Content uploaded by Adam Bulley
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Adam Bulley on Apr 02, 2019
Content may be subject to copyright.
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
1!
The future-directed functions of the imagination:
From prediction to metaforesight
Adam Bulley12, Jonathan Redshaw2 and Thomas Suddendorf2
1 Department of Psychology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA
2 Centre for Psychology and Evolution, School of Psychology, The University of
Queensland, Australia
Chapter for “The Cambridge Handbook of the Imagination”
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
2!
Abstract
One of the fundamental roles of human imagination is to enable the representation of
possible future events. Here, we survey some of the most critical abilities that this
foresight supports: anticipating future emotions, setting and pursuing goals,
preparing for threats, deliberately acquiring skills and knowledge, and intentionally
shaping the future environment. Furthermore, we outline how metacognition bolsters
human capacities even further by enabling people to reflect on and compensate for
the natural limits of their foresight. For example, humans make contingency plans
because they appreciate that their initial predictions may turn out to be wrong. We
suggest that the processes involved in monitoring, controlling, and ultimately
augmenting future-oriented imagination represent an important and understudied
parallel of “metamemory” that should be called “metaforesight”.
Keywords: episodic foresight, episodic future thinking, prospection, metamemory,
metaforesight, intertemporal choice, deliberate practice, goals, affective forecasting,
anxiety
Number of words - Total: 7978 (Main text: 5523 + References: 2455)
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
3!
“Man alone is able to manipulate time into past and future, transpose objects or
abstract ideas in a similar fashion, and make a kind of reality which is not present, or
which exists only as potential in the real world. From this gift comes his social
structure and traditions and even the tools with which he modifies his surroundings.
They exist in the dark confines of the cranium before the instructed hand creates the
reality.”
Loren Eiseley (1970, p. 145)
Where does our imagination come from, and what is it for? Here we argue
that one of the primary roles of the imagination as an evolved system is to facilitate
the acquisition of future benefits and the avoidance of future harms. To support this
claim, we survey some of the most critical abilities enabled by the future-oriented
imagination: anticipating future emotions, setting and pursuing goals, preparing for
threats, making flexible decisions, acquiring masterful skills, and building powerful
tools.
The idea that the capacity to imagine the future has adaptive behavioural
consequences has a long history. The ancient Greeks believed that Prometheus
(literally translated as ‘foresight’) stole fire from heaven and gave it to human beings
– the lowly animal left unequipped for the battleground of nature when capacities like
teeth, claws and thick hides were doled out (Suddendorf, 1994). The ability to
harness fire is indeed a prime example of the future-oriented power of imagination.
Controlled fires demand not only a stockpile of combustible materials, but also
knowledge of techniques to start, maintain, and contain the flames. Mastery in this
domain thus requires a suite of cognitive capacities that draw heavily on the
imagination, such as deliberate practice and planning. But the benefits are numerous
and profound: light, warmth, protection, and cooking – to name a few. Human control
of fire therefore illustrates the more general principle that imagining the future can be
decidedly useful. Despite whatever costs it may entail, foresight has been a driving
force in the evolutionary success of our species (Suddendorf & Corballis, 1997).
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
4!
1. Surveying the future-oriented functions of imagination
Among the first modern thinkers to identify the significant adaptive future-
oriented benefits of the imagination were Cyberneticists of the 1940s and 1950s. In
an oft-quoted passage, Craik (1943, pp. 59-61) noted:
“If the organism carries a ‘small-scale model’ of external reality and of its own
possible actions within its head, it is able to try out various alternatives,
conclude which is the best of them, react to future situations before they arise,
utilise the knowledge of past events in dealing with the present and the future,
and in every way to react in a much fuller, safe, and more competent manner
to the emergencies which face it.”
Many authors have built on this concept of future-oriented ‘mental models’,
and the resulting intellectual tradition is too rich for a full discussion here (see Bulley,
2018, for a review). In short, many prominent theories suggest we should consider
the imagination as a kind of simulation – often predictive – of interactions with the
environment (Barsalou, 2009; Clark, 2015; Hesslow, 2012; Pezzulo, 2008; Schacter,
Addis, & Buckner, 2008)
1
. Seen through this lens, the experiences that people have
throughout their lives form the raw material for the predictions they make about the
future (Hassabis & Maguire, 2009; Irish & Piguet, 2013; Klein, 2013; Schacter et al.,
2012; Suddendorf & Corballis, 1997; Szpunar, 2010). This does not mean, however,
that people are inflexibly bound to anticipate only that which has come before. On
the contrary, human imagination enables people to foresee situations they have
never previously experienced by combining basic elements from memory into novel
constellations. The scenarios people build in their imaginations transform and branch
in real-time as different paths of future action are considered and compared in terms
of their likelihood and desirability.
Humans often deliberately imagine the future, for instance when hatching a
plan or pondering what goals to pursue. However, at times people seem just to
!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!
!
1
For a discussion of simulations about atemporal or fictitious events and the past, as
well as the relationship between mental time travel into the past and future, see
Schacter and Addis chapter and Michaelian, Perrin & Sant’Anna chapter (this
volume) as well as Suddendorf (2010).
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
5!
daydream and inadvertently stumble upon future possibilities. Thus, some
researchers have suggested a distinction between voluntary and involuntary mental
time travel into the future (Finnbogadóttir & Berntsen, 2013), and others have
suggested that people tend to move back and forth between these modes when their
minds wander (e.g., Seli et al., 2018). The key point to recognize is that imagining
the future is a decidedly common human activity, even to the extent that people
cannot help but occupy themselves with it when they have nothing much else to
focus on (Corballis, 2013). In this section, we consider why this tendency is so
quintessentially human, by highlighting some of the powerful abilities that imagining
the future enables. We then explore how even more powerful benefits are unlocked
by our capacity to reflect on and critically appraise our simulations of the future –
through what we call metaforesight.
1.1 Affective forecasting and goals. Imagining the future enables people to
evaluate alternate possible paths forward, and to therefore choose which to pursue.
A common way to evaluate outcomes is to anticipate how we would feel if they
happened, and this has been called affective forecasting (Gilbert & Wilson, 2007).
