ArticlePDF Available

Abstract and Figures

Proving a violation of law is costly. Because of the cost, minor violations of law often go unproven and thus unpunished. To illustrate, almost everyone drives a little faster than the speed limit without getting a ticket. The failure to enforce the law against minor infractions is justifiable from a cost-benefit perspective. The cost of proving a minor violation—for example, a driver broke the speed limit by one mile per hour—outstrips the benefit. But it has the downside of underdeterrence. People drive a little too fast, pollute a little too much, and so on. This paper explores how insincere rules, meaning rules that misstate lawmakers’ preferences, might reduce proof costs and improve enforcement. To demonstrate the argument, suppose lawmakers want drivers to travel no more than 55 mph. A sincere speed limit of 55 mph may cause drivers to go 65 mph, while an insincere speed limit of 45 mph may cause drivers to drop down to, say, 60 mph—closer to lawmakers’ ideal. Insincere rules work by creating insincere evidence. In the driving example, the insincere rule is akin to adding 10 mph to the reading on every radar gun. We distinguish insincere rules from familiar concepts like over-inclusive rules, prophylactic rules, and proxy crimes. We connect insincere rules to burdens of persuasion, showing how they offset each other. Finally, we consider the normative implications of insincere rules for trials, truth, and law enforcement. The logic of insincerity is not confined to speed limits. The conditions necessary for insincerity to work pervade the legal system.
Content may be subject to copyright.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1115
VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW
VOLUME 105 OCTOBER 2019 NUMBER 6
ARTICLE
INSINCERE EVIDENCE
Michael D. Gilbert* and Sean P. Sullivan**
Proving a violation of law is costly. Because of the cost, minor
violations of law often go unproven and thus unpunished. To illustrate,
almost everyone drives a little faster than the speed limit, but rarely are
we ticketed for doing so. Failure to enforce the law against minor
infractions is justifiable from a cost-benefit perspective. The cost of
proving a minor violation—for example, that a driver broke the speed
limit by one mile per hour—outstrips the benefit. But systemic non-
enforcement has the downside of underdeterrence. People drive a little
too fast, pollute a little too much, and so on.
This Article explores how insincere rules, meaning rules that misstate
lawmakers’ preferences, might reduce proof costs and improve
enforcement. To demonstrate the argument, suppose lawmakers want
drivers to travel no more than 55 mph. A sincere speed limit of 55 mph
may cause drivers to go 65 mph, while an insincere speed limit of 45
mph may cause drivers to drop down to, say, 60 mph—closer to
lawmakers’ ideal. Insincere rules work by creating insincere evidence.
* Professor of Law, University of Virginia.
** Associate Professor of Law, University of Iowa. For helpful comments, we thank Matt
Adler, Omri Ben-Shahar, Darryl Brown, Tony Casey, Frank Easterbrook, Ofer Eldar, Lee
Fennell, Kim Ferzan, Michael Frakes, Paul Gowder, William Hubbard, Rich Hynes, Ben
Johnson, Richard McAdams, Robert Miller, Greg Mitchell, Mark Osiel, Todd Pettys, J.J.
Prescott, Fred Schauer, Bobbie Spellman, conference participants at the 2018 ComplianceNet
meeting, the 2019 American Law and Economics Association meeting, and the 2019 Political
Economy and Public Law Conference, and finally workshop participants at Duke University,
the University of Chicago, the University of Michigan, and the University of Iowa.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1116 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
In the driving example, the reduction in proof costs achieved by an
insincere rule is akin to adding an artificial 10 mph to the reading of
every radar gun.
The logic of insincere evidence is not confined to speed limits. The
conditions necessary for insincerity to work pervade the legal system.
We distinguish insincere evidence from familiar concepts like over-
inclusive rules, prophylactic rules, and proxy crimes. We connect
insincere evidence to burdens of persuasion, showing how it can offset
the effects of higher burdens. Finally, we consider the normative
implications of insincere evidence for trials, truth, and law
enforcement.
I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................ 1116
II. LAW IN BOOKS, LAW IN ACTION ..................................................... 1122
III. ENFORCEMENT AND INSINCERITY .................................................. 1126
A. The Costs of Proof .................................................................. 1127
B. The Benefits of Insincerity ...................................................... 1136
C. Interpretation and Implications .............................................. 1138
D. Generalizations and Applications .......................................... 1141
E. The Limits of Insincere Evidence ............................................ 1145
F. Summary ................................................................................. 1151
IV. DISTINGUISHING INSINCERE EVIDENCE ......................................... 1152
A. Gilbert on Insincere Rules ...................................................... 1152
B. Conduct and Decision Rules ................................................... 1153
C. Over-Inclusive Rules............................................................... 1155
D. Prophylactic Rules ................................................................. 1156
E. Pathological Laws .................................................................. 1158
F. Proxy Crimes .......................................................................... 1161
V. NORMATIVE IMPLICATIONS: COSTS, TRUTH, AND TRIALS ............... 1162
A. Are There Better Ways to Reduce Costs? ............................... 1163
B. Is This an Affront to Truth? .................................................... 1164
C. Is Cost Reduction Enough? .................................................... 1168
VI. CONCLUSION ................................................................................. 1169
TECHNICAL APPENDIX ......................................................................... 1172
I. INTRODUCTION
Law aims to deter bad behaviors, but the mere enactment of a statute
or regulation is not enough. Laws must be enforced to have effect. Alas,
enforcement is expensive. Sometimes enforcement is so expensive that
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1117
society would be better off without it. A modern controversy illustrates.
Some states want transgender people to use the bathroom that matches
their biological sex.
1
But the cost of enforcing such a law—inspectors in
every stall?
2
—would exceed any benefit (or purported benefit) that the
law would produce.
The bathroom laws are controversial, but laws on other topics like
corruption, pollution, theft, and discrimination are not. In a perfect world,
these laws would fully deter the targeted behavior. Enforcement costs
frustrate that ideal. Can we lower enforcement costs? Scholars and
policymakers have spent decades on this question. They have explored
solutions like ankle bracelets, red light cameras, extreme fines, and other
incentives.
3
This Article analyzes a different method for lowering enforcement
costs, one that has received little attention but that we believe may be
widespread in practice: the use of insincere rules to generate insincere
evidence.
4
To explain, a sincere rule mandates the rule-maker’s preferred
behavior while an insincere rule mandates something else. If the state
wants drivers to stay at or below 55 miles per hour, a sincere rule would
set the speed limit at 55 mph, while an insincere rule might set the speed
limit at, say, 45 mph.
1
See, e.g., Eric Lichtblau & Richard Fausset, U.S. Warns North Carolina that Transgender
Bill Violates Civil Rights Laws, N.Y. Times (May 4, 2016), https://www.nytimes.com/-
2016/05/05/us/north-carolina-transgender-bathroom-bill.html [https://perma.cc/6TCK-8N3-
H] (describing the law in North Carolina).
2
Samantha Michaels, We Asked Cops How They Plan to Enforce North Carolina’s Bath-
room Law, Mother Jones (Apr. 7, 2016), https://www.motherjones.com/politics/2016/04/-
north-carolina-lgbt-bathrooms-hb2-enforcement/ [https://perma.cc/3JPM-9BR4] (describing
the challenges of enforcement and quoting a police spokesperson: “We’re not checking birth
certificates. We just don’t have the police power to be able to do that in bathrooms.”).
3
See generally Gary S. Becker, Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach, 76 J. Pol.
Econ. 169, 174 (1968) (“It would be cheaper to achieve any given level of activity . . . the
more highly developed the state of the arts, as determined by technologies like fingerprinting,
wire-tapping, computer control, and lie-detecting.”); id. at 190–99 (providing a germinal
analysis of fines); James Byrne & Gary Marx, Technological Innovations in Crime Prevention
and Policing: A Review of the Research on Implementation and Impact, 20 Cahiers
Politiestudies 17 (2011) (reviewing technological innovations in law enforcement); Bruno S.
Frey, Punishment – and Beyond, 5 Contemp. Econ. 90 (2011) (discussing the limits of
punishment as a tool for crime prevention and considering alternatives).
4
One of us introduced insincere rules in a separate paper. See Michael D. Gilbert, Insincere
Rules, 101 Va. L. Rev. 2185 (2015). The current Article explores a different mechanism
through which insincere rules can improve compliance. We distinguish the two projects in
Section IV.A, infra.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1118 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
Insincere rules lower enforcement costs by making violations of law
easier to prove. Enforcing laws requires many steps. At a minimum, the
state must (1) observe a bad act, (2) identify and apprehend the
perpetrator, (3) prove that the perpetrator committed the bad act, and (4)
enjoin or punish the perpetrator. Many papers focus on the first, second,
and fourth steps in this chain.
5
We focus on the third step. Proving the
commission of a wrong is not easy. The state must gather evidence,
prepare witnesses and exhibits, try the case, and ultimately convince a
judge or jury of the wrong beyond the appropriate burden of persuasion,
to say nothing of appeals and retrials. Every step of this process involves
costs. Insincere rules make the process easier—make enforcement
cheaper—by turning hard cases into easy cases.
6
Below we develop the
argument with rigor. Here we illustrate with an example.
Suppose the state wants drivers to go 55 mph. The state sets the speed
limit at 55 mph, meaning the rule is sincere. If a driver gets caught going
85, the case is easy. Yes, the state burns resources monitoring the road,
stopping the driver, and administering a fine.
7
But on the question of guilt
the case is open-and-shut: he sped. Now what if a driver gets caught going
56 mph? This case is hard. The driver might fight the ticket. He might
argue that the officer made a mistake by failing to hold the radar still. He
might argue that the radar measures with error on sharp curves like the
one he traversed. Even if the driver is lying, proving it takes work. The
officer would likely need to testify, and the state may have to present
evidence on the trustworthiness of the radar. The state might lose despite
this effort. Deterring someone from going 56 mph is not worth the trouble.
By the same logic, deterring someone from going up to 65 mph may not
5
See, e.g., A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell, The Theory of Public Enforcement of
Law, in 1 Handbook of Law & Economics 403, 405 (A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell
eds., 2007) (“The theoretical core of our analysis addresses the following basic questions:
Should the form of the sanction imposed on a liable party be a fine, an imprisonment term, or
a combination of the two? Should the rule of liability be strict or fault-based? If violators are
caught only with a probability, how should the level of the sanction be adjusted? How much
of society’s resources should be devoted to apprehending violators?”).
6
Cf. Charles L. Barzun, Rules of Weight, 83 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1957 (2008) (proposing
a distinct but conceptually related mechanism in which legal rules might be used to impose
specific fact-finding weights on various items of evidence).
7
In the economics literature on enforcement, fines are usually treated as costless transfers
of wealth from perpetrators to the state. In reality, fines must have some social cost, however
small, because they must be administered. See Polinsky & Shavell, supra note 5, at 430–31
(analyzing enforcement when fines are socially costly); see also Richard A. Posner, An
Economic Theory of the Criminal Law, 85 Colum. L. Rev. 1193, 1207–08 (1985) (noting
other frictions that complicate the calibration and administration of penal fines).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1119
be worth the trouble. Savvy drivers realize this and see that they can drive
as fast as 65 mph with impunity.
Now rerun the example with one change: an insincere rule. Instead of
setting the speed limit at 55 mph, suppose that the state makes it 45 mph.
The case of the driver going 85 mph remains easy. But the case of the
driver going 65 mph is now easy as well. Even after accounting for
potential errors by the officer and radar, judges and jurors probably would
conclude that a driver clocked at 65 mph in a 45-mph zone had broken
the law. Foreseeing that proof will be easy, the officer will ticket the
driver going 65 mph. And foreseeing the ticket, the driver will slow down.
He may slow to 60 mph—closer to the speed that lawmakers wanted in
the first place. By making hard cases easy, the insincere rule improves
behavior.
Our title captures the mechanism by which insincerity lowers the cost
of proof. An insincere rule can be viewed as giving the state a block of
free” or “artificial” evidence to help prove a violation of law. Consider
the driving example. From a proof-cost perspective, adopting an
insincerely low speed limit is like handing the officer a rigged radar gun.
It is easy to see that a radar gun which secretly adds an extra 10 mph onto
every measurement would make it easier to prove a speeding violation.
Every arguable 5-mph infraction would suddenly appear to be an
unambiguous 15-mph infraction. Insincere rules have a similar effect.
Reducing the speed limit from the sincere 55 mph level to the insincere
45 mph level does not change the speed that a 60-mph driver was actually
going. It simply turns what had been a 5-mph infraction into what is now
a 15-mph infraction.
Insincere rules offer a mechanism by which lawmakers—legislators,
agencies, judges—can lower enforcement costs and induce better
behavior in regulated parties. The mechanism is very general.
