Content uploaded by Marij van Strien
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Marij van Strien on Apr 09, 2019
Content may be subject to copyright.
1
Pluralism and Anarchism in Quantum Physics
Paul Feyerabend’s writings on quantum physics in relation to his general
philosophy of science
Marij van Strien
Studies in History and Philososphy of Science, DOI 10.1016/j.shpsa.2019.03.006
Abstract
This paper aims to show that the development of Feyerabend’s philosophical ideas in the
1950s and 1960s largely took place in the context of debates on quantum mechanics.
In particular, he developed his influential arguments for pluralism in science in discussions
with the quantum physicist David Bohm, who had developed an alternative approach to
quantum physics which (in Feyerabend’s perception) was met with a dogmatic dismissal by
some of the leading quantum physicists. I argue that Feyerabend’s arguments for theoretical
pluralism and for challenging established theories were connected to his objections to the
dogmatism and conservatism he observed in quantum physics.
However, as Feyerabend gained insight into the physical details and historical complexities
which led to the development of quantum mechanics, he gradually became more modest in his
criticisms. His writings on quantum mechanics especially engaged with Niels Bohr; initially,
he was critical of Bohr’s work in quantum mechanics, but in the late 1960s, he completely
withdrew his criticism and even praised Bohr as a model scientist. He became convinced that
however puzzling quantum mechanics seemed, it was methodologically unobjectionable – and
this was crucial for his move towards ‘anarchism’ in philosophy of science.
Introduction
During the first two decades of his career, Paul Feyerabend worked intensely on the
foundations of quantum mechanics. He had studied physics in Vienna; but after getting stuck
with his doctoral research he instead wrote a PhD dissertation in philosophy. However, he
retained a strong interest in physics, and throughout the 1950s and the early 1960s, the
foundations of quantum mechanics were a main area of his research. His writings on quantum
physics fill up the fourth volume of his collected papers (Philosophical Papers 4: Physics and
philosophy, ed. S. Gattei and J. Agassi, 2015), and about half of the first volume.
Despite the sheer volume of his writings on the foundations of quantum physics,
Feyerabend’s work in this area seems not to have made a lasting impact. Whereas Jammer in
his classic work The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (1974) makes a couple of references
to Feyerabend’s contributions to the field, in more recent literature on the foundations of
physics one finds scarcely any mention of Feyerabend. Feyerabend’s real impact, of course, is
2
in general philosophy of science. In 1970 he published an essay titled “Against Method”,
followed in 1975 by a book with the same title, with which he became well established, as
well as notorious, as a philosopher of science arguing against the idea that science has a fixed
methodology. After that, he wrote little on the philosophy of physics, and rarely returned to
his previous work on the foundations of quantum physics.
As contributions to the field of foundations of physics, Feyerabend’s publications on
quantum mechanics had some merit, but they were not ground-breaking. However, they form
a major context for the development of Feyerabend’s philosophy of science. I aim to show
that there are close connections between Feyerabend’s writings on quantum physics and his
general philosophy of science: his ideas in philosophy of science were partly motivated by
concerns about quantum physics, shaped by his developing insight in the intricacies of
quantum physics, and influenced in particular by the quantum physicists David Bohm and
Niels Bohr.
In particular, I argue that Feyerabend’s arguments for pluralism in science were heavily
influenced by the quantum physicist David Bohm, who was his colleague in Bristol in 1957
and 1958, and who had proposed an alternative approach to quantum physics and convinced
Feyerabend of its feasibility. Feyerabend perceived how the community of quantum physicists
dogmatically excluded alternative approaches, including the one of Bohm. Moreover,
Feyerabend identified conservative and dogmatic elements in quantum theory itself, in
particular in Niels Bohr’s account of quantum mechanics.
However, in the mid-1960s, Feyerabend came to realize that his criticisms of quantum
physics were at least partly misplaced; in particular, he came to realize that Niels Bohr had
had very good reasons to develop his ideas in quantum physics the way he did, and was far
from having been a conservative scientist. Feyerabend’s realization that he had no reason to
criticize quantum physics on methodological grounds led him to take a step back and as he
himself claimed, this was decisive in his move towards anarchism in philosophy of science.
Despite the continued interest in Feyerabend’s philosophy of science, there have only been
limited attempts to examine the relevance of this work on quantum physics for the
development of his ideas. The most comprehensive account seems to be the entry on Paul
Feyerabend in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, which contains a few paragraphs on
Feyerabend’s work on quantum mechanics (Preston, 2016). Oberheim, in Feyerabend's
Philosophy (2006), writes that “Feyerabend’s enormous debt to Bohm has gone largely
unnoticed in the hefty secondary literature on Feyerabend’s philosophy”, but otherwise only
offers some brief remarks on Feyerabend’s relation to Bohm; also Preston (2016) and
Collodel (2016) mention Bohm’s influence on Feyerabend, but provide little detail, and do not
mention Bohm’s alternative approach to quantum physics.
1
In section 1, I show how Feyerabend developed his arguments for pluralism in science and
how this can be placed in the context of debates on David Bohm’s alternative approach to
quantum physics, starting with a brief sketch of Bohm’s approach to quantum physics and his
position in the physics community. Section 2 deals with Feyerabend’s move to anarchism
which went together with a reappraisal of the work of Niels Bohr.
1
While writing this paper I became aware of the fact that Daniel Kuby was working on a paper which also deals
with Feyerabend’s writings on quantum mechanics, see Kuby (forthcoming).
3
1. Pluralism
1.1 David Bohm’s Position at the Margins of Physics
In the 1950s, a number of alternative approaches to quantum physics appeared, which
challenged the consensus about the foundations of quantum physics (see Camilleri 2009,
Freire 2015). Partly, these criticisms of orthodox quantum physics came from a Marxist or
Soviet corner (Camilleri, 2009). These critics often objected to what they saw as the idealism
or subjectivism of quantum physics and to the active role attributed to the observer, and
argued against the idea that quantum mechanics should only deal with measurement outcomes
and not with what happens between measurements.
Most notable among these critics was David Bohm. Regarded as a very promising young
physicist in the 1940s, he got into trouble because of his links with communism. The cold war
era was difficult for all US academics with communist sympathies, but especially for quantum
physicists, whose work could potentially be relevant for atomic weapons. In 1951, Bohm was
suspended from his position at Princeton University because of his former links with the
Communist Party, and realizing that there was no future for him in US academia, he left for
Brazil, where he got a position at the University of São Paulo (Freire, 2015, 49).
In 1952, Bohm published an alternative account of quantum physics, which is deterministic
and in which particles have a well-defined position at all times (Bohm, 1952). It is known as a
‘hidden variable’ theory of quantum mechanics in the sense that it adds variables to the
existing theory, which make it deterministic. Bohm presented his proposal as a demonstration
that an alternative theory of quantum mechanics was possible and as a starting point for
reworking the foundations of quantum mechanics, rather than as a finished theory. Bohm’s
approach gained a couple of supporters, notably Louis De Broglie (who had made a similar
proposal already in the 1920s, but had given up on it in the light of criticism he received),
Jean-Pierre Vigier, and for a brief period Mario Bunge; but otherwise it did not receive the
reception Bohm had hoped for (Freire, 2015). Because it did not lead to new predictions,
many working physicists found it irrelevant, and it came to be labeled as philosophy. In the
field of philosophy of physics, it proved to attract enduring attention and is nowadays
regarded as one of the main options for the interpretation of quantum mechanics. However,
Bohm had intended for his theory to be physics, rather than philosophy, and hoped that a
further development of his ideas would lead to new predictions and to progress in physics.