Simulating an interaction with the environment allows people to respond emotionally
‘as-if’ the event were really occurring (Damasio, 1994; Pezzulo, 2008). However, the
relationship between emotion and foresight is complex. Aside from anticipated
emotions (those predicted to occur in response to a future event), humans also have
anticipatory emotions felt in the present about an upcoming event, such as
excitement or dread (Berns et al., 2006; Loewenstein & Lerner, 2003). The very act
of anticipation can be strongly emotive – as the German vernacular recognizes:
“Vorfreude ist die schönste Freude” (anticipated joy is the greatest joy).
Goals are desired possible future states, which implies an emotional
assessment of potential scenarios. However, a goal is more than an “affective
forecast” or a basic evaluation of a possible situation – it is a motivator (Pezzulo &
Rigoli, 2011). Once emotions have been forecasted, they can rally cognitive and
behavioural resources towards or away from different possible future scenarios.
Indeed, mental simulations of the future tend to cluster around personal objectives
(D’Argembeau, 2016). People can even anticipate drive states and physiological
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
6!
needs they do not currently possess – an ability perhaps out of reach for other
animals (Bischof-Köhler, 1985; Köhler, 1925; Suddendorf & Corballis, 2007).
Humans alone build fires before they are cold and stuck in the dark.
1.2 Preparation for threats. This same ability to anticipate future emotions and
organise current behaviour accordingly underlies flexible and advanced preparation
for future dangers (Miloyan, Bulley, & Suddendorf, 2016, 2018). Of course, many
different species exhibit a capacity for defence in the face of immediate danger.
Indeed, some animals even have sophisticated responses to indicators of their own
vulnerability (Bateson, Brilot, & Nettle, 2011). For example, starlings spend more
time glancing around when they are foraging further apart from their flock neighbors
– and thus are more succeptible to attacks (Devereux, Whittingham, Fernández-
Juricic, Vickery, & Krebs, 2006). But humans can prop open the window of time for
defense still farther. With the imagination, anxiety can be evoked regardless of what
is currently perceived. Humans were therefore motivated to craft spears that would
only later pierce the heart of their predators (Bulley, Henry, & Suddendorf, 2017).
In addition to extending the preparatory window, it is the flexibility afforded by
foresight that makes human defence so uniquely powerful. Consider the burrows that
many animals create, into which they can scurry when they sense a nearby predator.
Although burrows can be very complex, they are nevertheless built according to fixed
rules and offer only a limited set of hiding places. Humans, however, can anticipate
the failures of their hiding places and therefore place a trap at the entrance, cause a
distraction, or create a hidden escape route, and rapidly adjust these strategies
when they learn about new threats and possibilities. Consider, for instance, the
ingenious ways in which human cities have subsisted during prolonged periods of
siege warfare, by employing walls, tunnels, moats, traps and all sorts of
sophisticated battle plans, distractions and deceit.
1.3 Flexible decision-making. It should be clear that imagining the future allows
humans to fine-tune their behaviour to optimise long-term outcomes. Often, however,
present-moment behaviour is pitted in opposition to future outcomes – for example
when capitalising on some opportunity now cuts off paths to a possibly greater but
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
7!
delayed reward. Humans, like other animals, face a variety of ‘intertemporal’ trade-
offs as a result (Loewenstein, Read, & Baumeister, 2003; Stevens & Stephens,
2008). To eat the fruit now, or wait for the added taste and nutrition afforded by it
ripening?
The capacity to subordinate immediate pleasure to more long-term aims has
long been emphasized as a strategy for personal success and as a powerful tool in
the arsenal of human cognition (Ainslie, 1975; Baumeister & Tierney, 2011).
Mischel’s seminal marshmallow tests with young children are prominent examples of
early psychological work on the topic (Mischel, Shoda, & Rodriguez, 1989).
However, the question of how humans deal with such trade-offs has been studied
since antiquity; for instance as Plato’s concept of akrasia (e.g., Rorty, 1980). Akratic
behaviours are those in opposition to one’s own better judgement, with the word
akrasia translating to “without strength” or “lacking command”. Akrasia is also core to
many world religious traditions: one must wait patiently and act prudently in the now
for the promise of reward in the afterlife. Thus, there is often a struggle between
immediate gratifications and higher ideals or goals (which is in many cases to simply
say imagined future payoffs).
Human adults’ intertemporal trade-offs are studied in many ways, but perhaps
most commonly with so-called intertemporal choice tasks. In such tasks, participants
make choices between immediate and delayed rewards, such as between $25 today
and $60 in 14 days (Kirby, Petry, & Bickel, 1999). The extent to which someone
discounts future rewards can be calculated based on their answers to multiple
intertemporal questions with different values and delays. Recent evidence suggests
that imagining future events when making intertemporal choices can shift
preferences towards future outcomes, reducing delay discounting. For example, in a
study by Peters and Büchel (2010), participants chose between monetary rewards
such as 20€ now, or 35€ in 45 days – while sometimes being cued to imagine an
actual event they had planned around the same time as the delayed option. When
they were cued in this way, participants more often said they would be willing to wait
for the extra euros, and the more vividly they reported imagining the event, the
stronger the shift in their preferences (for reviews see Bulley, Henry, & Suddendorf,
2016; Schacter, Benoit, & Szpunar, 2017). This work dovetails with numerous
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
8!
theoretical perspectives on the role of the imagination in intertemporal preferences.
Boyer (2008), for instance, suggested that one evolutionary function of imagining the
future is to act as a motivational brake on shorter-term impulses such as the
temptation to take advantage of another person for selfish gains.
It is important to note, however, that prudent reflection may not always
encourage choices for delayed over immediate rewards. Sometimes it is most
beneficial to pursue instantly available rewards. As the saying goes: a bird in the
hand is worth two in the bush. In nature, and in human cultural systems, delaying
gratification fundamentally relies on trust that the anticipated or promised outcome
will manifest. There are thus many circumstances where it is smart to take the
immediate but smaller reward, such as when the future outcome is particularly
uncertain or remote (Fawcett, McNamara, & Houston, 2012; Stevens & Stephens,
2008). When put to the extreme, too much patience can result in decision makers
dying “of starvation waiting for the windfall” (Santos & Rosati, 2015, p. 337). The
challenge is to know when to pursue immediate gratification and when to work
towards longer-term pay-offs.