8
Insincere
rules do not require deception; even if everyone knows a rule is insincere,
it can still lower proof costs. Insincere rules do not require irrationality
among regulated parties; they work even when everyone is strongly
rational. Insincere rules do not require objective evidentiary uncertainty;
they can improve behavior in the face of perceived uncertainty as well.
Insincere rules can benefit the state whether its objective is deterrence,
corrective justice, or any other end connected to the behavior of regulated
parties.
8
See infra Section III.D.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1120 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
Here is a sampling of the kinds of laws to which our analysis applies:
blood alcohol content while operating a vehicle; emissions of carbon,
lead, or other pollutants; the length, weight, and number of fish caught in
protected waters; noise limits at airports and nightclubs; the amounts (e.g.,
milligrams) of particular ingredients allowed in each dose of medicine;
distances between guns and schools, protesters and abortion clinics,
smokers and public buildings. These examples canvass precise laws: for
example, laws prohibiting the possession of more than “[o]ne ounce of
useable marijuana.”
9
But insincere rules can improve enforcement of
vague laws too. For example, laws requiring pharmaceutical companies
to “[b]e maintained in a clean and orderly condition,”
10
or prohibiting
mergers “the effect of [which] may be to substantially lessen
competition . . . .”
11
Given the benefits and general applicability of insincere rules, we
suspect that this mechanism, while new to scholars, is not new to
lawmakers. Scholars have long observed gaps between the law in books
and the law in action.
12
Laws mandate one thing while regulated parties
do another. Scholars bemoan these gaps,
13
but perhaps their anguish is
misplaced. Perhaps some of these gaps reflect strategic and beneficial
uses of insincere rules, with lawmakers intentionally getting the law in
books “wrong” in order to get the law in action “right.”
Beyond identifying the potential benefits of insincere evidence, our
analysis uncovers an overlooked connection between the substance of law
and its processes. Speeding tickets are typically civil offenses. Thus, the
state’s burden of persuasion would usually be preponderance of the
evidence. What would happen if the state’s burden were to prove guilt
9
Wash. Rev. Code § 69.50.360(3)(a) (2015).
10
21 C.F.R. § 205.50(a)(4) (2019).
11
Clayton Antitrust Act, ch. 323, § 7, 38 Stat. 730, 731–32 (1914) (current version at 15
U.S.C. § 18 (2012)).
12
Roscoe Pound, Law in Books and Law in Action, 44 Am. L. Rev. 12, 34 (1910). For
perspective on the large literature on “gap studies,” see Jon B. Gould & Scott Barclay, Mind
the Gap: The Place of Gap Studies in Sociolegal Scholarship, 8 Ann. Rev. L. & Soc. Sci. 323
(2012).
13
For example, Max Rheinstein has called pervasive differences between law and practice
in family law “inan[e].” Max Rheinstein, Marriage Stability, Divorce, and the Law 351–53
(1972). Richard Abel states that early gap studies “were frequently directed by the belief that
the gap, once revealed, could and should be eliminated.” Richard L. Abel, Law Books and
Books About Law, 26 Stan. L. Rev. 175, 188 (1973) (reviewing Max Rheinstein, Marriage
Stability, Divorce, and the Law (1972)). Roscoe Pound blamed gaps on “our machinery of
justice” that is “too slow, too cumbersome and too expensive” and argued that lawyers must
“make the law in action conform to the law in the books.” Pound, supra note 12, at 35–36.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1121
beyond a reasonable doubt? Given a speed limit of 55 mph, the driver
clocked at 85 mph would probably still present an easy case and the driver
clocked at 56 mph would still present a hard case. But the higher burden
could be an obstacle to the state securing a verdict for many speeds in
between. Lowering the speed limit—adopting an insincere rule—would
make some of these cases easier. Under the preponderance of the evidence
standard, a speed limit of 50 mph might be enough to make a driver
clocked at 60 mph an easy case. For proof beyond a reasonable doubt, it
might take more insincerity—a speed limit of 45 mph—to make the driver
clocked at 60 mph an easy case.
To generalize, insincere evidence can offset the cost of meeting higher
burdens of persuasion. The more stringent the burden, the more insincere
the law must be. This suggests that rule-makers may adopt the strictest
rules in criminal law—which is exactly what some scholars perceive. In
a classic paper, Professor Bill Stuntz argued that criminal liability has
broadened, leading to a “world in which the law on the books makes
everyone a felon.”
14
Our work relates to Stuntz’s. We generalize,
improve, and challenge his analysis.
15
As this discussion suggests, insincere evidence raises difficult
normative questions. It can unwind judicial protections, especially in
criminal law. It appears to require dishonesty by the state. (Actually,
lawmakers do not have to lie or deceive for insincerity to work this way,
but a wedge does open between laws and preferred behavior.) Insincere
evidence also raises practical problems. It may, for example,
unintentionally distort the behavior of scrupulously law-abiding citizens
and unsophisticated enforcement agents. For reasons like these, we do not
believe that insincere evidence strategies would work or should be
adopted in every setting. Our objective is not to champion or vilify
insincere evidence but to study and explain it.
The remainder of this Article proceeds as follows. Part I provides
background on enforcement and other literatures related to our work. Part
II develops our theory. Part III relates our theory to other concepts such
as over-inclusive rules, prophylactic rules, proxy crimes, and acoustic
separation. Part IV considers normative implications, placing our theory
in the context of evidence law, enforcement, deterrence, and truth. We
14
William J. Stuntz, The Pathological Politics of Criminal Law, 100 Mich. L. Rev. 505, 511
(2001).
15
See infra Section IV.E.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1122 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
conclude with brief remarks on implications for other areas of law. A
technical appendix appears at the end.
II. LAW IN BOOKS, LAW IN ACTION
This Part briefly reviews the literature on enforcement. The main point
is that one can improve enforcement by raising penalties (the focus of
much scholarship) or lowering proof costs (the focus of relatively little
scholarship). One can lower proof costs by loosening the burden of
persuasion. Or—this is where our intervention begins—one can lower
proof costs by tightening rules. Readers familiar with the enforcement
literature can safely skip ahead.
Cyclists ride without helmets. Stores sell alcohol to minors. Truckers
drive longer shifts than legally allowed. City ordinances prohibit smoking
at bus stops, but smokers linger nearby. A quick glance at just about any
slice of life reveals a pervasive and important phenomenon: law mandates
one behavior but yields another. Sometimes the slippage is minor, as in
our bus stop example. Other times the stakes are high. Twenty years after
the Clean Water Act, 10,000 dischargers still lacked permits.
16
Around
the world, governments fail systematically to protect the rights enshrined
in their national constitutions.
17
The legal scholar Roscoe Pound captured
this regularity with a memorable phrase: there is a gap between the “law
in books” and the “law in action.”
18
16
See Daniel A. Farber, Taking Slippage Seriously: Noncompliance and Creative
Compliance in Environmental Law, 23 Harv. Envtl. L. Rev. 297, 304 (1999) (citing Robert
W. Adler et al., The Clean Water Act: 20 Years Later 151 (1993)).
17
See generally David S. Law & Mila Versteeg, Sham Constitutions, 101 Calif. L. Rev.
863, 863 (2013) (documenting the “global prevalence and severity of constitutional
noncompliance over the last three decades”). Perhaps constitutions get ignored because
political actors do not pay a price for violating law. See Frederick Schauer, The Political Risks
(If Any) of Breaking the Law, 4 J. Legal Analysis 83 (2012).
18
Pound, supra note 12; see also Eugen Ehrlich, Fundamental Principles of the Sociology
of Law, at xxvii (Walter L. Moll trans., 1936) (distinguishing legal propositions from “living”
law); Jason S. Johnston, Bayesian Fact-Finding and Efficiency: Toward an Economic Theory
of Liability Under Uncertainty, 61 S. Cal. L. Rev. 137, 139 (1987) (distinguishing “nominal”
and “administered” rules); Karl N. Llewellyn, A Realistic Jurisprudence—The Next Step, 30
Colum. L. Rev. 431, 439 n.9 (1930) (distinguishing “paper” rules from real or “working”
rules).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1123
Why do gaps arise? Prior scholarship has answers.
19
Consider the
Holmesian “bad man” deliberating over whether to break the law.
20
This
person is not deterred by any abstract force of nature or internal
commitment to justice. Instead, he weighs the expected benefits of
breaking the law (profits, revenge, the pleasure of listening to illegally-
downloaded music) against the expected costs (potential fines,
imprisonment, social opprobrium). If the benefits exceed the costs, the
bad man breaks the law. The law in books is whatever the statutes or
regulations say. The law in action is what the bad man is actually deterred
from doing.
21
The state can close the gap between the law in books and the law in
action by increasing the expected cost of breaking the law.
22
It has many
levers for doing so. It can raise the probability that a transgressor will be
caught in the act.
23
More cops usually means less crime. Alternatively,
the state can adopt heavier sanctions.
24
Want to reduce littering in parks?
Replace small fines with imprisonment.
19
For overviews of the literature on the economic theory of law enforcement, see Nuno
Garoupa, The Theory of Optimal Law Enforcement, 11 J. Econ. Survs. 267, 267–68 (1997);
A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell, The Economic Theory of Public Enforcement of Law,
38 J. Econ. Lit. 45 (2000) [hereinafter Polinsky & Shavell, Economic Theory of Public
Enforcement of Law]; and A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell, Public Enforcement of
Law, in 5 The New Palgrave: Dictionary of Economics 38 (Steven N. Durlauf & Lawrence E.
Blume eds., 2d ed. 2008). This literature presents the law and economics perspective on the
“gap.” For a philosophical perspective, see, for example, Heidi M. Hurd, Moral Combat 185
202 (1999), and Larry Alexander, The Gap, 14 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 695 (1991).
20
See Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457, 459 (1897)
(“You can see very plainly that a bad man has as much reason as a good one for wishing to
avoid an encounter with the public force . . . . A man who cares nothing for an ethical rule
which is believed and practised by his neighbors is likely nevertheless to care a good deal to
avoid being made to pay money, and will want to keep out of jail if he can.”).
21
Id. (“If you want to know the law and nothing else, you must look at it as a bad man . . . .”).
22
See Becker, supra note 3, at 179–85.
23
See id. at 174.
24
See id. at 179–80. Relatedly, the government can affect perceptions of the sanction. See
Bert I. Huang, Shallow Signals, 126 Harv. L. Rev. 2227, 2253–57 (2013) (analyzing the failure
to publicize when one actor has permission to engage in behavior that is forbidden for other
actors). The state can also effectively raise sanctions by increasing the costs to defendants of
defending themselves. Cf. Maximilian A. Bulinski & J.J. Prescott, Online Case Resolution
Systems: Enhancing Access, Fairness, Accuracy, and Efficiency, 21 Mich. J. Race & L. 205,
208–10 (2016) (proposing solutions to the high cost of accessing the justice system); J.J.
Prescott, Improving Access to Justice in State Courts with Platform Technology, 70 Vand. L.
Rev. 1993 (2017) (discussing the sources of costs in the criminal justice system and evaluating
online platform technology as a structural reform to remedy the problem).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1124 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
Professor Gary Becker developed the latter idea, arguing that a
combination of fewer police and severe sanctions will efficiently deter
bad men from breaking the law.
25
To illustrate, suppose that drivers will
stop at red lights only if the expected cost of running the light is $100 or
more. How can the state set the expected cost at $100? It can install a red-
light camera at every intersection, making the probability of getting
caught 100 percent, and set the fine at $100. Or it can secretly install one
red-light camera in every hundred intersections, making the probability
of getting caught one percent, and set the fine at $10,000.
26
The expected
cost of running the light is the same (1% × $10,000 = $100), but the latter
approach economizes on red-light cameras, saving the state money.
27
Becker’s prescription works in theory but faces challenges in practice.
Publicity and morals place an upper bound on sanctions. “Tough on
crime” makes for good politics. “Tough on trivial regulatory infractions”
does not. A street vendor in New York received $2,250 in fines for using
a table that was an inch too tall and two inches too close to a store
entrance.
28
A student was fined $675,000 for illegally downloading 30
songs.
29
Run-of-the-mill traffic violations in California cost $500.
30
Sanctions like these generate negative attention and political pressure,
making it hard for politicians to follow Becker’s severe-sanction advice.
Even if they could, severe sanctions might not deliver on the promise.
Becker’s approach fails when law-breakers exhibit certain cognitive
biases. Some people might treat the very low probability of punishment
25
See Becker, supra note 3, at 183–84.
26
For simplicity, we assume drivers cannot tell which intersections have cameras. Thus,
they assume the probability of getting caught at any given intersection equals one percent.
27
According to a 2001 study, a single red-light camera costs at least $50,000. Robert P.
Maccubbin, Barbara L. Staples & Arthur E. Salwin, Automated Enforcement of Traffic
Signals: A Literature Review, at ES-1 (2001), https://rosap.ntl.bts.gov/view/dot/3822
[https://perma.cc/8XTF-UW6B].