While rethinking the foundations of quantum physics in Brazil, Bohm thus found himself
not only geographically at the margins of the physics community, but also with respect to his
ideas. It has been argued that Bohm’s theory was unrightfully ignored (Cushing 1994, Beller
1999), and that this can be explained through the marginalization of those with links to
communism during the cold war. Against these claims, Myrvold (2003) has argued that
Bohm’s theory did get a response from the physics community, and was met with criticisms
from Einstein, Pauli and Heisenberg. Besides these criticisms on the level of physics, Bohm’s
proposal was also criticized on ideological grounds. Freire recounts how the Belgian physicist
Léon Rosenfeld, who worked with Bohr in Copenhagen and has been called “Bohr’s
bulldog”, did everything in his power to work against Bohm’s interpretation of quantum
mechanics:
4
Rosenfeld mobilized colleagues wherever he could to take up the fight against the causal
interpretation [Bohm’s interpretation]. (...). He pushed Frédéric Joliot-Curie—a Nobel prize
winner and member of the French Communist Party—to oppose French Marxist critics of
complementarity; advised Pauline Yates— Secretary of the “Society for cultural relations
between the peoples of the British Commonwealth and the USSR”—to withdraw her
translation of a paper by Yakov Ilich Frenkel critical of complementarity from Nature; asked
Nature not to publish a paper by Bohm entitled “A causal and continuous interpretation of the
quantum theory;” and advised publishers not to translate one of de Broglie’s books dedicated
to the causal interpretation into English. (Freire, 2015, 37).
Like Bohm, Rosenfeld sympathized with Marxism; but he took himself to be defending the
correct Marxist interpretation of quantum mechanics against a new generation of Marxist
critics – this shows that ideological factors in the debates on quantum mechanics could be
complicated, as also Freire (2015) has pointed out.
2
1.2 The Colston Symposium (1957)
In 1957, Bohm came to Bristol for the Ninth Symposium of the Colston Research Society,
which brought together physicists and philosophers to talk about quantum physics (on this
conference, see Kožnjak, 2018).
3
Feyerabend, who was then appointed in Bristol, was
involved in organizing the conference. Other participants included Rosenfeld, Vigier, Ayer,
and Popper (who could not attend but had his paper read by Feyerabend). Bohm gave an
introduction to his hidden variable theory, which was followed by a talk by Rosenfeld, who
was extremely dismissive about Bohm’s proposal. Rosenfeld’s talk, titled “Misunderstandings
about the foundations of quantum theory”, starts as follows:
Recent criticism of the foundations of quantum theory originates from a number of physical
and epistemological misconceptions. To point out, with painful explicitness, the most serious
of these might be helpful to those whom this criticism seems to have caught unprepared
(Rosenfeld, 1957, 41).
Instead of examining the content of Bohm’s theory, Rosenfeld gave a general criticism of
alternative interpretations of quantum mechanics, arguing against the very notion that there
can be something like an ‘alternative interpretation’: he argues that the interpretation which
can be given to a physical theory is generally unique. Rosenfeld admits that there are
unsolved problems in fundamental physics; he points out that some critics, such as Bohm,
think that a solution will be found through the development of a new theory at the sub-
quantum level, but “Unfortunately for them, all the evidence points with merciless
definiteness in the opposite direction” (Rosenfeld, 1957, 44). It is clear, according to
Rosenfeld, that further progress will be made through an extension of the current theory of
quantum mechanics, rather than through the development of a hidden variable theory such as
Bohm’s.
2
In particular, Rosenfeld regarded Bohr’s notion of complementarity as a dialectical notion, which fits within
the dialectical materialism of Engels. See Jacobsen (2007).
3
The contributions to the conference including the discussions were published as Körner (ed.): Observation and
Interpretation: A Symposium of Philosophers and Physicists (1957). According to the preface, “Dr. Feyerabend
undertook the arduous task of supervising the recording of the discussions from tape-recorder to the printed
page.”
5
Rosenfeld’s talk was not well received: it led to a discussion about the role of speculation in
physics, and even relatively conservative physicists such as Fierz and Pryce, who were
generally not in favor of Bohm’s approach, thought that Rosenfeld was not justified in
excluding its very possibility. Kožnjak (2018) argues that as a result, Bohm came out well:
even if many participants were not convinced of the success of his theory, at least it was
admitted by most of the participants that it was an option which could not be dogmatically
excluded.
4
Feyerabend thus witnessed at the Colston Symposium how an alternative theory of quantum
mechanics was met with a dogmatic dismissal from a leading physicist, which led to a
discussion on the role of speculation and the desirability of alternative approaches in physics.
This event made an impact on Feyerabend: in later publications, he often quoted Rosenfeld’s
response to Bohm as an example of a dogmatic attitude in quantum physics (e.g. Feyerabend
1961a, 89, 94; 1962, 145, 1975).
Feyerabend’s own position at the conference appears ambivalent. During the discussion he
supported the idea that there is room for speculation and for alternative approaches in
quantum physics, but expressed doubts about the adequacy of Bohm’s proposal. In his own
talk, however, Feyerabend argued that, although there are conceptual difficulties with
quantum mechanics, these “can be solved within the present theory” (Feyerabend, 1957, 129).
The difficulty he points out is the problem of measurement. A problematic issue in quantum
mechanics is that in order to connect the wave function which is described by the Schrödinger
equation with measurement outcomes, it seems that there has to be something like a wave
function collapse, but it is unclear how and why this occurs exactly. Feyerabend argues that
the measurement process can be understood in a way which does not require a wave function
collapse: the reason why we observe a definite measurement outcome, rather than a
superposition, lies in the fact that at the macroscopic level, a definite outcome is
indistinguishable from a superposition. Feyerabend concludes that “Apart from leading to the
rejection of part of the current interpretation of QM the result of our analysis can also be used
for showing the inadequacy of various attacks against the theory itself.” (Feyerabend, 1957,
129). It seems that with these inadequate attacks against quantum mechanics, Feyerabend has
among others Bohm in mind (Feyerabend, 1957, 124).
Kuby (forthcoming) argues that after giving this talk, Feyerabend found out that his account
of measurement was in fact close to that of Niels Bohr, and that this was the start of a
reappreciation of Bohr by Feyerabend. However, as we will see, Feyerabend still engaged
critically with Bohr’s ideas in the following years.
After the Colston conference, Feyerabend also became more appreciative of Bohm’s
program. A few months after the conference, and after having spent several years in Brazil
and Israel, Bohm moved to Bristol to take up a position in the physics department. Thus,
Bohm and Feyerabend became colleagues, and regularly spent time discussing physics and
philosophy together while they were both in Bristol (Kožnjak, 2018). In the following years,
Feyerabend supported Bohm in arguing for the need to develop alternatives to the current
theory of quantum mechanics.
4
According to Kožnjak (2018), this meant a turn in the reception of Bohm, whose theory was mostly criticized
and ignored before this conference, and started to get some recognition afterwards; however, it was only in the
1970s and 1980s that Bohm’s theory really gained popularity.
6
1.3 Conservative Elements in Quantum Physics
Before the Colston conference, Feyerabend published a few texts on quantum mechanics,
which are heavily influenced by Popper, and in which it is difficult to find a common line.
