Of all legal dicta, perhaps none is quite so hackneyed as that which states that hard cases make bad law. Each time that a court issues an opinion on a controversial issue, the ‘hard cases’ adage is trotted out. However, to the seasoned scholar of the law, such a position, while indeed well-travelled, reflects a somewhat strange conception of legal logic. First of all, cases are generally decided
... [Show full abstract] upon by courts, institutions empowered not to make law, but rather to dispose of specific cases through applying law previously enacted elsewhere. Second, courts are staffed by judges or juries - essentially, norm interpreters - empowered by law to issue an authoritative interpretation of the precise meaning of the contested norms in the context at hand. Such an interpretation is generally incontestable by any other organ (though it may be subject to appeal to a higher court, which will have to dispose of the same basic problems) and therefore, since the court has merely applied the pre-existing law according to its prescribed rules of interpretation, its findings are neither good nor bad. They merely represent an in concreto application of the law as it stands. The preceding doubtless amounts to something of an oversimplification. While courts should, in principle, refrain from ‘making’ law, rather interpreting and applying it, and while such interpretation and application - if undertaken in accordance with formal rules - should certainly not result in the making of ‘bad’ law, we should remind ourselves that the dictum treats hard cases, that is, cases that are necessarily difficult in terms of their content. As Oliver Wendell Holmes noted, ‘great cases are called great, not by reason of their importance … but because of some accident of immediate overwhelming interest which appeals to the feelings and distorts the judgment’. So too with hard cases. Glanville Williams’ position in this regard was that cases ‘in which the moral indignation of the judge is aroused frequently make bad law’. Thus, the norm interpreter finds himself confronted with a difficult factual situation - a factual situation that does not correspond exactly and unambiguously to a provision of the settled, written law - which precludes his dispassionate disposal of the case.