Many critical human systems (including, but not limited to banks)
fundamentally rely on the capability to establish long-term trust in the name of
collaboration. The same is true even of rudimentary trading relationships in which
goods and services are exchanged after a delay. A growing body of evidence
suggests that foresight can encourage prosocial behaviour, implicating future-
oriented imagination in establishing and solidifying interpersonal trust (e.g., Gaesser
& Schacter, 2014; Sjåstad, 2019). Conversely, violations of trust undermine the
reasons for delaying gratification (Mischel, 2014). Even young children are less
willing to wait for a delayed reward if the experimenter has broken a promise (Kidd,
Palmeri, & Aslin, 2013).
1.4 Deliberate practice. To build a sustained fire, craft and use a sturdy weapon,
or play an instrument, one must attain mastery of a skill. Practicing is the way to
achieve such mastery. It requires thinking about one’s future self as alterable. Once
an upgraded future self can be envisioned, say with improved abilities and
knowledge, people can become motivated to pursue steps towards making this a
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
9!
reality (Davis, Cullen, & Suddendorf, 2015; Suddendorf, Brinums, & Imuta, 2016).
Through many hours of practice humans pursue a seemingly endless variety of
skills. And while deliberate practice usually involves repetitions of physical actions, it
is also the case that humans can improve their skills by merely imagining the
relevant actions (e.g., Coffman, 1990).
Some of the earliest material evidence for deliberate practice in our lineage
comes in the form of Acheulean handaxes and cleavers associated with Homo
erectus (Suddendorf et al., 2016). The oldest surviving examples of the symmetrical
handaxes – which potentially had many different uses including cutting meat from
carcasses, digging for tubers, and woodworking – are over 1.76 million years old
(Lepre et al. 2011). There are some archaeological sites where a bounty of bifacial
handaxes lies discarded, for example at Olorgesailie in Kenya. This abundance of
intricately crafted tools suggests that their makers were practicing the manufacturing
skill. After all, if merely a handaxe was needed, they could have just picked up one of
the ones lying around. Instead, new ones were made again and again, and their
makers would have carried with them not just a tool, but the capacity to craft a new
one whenever needed (Suddendorf et al., 2016). The tools themselves exhibit signs
of effortful and detailed production, such as an aesthetic bi-directional symmetry that
would have required mastery of the relevant knapping skills (Mithen, 1996; Shipton &
Nielsen, 2015). The tools are complex and uniform enough that they must also have
emerged through iterative social learning, and perhaps teaching (Legare & Nielsen,
2015; Whiten & Erdal, 2012).
Another hypothesis about the overabundance of Acheulean handaxes is that
they represent a form of sexual signalling of desirable qualities such as the
competence of the creator (Kohn & Mithen, 1999). However, this possibility is clearly
complementary with the deliberate practice account. Even as a sexual signal, the
creation of a bifacial handaxe requires deliberate practice of flint knapping. Consider
the West Tofts handaxe, which has a shell embedded at its centre. The creator of
this object appears to have selected the flint and knapped it so that the shell stayed
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
10!
in the middle — demonstrating not only competence but perhaps also a sense of
beauty (Oakley, 1981).
2
Figure 1. The West Tofts Handaxe. A shell of the Cretaceous bivalve mollusc
Spondylus spinosus is embedded at the centre of the tool. This image is copyrighted.
Reproduced by permission of University of Cambridge Museum of Archaeology &
Anthropology (accession number!1916.82).
2. Compensating for anticipated limits: introducing “metaforesight”
Humans, perhaps uniquely, are capable of meta-representational insight into
the relationship between their imagination and reality. In other words, people can
!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!
!
2
It is also possible that the shell placement is a complete coincidence. The interpretation of handaxes
in general, and especially with regards to what they tell us about ancient cognition, is contentious
within archaeology (for example see Machin, 2008).
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
11!
evaluate how imagined scenarios link in with the external world, and thus assess
whether what is imagined is likely to actually occur in the future, and whether it is
biased, pessimistic, or hopeful and so forth. In the broad sense, meta-representation
involves representing the relation between (i) a representation and (ii) what that
representation is about (Pylyshyn, 1978). The development of such a capacity in
childhood is widely considered as critical to the emergence of an understanding of
other people’s minds (e.g., Perner, 1991). In the domain of foresight, this form of
metacognition has long been given a central role (Suddendorf, 1999). Once one
appreciates that one’s thoughts about the future are just representations, one is in a
position to evaluate them, to modify them, to discount them, to discuss them, and to
try to compensate for their shortcomings (Redshaw, 2014; Redshaw & Bulley, 2018).
Indeed, this capacity may be crucial to children acquiring a mature sense of future
time itself – as a series of possible chains of events of which only one will actually
happen (see Hoerl & McCormack, 2018).
In this section, we will discuss a number of ways that metarepresentational
foresight unlocks a new suite of adaptive benefits for future-oriented imagination in
each of the domains surveyed above. Our primary argument is that metacognition
enables people to evaluate the strengths and limitations of their own predictions and
the future operation of other cognitive systems. These insights can then drive
compensatory action in preparation for possible cognitive failures, such as
contingency planning and the use of external reminders (Redshaw & Bulley, 2018;
Risko & Gilbert, 2016). We propose that together these processes be called
metaforesight. Given the established links between memory and foresight, this name
offers a fitting parallel to metamemory. Metamemory processes are those that
enable people to monitor and control their memory capacities, and this has long
been a subject of intense research (Bjork, 1994; Dunlosky & Tauber, 2016; Flavell &
Wellman, 1975; Nelson & Narens, 1990).
We have recently begun to examine how aspects of metaforesight develop in
childhood, and whether certain fundamentals are shared with other animals. In one
study, children and great apes were given the opportunity to catch a desirable target
dropped into an inverted “Y” shaped tube. Two-year-old children and apes typically
covered only a single exit from the tube, and thus missed the reward on
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
12!
approximately half of the trials. By age four, however, most children consistently
covered both exits from the first trial onwards, ensuring they would always catch the
reward (Redshaw & Suddendorf, 2016). One interpretation is that the older children
understood that their prediction of the future target location could be wrong, and that
therefore it was worth covering both bases (Redshaw, Suddendorf, et al., 2018;
Suddendorf, Crimston, & Redshaw, 2017).