5
After the conference, however, Feyerabend’s position becomes more clear. He identifies
certain elements in quantum mechanics as conservative and as an obstacle to progress; in
particular, he objects to the idea that measurement outcomes necessarily have to be
formulated in terms of classical physics. Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle states that
particles do not simultaneously have a well-defined position and momentum; similarly, in
quantum theory, light appears in certain conditions as waves and in other conditions as
particles, but cannot be conceived as waves and as particles simultaneously. From this, one
could conclude that the concepts of position, momentum, particle and wave have a limited
applicability in the quantum domain, and that one should look for new concepts which
describe properties which are well-defined in all circumstances. However, quantum
physicists, including Bohr, Heisenberg and von Weizsäcker, argued that the development of
such new concepts is impossible, if not in principle then at least in practice, and that it is
necessary to use classical concepts to describe quantum phenomena, despite their limitations.
Bohr’s principle of complementarity expresses the idea that there are concepts and modes of
description which are required to describe phenomena, but which cannot be applied
simultaneously.
Feyerabend quotes Bohr saying that “however far the phenomena transcend the scope of
classical physical explanation, the account of all evidence must be expressed in classical
terms”; Feyerabend describes this as a “defeatist attitude”, arguing that Bohr underestimates
our capacity to develop new concepts (Feyerabend, 1958a, 152).
6
Feyerabend’s attitude is
close to Einstein’s, who also argued for the need of developing new concepts to deal with the
problems in quantum mechanics (Fine, 1986). Bohm too argued that the present situation in
fundamental physics required “radically new concepts” (Bohm, 1957, 98). Bohm thought that
his own proposal from 1952 did not go far enough in this respect, as the concepts it used were
still too classical; during the late 1950s and 1960s, Bohm worked on developing new concepts
for quantum physics, based on topological relations (Bohm, 1962).
Feyerabend makes a connection between what he sees as the conceptual conservatism of
quantum mechanics and positivism: Feyerabend criticizes positivists for taking observations
to be stable elements which cannot be doubted or revised, and he similarly criticizes quantum
physicists for taking classical concepts to be unrevisable, despite their limited applicability
(Feyerabend, 1958a). In (1958a), he takes quantum mechanics, and especially Niels Bohr’s
formulation of quantum mechanics, to be the ultimate example of the positivist attitude in
modern science.
Feyerabend finds a further conservative element in Bohr’s correspondence principle,
according to which a number of laws of classical physics are absolutely valid in the quantum
5
These include a short paper on von Neumann’s proof against hidden variables (1956) and a paper on
determinism (1954). There is also an unpublished text which Feyerabend wrote as a student in Vienna in 1948,
titled “The concept of intelligibility in modern physics”; see Kuby (2016).
6
He also quotes von Weizsäcker, who writes that “Every actual experiment we know is described with the help
of classical terms and we do not know how to do it differently.” Feyerabend: “The obvious reply is, of course:
‘Too bad; try again!’” (Feyerabend, 1962a, 155).
7
domain. In (1960a), Feyerabend writes about the way Bohr and Heisenberg have employed
the correspondence principle: “Their main objective was not the construction of a new
physical theory about a world that existed independently of measurement and observation;
their main objective was rather the construction of a logical machinery for the utilisation of
those parts of classical physics which could still be said to lead to correct predictions.”
In several texts, Feyerabend contrasts Bohr’s way of doing science with Einstein’s: whereas
Einstein develops a new theory by making bold new assumptions and inventing new concepts,
Bohr basically builds up a new theory by holding on to the laws and concepts of the old
theory as much as possible, using the correspondence principle to establish classical laws in
the quantum domain, and restricting the validity of classical concepts without replacing them
(Feyerabend, 1965a, 218; and see Oberheim 2016 on Einstein’s influence on Feyerabend).
Feyerabend emphasizes that Bohr’s approach has been fruitful to some degree; however, it
will necessarily lead to stagnation sooner or later: “Only the invention of a new set of ideas
which boldly oppose appearances and common belief, and which attempt to explain both in a
deeper way, can then lead to further progress and to the continuation of a rational argument”
(1958b, 72).
1.4 Interpretations versus Theories
We have seen how both Bohm and Feyerabend argued for rethinking the foundations of
quantum physics and developing new concepts, which would result in a genuinely new theory
of quantum physics. However, the account of quantum physics which Bohm had proposed in
(1952) was framed as an alternative interpretation of the theory of quantum mechanics, rather
than as an alternative theory of quantum mechanics.
This interpretation of quantum mechanics was contrasted with the ‘Copenhagen
interpretation’. The latter term was introduced by Heisenberg (1955), in response to the
emergence of alternative interpretations of quantum mechanics such as Bohm’s (Camilleri,
2009). The ‘Copenhagen interpretation’, according to Heisenberg, was the interpretation for
which there was a broad consensus among quantum physicists.
7
The philosopher of science Norwood Russell Hanson argued against the idea that the issue
was that of different interpretations of the same theory. Hanson argued that one cannot get rid
of the puzzling features of quantum mechanics, such as wave-particle duality and
Heisenberg’s uncertainty relation, through a mere re-interpretation of the theory:
One cannot maintain a quantum-theoretic position and still aspire for the day that the
difficulties of the uncertainty relations will have been overcome. This would be like playing
chess and yet hoping for the day when the difficulties of possessing but one king will have
been overcome. (Hanson, 1958, 149).
To do without duality and the uncertainty relations would mean to do without quantum
mechanics altogether and to develop a completely new theory, rather than merely a different
7
Howard (2004) and Camilleri (2009) have argued that Heisenberg made it seem like there was more consensus
than there actually was; in fact, there was a large variety in the ways in which physicists interpreted quantum
mechanics. Howard (2004) argues that Feyerabend was one of the philosophers of science who contributed to the
establishment of the myth of the Copenhagen interpretation. This is not right – on the contrary, Feyerabend was
well aware of the diversity of interpretations among quantum physicists, and in (1962, 147) remarks that “Quite
obviously, the fictitious unity conveyed by the term ‘Copenhagen interpretation’ must be given up.”
8
interpretation. And to develop such a completely new theory to account for quantum
phenomena would not be an easy task. Like Feyerabend, Hanson argues that what we observe
is not independent of the theories we work with. Hanson’s Patterns of Discovery (1958) is
mainly known for his account of the theory-ladenness of observation: our theories influence
what we observe and what kind of experiments we can do. This means that the development
of a new theory goes together with the development of a new way of observing and
experimenting: to develop a theory means to find a ‘pattern of explanation’ within which
observations fit and make sense. The simultaneous changes in theoretical framework and
observation which Hanson describes are close to the “paradigm shifts” which Kuhn described
a few years later in his Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) – indeed, Kuhn
acknowledged an indebtedness to Hanson in the introduction of this book.
Hanson’s argument, that quantum mechanics cannot be modified without being changed
completely, was meant as an argument against alternative accounts of quantum mechanics
such as Bohm’s. However, Bohm was in fact in agreement with the idea that an alternative
account of quantum mechanics would require fundamental change. Bohm again and again
emphasized that his (1952) paper was merely a starting point and a more thorough rethinking
of the foundations of quantum physics was needed. According to Pinch (1977), what Bohm in
fact had offered in his (1952) paper was a new interpretation of quantum mechanics plus an
outline of a research program that goes beyond mere interpretation.
In Causality and Chance in Modern Physics (1957), Bohm argues that there is currently a
crisis in fundamental physics: current theories predict infinite values for certain physical
properties, and the so-called elementary particles are falling apart into ever more particles
(Bohm, 1957, 121-22). He notes that “modern physicists feel that the present crisis in physics
will be resolved by revisiting the details of the general kinds of probabilistic theories that are
now current”. Bohm, however, thinks that this is not enough; he argues that revolutionary
changes in the theory and concepts of quantum mechanics are needed.