28
Sally Goldenberg, Street Vendor Selling Cellphone Cases Fined 2G Fine for Inches, N.Y.
Post (Oct. 8, 2012, 4:00 AM), http://nypost.com/2012/10/08/street-vendor-selling-cellphone-
cases-fined-2g-fine-for-inches/ [http://perma.cc/E5Q4-4Z45].
29
Denise Lavoie, Joel Tenenbaum Boston University Student Download Fine: Court Won’t
Reduce $675,000 Penalty, HuffPost College (May 21, 2012, 11:10 AM),
[http://perma.cc/45RG-8KLB].
30
Editorial, Relief from the High Cost of Traffic Tickets — For Some Californians, at Least,
L.A. Times, (Aug. 11, 2017), https://www.latimes.com/opinion/editorials/la-ed-fairer-traffic-
ticket-20170811-story.html [https://perma.cc/XD7J-9M8N] (“The state’s exorbitant traffic
fines are tough for anyone to pay, so laden as they are with add-on fees that inflate a $100
ticket to nearly $500 in the end.”).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1125
for breaking the law as a zero probability of punishment.
31
The threat of
a sanction, even a severe one, will not deter these people. Others might
heavily discount future punishments relative to current benefits.
32
For
them, today’s pleasure is a greater concern than next month’s pain. Again,
severe penalties will not deter these people, as long as there is a big
enough lag between the benefit of breaking the law and the punishment.
If the state cannot enact severe enough sanctions, or if those sanctions
fail to achieve deterrence, then another option remains: increase the odds
of detection. The state can detect violations more accurately and more
quickly by hiring more enforcement officers (cops, forest rangers, air-
quality regulators), purchasing more surveillance equipment (drones,
listening devices, testing kits), and paying more informants (street
criminals, whistleblowers, foreign agents). These investments increase
the probability of a law breaker getting caught. But this approach faces a
political and moral objection. All of these investments are costly. The
resources may be needed elsewhere. Spending another $1,000 on schools
may do more good for society than spending another $1,000 on red-light
cameras.
Given this tradeoff, slippage against the law in the books is inevitable.
In a sense, it is even desirable. As Professors Mitchell Polinsky and
Steven Shavell put it, “[o]ptimal enforcement tends to be characterized
by some degree of underdeterrence . . . because allowing some
underdeterrence conserves enforcement resources.”
33
In other words,
31
On the underweighting on low probability risks, see, for example, Greg Barron & Ido
Erev, Small Feedback-Based Decisions and Their Limited Correspondence to Description-
Based Decisions, 16 J. Behav. Decision Making 215, 223–24 (2003); Ralph Hertwig, Greg
Barron, Elke U. Weber & Ido Erev, Decisions from Experience and the Effect of Rare Events
in Risky Choice, 15 Psychol. Sci. 534, 537 (2004); and Dov Zohar & Ido Erev, On the
Difficulty of Promoting Workers’ Safety Behaviour: Overcoming the Underweighting of
Routine Risks, 7 Int’l J. Risk Assessment & Mgmt. 122, 125–26 (2007).
32
For critical reviews of models related to present-bias, see Shane Frederick, George
Loewenstein & Ted O’Donoghue, Time Discounting and Time Preference: A Critical Review,
40 J. Econ. Lit. 351 (2002); and Ariel Rubinstein, “Economics and Psychology”? The Case of
Hyperbolic Discounting, 44 Int’l Econ. Rev. 1207 (2003). For recent empirical work on this
topic, see Jess Benhabib, Alberto Bisin & Andrew Schotter, Present-Bias, Quasi-hyperbolic
Discounting, and Fixed Costs, 69 Games & Econ. Behav. 205 (2010).
33
Polinsky & Shavell, Economic Theory of Public Enforcement of Law, supra note 19, at
70. “Optimal” enforcement means social welfare-maximizing enforcement. The dominant
strand in the enforcement literature assumes that the state maximizes social welfare. See, e.g.,
Becker, supra note 3, at 207; Polinsky & Shavell, Economic Theory of Public Enforcement of
Law, supra note 19, at 49. A second line, growing from public choice theory, examines
enforcement when the state is self-interested. See, e.g., David Friedman, Why Not Hang Them
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1126 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
society is better off with some lawbreaking—but with money for roads
and schools—than with no lawbreaking but no money for other needs.
Of course, if enforcement were costless there would be no gap between
the law in the books and the law in action. Gaps only arise because the
costs of enforcing the law sometimes exceed the benefits. No one contests
that enforcement is costly.
34
But what if enforcement costs could be
reduced? The state could elicit better behavior and still have money for
schools and roads.
Policymakers have long sought to lower enforcement costs. Their ideas
have included technological innovations like red-light cameras, ankle
bracelets, and smoke stack monitors.
35
These innovations help, but
enforcement is still costly. In the following pages we describe a different
strategy with general applicability for reducing enforcement costs. The
strategy we consider does not arise out of technical innovation but instead
out of legal innovation regarding the content of law.
III. ENFORCEMENT AND INSINCERITY
This Part develops our theory. We begin by pinpointing an
underappreciated source of enforcement costs: a violation of law must be
proved before a penalty can be imposed. Like the costs of police, the costs
of proof lead to underenforcement of laws. We show how insincere rules
can reduce proof costs. Lawmakers can achieve better compliance by
misrepresenting the conditions under which a wrong has been committed.
In short, hard cases can be turned into easy cases. We discuss when this
All: The Virtues of Inefficient Punishment, 107 J. Pol. Econ. S259, S262 (1999); Nuno
Garoupa & Daniel Klerman, Optimal Law Enforcement with a Rent-Seeking Government, 4
Am. L. & Econ. Rev. 116, 116–17 (2002). In both cases, enforcement costs can limit
enforcement. Sometimes non-enforcement today can lead to deteriorating behavior tomorrow.
See Omri Ben-Shahar, The Erosion of Rights by Past Breach, 1 Am. L. & Econ. Rev. 190
(1999). This temporal dynamic complicates the cost-benefit analysis, but the same
fundamental tradeoff remains.
34
Cf. Douglass C. North, Nobel Prize Lecture: Economic Performance Through Time (Dec.
9, 1993), https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/economic-sciences/1993/north/lecture/ [https://-
perma.cc/AJ7S-QNWL] (“Only under the conditions of costless bargaining will the actors
reach the solution that maximizes aggregate income regardless of the institutional
arrangements. When it is costly to transact then institutions matter. And it is costly to
transact.”).
35
See generally Byrne & Marx, supra note 3, at 25–28 (examining a wide range of new
technological innovations with applications in the areas of crime prevention generally and
crime control by police).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1127
mechanism works or fails, and we identify important implications for
burdens of persuasion.
A. The Costs of Proof
The ideas we develop have broad application, as we explain below.
36
To keep things as clear as possible, though, we begin by focusing on the
simple example raised in the Introduction. To repeat the setup, suppose
that lawmakers have decided drivers should travel no faster than 55 mph
on a particular stretch of highway. This speed strikes the optimal balance
of convenience, safety, and other factors. How might lawmakers go about
enacting and enforcing the speed limit?
A natural option would be to enact a 55 mph speed limit and deploy
cops to watch for speeding vehicles. Of course, there are many other
details to consider. How many police should be assigned to monitor this
highway? How severe should the punishment for speeding be? Others
have explored these questions and we will not discuss them.
37
We assume
that the state has already optimized these levers as best it can.
38
Our focus is on the proof process. Even when a violation of the speed
limit is committed and detected, it is not certain that a penalty will be
imposed. The driver can always dispute a ticket. And if the driver disputes
the ticket, the state cannot impose a penalty without first proving in court
that a violation has occurred.
Much goes into proving a violation of law, even in this simple setting.
Prosecutors, judges, clerks, and possibly jurors need to devote time and
resources to the case. The ticketing officer needs to take the stand to
testify. Time that these actors spend on traffic cases is time not spent on
other, more serious cases. Assuming the officer relied on something more
than subjective observation, details will need to be provided about how
the driver’s speed was measured. Was it measured by the officer’s
speedometer while pacing the driver down a length of road?
39
By a hand-
36
See infra Section III.D.
37
See supra note 19 (citing several good overviews of the existing literature).
38
For completeness, we could also assume that the state will re-optimize these levels to
account for any changes to the setup we introduce in the following pages. The point is that we
are abstracting from these standard enforcement considerations.
39
See David Brown, Fight Your Speeding Ticket: Determining Your Speed, Nolo, https://-
www.nolo.com/legal-encyclopedia/free-books/beat-ticket-book/chapter6-1.html [https://per-
ma.cc/6PT9-CDW4] (last visited May 14, 2019) (describing different forms of speed detection
and commenting on their comparative accuracies).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1128 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
held radar or laser gun?
40
By aerial surveillance?
41
None of these
detection technologies is perfect.
42
Absent special laws to the contrary,
43
the state would need to prove the accuracy of whatever method the officer
used to estimate the driver’s speed.
44
In principle, this would include not
only the accuracy of the detection method (use of a radar gun) but also
the accuracy of any techniques used to ensure the accuracy of the
detection method (calibration of a radar gun by speedometer or tuning
fork), which themselves have different rates of error.
45
Even with every
piece of foundational testimony in place, uncertainty will remain.
46
Now consider the driver’s defense. The driver could take the stand to
testify—perhaps compellingly—that he was not speeding. The driver
might call a disinterested passenger to testify that the driver was obeying
the speed limit at the time of the stop. The driver might also point to
factors that can throw off the reading of a radar gun: detection angles,
40
Id.
41
Id.
42
See, e.g., Nat’l Highway Traffic Safety Admin., LIDAR Speed-Measuring Device Per-
formance Specifications, at 7, 10, 12, 17–28, (Mar. 2013), https://www.nhtsa.gov/sites/-
nhtsa.dot.gov/files/documents/809811-lidarspeedmeasuringdevice.pdf [https://perma.cc/2Z-
P8-W63D] (providing test procedures and tolerances for how much inaccuracy a LIDAR unit
may exhibit in different operating conditions).
43
E.g., Va. Code Ann. § 46.2-882 (2017) (providing that a radar gun reading “shall be
accepted as prima facie evidence” of the speed a vehicle was driving, and providing that “a
certificate, or a true copy thereof, showing the calibration or accuracy of . . . any tuning fork
employed in calibrating or testing the radar . . . and when and by whom the calibration was
made, shall be admissible [to address questions about calibration or accuracy]” as long as such
calibration or testing was conducted within the last six months). But cf. State v. Bonar, 319
N.E.2d 388, 389 (Ohio Ct. App. 1973) (finding that the State’s failure to present evidence of
a radar gun’s accuracy, while not rendering the evidence inadmissible, does entitle the
defendant to a directed verdict when the State’s only evidence was the radar gun reading).
44
See, e.g., Fed. R. Evid. 901 (requiring in federal courts, as in most state courts, that the
proponent of evidence must show that the evidence is what it purports to be, including, for
example, the basis for believing that a process or system—i.e., radar gun—produces an
accurate result); see also Fed. R. Evid. 104(b) (providing that when evidence is relevant only
upon the support of a foundational fact, evidence must be introduced sufficient to support a
finding that the foundational fact exists).
45
See, e.g., John Jendzurski & Nicholas G. Paulter, Calibration of Speed Enforcement
Down-the-Road Radars, 114 J. Res. Nat’l Inst. Standards & Tech. 137 (2009) (comparing the
accuracy of different techniques for calibrating radar guns).
46
See, e.g., Mobile Speed Cameras, BBC Inside Out — South West (Feb. 28, 2005),
http://www.bbc.co.uk/insideout/southwest/series7/speed-cameras.shtml [https://perma.cc/Q-
R29-R3WA] (illustrating some potential errors in speed detection and describing case studies
of individuals who successfully opposed tickets based on speed gun readings).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1129
intervening vehicles, and reflective surfaces;
47
wind or weather
conditions;
48
the officer’s shaky hands or inexperience.
49
If the proof process in even this simple example sounds like an ordeal,
imagine how much more involved it would be in other settings. In
antitrust practice, for example, the state’s proof that a merger could have
anticompetitive effects will often involve hundreds of hours of
depositions and live testimony, and thousands of pages of reports and
exhibits. In 1934, the trial of monopolization charges against Alcoa took
two years and three months from start to finish.
50
Securities fraud,
environmental regulations, tax fraud, banking regulations, discrimination
claims—in all these areas and many others, the costs of proof can be
substantial.
51
One takeaway from this discussion is that the state’s detection of a
violation of law does not end the costs it faces in seeking to enforce the
law. Proving a violation is as costly as the proof process makes it.
A second takeaway is that even the state’s decision to shoulder the cost
of proving a violation does not guarantee that a violator will actually be
punished. The judge or jury could always be unpersuaded by the state’s
evidence, in which case the lawbreaker walks away scot-free.