In another recent study, we tested young children’s metacognitive
compensation for their anticipated memory failures (Redshaw, Vandersee, Bulley, &
Gilbert, 2018). Children aged 7 to 13 were given a computerized task which required
them to remember to carry out future intentions after a delay – analogous to a
prospective memory situation such as needing to remember to bring home a book
from school (Brandimonte, Einstein, & McDaniel, 2014). We then gave participants
the opportunity to set themselves reminders of the future intentions if they wished to
do so. Children of all ages demonstrated appropriate knowledge about their potential
memory failures – recognizing that it would be harder to perform the task when there
were more intentions to remember. However, we found that only children from about
9 years onwards set themselves more reminders in conditions in which they
anticipated their future memory performance would be worse.
Children’s age-related improvements on these specific tasks may be driven by
more general developments in both metacognitive insight and metacognitive control.
Metacognitive insight refers to beliefs about the capacities and limitations of our own
minds (Nelson & Narens, 1990), and typically develops during the preschool years.
Even 3.5-year-olds, for instance, seem to understand when they are uncertain about
the location of a hidden object (Neldner, Collier-Baker, & Nielsen, 2015) or if they
have previously learned an item from a memory list (Balcomb & Gerken, 2008).
Metacognitive control, on the other hand, refers to the use of metacognitive insight to
flexibly adopt behavioural strategies in varied situations, and typically develops
during the primary school years. For example, although 6- and 7-year-olds know the
difference between easy and hard items to learn for a memory test, only around age
9 do children dedicate proportionately more time to studying hard items than easy
items (Dufresne & Kobasigawa, 1989). Such fundamentals of metaforesight may
underlie a range of powerful abilities that we will now explore in more detail.
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
13!
Figure 2. Recent studies into the fundamentals of metaforesight in development. (i)
Catching the ball dropped into the tube is guaranteed only by covering both exits
simultaneously – a rudiment of contingency planning. Reprinted from Current
Biology, 26 (13), Redshaw, J., & Suddendorf, T., Children and Apes’ Preparatory
Responses to Two Mutually Exclusive Possibilities, 1758-1762, Copyright (2016)
with permission from Elsevier (ii) In a reminder-setting task, participants drag
numbered circles in ascending order to the bottom of the box. They must also
remember to carry out either one or three alternative actions for specific numbers
(dragging them to a particular edge) (A-B). In some conditions, participants have the
option of dragging the target circles to the relevant edge of the box at the beginning
of the trial – a reminder setting strategy (C). If participants do pursue this option,
then—after dragging non-target circles to the bottom of the box (D-E)—the new
location of the target circles will remind them of the required action (F). Reprinted
from Child Development, 89 (6), Redshaw et al. Development of Children’s Use of
External Reminders for Hard-to-Remember Intentions, 2099-2108, Copyright (2018)
with permission from John Wiley and Sons. Child Development © 2018 Society for
Research in Child Development, Inc. All rights reserved. 009-3920/2018/8906-0015.
2.1 The power of metaforesight
Appreciating that the future may not pan out according to their best-laid plans,
people frequently establish diverse contingencies and ‘if-then’ conditionals – much to
their benefit (and to the profit of insurance salespeople). Counterfactual thinking
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
14!
about how things might have been is a boon to this kind of flexible planning because
it lets people simulate how their mistakes might have cost them – and how to avoid
repeating errors (Beck, Robinson, Carroll, & Apperly, 2006; Byrne, 2016; Rafetseder,
Cristi-Vargas, & Perner, 2010; Schacter, Benoit, De Brigard, & Szpunar, 2015).
People also frequently set up choices that are changeable – for instance by keeping
receipts so that clothing can be returned if one no longer likes how it looks. In setting
out on a clear morning, with fine weather predicted all day, people might nonetheless
decide to bring a coat because they realise that their initial sunny outlook (or that of
the weather forecaster) could be mistaken.
In the domain of deliberate practice, humans frequently face the problem of
deciding what skills to try and master given that there is only so much time in a day.
Should I try and master the piano, or pick an easier but perhaps less impressive
instrument? Notably, this can also take the form of ‘second-order volitions’ –
attempting to determine what we should want, and, indeed, wanting to want other
things (Frankfurt, 1988). Together, these processes enable people to become
knowledgeable and proficient in vastly disparate areas of mastery. The fact that
individuals make such different choices goes some way to explaining why humans
are so diverse in their expertise. Indeed, when wired together in reciprocal networks,
this range of expertise has accelerated human innovation and potent cooperation,
and has played a critical role in our dominance on the planet (Legare & Nielsen,
2015; Suddendorf, 2013).
Most research on the role of metacognition in future-oriented mental time
travel comes from the domain of flexible decision-making and willpower. This reflects
the practical importance of this question for understanding a vast swathe of
unhealthy behaviour in so-called ‘impulse-related disorders’ including drug use and
overeating (Koffarnus, Jarmolowicz, Mueller, & Bickel, 2013): why, exactly, do
people often fail to control their behaviours even when they are fully aware of the
prospective costs? However, even everyday drug use such as drinking coffee
involves, often implicitly, some strategic compensation for one’s own future cognitive
limitations. One might hope for a perfectly chipper morning meeting, but also realise
that without same caffeine this is likely to be little more than wishful thinking. The
vast majority of human drug use is not clinically problematic and does not reach the
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
15!
threshold for diagnosis, leading some authors to argue that most drugs are instead
used strategically as tools to modify and enhance cognition in various domains
(Müller & Schumann, 2011).
On the other hand, people often employ metaforesight to align their
anticipated future behaviours with their ‘better judgement’ – as in the akrasia
examples discussed earlier. Odysseus, in the archetypal display, has himself lashed
to the mast of his ship to prevent an anticipated failure of willpower when he hears
the sirens calling (Ainslie, 1975; Boyer, 2008; Elster, 2000). Here, Odysseus realised
that an imagined future in which he successfully avoided the sirens was just one way
things could turn out, and a dangerous alternative was likely unless he took steps in
the present to guard against his future temptations. To do it, he offloaded his
cognition – relying on other people in the environment as mechanisms for situational
self-control (Duckworth, Gendler, & Gross, 2016). The dieter who, in a cool moment
of insight, tells his spouse to hide the cookies is applying the same strategy.