Feyerabend also accepted the idea that in order to deal with puzzling features of quantum
mechanics such as uncertainty and complementarity, a mere re-interpretation of the theory
was not enough: “The issue of the foundations of the quantum theory can therefore be solved
only by the construction of a new theory (...) it cannot be solved by alternative interpretations
of the present theory” (Feyerabend, 1962, 114).
In the early 1960s, Feyerabend increasingly distanced himself from his earlier claim that the
puzzling features of quantum mechanics were the result of a positivist attitude: it was not
positivist philosophy but physical reasons which led physicists to develop quantum mechanics
the way they did (1962, 121, 162). In particular, Feyerabend argues that quantum uncertainty
is a direct result of a few postulates, which are supported by experiment and therefore
generally accepted as scientific facts, namely the quantum postulate, the duality of light and
matter, and conservation of energy and momentum (1962; 1964). This means that doing away
with uncertainty would require going against established experimental results. Feyerabend
thus agrees with Hanson that developing an alternative theory of quantum physics would not
be an easy task. However, he emphasizes that none of this shows that alternative theories are
impossible or cannot be expected to be successful. He makes a comparison with objections
made against Copernicus:
9
...any attempt to give a realistic account of the behaviour of the elementary particles is bound
to be inconsistent with some very highly confirmed theories. Any such attempt therefore
amounts to introducing unsupported conjectures in the face of fact and well-supported
physical laws. This is the main objection which is used today against the theories of Bohm,
Vigier, de Broglie and others. It is similar to the objections which were raised, at the time of
Galileo, against the idea that Copernicus should be understood realistically. (Feyerabend,
1964).
Feyerabend argues that also von Neumann’s proof against hidden variables does not show that
an alternative, deterministic theory of quantum mechanics is impossible. Von Neumann had
shown in 1932 that given the postulates of quantum mechanics, one can prove that quantum
mechanics cannot be expanded with hidden variables to make it deterministic. His proof was
frequently used against hidden variable theories of quantum mechanics, including Bohm’s –
however, it was not easy to see where Bohm’s theory went wrong, and for many years there
was a confusion about whether and how exactly it could escape von Neumann’s proof, and
whether von Neumann’s proof was generally valid (Pinch, 1977). In (1962, 167), Feyerabend
argues that since the proof uses the postulates of quantum mechanics as premises, it can be
circumvented by coming up with an alternative theory of quantum mechanics which does not
share these postulates.
8
Thus, Hanson, Bohm and Feyerabend were in fact in agreement that developing a
satisfactory theory of quantum physics without features such as uncertainty and
complementarity would require something akin to a paradigm shift – it would require the
development of new concepts as well as a reinterpretation of experimental results. The main
issue on which they differed regarded the feasibility and desirability of developing such a new
theory.
In “Five Cautions for the Copenhagen Interpretation’s Critics” (1959a), Hanson warns
critics of the Copenhagen interpretation, “particularly Bohm and Feyerabend”, that currently,
giving up on the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics is not an option, because
no satisfactory alternative exists at the moment. As he states in (1959b), “There is as yet no
working alternative to the Copenhagen interpretation. Ask your nearest synchrotron operator.”
He admits that quantum theory in its current form is not entirely without problems, but despite
these problems, quantum mechanics is a theory which is effective, physicists can work with it,
and this is not something to give up lightly: “physicists, being reasonable men, will not
abandon the imperfect tools in their hands for the ingenious and optimistic expectations in
philosophers’ minds” (Hanson, 1959a).
In a response to Hanson, Feyerabend argues that Bohm’s proposal is a viable option and that
it should not be shoved aside just because it had not yet been developed in full detail:
Being well versed in the history of the sciences and in the considerations which play a role in
the process of discovery, Professor Hanson surely knows that elaborate theories are preceded
8
Feyerabend had struggled with Von Neumann’s proof for many years, and wavered on its validity. Already in
(1954), Feyerabend argued that von Neumann’s proof would not apply to a fundamentally new theory. In (1956),
he claims to give a general refutation of the proof. However, Feyerabend came to believe that his refutation had
been based on a mistake, and in (1957) he states that von Neumann’s proof is valid and rules out hidden variable
theories. Then, in (1962a, 127, 166), he credits Bohm with having refuted von Neumann’s proof.
Dieks (2017) points out that von Neumann himself never claimed to have shown that hidden variable theories are
impossible: von Neumann pointed out that his proof relies on the formalism of quantum mechanics, so if you are
prepared to change the formalism, you may circumvent the proof.
10
by more or less general considerations which sometimes are inconsistent with the prevalent
philosophy. But should Copernicus have abandoned the idea of Aristarch just because it was
not yet worked out in as great detail as was the geocentric idea? By no means; he perceived,
and justly so, that his idea was a possible one, and he had no reason to assume that the finished
theory would be worse than Ptolemy’s system. (Feyerabend, 1961b).
In (1962, 165), Feyerabend argues that developing alternatives takes time, and therefore it
cannot be expected that someone will come up with a fully developed alternative theory of
quantum physics at once. Feyerabend furthermore points out that “the point of view of Bohm
and Vigier has already been developed in much greater detail than commonly supposed by
most of the opponents” and therefore cannot be disregarded as an alternative (Feyerabend,
1962, 160f).
Whereas Hanson emphasizes that one should not give up a working theory without strong
motivation, Feyerabend implores physicists to be open to alternatives. He stresses that “future
research need not (and should not) be intimidated by the restrictions which some high priests
of complementarity want to impose upon it” (1962, 103) and that “Now, as ever, the future
development of physics is a completely open matter” (1962, 116).
1.5 Why alternatives?
We have seen that Feyerabend argued for the possibility and desirability of developing
alternative accounts of quantum physics. What exactly was his motivation for this? As we
have seen in section 1.3, Feyerabend objected to the principle of complementarity and the
correspondence principle because he saw these as ways to hold on to the concepts and laws of
classical mechanics instead of developing a new theory on new foundations. But are there any
intrinsic reasons why such a new theory would be preferable?
Feyerabend never seems to have been very concerned about determinism: in (1954), he even
argued that determinism is a philosophical prejudice.
9
He considered Bohr’s answer to the
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox to be satisfactory (1958b, 1962), and also the measurement
problem was not a central issue for Feyerabend: as we saw in section 1.2, in 1957 he argued
that measurement in quantum mechanics could be dealt with without requiring a new theory,
and although in later publications he did regard measurement as problematic, it never seems
to have been his main concern.
Feyerabend does often emphasize the need for a realist account of quantum mechanics,
especially in his earlier publications. This means that quantum physicists should not restrict
themselves to giving predictions of measurement outcomes, but should aim to provide an
account of what happens between measurements. This also means that theories should be
formulated in terms of concepts which are universally applicable, and not only applicable
under specific experimental conditions (1958b). Feyerabend ultimately defended his
preference for realism on the basis of methodological arguments: a realist approach motivates
the search for theories and explanations, since it motivates attempts to go beyond observation
and measurement outcomes and to entertain hypotheses about unobserved processes, and in
this way it leads to progress.
9
Probably under influence of Popper, he defined determinism in terms of predictability. With this definition,
Bohm’s account does not come out as deterministic and even classical mechanics is not deterministic.
11
In the early 1960s, Feyerabend developed further arguments for the development of
alternative theories of quantum mechanics; again, these arguments were methodological.