52
47
See, e.g. Myatt v. Commonwealth, 397 S.E.2d 275, 277 (Va. Ct. App. 1990) (discussing
expert testimony about “[t]he reflective qualities of the appellant's motor vehicle, the presence
of the tractor-trailer truck behind the appellant’s vehicle, the angle of the radar unit with
respect to the highway, and its height above the highway” as factors properly challenging a
radar unit’s accuracy on a particular occasion).
48
See, e.g., Brown, supra note 39 (discussing how wind and weather conditions might cause
spurious radar readings).
49
Cf. Decatur Electronics, GHD & SCOUT Handheld Directional Radar User’s Manual
§ 7.4 (2010), http://www.decatureurope.com/uploads/Brochures/GHD-SCOUT%20User%-
20Manual%206-10-10-E.pdf [https://perma.cc/B55Z-C2VF] (“Fan interference is the most
common form of interference that you are likely to experience [when trying to measure driving
speeds]. It is caused when the radar measures the speed of the vehicle blower fan.”); id. § 12
(“Q. Will my radar work while my vehicle is moving? A. No, the GHD and SCOUT radar
guns are a [sic] stationary only models, so your vehicle should be parked. You need to hold
the radar steady while operating it.”).
50
See Spencer Weber Waller, The Story of Alcoa: The Enduring Questions of Market
Power, Conduct, and Remedy in Monopolization Cases, in Antitrust Stories 121, 127–28
(Eleanor M. Fox & Daniel A. Crane eds., 2007).
51
See, e.g., Stagi v. Nat’l R.R. Passenger Corp., 880 F. Supp. 2d 564, 570 (E.D. Pa. 2012)
(class counsel spent nine years litigating Title VII class action); Carpenters Health & Welfare
Fund v. Coca-Cola Co., 587 F. Supp. 2d 1266, 1271 (N.D. Ga. 2008) (class counsel spent
eight years litigating securities fraud class action).
52
We ignore the possibility that the cost to the defendant of trial, even if he wins, may itself
act as a form of punishment and deterrent. Accounting for this possibility appears to
complicate matters without fundamentally changing our results.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1130 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
Not all cases are equally difficult though. All else equal, the probability
of an innocent verdict would seem to shrink as the extent of the violation
grows.
53
This is easily illustrated. Suppose that a hypothetical driver has
been ticketed for going 90 mph in a 55-mph zone. The officer testifies
that the driver appeared to be going about this speed, and that the radar
gun confirmed it. Can the driver really undermine this evidence? Setting
aside the possibility of pure fabrication by the officer, uncertainty around
the measurement seems unlikely to win the day. The radar gun may be
imperfect, but not that imperfect. Proving that the driver was speeding
seems almost certain.
Now suppose the driver has been ticketed for going 56 mph in the 55-
mph zone. Even small uncertainties loom large. The state can call all the
experts it wants in trying to bolster the 56-mph reading. When considering
the many ways that the radar could possibly have been a mere 1 mph high,
the fact-finder could remain unpersuaded. The odds of the state winning
at trial now seem low—maybe no better than a coin flip.
This thought experiment shows that even when a violation of law is
detected, there may be good reasons for the state to decline to enforce. At
a minimum, it should not attempt to prove a violation unless the expected
benefits of doing so exceed the costs.
We can capture this with a simple equation. When the state chooses to
enforce the law, it pays a cost of C. This cost could be fixed, or it could
vary, increasing for harder cases (the state needs more evidence) and
decreasing for easier cases. The benefit of enforcement is B, which is not
fixed. B grows with the magnitude of the infraction. Intuitively, the state
gets more benefit from penalizing a 90-mph speeder than it does from
penalizing a 56-mph speeder. Proof is never certain; there is always a
chance that the state’s case falls apart. Thus, the benefit must be
discounted by the probability of conviction, p, which varies with the
extent of the violation, as discussed above. The state would not rationally
seek to enforce the law unless pB > C. Rearranging terms for clarity, the
state would not enforce unless B > C/p.
53
Holding all else equal means, among other things, holding fixed the amount of resources
that the defendant is willing to spend on fighting the charge or claim. We accept that—
depending on punishments and collateral implications—defendants might often feel more
compelled to fight larger alleged infractions. Our point is to identify a marginal property of
the system that applies regardless of what defendants choose to do with their resources.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1131
Figure 1 illustrates. The benefit line captures B, the social gain from
successfully penalizing a speeding driver at a violation of a certain size.
54
Punishing a driver going 85 yields a large benefit; punishing a driver
going 65 yields a small benefit; punishing a driver going 55 or slower
yields no benefit at all.
55
The cost line captures C/p. It illustrates the
opportunity cost of trying to prove a given violation of law. For large
violations, like speeds of 90 mph and above, the probability of victory is
almost certain (p approaches 1), so the line simply reflects C, the
resources that go into putting on witnesses and presenting evidence at
trial. For smaller violations, like speeds of 56 mph, the cost line reflects
these same expenses scaled up to account for the possibility that the state
could lose (C/p grows as p approaches 0). The intuition is that as the
probability of conviction shrinks, the social resources expended on
prosecution are less likely to yield a benefit.
56
Resources wasted on a loss
could have been spent elsewhere. Thus, the opportunity cost of attempting
to punish a lawbreaker grows as the difficulty of the case rises.
54
Nothing turns on this being the only value that the state perceives from enforcing the law.
Fines, for example, may be an important source of revenue for the state. And the public at
large may derive some form of deontological value from seeing popular laws enforced. These
additional benefits could be factored into the following analysis with few real changes in result
or prediction. Note also that while the benefit line in Figure 1 originates at 55 mph—implying
that deterring drivers from going 54 mph provides no benefit to society—nothing in our
analysis is particularly sensitive to this assumption. Finally, we assign the benefit line a
specific shape in Figure 1, starting at zero at the legal limit. Nothing turns on the shape, as
long as it slopes upward.
55
Consistent with this description, the benefit line slopes upward. One could characterize
the benefits of enforcement in different ways, and the line could take different shapes.
However, this is not critical to our results. As long as the benefit line is not vertical, insincere
rules can improve enforcement.
56
Recall that we assume that the state gets no deterrence benefit from a loss at trial. See
supra note 53. This is not critical to our results.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1132 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
As Figure 1 shows, the state should not even try to prove small
violations of the speed limit. The cost of attempting to enforce the law
against a driver clocked at 60 mph exceeds the benefit. The speed at which
the lines intersect is the breakeven point. This does not occur until 65
mph. It is irrational for the state to seek to enforce the law against drivers
going less than 65 mph.
Recall Justice Holmes’s suggestion that one should consider law from
the perspective of the bad man.
57
Figure 1 shows that being clocked at
speeds above the legal limit does not necessarily carry with it even the
threat of punishment. Correctly observing or intuiting this, the bad man
realizes that he can go as fast as 65 mph without fear of any punishment
at all, whether his speeding is detected or not. The speed limit in the books
is 55 mph, but the speed limit in action is 65 mph.
58
57
See supra notes 20–21 and accompanying text.
58
For ease of exposition, the following discussion presumes that the bad man does drive 65
mph under this insincere rule. That is not necessarily right. The bad man may go faster than
65 mph if he thinks that he will not be detected, or if he values speeding more than he fears
the potential punishment, or if his risk preferences make it rational for him to further violate
the law. These details complicate analysis without adding or clarifying anything important, so
we omit them in our simple model. Still, the careful reader may keep in mind that while
Benefit
+
0
Figure 1. Social Cost and Benefit of Trying to Prove a Wrong
Value
Speed
55 65
45
Sincere
speed limit
Law in
action
Cost
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1133
Figure 1 illustrates a previously underexplored source of gaps between
law in books and law in action. While this is similar in some respects to
the rational slippage that results from a decision to spend less on police
so that resources will be available for schools and roads, it is actually a
functionally distinct and additive source of slippage that results from the
cost of the proof process itself. Being connected to the proof process gives
this source of slippage some concerning properties but also opens up
novel avenues for mitigation.
To start with the concerning properties, consider what happens to
enforcement as the burden of persuasion rises. Speeding is typically a
civil offense, so our example implicitly assumes that the state’s burden of
persuasion is preponderance of the evidence. In criminal cases, due
process demands that the state prove a violation of law beyond a
reasonable doubt.
59
Suppose we were to change the burden of persuasion
in our driving example, raising it from proof by a preponderance of the
evidence to proof beyond a reasonable doubt.
60
For any given size of
infraction, the state has a weaker case under the reasonable doubt standard
than it does under the preponderance standard. Graphically, this equates
to an outward shift of the cost curve, as Figure 2 illustrates.
61
Figure 1 shows the law imposes no incentive for the bad man to go slower than 65 mph, it is
possible that the bad man would go faster than this in practice.
59
See In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 364 (1970) (holding “that the Due Process Clause
protects the accused against conviction except upon proof beyond a reasonable doubt of every
fact necessary to constitute the crime with which he is charged”).
60
See Sean P. Sullivan, A Likelihood Story: The Theory of Legal Fact-Finding, 90 U. Colo.
L. Rev. 1, 18–22 (2019) (commenting on the interpretation of these intermediate standards).
61
Recall that the cost curve is defined as
!"#
. The probability of conviction is everywhere
lower under the higher burden of persuasion. Since
#
is everywhere lower, the cost curve is
everywhere higher under the higher burden of persuasion.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1134 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
The breakeven point at which the state might rationally start trying to
enforce the law has shifted rightward. The speed limit remains 55 mph,
but under the higher burden of persuasion, drivers can now go as fast as
70 mph with impunity.
62
The higher the burden of persuasion, the greater
the violation of law must be before it will be rational for the state to
enforce. That is, higher burdens of persuasion lead to greater proof costs,
in turn leading to greater gaps between the law in books and the law in
action.
The point is not that higher burdens of persuasion are bad. The received
wisdom is that the social cost of proving guilt beyond a reasonable doubt
(including the cost of letting guilty people go free) is justified by the
benefit of avoiding false positives (the benefit of fewer innocent people
in jail).
63
This false positive versus false negative tradeoff is well
62
These numbers are stylized. In reality, a switch to the reasonable doubt standard could
result in much greater slippage than this.
63
See, e.g., Addington v. Texas, 441 U.S. 418, 423–24 (1979) (“In a criminal case . . . the
interests of the defendant are of such magnitude that . . . they have been protected by standards
of proof designed to exclude as nearly as possible the likelihood of an erroneous [conviction].
In the administration of criminal justice, our society imposes almost the entire risk of error
upon itself.”); In re Winship, 397 U.S. at 372 (Harlan, J., concurring) (“I view the requirement
of proof beyond a reasonable doubt in a criminal case as bottomed on a fundamental value
Benefit
+
0
Figure 2. Greater Slippage under Higher Burdens of Persuasion
Value
Speed
55 65
45
Cost
Sincere
speed limit
Law in
action
Higher
burden
70
Law in
action
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1135
known.
64
What Figure 2 illustrates is not well known. As the burden of
persuasion rises, the band of marginal violations that the state will not
enforce also expands. The cost of raising the burden of persuasion is not
just that more guilty people go free. The cost is also that all bad men are
empowered to violate the law a little more extensively than they could
before.
The discussion up to this point can be summarized succinctly:
underdeterrence is inevitable when proof is costly. The reason is not any
of the traditional sources explored in the literature like monitoring costs
or inadequacy of the threatened sanction. Rather, this underdeterrence
traces to the costs of proving a violation of law. Proof is expensive,
particularly when the violation is small and the burden of persuasion is
heavy.
If proof costs frustrate enforcement, one wonders what lawmakers
could do to combat the problem.
65
Committing additional resources to
fund the litigation of small violations is not the answer. This would be
throwing money away on a gamble for which the costs have already been
shown to outweigh the benefits. What lawmakers would ideally do is
lower the cost of proof. How might this be achieved?
One idea might be to reduce the burden of persuasion. Figure 2 shows
that raising the burden of persuasion increases the cost of proof, thereby
increasing the gap between the law in books and the law in action. If
lawmakers could lower the burden of persuasion, they could shrink this
gap. The idea of varying the burden of persuasion to improve enforcement
has received considerable scholarly attention.
66
But while the idea works
determination of our society that it is far worse to convict an innocent man than to let a guilty
man go free.”); 2 McCormick on Evidence § 341 (Kenneth S. Broun ed., 7th ed. 2013)
(“Society has judged that it is significantly worse for an innocent person to be found guilty of
a crime than for a guilty person to go free.”).
64
See generally Larry Laudan, Truth, Error, and Criminal Law: An Essay in Legal
Epistemology (2006) (evaluating “legal errors” and strategies for their reduction).
65
The idea that legislators should act in conscious consideration of the implications of the
proof process and rules of evidence is not novel. See, e.g., 6 Jeremy Bentham, The Works of
Jeremy Bentham, chs. 3–4 (London, Simpkin, Marshall, & Co. 1843) (discussing the ends of
a legal system of proof and the duties of the legislator in relation to proof and evidence
problems).