Humans implement such strategies in a form of negotiation with their own
future self (Parfit, 1971; Rachlin, 2016; Schelling, 1960; Thaler & Shefrin, 1981).
There are apps one can download, for example, that once activated simply block
access to various social media, news, and entertainment websites. It is common
practice in trying to quit biting one’s nails to apply a clear nasty-tasting liquid so that
future failures are punished and corrected by one’s own past compensatory
behaviour. A clinical treatment, ‘antabuse’ (disulfiram) produces the effects of a
hangover immediately after consuming alcohol, and not after the typical delay
(Rachlin, 1995; Shelling, 1983). In all of the above cases the common thread is that
a future is imagined wherein the person recognizes that their future self will have
particular limits – with precursory compensating action a downstream effect of this
insight.
Finally, we note that metaforesight may play a particularly crucial role in
solving one of the most archetypal future-oriented problems that humans face: how
to anticipate and act to satisfy future desires that we currently do not experience
(Suddendorf & Corballis, 1997). Indeed, anticipation of future desire states need not
necessarily be based on pre-experiencing these desire states. Rather, we may often
project our current drive states and physiological needs into our future selves – and
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
16!
then meta-cognitively recognise that these imagined states are misleading and alter
our behaviour accordingly (Redshaw & Bulley, 2018). Thus a fully-sated shopper
does not necessarily need to imagine being hungry in order to buy next week’s
groceries; she merely needs to know that she (and the rest of her family) will not be
sated in the future.
3. Tools that metaforesight helps to build
As discussed earlier, bifacial hand axes from the Acheulean represent
perhaps the earliest hard evidence for complex prospective cognition in any Homo
species (Hallos, 2005). However, metaforesight allows humans to create still more
complex tools – or cognitive artefacts – that extend and buttress the mind (Clark,
2008, 2015; Clark & Chalmers, 1998; Donald, 1991; Dror & Harnad, 2008;
Heersmink, 2013; Hutchins, 1999; Jones, 2007; Sterelny, 2010; Sutton, 2006). There
is some Palaeolithic evidence for representations of landscape features for use in
navigation or planning that might fairly be called ‘maps’ (Clarke, 2013; Smith, 1987),
including a recently discovered set of engraved stone blocks from Abauntz Cave in
Navarra, Spain dating back approximately 13,000 years (Utrilla, Mazo, Sopena,
Martínez-Bea, & Domingo, 2009). The tablets may have been portable, weighing
less than the average modern laptop (Clarke, 2013), and thus built in advance to
compensate and extend for known limitations in unaided navigation. Interpretations
of these engravings and other similar artefacts, such as an 8200-year-old Neolithic
“settlement plan map” in Çatalhöyük, Anatolia (Mellaart, 1967), are contentious
(Meece, 2006; Woodward & Harley, 1987). We must also consider that maps are
most useful if they can be created and used ‘on-the-go’, and are thus likely to have
been produced for thousands of years with transient materials prior to the earliest
remaining evidence (Dawkins, 1998). Lines drawn in the sand, however, are
famously ephemeral.
Indications of metaforesight in tool use are non-contentious by the time of
Babylonian Mesopotamia around 5000 years ago, where evidence for expert
cartography abounds, as does cuneiform script (Clarke, 2013; Fischer, 2001;
Woodward & Harley, 1987). Maps and writing are of course both excellent evidence
that future-directed metacognitive insight and control had emerged because they
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
17!
enable the user to outsource various cognitive processes including memory,
mathematics, and even trust. Consider that early recordings of trade and debt took
the form of a single marked wooden block called a tally that could be split into two
halves – the ‘foil’ and the ‘stock’ (Baxter, 1989). Putting both halves back together
again in the future to read the inscription would expose any tampering, negating the
need for perfect mental accounting of what was sold or owed.
Numerous artefacts abound from diverse cultures that served similar roles, for
example the intricate knotted string ‘Quipus’ used by the Incans and other Andean
cultures to store complex records including census and tax information (for multiple
other examples see Kelly, 2017). By the rise of ancient Greece, complex water
clocks had been developed to keep track of time during political speeches (Dohrn-
van Rossum, 1996). All subsequent alarm clocks and external reminders employ the
same underlying logic – recognition of, and compensation for, an expected failure of
prospective memory.
Once these kinds of complex tools are invented, it becomes fruitful to assess
their ability to perform cognitive work in a similar way to how one might evaluate
one’s own abilities (Risko & Gilbert, 2016). Thus, although one might use Google to
help plan the location of a first date, it is inadvisable to use Google during the date to
help plan the next topic of conversation. Science, as a ‘thinking tool’ takes this to its
extreme: a hypothesis is generated alongside an explicit assessment of its possible
incorrectness, and, furthermore, a test that could falsify it (Popper, 1934). Indeed, it
is now customary to report metacognitive assessments such as confidence intervals,
statistical power and the standard errors of estimates in empirical articles. Scientific
instruments are often themselves extensions of sensory apparatuses (like
telescopes) as well as tools for the enhancement of cognitive labour (like computers)
– but their capacities and uses must be assessed accurately for offloading to be
productive (Heersmink, 2016).
People may likewise selectively offload cognitive tasks into other people’s
minds, for instance when trusting an elder with the details of a creation myth, an
experienced tracker to navigate through treacherous terrain, or a spouse with
remembering a family appointment (Kelly, 2015; see also Michaelian & Sutton, 2013;
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
18!
Nestojko, Finley, & Roediger, 2013; Palermos, 2016)
3
. There is, however, limited
research on how and when people perform prospective cognitive offloading into the
minds of other people (‘distributed cognition’), or its development in children (though
see for example Barnier, Sutton, Harris, & Wilson, 2008; Hirst & Echterhoff, 2012). In
further studying social cognitive offloading, it may prove fruitful to borrow from the
growing body of work on the role of metacognition in social learning strategies – that
is, how people come to ‘know who knows’ desired information and use that
information to learn selectively from others (Heyes, 2016).
4. Future directions and concluding remarks
The human imagination facilitates a large array of future-oriented faculties.