Feyerabend argued that developing alternatives to existing theories is in general crucial for
the scientific enterprise. He argues that developing alternatives to an existing theory can
uncover problems with the theory which would otherwise have remained undiscovered. This
means that if you don’t consider alternatives to an established theory, you eliminate
potentially refuting facts (Feyerabend, 1963). His main example is Brownian motion, which is
the random motion of particles in a fluid, which can be observed through a microscope
(Feyerabend, 1993, 262). It was first described by Robert Brown in 1827, but was not given
any particular significance until Einstein showed in 1905 that it is possible to account for
Brownian motion through the kinetic theory of heat, and on this basis it can be shown that
Brownian motion involves a violation of the second law of thermodynamics on small scales.
Thus, with the help of the kinetic theory (alternative theory), the observable phenomenon of
Brownian motion was reinterpreted and used to refute a result from thermodynamics
(established theory).
Interestingly, Feyerabend has attributed his arguments for the importance of developing
alternative theories in order to test established theories to David Bohm, along with Karl
Popper, and specifically attributes the example of Brownian motion to Bohm (Feyerabend,
1993, 262). In (1965b), Feyerabend writes:
My general outlook derives from the work of David Bohm and K. R. Popper and from my
discussions with both. The idea that a theoretical pluralism should be the basis of knowledge
can be found both in the dialectical philosophy of Bohm and in Popper’s critical rationalism.
However, it seems to me that it is only within the framework of the latter that it can be
developed without undue restrictions. (Feyerabend, 1965b, 153).
There is a relation between Feyerabend’s pluralism and Popper’s falsificationism: one should
use all possible means to relentlessly test theories, even those which are already established,
and this includes trying to develop alternative accounts. In later editions of Against Method,
however, Feyerabend writes that Bohm helped him to go beyond Popper’s falsificationism:
“That falsification is not a solution became very clear in discussions with David Bohm who
gave a Hegelian account of the relation between theories, their evidence, and their successors”
(Feyerabend, 1993, 262).
Several authors have argued that although Bohm was very influential for Feyerabend, this
influence started quite late, in the late 1960s (Collodel, 2016) or early 1970s (Preston, 2016).
This is based on the fact that in a review of a book by Bohm which Feyerabend published in
(1960), Feyerabend was critical about what he described as a Hegelian structure of reality
adopted by Bohm, which includes the idea that nature is infinitely complex, that all theories
have a restricted domain of application and that no scientific result can ever be taken as more
than approximately valid. It may be true that these ideas only started to play a role for
Feyerabend later on; but the argument that developing alternatives to a theory is needed in
order to test this theory also works independently of this broader metaphysical picture. This is
an argument which Feyerabend developed in discussions with Bohm, in the context of
discussions on the foundations of quantum mechanics.
The argument that a theory can be tested by developing alternatives to it can also be found
in a paper by Bohm and Bub from 1966. Here, Bohm and Bub argue that “there is a very
12
important methodological justification for the consideration of hidden variable theories, even
those which are not necessarily seriously regarded as ‘right’ ones”: as long as we stay within
the framework of quantum mechanics, the basic postulates of quantum mechanics are unlikely
to be exposed to tests, because only those certain questions can be meaningfully asked and
only those experiments can be considered which do not go outside this framework. By
developing hidden variable theories, it may become possible to test the basic postulates of
quantum mechanics experimentally, and possibly falsify them (Bohm and Bub, 1966).
In (1963, 80), Feyerabend proposes a “positive methodology” based on pluralism in the
sciences. Feyerabend puts the need for developing alternatives in strong terms: he argues that
if no alternatives to a theory are considered, the success of the theory will be entirely due to
the exclusion of alternatives, and the theory is therefore not much better than a myth. This
would imply that the defense of the Copenhagen interpretation as the only possible account of
quantum mechanics has the potential of reducing quantum mechanics to a myth. Feyerabend
draws this conclusion in a letter to Kuhn from 1961, in which he comments on a draft of
Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions:
Your insistence upon faithfulness to one and only one paradigm is bound to result in the
elimination of otherwise very important tests and it is bound in this way to reduce the
empirical content of the paradigm you want to be accepted. It may well be – and Bohm and
Vigier are definitely of this opinion – that the situation is the same in the present quantum
theory. The ‘orthodox’ refuse considering alternatives and their argument is that the present
point of view has not yet encountered anomalies which would necessitate reconsideration of it
in its entirety. Bohm points out that the limitations of the present point of view will become
evident only if one has first introduced an alternative and shown that it is preferable. Hence if
the absence of limitations is taken as a reason for not considering alternatives, then trouble
will never be discovered, simply because it could be discovered only with the help of
alternatives. This, then, would make the present quantum theory a wonderful metaphysics.
(Feyerabend, in Hoyningen-Huene, 1995, 365).
The arguments which Feyerabend gives for the development of alternative theories of
quantum physics, such as the one proposed by Bohm, seem to be essentially methodological:
in all areas of science, developing alternatives is essential for testing established theories, and
this also holds for quantum mechanics. However, Feyerabend’s arguments still seem to be
motivated by the idea that there is something wrong with quantum mechanics specifically,
and that quantum physicists are particularly dogmatic in excluding alternatives to their
theories.
Thus, to a considerable degree, Feyerabend developed his arguments for pluralism in
science in the context of debates on quantum mechanics, in dialogue with Bohm and
motivated by what he perceived as the dogmatism of quantum physicists and their negative
reactions to Bohm’s alternative account of quantum mechanics. Feyerabend then applied his
arguments for pluralism to science as a whole; the fact that he developed these arguments
within this specific context may be a reason to re-evaluate how far this pluralism can be
extended to other scientific disciplines.
2. Anarchism
13
In the mid-1960s, Feyerabend changed his views on quantum mechanics; as he recalled later,
this was due to a discussion he had with Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker in 1965. As he recalls
in his autobiography:
In the late sixties or early seventies I gave a public talk in Hamburg, with von Weizsäcker in
the chair. In the seminar that followed I repeated my reasons for basing research on sets of
conflicting theories. Both confirmation and content, I said, depend on a confrontation with
alternatives (hidden variable theories in the case of quantum mechanics). Von Weizsäcker
responded with a detailed account of the problems that had arisen; he showed how these
problems had been attacked and solved and to what extent the new predictions had been
confirmed. Compared with this rich pattern of facts, principles, explanations, frustrations, new
explanations, analogies, predictions, etc., etc., my plea seemed thin and insubstantial. It was
well enough argued, but the arguments occurred in outer space, as it were; they had no
connection with scientific practice. For the first time I felt, I did not merely think about, the
poverty of abstract philosophical reasoning. (Feyerabend, 1995, 141).
He brought up the same anecdote in an interview he gave in 1994, two weeks before his
death:
You see, I was once [in 1965] in Hamburg with Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker, who invited
me to give a talk there. At that time I was still a methodology freak. At that time I believed
that it made sense to argue for certain procedures in science. And my arguments were
excellent. But von Weizsäcker gave a historical account of the rise of quantum theory and this
was much richer and more rewarding and I realized that what I was talking about was just a
dream. Just as Ceaucescu wanted to have order in his country, so he tore down the little houses
and built up his concrete monsters. When von Weizsäcker started describing the development
of quantum theory he was just pointing out the little houses, because there were so many little
steps being made. Niels Bohr said: ‘When you do research you cannot be tied down by any
rule, not even the rule of noncontradiction. One must have complete freedom’. So, as he
explained that to me, I recognized that my arguments were excellent but that excellent
arguments don’t count when you want to deal with something which is as rich as nature, or
other human beings. (Feyerabend, in Jung 2000, 162).
The anecdote also appears in the 1993 edition of Against Method, where he adds: “Thus
Professor von Weizsäcker has prime responsibility for my change to ‘anarchism’ – though he
was not at all pleased when I told him so in 1977” (Feyerabend, 1993, 262).