66
See, e.g., Michael L. Davis, The Value of Truth and the Optimal Standard of Proof in
Legal Disputes, 10 J.L. Econ. & Org. 343, 344 (1994); Louis Kaplow, Likelihood Ratio Tests
and Legal Decision Rules, 16 Am. L. & Econ. Rev. 1, 35 (2014); Louis Kaplow, Burden of
Proof, 121 Yale L.J. 738, 815 (2012); Louis Kaplow, On the Optimal Burden of Proof, 119 J.
Pol. Econ. 1104, 1105 (2011); see also James Andreoni, Reasonable Doubt and the Optimal
Magnitude of Fines: Should the Penalty Fit the Crime?, 22 RAND J. Econ. 385, 393 (1991)
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1136 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
in theory, it has little practical potential. The justice system has long
encompassed roughly three burdens of persuasion,
67
and there is little
appetite for introducing more.
68
Even if there were such an appetite, the
constitutional mandate of proof beyond a reasonable doubt in criminal
cases would frustrate efforts to vary the burden in important
circumstances.
69
And even without these hurdles, it might simply be too
difficult to articulate burdens of persuasion with any greater granularity.
Even the existing burdens of persuasion seem to draw distinctions finer
than the legal system can handle.
70
Fine tuning the burden of persuasion is not the answer. Fortunately,
this does not end the analysis. There is another strategy that lawmakers
could use.
B. The Benefits of Insincerity
The state can lower the cost of proof, and thereby improve compliance,
by redefining the content of a wrong. Recall that lawmakers believe the
optimal speed is 55 mph. What if they do not adopt a sincere speed limit
of 55 mph but instead an insincere speed limit of 45 mph? Previously the
probability of convicting a driver clocked at 60 mph was relatively low,
so the opportunity cost of ticketing such a driver was high. With a 45-
mph speed limit, the probability of convicting a driver clocked at 60 mph
(discussing possible interdependence between the severity of a crime and fact-finders’
subjective burden of persuasion); Jack B. Weinstein, Some Difficulties in Devising Rules for
Determining Truth in Judicial Trials, 66 Colum. L. Rev. 223, 236 (1966) (commenting that,
while affording criminal defendants the benefits of a high burden of persuasion is a “deliberate
choice . . . based upon deeply held moral values and ethical judgments[,]” in the case of a
“particularly dangerous crime indulged in by relatively small numbers of the population and
a relatively small number of suspects, a perfectly rational argument could be developed for
conviction on the least shadow of a doubt.”).
67
See 2 McCormick on Evidence, supra note 63, §§ 339–41 (summarizing and discussing
the common burdens of persuasion); Sullivan, supra note 60, at 18–19 (same).
68
Cf. Michelson v. United States, 335 U.S. 469, 486 (1948) (explaining that while a
significant part of the law of evidence is archaic, paradoxical, and irrational, it should not be
disturbed because “somehow it has proved a workable even if clumsy system . . . . [and so to]
pull one misshapen stone out of the grotesque structure is more likely simply to upset its
present balance between adverse interests than to establish a rational edifice”).
69
The clear-and-convincing evidence standard, for example, has long been criticized as
vague and inconsistent in its application across proceedings. See Sullivan, supra note 60, at
19.
70
Cf. 2 McCormick on Evidence, supra note 63, § 340 (commenting that “[n]o high degree
of precision can be attained” through things like alternative articulations of intermediate
burdens of persuasion).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1137
is higher, making the opportunity cost of enforcing the law lower. In short,
the state can now enforce the speed limit more aggressively than before.
Figure 3 illustrates. The optimal speed remains 55 mph. Thus, the
benefit line does not change position. What changes is the cost curve. It
shifts inward. This captures the fact that some cases which were
previously hard have now become easy. A 1-mph violation has become
an easier-to-prove 11-mph violation. A 5-mph violation has become a 15-
mph violation, and so on. For any given degree of speeding, the
probability of successful proof has gone up. Thus, the cost of proving
every violation has gone down.
The shift in the cost curve changes the breakeven point at which
enforcement becomes worthwhile. As illustrated in Figure 3, when the
speed limit is set at the sincere 55 mph level, it is irrational for the state
to try to prove violations of the speed limit by drivers clocked at anything
less than 65 mph. When the speed limit is reduced to the insincere level
of 45 mph, it becomes rational to prove violations at a speed of 60 mph.
The gap between the law in the books and the law in action looks even
Benefit
+
0
Figure 3. The Insincere Rule
Value
Speed
55 65
45
Insincere
speed limit
Law in
action
60
Cost
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1138 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
worse than before: previously it was 10 mph,
71
now it is 15 mph.
72
But
compliance with the sincere (55 mph) benchmark has actually improved:
drivers travel 60 mph instead of 65 mph.
73
We want to emphasize that the state does not achieve the mandate of
the insincere rule. Drivers still violate the posted speed limit. But the state
does not care. It focuses on what the bad man prioritizes: the point at
which enforcement becomes rational for the state. This is what determines
the law in action. By reducing the cost of proof, the insincere rule gives
the state a credible threat of punishment against some infractions for
which it was previously helpless. Consequently, the bad man slows down.
C. Interpretation and Implications
Our title, Insincere Evidence, captures the mechanism by which
insincerity reduces proof costs. An insincere rule gives the state a block
of “free” or “artificial” evidence that can be used to help prove a violation
of law. From a proof-cost perspective, adopting an insincerely low speed
limit is the functional equivalent of the state secretly giving police officers
rigged radar guns that tack an extra 10 mph onto every reading.
In retrospect, this property is obvious. The effect of moving the speed
limit from the sincere (55 mph) level to the insincere (45 mph) level is
not to change the speed that a 65-mph driver was actually going. The
effect is simply to turn what had been a 10-mph infraction into what is
now a 20-mph infraction. And, from a proof-cost perspective, that is no
different than simply adding 10 mph onto whatever speed the radar gun
would have otherwise shown.
In respects other than proof-cost, however, an insincere rule is quite
different from a rigged radar gun. Indeed, it may out-perform the rigged
radar gun in practice. Judges and jurors are unlikely to convict if they
learn that the radar gun has been manipulated. An insincere rule could
continue to function even if the fact-finder doubted its sincerity.
The difference relates to the location of the insincerity. With a rigged
radar gun, insincerity is about the facts. The finding of legally operative
facts is the province of the fact-finder (judge or jury). The fact-finder
71
Under the sincere speed limit of 55 mph, Figure 3 indicates a breakeven point of 65 mph.
Thus, the gap between the law in action and the law in the books is 65 – 55 = 10 mph.
72
Under the insincere speed limit of 45 mph, Figure 3 indicates a breakeven point of 60
mph. Thus, the gap between the law in action and the law in the books is 60 – 45 = 15 mph.
73
As discussed previously, we assume for ease of exposition that drivers go as fast as they
can without triggering enforcement. See supra note 58.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1139
would not only be entitled to reject falsified evidence but probably
required to do so. By contrast, with an insincere rule, insincerity is about
the law. The statement of legal standards is the province of lawmakers,
not fact-finders. In a legal proceeding, under the charge of deciding
whether the evidence shows that the posted speed limit has been violated,
the fact-finder might well answer in the affirmative even if she personally
doubts the optimality of that speed limit.
We should emphasize this point. The rule-maker does not have to fool
the judge, the jury, the regulated parties, or anyone else in order for the
insincere rule to reduce the cost of proof. Everyone can understand and
agree that 55 mph is the optimal speed, even though the speed limit is 45
mph. The logic works as long as the judge or jury applies the law as
written: weighing the evidence against the posted speed limit. As a matter
of principle, this is how the legal system usually assumes that judges and
jurors will behave. As a matter of practice, judges and juries might often
behave this way. They might not know the optimal speed, so they just
enforce the law as written, or they might understand that enforcing the
law as written will draw actual speeds closer to the optimum. The logic
does not extend forever. Suppose lawmakers set the speed limit at 1 mph.
Officers might refuse to enforce such an absurd rule. Jury nullification
might result. But for the type of marginal shading of legal standards that
we discuss in this Article, abject refusals to enforce the law seem unlikely.
We have connected insincere evidence to artificial evidence. Now we
connect it to burdens of persuasion. Just as insincere rules and rigged
radar guns have the same theoretical effect on deterrence and
enforcement, there is a functional equivalence between adopting an
insincere rule and lightening the state’s burden of persuasion.
Figure 4 illustrates. To understand the figure, consider a series of
events. To begin, the state’s burden is preponderance of the evidence.
This corresponds to the solid cost curve which intersects the benefit curve
at 65 mph. Now suppose that the state is suddenly required to meet the
higher burden of proof beyond a reasonable doubt. This change has the
effect of shifting the cost curve to the right, as illustrated by the dashed,
black cost curve which intersects the benefit curve at 70 mph. The gap
between the law in the books and the law in action has widened. Finally,
suppose that lawmakers react to this higher burden of persuasion—and
the weaker enforcement achieved under it—by reducing the speed limit
to an insincerely low level. As illustrated by the dashed, gray cost line,
the insincere speed limit mitigates the increase in proof costs created by
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1140 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
the higher burden of persuasion. With a little bit more insincerity, this
offset would have returned the cost curve to the initial preponderance-of-
the-evidence level.
This may seem alarming. Consider criminal defendants and their
constitutional right to the protection afforded by proof beyond a
reasonable doubt. One implication of Figure 4 is that the benefit of this
protection may be weakened, or even eliminated, by the simple act of
more strictly defining what constitutes a wrong. While this is an accurate
statement, any alarm arising from it owes only to a naïve view of the
protection that a burden of persuasion affords. Figure 4 does not show
that insincere rules threaten the protection of the reasonable doubt
standard; it shows that the reasonable doubt standard is not—by itself—
much protection. The benefit enjoyed by a defendant is a function of both
the burden of persuasion and the definition of a wrong.
74
To the extent
that the Constitution constrains only one of these levers, its protection has
never been more than what Figure 4 suggests it to be.
74
See Richard H. McAdams, The Political Economy of Criminal Law and Procedure: The
Pessimists’ View, in Criminal Law Conversations 517, 519–20 (Paul H. Robinson, Stephen
P. Garvey & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan eds., 2009) (arguing that the state can make violations
of law easier to prove by lightening the burden of persuasion or by changing the elements of
the crime).
Benefit
+
0
Figure 4. Equivalence of Insincere Rule and Reduced Burden of Persuasion
Value
Speed
55 65
45
Cost
Insincere
rule
Higher
burden
70
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1141
There is a more constructive way to think about the equivalence of
insincere evidence and burdens of persuasion. As noted, scholars have
long discussed manipulation of burdens of persuasion as a way of
achieving more efficient deterrence outcomes. Burdens of persuasion are
not susceptible to fine tuning, and thus have failed to deliver on this idea.
But many substantive legal thresholds are susceptible to detailed
refinement. Insincere evidence may be a practical way to unlock the long-
sought promise of variable burdens of persuasion.
D. Generalizations and Applications
We have explained our idea using a simple speed limit example. But
the idea is not limited to this context. Insincere rules function the same
way in any setting that meets the following three conditions: (1) the cost
of proof decreases as the magnitude of the legal violation grows; (2) the
rule-maker can adjust the content of the law in a way that converts
relatively minor violations of law into relatively major violations; and (3)
adjudicators apply the law as written. To emphasize the generality of
these conditions, we highlight several that do not appear on the list.
Deceit. As explained above, the rule-maker does not have to fool
anyone. Judges, jurors, the public—everyone can know that the law in
books is insincere. This does not matter. As long as the judge or jury
weighs the evidence against the stated rule—the actual, duly-enacted
law—then the cost of proof goes down. In many settings it seems
reasonable to assume that judges and jurors will often behave this way.
They may have no strong sense of what the sincere law would be (what
are the optimal mercury emissions from a power plant?), in which case
they simply apply the law in books. Or they may prioritize the law in
action, not the law in books, and realize that enforcing the insincere law
in books will improve the law in action.
Knowledge. Similarly, the functionality of insincere evidence does not
require the public to know the law is insincere. In some cases, regulated
parties may mistakenly believe that the law is sincere when it is insincere.
This does not matter. Think again of the speed limit example. If bad men
observe a posted speed limit of 45 mph, and if they learn from experience
or intuition that they can go as fast as 60 mph with impunity, they will go
60 mph. It does not matter whether they believe that the 45-mph speed
limit is sincere or not. The potential for state enforcers to become
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1142 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
confused about the sincerity of law is slightly more problematic, a point
we address in detail below.
75
Irrationality. Some people might imagine that insincere rules improve
behavior through a psychological mechanism. Judge Calabresi has argued
that “use of . . . ‘technically incorrect’ language”—the First Amendment
says Congress shall not abridge speech, but occasionally it does—“can
bring us closer to the desired result than would use of more precise
language.”