These include anticipating future emotions, complex planning, preparation for
threats, flexible decision-making, and deliberate practice, all of which are immensely
powerful in their own right. However, we have also identified how a capacity for
metacognition bolsters these capacities even further. We have proposed
“metaforesight” – the processes involved in monitoring, controlling, and ultimately
augmenting foresight – as an important and understudied parallel of metamemory.
The study of this set of processes is in its infancy. There are numerous open
questions, such as how metaforesight develops in childhood, what aspects of it are
shared with other animals, when and where it emerges in the archeological record,
its underlying cognitive and neural mechanisms, and its deterioration in aging and
disease. When is it optimal to ‘offload’ cognition on the basis of our anticipated limits,
and does frequent offloading have any negative consequences? Do non-human
animals ever place objects strategically to remind themselves of things in the future?
Can metaforesight degrade in clinical disorders while foresight remains intact? With
the capacity to recognise and reflect on the natural limits of foresight comes the
creation of mental, cultural and technological means to compensate for these limits.
The human imagination is a tool – and like any tool it is wielded more effectively
when you know where its limits lie.
!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!
!
3
Andy Clark has gone one step further still, and argues that language itself evolved because it
enables people to offload their thoughts into the external environment as perceptible ‘objects’ that
they and other people can then ‘use’ in further cognition (Clark, 2006).
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
19!
References
Ainslie, G. (1975). Specious reward: A behavioral theory of impulsiveness and
impulse control. Psychological Bulletin, 82, 463–496.
Balcomb, F. K., & Gerken, L. A. (2008). Three-year-old children can access their
own memory to guide responses on a visual matching task. Developmental
Science, 11, 750–760.
Barnier, A. J., Sutton, J., Harris, C. B., & Wilson, R. A. (2008). A conceptual and
empirical framework for the social distribution of cognition: The case of memory.
Cognitive Systems Research, 9, 33–51.
Barsalou, L. W. (2009). Simulation, situated conceptualization, and prediction.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 364,
1281–1289.
Bateson, M., Brilot, B., & Nettle, D. (2011). Anxiety: an evolutionary approach. Can J
Psychiatry, 56, 707–715.
Baumeister, R. F., & Tierney, J. (2011). Willpower: Rediscovering the greatest
human strength. Penguin.
Baxter, W. T. (1989). Early accounting: The tally and the checkerboard. The
Accounting Historians Journal, 16, 43–83.
Beck, S. R., Robinson, E. J., Carroll, D. J., & Apperly, I. A. (2006). Children’s thinking
about counterfactuals and future hypotheticals as possibilities. Child
Development, 77, 413–426.
Berns, G. S., Chappelow, J., Cekic, M., Zink, C. F., Pagnoni, G., & Martin-Skurski,
M. E. (2006). Neurobiological Substrates of Dread. Science, 312, 754–758.
Bischof-Köhler, D. (1985). Zur phylogenese menschlicher motivation.
Bjork, R. A. (1994). Memory and metamemory considerations in the training of
human beings. In Metacognition: Knowing about knowing (Vol. 185).
Boyer, P. (2008). Evolutionary economics of mental time travel? Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 12, 219–224.
Brandimonte, M. A., Einstein, G. O., & McDaniel, M. A. (2014). Prospective memory:
Theory and applications. New York: Psychology Press.
Bulley, A. (2018). The History and Future of Human Prospection. Evolutionary
Studies in Imaginative Culture, 1, 75–93.
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
20!
Bulley, A., Henry, J. D., & Suddendorf, T. (2017). Thinking about threats: Memory
and prospection in human threat management. Consciousness and Cognition,
49, 53–69.
Bulley, A., Henry, J., & Suddendorf, T. (2016). Prospection and the present moment:
The role of episodic foresight in intertemporal choices between immediate and
delayed rewards. Review of General Psychology, 20, 29–47.
Byrne, R. M. J. (2016). Counterfactual Thought. Annual Review of Psychology, 67,
135–157.
Clark, A. (2006). Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 10, 370–374.
Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension.
Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195333213.001.0001
Clark, A. (2015). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind.
Oxford University Press.
Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.
Clarke, K. C. (2013). What is the World’s Oldest Map? The Cartographic Journal, 50,
136–143.
Corballis, M. C. (2013). Wandering tales: evolutionary origins of mental time travel
and language. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 485.
D’Argembeau, A. (2016). The Role of Personal Goals in Future-Oriented Mental
Time Travel. In K. Michaelian, S. B. Klein, & K. K. Szpunar (Eds.), Seeing the
Future: Theoretical Perspectives on Future-Oriented Mental Time Travel. New
York: Oxford University Press.
doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190241537.003.0010
Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error: emotion, reason, and the human brain.
Putnam Publishing.
Davis, J. T. M., Cullen, E., & Suddendorf, T. (2015). Understanding deliberate
practice in preschool aged children. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 1–43.
Dawkins, R. (1998). Unweaving the rainbow: Science, delusion and the appetite for
wonder. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.
Devereux, C. L., Whittingham, M. J., Fernández-Juricic, E., Vickery, J. A., & Krebs,
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
21!
J. R. (2006). Predator detection and avoidance by starlings under differing
scenarios of predation risk. Behavioral Ecology, 17, 303–309.
Dohrn-van Rossum, G. (1996). History of the hour: Clocks and modern temporal
orders. University of Chicago Press.
Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind: Three stages in the evolution of
culture and cognition. Harvard University Press.
Dror, I., & Harnad, S. (2008). Offloading cognition onto cognitive technology. John
Benjamins Publishing.
Duckworth, A. L., Gendler, T. S., & Gross, J. J. (2016). Situational Strategies for
Self-Control. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11, 35–55.
Dufresne, A., & Kobasigawa, A. (1989). Children’s spontaneous allocation of study
time: Differential and sufficient aspects. Journal of Experimental Child
Psychology, 47, 274–296.
Dunlosky, J., & Tauber, S. K. (2016). The Oxford Handbook of Metamemory. Oxford
University Press.
Eiseley, L. C. (1970). The invisible pyramid. University of Nebraska Press.
Elster, J. (2000). Ulysses unbound: Studies in rationality, precommitment, and
constraints. Cambridge University Press.