Feyerabend’s anarchism, which he first expressed in his essay ‘Against Method: Outline of
an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge’ (1970) and a few years later in a book format in
Against Method (1975), has been interpreted in different ways, but most commentators agree
that the point is not that science has no methodology at all: rather than rejecting rules and
standards altogether, Feyerabend emphasizes that all rules and standards have their limits.
There are no universal methodological rules: for each methodological principle in science
there are circumstances in which it may be broken. “...there is only one principle that can be
defended under all circumstances and in all stages of human development. It is the principle:
anything goes” (Feyerabend, 1975, 28). Secondly, Feyerabend emphasizes that methodology
should not be imposed on science: scientists do not need ‘help’ from philosophers of science
who prescribe them a methodology. There is still normativity in Against Method: scientists
should not be too strict in their methodologies and should be open to breaking the rules, and
14
Feyerabend still seems to think that considering alternatives is generally fruitful, but this is
not made into a hard methodological rule.
10
Feyerabend’s move towards anarchism has often been understood as a break with Popper’s
critical rationalism (see e.g. Preston 1997, 79, Collodel 2016). Feyerabend had been strongly
influenced by Popper, who had been his supervisor at the London School of Economics in
1952-53. Feyerabend’s earlier pluralism can be understood as Popperian in so far as it
includes a strong normative emphasis on testing: Feyerabend emphasized that developing
alternatives to established theories is essential for testing these theories. But during the 1960s
Feyerabend gradually broke with Popper. Collodel (2016) describes the personal factors
which played a role in this break: it involved hurt feelings and resentment on both sides, and
Feyerabend’s philosophical disagreements with Popper were often fueled by personal factors.
However, Collodel also notes that the break cannot be fully explained through personal
factors, and argues that partly through his studies in the history of science, Feyerabend
gradually became convinced that actual science was too complex to satisfy Popper’s general
methodological rules. Also Preston (1977, p. 178) writes that Feyerabend’s move towards
anarchism took place “probably as the result of studies in the history of science.” Oberheim
(2006) also notes that during the late 1960s and 1970s, Feyerabend became increasingly
critical of Popper and attributed increasing significance to the history of science, but argues
against a discontinuous break, emphasizing the continuities in Feyerabend’s thought.
However, when Feyerabend recalls the development of his own thought correctly, it was a
discussion with Von Weizsäcker about the history of quantum mechanics which pushed him
towards anarchism. How to understand this claim?
I argue that Feyerabend’s move to anarchism can indeed be understood as an outcome of his
reflections on quantum physics. But although Feyerabend presents his discussion with von
Weizsäcker as a turning point in his thought, it was actually part of a development which
already started earlier, and the change in Feyerabend’s thought was thus more gradual.
11
From
the early 1960s, Feyerabend’s criticisms of quantum physics gradually became milder.
Whereas Feyerabend argued in (1958a) that quantum mechanics was based on an ill-founded
positivism, in the early 1960s, he argued that this type of criticism could not be maintained,
and that there were good physical arguments for why quantum mechanics had developed the
way it did. Therefore, criticizing quantum mechanics on purely philosophical grounds does
not suffice. In (1962), Feyerabend thus defended orthodox quantum mechanics against what
he saw as superficial philosophical criticisms. However, he then went on to argue that
however strong the physical arguments for the present theory of quantum mechanics were,
they could not exclude the possibility of developing an alternative theory of quantum physics
on new foundations. His main target here was Popper, who, according to Feyerabend, gave
unjustified criticisms of quantum mechanics from a purely philosophical perspective. Thus,
Feyerabend’s break with Popper was directly connected to the development of his ideas on
quantum physics.
The change in Feyerabend’s thought on quantum mechanics can be seen most clearly in his
writings on Niels Bohr. Already from the early 1950s, Feyerabend had been particularly
interested in Bohr’s account of quantum mechanics: he thought that Bohr gave the strongest
10
On ways to understand Feyerabend’s anarchism, see Shaw (2017).
11
See also Kuby (forthcoming), who argues that Feyerabend’s reappreciation of Bohr already started in 1957.
15
account of what could count as ‘orthodox’ quantum mechanics, and for this reason chose
Bohr as the focus of his criticism. Whereas in his earlier critiques of positivism (e.g. 1958a),
Feyerabend took Bohr as a core example of a positivist scientist, and regarded Bohr’s account
of quantum mechanics as the product of a misguided positivist philosophy, from the early
1960s Feyerabend distanced himself from these views. Until the mid-1960s, Feyerabend still
objected to what he saw as conservative elements in Bohr’s thought; in particular, he regarded
Bohr’s correspondence principle as a means to construct a new theory by holding on to an
older theory as much as possible, rather than developing new foundations. He thought that
quantum physicists, including Bohr, had not looked hard enough for alternative accounts and
new foundations for quantum physics.
However, in “On a Recent Critique of Complementarity” (published in two parts in 1968
and 1969),
12
Feyerabend seems to take back all his former criticisms of Bohr and even praises
Bohr as a creative physicist, and the correspondence principle as a creative methodological
step. A footnote at the beginning of the paper states: “This paper is a belated aftereffect of a
discussion with Professor C. F. von Weizsaecker in autumn 1965.” The main aim of the paper
is to defend Bohr against criticisms by Popper, who had criticized quantum mechanics for
being positivistic, and objected to the fact that quantum mechanics only offers predictions of
measurement outcomes and no description of the actual processes that take place at the
quantum level.
13
Feyerabend argues that Popper’s criticism is naive and uninformed about the
history of quantum mechanics. Popper does not take account of the fact that Bohr tried to give
an account of atomic processes which goes beyond measurement, but was refuted at every
attempt:
Every paper of Bohr’s emphasizes that so far an instrument of prediction is all one can have
and that this shortcoming is due to the absence of unrefuted hypotheses about the nature of
atomic processes. (...) It is true that Bohr eventually arrived at the position that “the whole
purpose of the formalism of the quantum theory is to derive expectations for observations
obtained under given experimental conditions” – but this was the result of a series of
refutations and discoveries which seemed to show that considerations of “nature” (and the
word here does not indicate essentialistic aberrations!) had been removed very far indeed.
Now it is of course Professor Popper's privilege to disregard such refutations and to continue
believing in the correctness of his own microphilosophy. But it is somewhat unjust to describe
those who took the refutations seriously as philosophical dogmatists who never realized that
there was an issue, and it is also somewhat optimistic, under such circumstances, to think that
one can teach them a lesson. (Feyerabend, 1969, 91-92).
We can now see how Feyerabend’s engagement with quantum physics pushed him in the
direction of anarchism. First, steps in the development of a scientific theory which seem
methodologically objectionable, such as Bohr’s employment of the correspondence principle
and Bohr’s violation of the methodological principle that scientists should try to go beyond
12
Collodel (2016) mentions that Feyerabend already finished a version of the paper in 1967, which was rejected
for publication.
13
In particular, Popper argued that certain puzzling features of quantum physics, including uncertainty and
complementarity, rest on a misinterpretation of the concept of probability. To deal with these issues he proposed
a propensity interpretation of probability. Feyerabend argues that although Popper attacks Bohr’s views on
quantum mechanics, Popper’s account of probability is actually very similar or even equal to that of Bohr, and
argues that this account of probability in itself does not suffice to do away with the puzzling features of quantum
mechanics.
