology.
Book
A fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge, and of the Royal Society, William Clifford (1845–79) made his reputation in applied mathematics, but his interests ranged far more widely, encompassing ethics, evolution, metaphysics and philosophy of mind. This posthumously collected two-volume work, first published in 1879, bears witness to the dexterity and eclecticism of this Victorian thinker, whose commitment to the most abstract principles of mathematics and the most concrete details of human experience resulted in vivid and often unexpected arguments. Volume 1 includes a detailed biographical introduction by Clifford's colleague, Frederick Pollock, who situates his close friend's interests in Darwin and Spinoza within a larger, life-long devotion to the principles of scientific enquiry and experiment. This volume also features two important essays, 'On Some of the Conditions of Mental Development', his first public lecture delivered at the Royal Institute in London, and 'The Philosophy of the Pure Sciences'.
Book
In the early 1890s the theory of evolution gained an unexpected ally: the Edison phonograph. An amateur scientist used the new machine—one of the technological wonders of the age—to record monkey calls, play them back to the monkeys, and watch their reactions. From these soon-famous experiments he judged that he had discovered “the simian tongue,” made up of words he was beginning to translate, and containing the rudiments from which human language evolved. Yet for most of the next century, the simian tongue and the means for its study existed at the scientific periphery. Both returned to great acclaim only in the early 1980s, after a team of ethologists announced that experimental playback showed certain African monkeys to have rudimentarily meaningful calls. Drawing on newly discovered archival sources and interviews with key scientists, Gregory Radick here reconstructs the remarkable trajectory of a technique invented and reinvented to listen in on primate communication. Richly documented and powerfully argued, The Simian Tongue charts the scientific controversies over the evolution of language from Darwin’s day to our own, resurrecting the forgotten debts of psychology, anthropology, and other behavioral sciences to the Victorian debate about the animal roots of human language.