76
He attributes this to a kind of psychological bias: “If we
admit that the state can regulate religion, we are psychologically . . . more
likely to allow such regulation than if we say that there can be no
regulation of religion and then from time to time” regulate it anyway.
77
Our idea does not hinge on psychology. Insincere rules can lower proof
costs, and therefore improve behavior, even if everyone is strictly rational,
meaning they mechanically weigh the personal benefit of violating the
rule against the pain of punishment.
Objective uncertainty. Insincere rules do not require objective
uncertainty about the facts to function as we describe. In our speeding
example, we assume that radar guns measure speeds with error. Those
errors create evidentiary uncertainty. Insincere speed limits overcome that
uncertainty by turning close calls into sure things. But objective
uncertainty is not required. Perceived uncertainty works just as well. If
judges or jurors believe that radar guns measure with error, then they will
not convict drivers clocked at one mile-per-hour over the speed limit—
even if radar guns are actually flawless. They will, however, convict
drivers clocked at 11 mph over the limit. Insincere rules can overcome
perceived as well as real measurement errors.
Deterrence. Like much of the enforcement literature,
78
we have
assumed that the goal of enforcement is deterrence. In reality, rule-makers
might have other (or additional) objectives, like retribution,
incapacitation, or some notion of corrective justice. Insincere rules can
benefit rule-makers even when deterrence is not their objective. Rule-
makers can further multiple goals by drawing the behavior of regulated
parties toward their ideal.
Precisely scalar legal standards. Our speed limit example is scalar: the
limit can move up or down continuously, as though set by a dial.
75
See infra Section III.E (including a discussion of credulous enforcement officers).
76
Guido Calabresi, A Common Law for the Age of Statutes 173 (1982).
77
Id.
78
See supra Part II.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1143
Moreover, the speed limit is precise in the sense that most everyone
agrees, conceptually if not empirically, on what constitutes a violation of
the posted speed limit. Laws addressing countless subjects have this
precisely scalar feature and are good candidates for insincere rules: blood
alcohol content while driving; emissions of mercury, sulfur, carbon, or
other pollutants; the length, weight, and number of fish caught; the time
of day when hunters can hunt and marchers can march; decibel limits at
airports and nightclubs; the number of milligrams of acetaminophen or
other ingredients in each dose of medicine; distances between guns and
schools, protesters and abortion clinics, and campaigners and voting
booths. The list goes on.
Yet the logic of insincerity reaches beyond this broad class of laws.
The underlying variable does not have to be precise. Consider a regulation
requiring that facilities storing prescription drugs have “adequate
lighting.”
79
“Adequate” is vague; no one can say what exactly adequate
means, so no one can say for sure when lighting is inadequate. Thus, a
claim that a facility has inadequate lighting might fail in court because of
differing opinions. To solve this problem, the state can require that
facilities have “excellent” lighting. Like “adequate,” the term “excellent”
is vague. Nevertheless, it helps. Evidence that a facility is somewhat
dimly-lit may fail to convince a judge when the standard is “adequate”
but easily convince a judge if the standard is “excellent.” Foreseeing the
ease of proof, the facility will install better lighting if the standard
switches from “adequate” to “excellent.”
The previous example is straightforward but mundane. An example
with greater economic heft is the lack of a de minimis standard in U.S.
antitrust law. In many respects, U.S. and E.U. competition policy is
similar.
80
But unlike the E.U., which provides a safe harbor for small
violations of European competition laws,
81
U.S. antitrust law has never
79
See, e.g., 21 C.F.R. § 205.50 (2019).
80
See generally Margaret Bloom, The U.S. and EU Move Towards Substantial Antitrust
Convergence on Consumer Welfare Based Enforcement, 19 Antitrust 18 (2005) (discussing
the perception and reality of convergence between the U.S. and E.U. on a consumer welfare
standard in antitrust); Larry Fullerton & Megan Alvarez, Convergence in International Merger
Control, 26 Antitrust 20 (2012) (discussing the perception and reality of international
convergence in merger law).
81
See 2014 O.J. (C 291) 1 (describing conditions under which “agreements of minor
importance . . . do not appreciably restrict competition under Article 101(1) of the Treaty on
the Functioning of the European Union”).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1144 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
evolved a clear minimum injury requirement.
82
In both regimes, small
antitrust violations are likely to go unpunished as too minor to warrant the
cost of enforcement. But, due to the lack of a de minimis standard,
moderate violations may be easier to prove in the U.S. than they are in the
E.U. If so, compliance with the antitrust laws may be stronger in the U.S
than it is in Europe.
Or consider an even more fundamental example. Some scholars argue
that the reasonable person standard in tort demands a higher level of care
than most people are capable of exercising on a regular basis.
83
This is
consistent with an insincere evidence strategy. The cost of proving
liability makes small acts of negligence too costly to prove, leading to
under-deterrence. The system corrects by requiring an insincerely strict
standard of care. Small acts of negligence that would be hard to prove
under a more subjective reasonable person standard may be easy to prove
under an artificially demanding objective standard.
The logic of insincerity extends further yet. It does not require even a
vaguely scalar variable. It can also work with “lumpy” variables, like
elements of a crime. To make a violation of law easier to prove, subtract
an element from the offense. We explain and comment further on this idea
below.
84
In sum, the conditions needed for insincere evidence to lower the cost
of proof are simple and general. This means insincere rules can be
deployed across the legal system. Are they? Professor Stuntz, to whom
we will return,
85
argues that criminal liability has broadened, leading to a
“world in which the law on the books makes everyone a felon.”
86
Professor Farber characterizes environmental standards as “threat points
82
U.S. law does have qualitative standards for the requisite degree of injury. See, e.g.,
Clayton Act, ch. 323, § 7, 38 Stat. 730, 731–32 (1914) (current version at 15 U.S.C. § 18
(2012)) (prohibiting mergers, the effects of which “may be to substantially lessen
competition . . . , or tend to create a monopoly”).
83
See, e.g., Fleming James, Jr., The Qualities of the Reasonable Man in Negligence Cases,
16 Mo. L. Rev. 1, 1–2 (1951) (“[M]any of the actor’s shortcomings such as awkwardness,
faulty perception, or poor judgment, are not taken into account [in the reasonable man
standard] if they fall below the general level of the community. This means that individuals
are often held guilty of legal fault for failing to live up to a standard which as a matter of fact
they cannot meet.”); see also Mark Grady, Res Ipsa Loquitur and Compliance Error, 142 U.
Pa. L. Rev. 887, 900 (1994) (“It is impossible to drive a car for any period of time without
missing a required precaution.”).
84
See infra Section IV.E (discussing adding and subtracting elements and the connection
between our theory of insincere rules and the work of Professor Stuntz).
85
See infra Part IV.E.
86
Stuntz, supra note 14, at 510–11.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1145
in negotiation,” arguing that “the criticism that regulatory standards are
too harsh loses some of its force, once it is recognized that the standards
are often only partially implemented.”
87
In principle, the IRS requires
extensive recordkeeping by some taxpayers, but in practice those
taxpayers have “been held to a somewhat less rigorous standard.”
88
A
New Jersey legislator proposed to double fines for speeding, and then,
when his proposal failed, introduced a bill to reduce speed limits.
89
All of
these examples and many others are consistent with the use of insincere
rules to generate insincere evidence.
E. The Limits of Insincere Evidence
This may sound too good to be true. The strategy of mitigating proof
costs through insincere evidence exhibits all the benefits of theft over
honest toil.
90
It drives down the cost of proving a violation of law, making
it easier for the state to punish transgressors. In so doing, it increases the
state’s ability to deter violations of law, and more efficiently incentivizes
compliance with laws. And it does all of this at seemingly no cost to the
state or society. No new police need to be hired. No new penalties need
to be administered. At no greater cost than the ink needed to change the
law, social benefits are unlocked.
There are indeed benefits to an insincere rule. But there are also
situations in which insincerity is an ineffective strategy. There are also
situations in which insincerity may backfire. We explore several of these
below.
To begin, the benefits of adopting an insincere rule depend on how
much the possibility of losing at trial factors into enforcement decisions.
Figures 5 illustrate this point. Unlike the figures above, this figure depicts
a cost curve that is already becoming flat when it intersects the benefit
curve. Shifting this cost curve to the left hardly changes the intersection
point: the law in action is 65 mph under the sincere rule and about 64 mph
87
Farber, supra note 16, at 315–16.
88
Stephen A. Zorn, The Federal Income Tax Treatment of Gambling: Fairness or Obsolete
Moralism?, 49 Tax Law. 1, 48 (1995).
89
Christopher Baxter, N.J. Assembly Panel Clears Bill Allowing Lower Speed Limits on
Quiet Residential Streets, NJ.com (May 13, 2013), https://www.nj.com/politics/2013/-
05/nj_assembly_panel_clears_bill.html [https://perma.cc/C5KE-H3S6].
90
Bertrand Russell, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy 71 (1919) (“The method of
‘postulating’ what we want has many advantages; they are the same as the advantages of theft
over honest toil.”).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1146 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
under the insincere rule. Intuitively, the fixed costs of proof (things like
the cost of preparing for trial) are the main drivers of slippage against the
posted speed limit. Since adopting an insincere rule does not change any
of these costs, its adoption has little effect on behavior. To restate that
point, the benefit of the insincere rule grows from the artificial evidence
that it gives the state to make its case. If the state does not need that
evidence because the violation is already easy to prove, then the adoption
of an insincere rule does not change behavior substantially.
One conclusion that seems to follow is that insincere rules may provide
the most benefit when applied to causes and crimes that require the state
to meet high burdens of persuasion. The higher the burden, the greater the
possibility of a loss. This is probably right, but the proposition could be
taken too far. With different assumptions about the shapes of the cost and
benefit curves, the effect of an insincere rule could be magnified, even
under the preponderance standard. And even if the insincere rule does not
imply as large a benefit under the preponderance standard as it does under
higher burdens of persuasion, its effect is not zero. To the extent that
insincere rules improve compliance without creating social costs, the
approach could be attractive.
Law in
action
Benefit
+
0
Value
Speed
55 65
45
Cost
Speed limit
Figure 5. Comparative Benefit of Insincere Rule
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1147
But do insincere rules really have no social costs? In practice, there are
at least two actors whose behavior could be distorted by insincere rules to
the detriment of society: “good men” and credulous law enforcement
agents.
To start with the first and more intuitive of these costs, everything thus
far has assumed a society composed entirely of Holmesian “bad men.”
This assumption focuses analysis and is common in the enforcement
literature. In reality, however, there could be “good men” who follow the
law more-or-less to the letter.
91
In the language of economics, these
people have a “taste” for obeying the law irrespective of the potential
threat of sanctions.
The existence and prevalence of such “good men” is hardly obvious. A
person who happens to prefer acting as the law commands might in a
sense comply regardless of the threat of enforcement. But when personal
preference and the law diverge, compliance seems unlikely without the
backing of a credible threat of sanction.
92
The sale and use of marijuana
is illegal under federal law,
93
but enforcement of the federal law is lax and
marijuana dispensaries operate openly in many states. The unauthorized
use of copyrighted music and movies is illegal under both federal law and
international treaty, yet the ease of downloading or streaming music and
movies, and the difficulty of tracking such acts, makes digital piracy a
perennial problem.
94
Federal laws provide standards for the minimally
humane treatment of animals,
95
but these laws are poorly enforced and
acts of cruelty abound.
96
Without strict sanctions for non-appearance, it
91
See generally Tom Tyler, Why People Obey the Law (2006) (exploring the variables that
govern citizen compliance with the law and possible threats to such compliance); Robert
Cooter, Do Good Laws Make Good Citizens? An Economic Analysis of Internalized Norms,
86 Va. L. Rev. 1577, 1579 (2000) (arguing that some individuals internalize values that give
them a “taste” for following laws).
92
Frederick Schauer, The Force of Law 65 (2015) (“Indeed, when we turn from
experimental research to data on actual legal compliance, we find substantial support for the
hypothesis that unenforced law that does not track people’s law-independent
preferences . . . is often ineffective.”).
93
See United States v. Pickard, 100 F. Supp. 3d 981, 1006–09 (E.D. Cal. 2015) (surveying
arguments and opinions concerning the classification of marijuana as a Schedule I drug).
94
See, e.g., George E. Higgins, Digital Piracy, Self-Control Theory, and Rational Choice:
An Examination of the Role of Value, 1 Int’l J. Cyber Criminology 33, 33–35 (2007)
(discussing the prevalence and illegality of digital content piracy).
95
E.g., Humane Slaughter Act, 7 U.S.C. §§ 1901–1907 (2012); Twenty-Eight Hour Act, 49
U.S.C. § 80502 (2012); Animal Welfare Act, 7 U.S.C. §§ 2131–2159 (2012).