16
mere observation and give a realist account of phenomena, can also be seen as creative
methodological steps. This supports the idea that there are no universal methodological rules,
and that flexibility in methodology is beneficial for scientific progress. On the very first page
of the first chapter of Against Method, Feyerabend praises Bohr for his creative methodology.
Feyerabend writes that for any methodological rule in science, there are circumstances in
which it is advisable to violate it, and adds in a footnote:
One of the few thinkers to understand this feature of the development of knowledge was Niels
Bohr: “…he would never try to outline any finished picture, but would patiently go through all
the phases of the development of a problem, starting from some apparent paradox, and
gradually leading to its elucidation. In fact, he never regarded achieved results in any other
light than as starting points for further exploration. In speculating about the prospects of some
line of investigation, he would dismiss the usual consideration of simplicity, elegance or even
consistency...” (Feyerabend, 1975, 24).
14
Ironically, the quote is from Léon Rosenfeld, Bohm’s most aggressive and dogmatic
opponent.
Secondly, Feyerabend gradually came to believe that his earlier criticisms of Bohr and of
quantum mechanics in general had been ill-founded. He already recognized in (1962) that one
cannot simply criticize quantum mechanics on philosophical grounds without engaging with
the physical details; now he recognized that, in light of the complex historical development of
quantum mechanics, it is too easy to blame physicists for not having looked hard enough for
alternative theories with which some of the puzzling features of quantum mechanics could
have been avoided.
The fact that Feyerabend’s increasing awareness of the complex history of quantum
mechanics made him retract some of his earlier normative pronouncements points to a
‘historical turn’ in Feyerabend’s thought. Feyerabend is usually counted, along with Kuhn and
Lakatos, among the philosophers responsible for a historical turn in philosophy of science, as
they gave serious attention to history (Bird 2008, Nickles 2017). The relevance Feyerabend
attributed to the history of science can be seen in particular from the central role played by his
studies of Galileo in Against Method. However, Kuby (forthcoming) argues that Feyerabend
was initially critical of this ‘historical turn’, as he thought that philosophy of science should
essentially be normative, and it was in the context of quantum physics that Feyerabend first
became aware of the pertinence of history. Also this development in Feyerabend’s thought
can thus be linked to his work on quantum physics.
We can still ask how these ‘anarchist’ views relate to Feyerabend’s earlier arguments for
pluralism in quantum physics. Feyerabend always remained a proponent of pluralism in the
sciences, and one could say that whereas in the 1960s he mainly argued for a plurality of
theories and theoretical approaches, with Against Method he extended his pluralism to
methodology, arguing for many scientific methodologies rather than one. So one would
expect that he would still be in favor of alternative accounts of quantum physics. But he no
longer seems to argue that there is something specifically wrong with quantum physics which
would make the development of alternatives particularly urgent in this case. If there is
anything wrong with current quantum physics, it is that the younger generation of physicists
14
See also (1993, 129): “I favor Niels Bohr’s ‘this is not crazy enough’.”
17
tends to defend quantum mechanics with ill-founded positivist arguments, and that Bohr’s
originals ideas are often misunderstood: “many contemporary physicists of the younger
generation take complementarity for granted without examining it and perhaps even without
understanding it” (Feyerabend, 1969, 103). Feyerabend argues that the remedy for this is to go
back to Bohr, and see exactly how Bohr has been led to his idea of complementarity.
The question whether Feyerabend still thinks that quantum physicists should try to develop
alternatives to the existing theory of quantum physics is answered in the abstract of his
(1968/69) paper:
Considering that [Bohr’s] views are more detailed, better adapted to the facts of the
microdomain than any existing alternative it follows that fundamental discussion must first
return to them. Their uniqueness is not asserted, however. Here the author still maintains that a
hundred shabby flowers are preferable to a single blossom, however exquisite. But a hundred
shabby flowers plus an exquisite blossom are more desirable still. (Feyerabend, 1968).
This indicates that while developing alternative theories of quantum physics is still
worthwhile, it would be better to return to Bohr’s original account of quantum mechanics and
start from there than to start from completely new foundations. This is a break with
Feyerabend’s previous writings on quantum physics, in which he emphasized that progress in
quantum physics may be made by developing new foundations.
However, it seems that Feyerabend did not fully give up on his support for Bohm: he ends
the paper by stating that “the first step in our attempt to achieve progress in microphysics will
have to be a return to Bohr”, and adds in a footnote: “This first step has been made by Bohr,
Vigier, and others who are taking into account the features which Popper, Bunge, and others
neglect” (Feyerabend, 1969). It seems that this is a typo and should have been “BOHM,
Vigier, and others”. This would indicate that he now thought of Bohm’s work as involving a
return to Bohr, rather than as an alternative based on altogether new foundations.
15
It is important to note that this paper on Bohr was Feyerabend’s last major publication on
the foundations of quantum mechanics. He does discuss Bohr’s views in some of his later
writings, but after the late 1960s, Feyerabend no longer seems to have had the ambition to
contribute to the field of foundations of quantum physics. After having worked on the
foundations of quantum mechanics for many years, Feyerabend no longer felt he could
contribute anything to the field, as he no longer thought that methodological criticism of
physics was fruitful. In essence, it was exactly this development which led to Against Method;
the end of Feyerabend’s career as a philosopher of physics thus meant the start of his big
success in general philosophy of science.
Conclusions
Feyerabend’s writings on quantum physics reveal how he developed his notions of pluralism
and anarchism in the context of debates on quantum mechanics, especially concerning the
15
It has to be noted that by the late 1960s, Bohm had abandoned the interpretation of quantum mechanics he had
proposed in 1952, and was working on a different approach; he only returned to his original theory much later
(Freire, 2015). Moreover, Bohm’s attitude towards Bohr was a complicated one: Bohm was critical of some
aspects of Bohr’s account of quantum mechanics but highly appreciative of others.
18
feasibility and desirability of alternative approaches to quantum mechanics. His earlier
writings (until the mid-1960s) on the role of alternative theories in science were motivated by
what he saw as the dogmatism of the quantum physics community, and called for openness to
alternative accounts of quantum mechanics, especially the one developed by Bohm. However,
Feyerabend’s criticisms of quantum physics gradually became milder. Initially, he objected to
certain puzzling features of quantum mechanics, such as the fact that it is not possible to
describe what happens between measurement and the use of complementary pairs of concepts
(e.g. in wave-particle duality), and he motivated these objections through methodological
concerns. But as he learned more about the physical details and historical complexities of
quantum mechanics, he gradually became more modest in his criticisms, and in the end
withdrew them altogether. This was crucial in his move towards anarchism, which includes
the idea that methodology cannot be imposed on science. With some simplification, the
ultimate outcome of Feyerabend’s extensive writings on quantum physics may be formulated
as follows: if even a theory as puzzling as quantum mechanics is methodologically
unobjectionable, then anything goes.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Jamie Shaw, Daniel Kuby, Oliver Passon, Gregor Schiemann and an
anonymous referee for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.
References
Beller, M. (1999). Quantum Dialogue: The Making of a Revolution. University of Chicago
Press.
Bird, A. (2008). The Historical Turn in the Philosophy of Science. In Stathis Psillos and
Martin Curd (eds.), Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Science, pp. 67-77.
Routledge.
Bohm, D. (1952). A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of ‘Hidden’
Variables, I and II. Physical Review, 85(2): 166–193.
Bohm, D. (1957). Causality and Chance in Modern Physics. London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Bohm, D. (1962). Classical and Non-Classical Concepts in the Quantum Theory. An Answer
to Heisenberg's Physics and Philosophy. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,
12(48), 265-280
Bohm, D. and Bub, J. (1966). A Proposed Solution of the Measurement Problem in Quantum
Mechanics by a Hidden Variable Theory. Rev. Mod. Phys. 38(3), 435-469.