Fawcett, T. W., McNamara, J. M., & Houston, A. I. (2012). When is it adaptive to be
patient? A general framework for evaluating delayed rewards. Behavioural
Processes, 89, 128–136.
Finnbogadóttir, H., & Berntsen, D. (2013). Involuntary future projections are as
frequent as involuntary memories, but more positive. Consciousness and
Cognition, 22, 272–280.
Fischer, S. R. (2001). A history of writing. Reaktion Books.
Flavell, J. H., & Wellman, H. M. (1975). Metamemory.
Frankfurt, H. G. (1988). Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. In What Is
a Person? (pp. 127–144). Springer.
Gaesser, B., & Schacter, D. L. (2014). Episodic simulation and episodic memory can
increase intentions to help others. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, 111, 4415–4420.
Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2007). Prospection : Experiencing the Future.
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
22!
Science, 317, 1351–1354.
Hassabis, D., & Maguire, E. A. (2009). The Construction System of the Brain.
Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences, 364, 1263–1271.
Heersmink, R. (2013). A Taxonomy of Cognitive Artifacts: Function, Information, and
Categories. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4, 465–481.
Heersmink, R. (2016). The cognitive integration of scientific instruments: information,
situated cognition, and scientific practice. Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences, 15, 517–537.
Hesslow, G. (2012). The current status of the simulation theory of cognition. Brain
Research, 1428, 71–79.
Heyes, C. (2016). Who Knows? Metacognitive Social Learning Strategies. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, xx, 1–10.
Hirst, W., & Echterhoff, G. (2012). Remembering in Conversations: The Social
Sharing and Reshaping of Memories. Annual Review of Psychology, 63, 55–79.
Hoerl, C., & McCormack, T. (2018). Thinking in and about time: A dual systems
perspective on temporal cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1–78.
Hutchins, E. (1999). Cognitive artifacts. The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive
Sciences, 126, 127.
Irish, M., & Piguet, O. (2013). The Pivotal Role of Semantic Memory in
Remembering the Past and Imagining the Future. Front Behav Neurosci, 7, 27.
Jones, A. (2007). Memory and material culture. Cambridge University Press
Cambridge.
Kelly, L. (2015). Knowledge and power in prehistoric societies: Orality, memory, and
the transmission of culture. Cambridge University Press.
Kelly, L. (2017). The Memory Code: The Secrets of Stonehenge, Easter Island and
Other Ancient Monuments. Pegasus Books. Retrieved from
https://books.google.com.au/books?id=dfa8DAEACAAJ
Kidd, C., Palmeri, H., & Aslin, R. N. (2013). Rational snacking: Young children’s
decision-making on the marshmallow task is moderated by beliefs about
environmental reliability. Cognition, 126, 109–114.
Kirby, K. N., Petry, N. M., & Bickel, W. K. (1999). Heroin addicts have higher
discount rates for delayed rewards than non-drug-using controls. Journal of
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
23!
Experimental Psychology: General, 128, 78–87.
Klein, S. B. (2013). The temporal orientation of memory: It’s time for a change of
direction. Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition, 2, 222–234.
Koffarnus, M. N., Jarmolowicz, D. P., Mueller, E. T., & Bickel, W. K. (2013).
Changing delay discounting in the light of the competing neurobehavioral
decision systems theory: A review. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of
Behavior, 99, 32–57.
Köhler, W. (1925). The mentality of apes. Read Books Ltd.
Kohn, M., & Mithen, S. (1999). Handaxes: products of sexual selection? Antiquity,
73, 518–526.
Legare, C. H., & Nielsen, M. (2015). Imitation and innovation: The dual engines of
cultural learning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 19, 688–699.
Loewenstein, G. F., & Lerner, J. (2003). The role of affect in decision making.
Handbook of Affective Science.
Loewenstein, G. F., Read, D., & Baumeister, R. F. (2003). Time and Decision:
Economic and Psychological Perspectives of Intertemporal Choice. Russell
Sage Foundation. Retrieved from
http://books.google.com.au/books?id=iHJcQJcg3BIC
Meece, S. (2006). A bird’s eye view–of a leopard’s spots The Çatalhöyük ‘map’and
the development of cartographic representation in prehistory. Anatolian Studies,
56, 1–16.
Mellaart, J. (1967). Çatal Hüyük: a neolithic town in Anatolia. McGraw-Hill.
Michaelian, K., & Sutton, J. (2013). Distributed Cognition and Memory Research:
History and Current Directions. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4, 1–24.
Miloyan, B., Bulley, A., & Suddendorf, T. (2016). Episodic foresight and anxiety:
Proximate and ultimate perspectives. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 4–
22.
Miloyan, B., Bulley, A., & Suddendorf, T. (2018). Anxiety: Here and Beyond. Emotion
Review. doi:10.1177/1754073917738570
Mischel, W. (2014). The marshmallow test: understanding self-control and how to
master it. Random House.
Mischel, W., Shoda, Y., & Rodriguez, M. I. (1989). Delay of gratification in children.
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
24!
Science, 244, 933–938.
Mithen, S. J. (1996). The Prehistory of the Mind a Search for the Origins of Art,
Religion and Science.
Müller, C. P., & Schumann, G. (2011). Drugs as instruments: A new framework for
non-addictive psychoactive drug use. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 293–
310.
Neldner, K., Collier-Baker, E., & Nielsen, M. (2015). Chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes)
and human children (Homo sapiens) know when they are ignorant about the
location of food. Animal Cognition, 18, 683–699.
Nelson, T., & Narens, L. (1990). Metamemory: A Theoretical Framework and New
Findings. Psychology of Learning and Motivation, 26, 125–173.
Nestojko, J. F., Finley, J. R., & Roediger, H. L. (2013). Extending Cognition to
External Agents. Psychological Inquiry, 24, 321–325.
Oakley, K. P. (1981). Emergence of Higher Thought 3.0-0.2 Ma B.P. Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 292, 205–211.
Palermos, S. O. (2016). The Dynamics of Group Cognition. Minds and Machines, 26,
409–440.
Parfit, D. (1971). Personal Identity. The Philosophical Review, 80, 3–27.
Peters, J., & Büchel, C. (2010). Episodic Future Thinking Reduces Reward Delay
Discounting through an Enhancement of Prefrontal-Mediotemporal Interactions.