96
See, e.g., Jo Warrick, They Die Piece by Piece, Wash. Post (Apr. 10, 2001),
https://www.washingtonpost.com/archive/politics/2001/04/10/they-die-piece-by-
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1148 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
seems that as few as twenty percent of people will even respond to a
summons for jury duty.
97
Assuming, however, that scrupulously law-abiding good men did exist
in large numbers, they could be a problem for the insincere evidence
strategy. To see why, consider how an insincere speed limit would work
in a society composed of both good and bad men. The insincere limit will
cause everyone to slow down. Bad men might go 60 mph instead of 65
mph, which is good. But good men will go 45 mph instead of 55 mph,
which is bad.
98
The benefit of the insincere rule in correcting the behavior
of the bad men is offset—and possibly overtaken—by the distorting effect
of the insincere rule on the behavior of the good men.
99
This is an important caveat, but it does not change the fundamental
availability of insincerity as a cost mitigation strategy. In a society
composed of both good and bad men, some insincerity may still be
efficient if the cost-mitigation benefits outweigh the distorting effects. As
the proportion of good men in the population declines, the cost of
distorting their behavior shrinks and the benefit of insincerity grows.
100
A second potential cost of generating insincere evidence lies in the risk
of overenforcement. The intuition runs as follows. Suppose, as before,
that lawmakers want drivers to go 55 mph and thus adopt an insincere
speed limit of 45 mph. What happens if law enforcement agents conclude
that driving faster than 45 mph is socially harmful? This conclusion would
piece/f172dd3c-0383-49f8-b6d8-347e04b68da1/?noredirect=on&utm_term=.e344064ae47b
[https://perma.cc/AKZ2-CUTU] (reporting the failure of the USDA to take substantive
remedial actions against even extreme violations of the Humane Slaughter Act); ASPCA,
USDA Enforcement of Animal Welfare Act Hits a New Low (Aug. 10, 2018),
https://www.aspca.org/news/usda-enforcement-animal-welfare-act-hits-new-low [https://per-
ma.cc/TQ3A-FC9E] (reporting a sharp decline in USDA’s already lax enforcement of the
Animal Welfare Act without reason to expect that violations of this law have become less
common).
97
See Schauer, supra note 92, at 65–66.
98
This is bad not only because good men go too slow, but because the speed differential
between good and bad men increases from 10 mph under the sincere rule to 15 mph under the
insincere rule. Higher speed differentials tend to cause more accidents. We thank Judge
Easterbrook for a conversation on this point.
99
To be clear, slowing down good men is costly in the following sense. They would prefer
to go faster, yet law slows them down (they pay a cost) that society does not recoup through
an offsetting benefit. In our setup, there is no gain associated with pushing drivers to go 45
mph.
100
We assume that the numbers of good and bad men in society are exogenous. In fact, the
numbers could be endogenous, meaning they change as rules become increasingly insincere.
This is an interesting possibility, but it does not fundamentally alter our analysis.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1149
be wrong: lawmakers think that driving faster than 55 mph is harmful, not
driving between 45 and 55 mph. But if these credulous law enforcers fail
to realize this, and if they act on their erroneous conclusions, then they
will seek to enforce the speed limit at speeds lower than what lawmakers
want.
Figure 6 illustrates. Lawmakers want drivers to go 55 mph and have
adopted an insincere speed limit of 45 mph to better achieve this end.
While the solid benefit line captures the true social benefits of enforcing
the law, credulous agents of the state think that 45 mph is the sincerely
optimal speed, and thus act as though the dashed benefit line reflects the
social benefits of enforcing the law. These credulous agents will try to
prove violations at lower speeds than they would if acting from the sincere
benefit curve. They begin enforcing the law at 55 mph. This is bad.
Punishing drivers for speeds around 55 mph entails greater social cost
than benefit. These credulous agents are over-enforcing the law.
Again, this is an important caveat, but it does not doom the strategy.
The problem does not arise at all if agents of the state focus on the correct
benefit curve. They might be directed to this curve by lawmakers or be
sophisticated enough to intuit its location. Even if the agents remain
Benefit
+
0
Value
Speed
55 65
45 60
Ins.
rule
Figure 6. Overenforcement
Perc eived
benefit
Speed limit Law in
action
Cost
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1150 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
credulous, lawmakers may have levers for limiting over-enforcement,
such as budgetary limitations or department policies. Consider, for
example, a Pennsylvania law stating that speeding drivers shall not be
convicted unless “the speed recorded is six or more miles per hour in
excess of the legal speed limit.”
101
Finally, even if the agents are
hopelessly credulous and lawmakers are unable to correct their behavior,
there may still be instances in which the adoption of an insincere rule
confers more benefits (in terms of reduced proof costs) than costs (in
terms of over-enforcement).
102
This discussion of agents provides an opportunity to address a concern
about discrimination in enforcement. If the speed limit is sincerely set at
55 mph, officers have legal authority to stop drivers going faster than 55
mph, including drivers going only, say, 56 mph. It would not be cost-
justified to ticket a 56-mph driver, but an officer could still do so to harass
certain drivers, like racial minorities. A reasonable apprehension is that
insincere rules could exacerbate this problem. Instead of having legal
authority to stop anyone exceeding the sincere 55 mph limit, officers
could now stop anyone exceeding the insincere 45 mph limit.
We share the overarching concern about discrimination in law
enforcement. However, insincere rules do not necessarily make this
problem worse. Discrimination may happen regardless of the content of
law. (When discriminatory police look to harass someone, do they care if
the speed limit is 35 or 45?) But suppose this is wrong and discrimination
does relate to the content of law. In other words, you must violate the
posted rule before the cops can harass you. Even in that scenario,
insincerity would only increase the potential for discriminatory
enforcement if it increased the number of people who violate the posted
rule. Our analysis precludes that possibility. We assume that everyone
violates the law to the extent they can, regardless of the rule. The same
number of people who speed under a sincere speed limit will speed under
an insincere speed limit. Thus, the insincere rule does not increase the
number of people subject to discriminatory enforcement.
101
75 Pa. Cons. Stat. § 3368(c)(4) (2018). This law does not eliminate hard cases. If the
posted speed limit is 55 mph, and if an officer clocks a driver at 62 mph, the officer might
have trouble proving that the driver exceeded the speed limit by at least six miles per hour. To
avoid this, officers might wait until drivers exceed the limit by, say, 10 mph. This is consistent
with our argument. The Pennsylvania rule, coupled with officers’ own incentives, mitigates
overenforcement.
102
The net benefit of an insincere rule with credulous enforcers depends on assumptions
about the shape and positions of the social cost and benefit curves, among other things.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1151
Of course, our analysis might be wrong. In reality, some people might
violate an insincere rule who would not have violated a sincere rule.
103
If
they do, and if enforcement agents discriminate, then insincere rules
increase the number of people subject to discriminatory enforcement. If
there were no way to counter that discrimination (e.g., better training or
agent screening), then we face a tradeoff. Insincere rules create benefits
by improving the behavior of regulated parties, and they create costs by
exacerbating discrimination by enforcers.
104
To optimize this tradeoff,
rule-makers can tinker with the rule. Perhaps it should be less insincere
than otherwise—for example, 50 mph instead of 45 mph. Perhaps it
should be sincere. Or perhaps it should be insincere in the other direction.
If the state sets the speed limit at 75 mph, drivers go too fast, which is
bad. But, because few people exceed the rule, discrimination by officers
is limited, and that is good.
105
F. Summary
The purpose of this discussion has been to explain how insincere rules
can reduce proof costs and thus improve compliance with law. We can
summarize the argument in short order. Enforcement costs cause
underdeterrence. Proving a violation of law is an underexplored but
potentially important source of enforcement costs. Anything that lowers
the costs of proof lowers enforcement costs, and thus improves behavior.
Insincere rules lower proof costs by turning minor violations (ordinarily
cost-prohibitive to prove in court) into major violations. This use of
insincere rules to generate insincere evidence will generally not lead to
fully optimal behavior, and is subject to potential costs and limitations.
The strategy is robust, however, and seems suited to modest deployment
in many settings.
103
Perhaps, for example, driving preferences are heterogeneous and distributed in such a
way that more drivers will elect to violate a lower speed limit than will elect to violate a higher
speed limit.
104
As is conventional in economics, we assume that all benefits and costs, including costs
of discrimination, are commensurable. In the grand social welfare function, better enforcement
and worse discrimination can be traded off against one another. We do not take a position on
how much weight to ascribe to these offsetting factors, but we share what we suspect is a
common view: it would take a lot in terms of improved enforcement to compensate for even
a little more discrimination.
105
Cf. Dhammika Dharmapala, Nuno Garoupa & Richard H. McAdams, Punitive Police?
Agency Costs, Law Enforcement, and Criminal Procedure, 45 J. Legal Stud. 105, 108 (2016)
(explaining that criminal procedure protections can offset excessive enforcement zeal).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1152 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
IV. DISTINGUISHING INSINCERE EVIDENCE
Besides us, scholars have not used the language of insincere evidence
to consider the relationship between the costs of proof and the efficiency
of enforcement. Scholars have, however, described concepts that relate to
our argument in various ways. These include conduct rules, decision
rules, over-inclusive rules, and the like. This Part distinguishes our focus.
The key insight is that lawmakers attempting to implement an insincere
evidence strategy do not intend or expect regulated parties to actually
obey the letter of an insincere rule. This insight puts distance between our
ideas and many others, and it makes all of them clearer.
A. Gilbert on Insincere Rules
In 2015, one of us (Gilbert) published a paper titled Insincere Rules.
That paper argued that lawmakers could improve behavior with
artificially demanding rules. To adapt one of the paper’s examples,
suppose lawmakers want factories to emit no more than 60 units of
pollution. An insincere rule might cap emissions at 50 units with the
expectation that factories would rationally choose to emit 60 units, the
actual amount that lawmakers wanted in the first place.
Gilbert’s paper introduced the term insincere rules, and the conclusion
of that paper—“By making the law in books wrong, lawmakers can get
the law in action right”
106
—resembles ours here. What makes the present
Article different is the context in which insincerity is considered. Our
focus on the proof process differs in fundamental ways from the two
channels that Gilbert initially investigated: (1) the use of insincerity as a
means of increasing sanctions, and (2) the use of insincerity to deceive
bad men.
Take the first channel. As explained, one way for lawmakers to
improve compliance is by increasing penalties. Gilbert showed that when
lawmakers cannot increase penalties directly—because of public outcry
against very high fines, for example—they may be able to increase
penalties indirectly by tightening rules. If a fine of $1,000 for every unit
of pollution above 60 is unpopular, lawmakers might replace it with a fine
of $500 for every unit of pollution above 50. A factory emitting 70 units
of pollution pays the same price either way ($1,000 × 10 = $10,000 is the
same as $500 × 20 = $10,000), but the latter strategy does not appear to
106
Gilbert, supra note 4, at 2187.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1153
involve as severe a penalty, and thus may be more politically feasible.
107
In short, insincere rules can act as penalty-enhancements. We discussed
penalties previously,
108
and we assume that they have already been
optimized for purposes of this Article.
109
Now consider Gilbert’s second channel, which involved deception.
Suppose the pollution law did not involve a fine but an injunction: if a
factory emits more than the pollution cap, the factory will be enjoined (via
a monitor) to comply with the legal limit moving forward. Insincerity may
allow enforcement agents to appear more aggressive than they really are.
If agents want pollution capped at 60 units and lawmakers set the law at
that level (i.e., the rule is sincere), factory owners may exploit detection
problems and other frictions to emit 70 units of pollution. Now suppose
lawmakers set the cap at 50 units (the insincere rule) but factory owners
believe this is what enforcement agents want. The same exploitation of
detection problems may lead them to emit 60 units of pollution—just what
the enforcement agents actually want. Unlike our focus in this Article,
Gilbert’s channel requires deception. Insincerity does not work, in this
way, unless factory owners are duped into thinking that the insincere rule
is sincere. Our approach does not require deception. Even if the bad man
realizes that lawmakers have adopted an insincere rule, the reduction in
proof costs remains the same.
In sum, Gilbert introduced insincere rules but studied only two
mechanisms by which they might elicit better behavior. Neither of those
mechanisms overlaps with the channel we develop here. Our focus is on
the use of insincerity as a means of lowering proof costs, which differs
fundamentally from what Gilbert developed in his earlier work. Insincere
evidence thus adds to the mechanisms Gilbert studied, and is, we suspect,
more common in practice.
B. Conduct and Decision Rules
Professor Meir Dan-Cohen distinguishes “conduct” rules, which direct
the public on how to behave, from “decision” rules, which direct officials
107
To express the idea in a different way, the insincere rule takes a particular behavior that
used to be classified as something akin to a misdemeanor and reclassifies it into something
akin to a felony. Because felonies carry larger fines, the insincere rule enhances punishment.
It does so without changing the fines for either misdemeanors or felonies.