Camilleri, K. (2009). Constructing the Myth of the Copenhagen Interpretation. Perspectives
on Science, 17(1), pp. 26-57
Collodel, M. (2016). Was Feyerabend a Popperian? Studies in History and Philosophy of
Science, 57: 27-56
Cushing, J. T. (1994). Quantum Mechanics: Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen
Hegemony. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
19
Dieks, D. (2017). Von Neumann’s Impossibility Proof: Mathematics in the Service of
Rhetorics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 60, 136-148.
Feyerabend, P. (1954). Determinism and Quantum Mechanics. In Feyerabend (2015), 25-45.
Original: Wiener Zeitschrift für Philosophie, Psychologie, Pädagogiek, vol. 5., no. 2,
1954, pp. 89-111.
Feyerabend, P. (1956). A Remark on Von Neumann's Proof. In Feyerabend (2015), 46-48.
Original: Zeitschrift für Physik, 145(4), 421-23.
Feyerabend, P. (1957). On the Quantum-theory of Measurement. In Körner, S (ed.),
Observation and Interpretation: a Symposium of Philosophers and Physicists.
London: Butterworths.
Feyerabend, P. (1958a). An attempt at a realistic interpretation of experience. Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society, 58, 143-170.
Feyerabend, P. (1958b). Complementarity. In Feyerabend (2015), 49-73. Original: in
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 32, 75-104.
Feyerabend, P. (1960). Professor Bohm's philosophy of nature. British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science.
Feyerabend, P. (1961a). Niels Bohr's interpretation of the quantum theory. In Feyerabend
(2015), 74-94. Original: in Feigl and Maxwell (ed), Current issues in the philosophy of
science, 371-90. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Feyerabend, P. (1961b). Rejoinder to Hanson. In Feyerabend (2015), 95-98. Original: in Feigl
and Maxwell (ed), Current issues in the philosophy of science, 398-400. New York:
Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Feyerabend, P. (1962). Problems of microphysics. In Feyerabend (2015), 99-187. Original in
Colodny (ed): Frontiers of science and philosophy, 189-283. Pittsburgh: University of
Pittsburgh Press.
Feyerabend, P. (1963). How to be a good empiricist: a plea for tolerance in matters
epistemological. In Baumrin (ed.), Philosophy of science: The Delaware Seminar,
volume 2, pp. 3-39. Interscience Publishers: New York.
Feyerabend, P. (1964). Realism and instrumentalism: comments on the logic of factual
support. In Mario Bunge (ed.): The Critical Approach to Science and Philosophy: In
Honor of Karl R. Popper, pp. 280-308. The Free Press of Glencoe: London and New
York.
Feyerabend, P. (1965a). Peculiarity and change in physical knowledge. In Feyerabend (2015),
211-218. Original: in Physikalische Blätter, 21(5), 197-203.
Feyerabend, P. (1965b). Problems of Empiricism. In Robert G. Colodny (ed.): Beyond the
Edge of Certainty: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy, University of
Pittsburgh Series in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 2, pp. 145-260. Prentice-Hall:
Englewood Cliffs (NJ).
Feyerabend, P. (1968). On a recent critique of complementarity: Part I. Philosophy of Science
35: 309-331.
Feyerabend, P. (1969). On a recent critique of complementarity: Part II. Philosophy of Science
36: 82-105.
Feyerabend, P. (1970). Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge.
Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 4, 17-130.
20
Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge.
London: New Left Books.
Feyerabend, P. (1993). Against Method (revised edition). London, New York: Verso.
Feyerabend, P. (1995). Killing Time: The Autobiography of Paul Feyerabend. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Feyerabend, P. (2015). Philosophical Papers 4: Physics and Philosophy (ed. S. Gattei and J.
Agassi). Cambridge University Press.
Fine, A. (1986). The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism and the Quantum Theory. University of
Chicago Press.
Freire Jr., O. (2015). The Quantum Dissidents: Rebuilding the Foundations of Quantum
Mechanics (1950–1990). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Hanson, N. R. (1972 [1958]). Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hanson, N. R. (1959a). Five Cautions for the Copenhagen Interpretation’s Critics. Philosophy
of Science 26(4): 325–337.
Hanson, N. R. (1959b). Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Theory. American Journal of
Physics 27(1), 1–15.
Heisenberg, W. (1955). The development of the interpretation of the quantum theory. In W.
Pauli (Ed.), Niels Bohr and the Development of Physics: Essays Dedicated to Niels
Bohr on the Occasion of his Seventieth Birthday, pp. 12–29. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Howard, D. (2004). Who invented the Copenhagen Interpretation? A Study in Mythology.
Philosophy of Science, 71(5).
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1995). Two Letters by Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on a Draft
of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Studies in History and Philosophy of
Science 26(3): 353-387.
Jacobsen, A. S. (2007). Léon Rosenfeld's Marxist defense of complementarity. Historical
Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences, 37, 3-34
Jammer (1974). The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics: The Interpretations of Quantum
Mechanics in Historical Perspective. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Jung, J. (2000). Paul K. Feyerabend: Last Interview. In John Preston, Gonzalo Munevar, &
David Lamb (ed.), The Worst Enemy of Science? Essays in Memory of Paul
Feyerabend, pp. 159-168. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Körner, S. (ed.) (1957). Observation and Interpretation: A Symposium of Philosophers and
Physicists. London: Butterworths Scientific Publications.
Kožnjak, B. (2018). The Missing History of Bohm's Hidden Variables Theory: The Ninth
Symposium of the Colston Research Society, Bristol, 1957. Studies in History and
Philosophy of Modern Physics 62:85-97.
Kuby, D. (2016). Feyerabend's ‘The concept of intelligibility in modern physics’ (1948).
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 57:57–63.
Kuby, D. (forthcoming). Feyerabend’s Reevaluation of Scientific Practice: Quantum
Mechanics, Realism and Niels Bohr. In K. Bschir and J. Shaw (ed.), Interpreting
Feyerabend: Critical Essays. Cambridge University Press.
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press.
Myrvold, W. (2003). On some early objections to Bohm's theory. International Studies In The
Philosophy Of Science, 17(1).
21
Nickles, T. (2017). Historicist Theories of Scientific Rationality. In E. N. Zalta (ed), The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition),
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/rationality-historicist/.
Oberheim, E. (2006). Feyerabend's Philosophy. Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter.
Oberheim, E. (2016). Rediscovering Einstein's Legacy: How Einstein Anticipates Kuhn and
Feyerabend on the Nature of Science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science,
57, 17-26
Pinch, T. (1977). What Does a Proof Do if it Does Not Prove? A study of the social
conditions and the metaphysical divisions leading to David Bohm and John von
Neumann failing to communicate in quantum physics. In E. Mendelsohn, P. Weingart,
and R. Whitly (ed.), The Social Production of Scientific Knowledge, pp. 171-215.
Reidel, Dordrecht.
Preston, J. (1997). Feyerabend: Philosophy, Science and Society. Polity Press.
Preston, J. (2016). Paul Feyerabend. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016
Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/feyerabend/
Rosenfeld, L. (1957). Misunderstandings about the foundations of quantum theory. In Körner,
S. (ed.) (1957) Observation and Interpretation: a Symposium of Philosophers and
Physicists, pp. 41-45. London: Butterworths.
Shaw, J. (2017). Was Feyerabend an Anarchist? The structure(s) of ‘anything goes’. Studies
in History and Philosophy of Science, 64:11-21.