Neuron, 66, 138–148.
Pezzulo, G. (2008). Coordinating with the future: The anticipatory nature of
representation. Minds and Machines, 18, 179–225.
Pezzulo, G., & Rigoli, F. (2011). The value of foresight: How prospection affects
decision making. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 5. doi:10.3389/fnins.2011.00079
Popper, K. (1934). The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge.
Rachlin, H. (2016). Self-Control Based on Soft Commitment. Behavior Analyst, 39,
259–268.
Rafetseder, E., Cristi-Vargas, R., & Perner, J. (2010). Counterfactual reasoning:
Developing a sense of “nearest possible world.” Child Development, 81, 376–
389.
Redshaw, J., & Bulley, A. (2018). Future-thinking in animals: Capacities and Limits.
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
25!
In G. Oettingen, A. T. Sevincer, & P. M. Gollwitzer (Eds.), The Psychology of
Thinking about the Future (pp. 31–51). Guilford Press.
Redshaw, J., & Suddendorf, T. (2016). Children’s and Apes’ Preparatory Responses
to Two Mutually Exclusive Possibilities. Current Biology, 26, 1758–1762.
Redshaw, J., Suddendorf, T., Neldner, K., Wilks, M., Tomaselli, K., Mishin, I., &
Nielsen, M. (2018). Young Children From Three Diverse Cultures
Spontaneously and Consistently Prepare for Alternative Future Possibilities.
Child Development, 00, 1–11.
Redshaw, J., Vandersee, J., Bulley, A., & Gilbert, S. J. (2018). Development of
Children’s Use of External Reminders for Hard-to-Remember Intentions. Child
Development, 89, 2099–2108.
Risko, E. F., & Gilbert, S. J. (2016). Cognitive Offloading. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 20, 676–688.
Rorty, A. O. (1980). Where does the akratic break take place? Australasian Journal
of Philosophy, 58, 333–346.
Schacter, D. L., Addis, D. R., & Buckner, R. L. (2008). Episodic simulation of future
events: Concepts, data, and applications. Annals of the New York Academy of
Sciences, 1124, 39–60.
Schacter, D. L., Addis, D. R., Hassabis, D., Martin, V., Spreng, R., & Szpunar, K.
(2012). The Future of Memory: Remembering, Imagining, and the Brain.
Neuron, 76, 677–694.
Schacter, D. L., Benoit, R. G., De Brigard, F., & Szpunar, K. K. (2015). Episodic
future thinking and episodic counterfactual thinking: Intersections between
memory and decisions. Neurobiology of Learning and Memory, 117, 14–21.
Schacter, D. L., Benoit, R. G., & Szpunar, K. K. (2017). Episodic future thinking:
mechanisms and functions. Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences, 17, 41–50.
Schelling, T. C. (1960). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, Mass.
Seli, P., Kane, M. J., Smallwood, J., Schacter, D. L., Maillet, D., Schooler, W., &
Smilek, D. (2018). Mind-Wandering as a Natural Kind : A Family-Resemblances
View. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 22, 479–490.
Shipton, C., & Nielsen, M. (2015). Before Cumulative Culture: The Evolutionary
Origins of Overimitation and Shared Intentionality. Human Nature, 26, 331–345.
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
26!
Sjåstad, H. (2019). Short-sighted greed? Focusing on the future promotes strategic
cooperation. Judgement and Decision Making, 14, 199–213.
Smith, C. D. (1987). Cartography in the prehistoric period in the Old World: Europe,
the Middle East, and North Africa. The History of Cartography, 1, 54–102.
Sterelny, K. (2010). Minds: Extended or scaffolded? Phenomenology and the
Cognitive Sciences, 9, 465–481.
Stevens, J. R., & Stephens, D. (2008). Patience. Current Biology : CB, 18, R11-2.
Suddendorf, T. (1994). Discovery of the Fourth Dimension: Mental time travel and
human evolution. Retrieved from http://cogprints.org/729/1/THESIS.txt
Suddendorf, T. (1999). The rise of the metamind. In L. C. Corballis MC (Ed.), The
Descent of Mind (pp. 218–260). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Suddendorf, T. (2010). Episodic memory versus episodic foresight: Similarities and
differences. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1, 99–107.
Suddendorf, T. (2013). The gap: the science of what separates us from other
animals. Basic Books.
Suddendorf, T., Brinums, M., & Imuta, K. (2016). Shaping One’s Future Self – The
Development of Deliberate Practice. In K. Michaelian, S. B. Klein, & K. K.
Szpunar (Eds.), Seeing the Future: Theoretical Perspectives on Future-Oriented
Mental Time Travel. New York: Oxford University Press.
Suddendorf, T., & Corballis, M. C. (1997). Mental time travel and the evolution of the
human mind. Genetic Social and General Psychology Monographs, 123, 133–
167.
Suddendorf, T., & Corballis, M. C. (2007). The evolution of foresight: What is mental
time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30,
299–351.
Suddendorf, T., Crimston, J., & Redshaw, J. (2017). Preparatory responses to
socially determined, mutually exclusive possibilities in chimpanzees and
children. Biology Letters, 13. doi:10.1098/rsbl.2017.0170
Sutton, J. (2006). Exaograms and Interdisciplinarity: history, the extended mind, and
the civilizing process.
Szpunar, K. K. (2010). Episodic future thought: An emerging concept. Perspectives
on Psychological Science, 5, 142–162.
FUTURE-DIRECTED FUNCTIONS OF THE IMAGINATION
!
27!
Thaler, R. H., & Shefrin, H. (1981). An economic theory of self-contol. Journal of
Political Economy.
Utrilla, P., Mazo, C., Sopena, M. C., Martínez-Bea, M., & Domingo, R. (2009). A
palaeolithic map from 13,660 calBP: engraved stone blocks from the Late
Magdalenian in Abauntz Cave (Navarra, Spain). Journal of Human Evolution,
57, 99–111.
Whiten, A., & Erdal, D. (2012). The human socio-cognitive niche and its evolutionary
origins. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences,
367, 2119–2129.
Woodward, D., & Harley, J. B. (1987). The History of Cartography, Volume 1:
Cartography in Prehistoric, Ancient, and Medieval Europe and the
Mediterranean.