108
See supra notes 24–32 and accompanying text (discussing the deterrence effects of strict
penalties).
109
See supra note 38 and accompanying text (discussing this maintained assumption).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1154 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
on how to treat people who violate the law.
110
For example, a conduct rule
forbids theft, while a decision rule instructs judges to punish theft unless
it is committed under circumstances like duress. Dan-Cohen argues that
with “acoustic separation,” members of the public do not perceive
decision rules, just conduct rules, which improves behavior and
outcomes.
111
People commit fewer thefts because they do not realize that
duress is a defense. Yet when thefts do occur, judges have the flexibility
to excuse them. Acoustic separation “permits the law to maintain higher
degrees of both deterrence and leniency than could otherwise coexist.”
112
Lawmakers might try to achieve acoustic separation, though Dan-
Cohen did not push this possibility.
113
Suppose they did. Would this
approximate an insincere rule?
The answer is no. By Dan-Cohen’s account, lawmakers expect the
public to obey the conduct rule. People should act as though theft is
forbidden. In contrast, lawmakers do not expect the public to obey an
insincere rule: they adopt the insincere rule with the expectation that
people will violate it. In the driving example, lawmakers adopt a speed
limit of 45 mph to elicit a speed like 60 mph. If people strictly obey the
speed limit—as we discussed in the case of too many “good men,” for
example
114
—the insincere rule will not function as expected.
Indeed, one way to think about insincere evidence is that it represents
a strategic response to the failure of acoustic separation. Insincere rules
presuppose that people have discovered the decision rule. In our running
example, the sincere speed limit (55 mph) is the conduct rule, and the
110
Meir Dan-Cohen, Decision Rules and Conduct Rules: On Acoustic Separation in
Criminal Law, 97 Harv. L. Rev. 625 (1984). Dan-Cohen traces his work to Bentham. See id.
at 626; see also Gerald J. Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition 408, 448–52
(1986) (explaining Bentham’s distinction between the law directing social interaction and the
law providing parameters for adjudication).
111
See Dan-Cohen, supra note 110, at 630–34.
112
Id. at 665.
113
Id. at 635 (“[A]ctual legal systems may in fact avail themselves of the benefits of acoustic
separation by engaging in ‘selective transmission’—that is, the transmission of different
normative messages to officials and to the general public, respectively. . . . I shall refer to these
techniques as strategies of selective transmission. The term ‘strategies’ calls for an
explanation. My use of the term should not be understood to connote deliberate, purposeful
human action. Imputing to the law strategies of selective transmission does not, therefore,
imply a conspiracy view of lawmaking in which legislators, judges, and other decisionmakers
plot strategies for segregating their normative communications more effectively. Instead,
strategies of selective transmission may be . . . strategies without a strategist . . . .” (footnotes
omitted)).
114
See supra Section III.E.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1155
speed limit coupled with the enforcement strategy (stop people going 65
mph or faster) is the decision rule. Our starting point is the assumption
that people know the decision rule, so they choose to drive 65 mph.
Changing the conduct rule, which everyone ignores, from 55 mph to 45
mph changes the decision rule, which everyone heeds, from 65 mph to 60
mph. Where acoustic separation has failed, insincere rules may succeed.
C. Over-Inclusive Rules
Rules are generally over- and under-inclusive when assessed against
their purpose.
115
Consider the 26th Amendment, which enfranchises
Americans aged 18 years or older.
116
Assume that the purpose of the age
requirement is to confine suffrage to those with sufficient maturity and
knowledge to cast votes in a socially responsible way.
117
The age
requirement is both over- and under-inclusive given this purpose. The
requirement is over-inclusive because it forbids too much: some 17-year-
olds are mature, knowledgeable, and responsible, yet they cannot vote.
118
And it is under-inclusive because it permits too much: some 18-year-olds
are not mature, knowledgeable, or responsible, yet they can vote. Good
rules balance the costs of over- and under-inclusiveness.
119
One might wonder if insincere rules have these features. Suppose
lawmakers want drivers to go 55 mph and adopt an insincere speed limit
of 45 mph. Is this simply an over-inclusive rule—one that prohibits
speeds (from 45 to 55 mph) that do not actually concern lawmakers at all?
The answer is no. Over-inclusiveness harms society. In the voting
context, if lawmakers want every responsible person to vote, they are
unhappy when their rule disenfranchises responsible 17-year-olds. This
does not mean they will change the rule. Perhaps the 18-year requirement
115
For a discussion, see Frederick Schauer, Playing by the Rules 31–34 (1991).
116
U.S. Const. amend. XXVI.
117
Some may dispute this. In the United States, the amendment was tied to the draft. See,
e.g., Jenny Diamond Cheng, Voting Rights for Millennials: Breathing New Life into the
Twenty-Sixth Amendment, 67 Syracuse L. Rev. 653, 668 (2017) (“This initial burst of interest
in eighteen-year-old voting lasted about five years and largely revolved around the perceived
injustice of drafting soldiers who were considered too young to vote.”). This does not matter
for our purposes.
118
And their vote today may affect whether they get conscripted at age 18.
119
“Good” rules do other things too. See generally Schauer, supra note 115, at 135–67; Cass
R. Sunstein, Problems with Rules, 83 Calif. L. Rev. 953, 971–77 (1995) (arguing that rules
minimize informational costs, reduce the likelihood of bias, embolden and constrain decision-
makers in particular cases, and promote predictability).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1156 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
strikes the best balance between the costs of under- and over-
inclusiveness. But lawmakers, and socially conscious citizens, still lament
the over-inclusiveness. By contrast, insincerity does not necessarily harm
society. Everyone could be happy to adopt a 45 mph speed limit—stricter
than sincere social preference—because it elicits better behavior by
regulated parties.
Here is another way to see the distinction. Lawmakers want and expect
people to obey over-inclusive rules. In the voting example, lawmakers
want everyone younger than 18 to stay away from the polls, regardless of
whether they are responsible. In contrast, lawmakers do not want or
expect people to obey insincere rules. They adopt insincere rules with the
hope and expectation that everyone will violate them.
D. Prophylactic Rules
Scholars use the term “prophylactic rules” in different ways. The
standard definition runs as follows: prophylactic rules are judge-made
rules that overprotect constitutional rights.
120
The classic example is the
Miranda warning.
121
If police coerce a suspect into confessing, the Fifth
Amendment’s privilege against self-incrimination prevents them from
using the confession in court. In Miranda v. Arizona, the U.S. Supreme
Court went further in holding that, for many confessions to be admissible,
police must have told suspects that they have the right to silence and
counsel, and the suspects must have voluntarily waived these rights.
122
The Miranda warning overprotects the privilege against self-
incrimination. It provides more protection for criminal suspects than the
Fifth Amendment requires.
120
Evan H. Caminker, Miranda and Some Puzzles of “Prophylactic” Rules, 70 U. Cin. L.
Rev. 1, 1 (2001). For other definitions, see id. at n.2; Brian K. Landsberg, Safeguarding
Constitutional Rights: The Uses and Limits of Prophylactic Rules, 66 Tenn. L. Rev. 925, 926–
30 (1999).
121
See Caminker, supra note 120; see also Mitchell N. Berman, Constitutional Decision
Rules, 90 Va. L. Rev. 1, 7, 13–14 (2004) (discussing the “battle . . . on the question of whether
Miranda announced a ‘prophylactic rule’”).
122
See, e.g., Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436, 444 (1966) (“The defendant may waive
effectuation of these rights, provided the waiver is made voluntarily, knowingly and
intelligently.”); Moran v. Burbine, 475 U.S. 412, 421 (1986) (elaborating that a waiver of
Miranda rights “must have been voluntary in the sense that it was the product of a free and
deliberate choice rather than intimidation, coercion, or deception” and that it also “must have
been made with a full awareness of both the nature of the right being abandoned and the
consequences of the decision to abandon it”).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1157
Scholars disagree on whether prophylactic rules are common or rare,
legitimate or illegitimate.
123
Prophylactic rules also have a converse
(albeit one without a name): rules that under-enforce constitutional
rights.
124
These details do not concern us; our interest is in showing that neither
prophylactic rules nor their converse are the same as insincere rules. To
see the difference, consider a question: why do courts adopt prophylactic
rules? Professor Evan Caminker provides an explanation in the Fifth
Amendment context:
[A] seemingly straightforward, case-by-case inquiry into whether a
constitutional norm has been transgressed will result in what might be
called “adjudication errors,” meaning the production of false-negatives
and false-positives. . . . [S]ometimes, the Court will conclude that the
likelihood of false-negatives is unacceptably high; in other words, the
direct doctrinal inquiry actually proves to be insufficiently protective of
the constitutional values at stake given the persistence of
unconstitutional conduct. I believe this is the best, and a fully sufficient,
explanation for and justification of Miranda’s so-called prophylactic
rule . . . .
125
This logic is familiar from above. Rules, including constitutional
doctrines, are both over- and under-inclusive. The precursor to Miranda
was a totality-of-the-circumstances test. Courts considered, on a case-by-
case basis, whether a suspect’s confession was coerced. In practice, this
was imperfect.
126
Some coerced confessions were admitted (the approach
was under-inclusive); some uncoerced confessions were excluded (the
approach was over-inclusive). In Miranda, the Court concluded that the
balance was off. The problem of under-inclusiveness was too great and
the costs of mistakenly admitting coerced confessions were too high. The
123
Compare Joseph D. Grano, Prophylactic Rules in Criminal Procedure: A Question of
Article III Legitimacy, 80 Nw. U. L. Rev. 100, 106–11 (1985) (arguing that some prophylactic
rules like the Miranda warning are illegitimate), with David A. Strauss, The Ubiquity of
Prophylactic Rules, 55 U. Chi. L. Rev. 190, 190 (1988) (arguing that prophylactic rules “are
not exceptional measures of questionable legitimacy but are a central and necessary feature of
constitutional law).
124
Lawrence Gene Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional
Norms, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 1212, 1213 (1978). According to Professor Mitchell Berman, “the
debate over prophylactic rules is parasitic upon a more fundamental contest over the logical
structure of constitutional adjudication.” Berman, supra note 121, at 50.
125
Caminker, supra note 120, at 9.
126
Berman, supra note 121, at 127.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1158 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
solution lay in rebalancing the rule. The Miranda warning overprotects
the Fifth Amendment in the sense that it is self-evidently over-inclusive.
This has the undesirable effect of excluding many uncoerced confessions
from evidence, but may still strike the best balance of under- and over-
inclusion costs.
As this discussion shows, prophylactic rules are akin to over-inclusive
rules. The distinction between insincere rules and prophylactic rules is
thus the same as above. Lawmakers lament the over-inclusiveness of
prophylactic rules, but they expect people to follow them. Lawmakers
welcome the over-inclusiveness of insincere rules, and they do not expect
people to follow them.
E. Pathological Laws
Insincere rules are distinct from many common legal concepts, but they
resemble one important idea in criminal law. In 2001, Professor William
Stuntz published a paper called The Pathological Politics of Criminal
Law. Consider this quote from his article:
Suppose a given criminal statute contains elements ABC; suppose
further that C is hard to prove, but prosecutors believe they know when
it exists. Legislatures can make it easier to convict offenders by adding
new crime AB, leaving it to prosecutors to decide when C is present and
when it is not.
127
Stuntz characterizes this scenario in different ways. In one, he explains
the replacement of crime ABC with crime AB in terms of enforcement
costs: “Substituting an easy-to-prove crime for one that is harder to
establish obviously makes criminal litigation cheaper for the
government.”
128
We would put it like this: Stuntz imagines a multi-
element, binary, insincere rule.
We can unpack this phrase. Our running example, speed limits,
involves a single-element offense. Whether a driver breaks the law
depends on a single variable. Imagine a multi-element offense instead.
Suppose a motorcyclist engages in reckless driving when he (1) drives
faster than 55 mph and (2) raises his front tire more than five inches off
the ground. As we have explained, the cost of proof will prevent perfect
enforcement. The law in books is 55 mph/five inches, but the law in action
127
Stuntz, supra note 14, at 519.
128
Id. at 520.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1159
is, say, 65 mph/eight inches. Lawmakers could benefit from an insincere
rule. They could make the law in books, say, 45 mph/two inches. This
might improve the law in action. Because the law involves more than one
element, and because the threshold for each element is insincere, this is a
multi-element, insincere rule. The logic behind the rule—how it elicits
better behavior—matches the logic from above. The only difference is we
have two elements instead of one.
Consider another distinction: elements and thresholds. Elements of an
offense can be added or subtracted. Reckless driving can have two
elements (speed and wheelies) or just one element (speed). Once the
elements are determined, each gets a threshold.
129
Driving turns into
speeding when it surpasses the speed limit. Likewise, lawful wheelies
become unlawful at some threshold—say, five inches off the ground.
When a threshold reaches zero, its element disappears.
130
To illustrate,
suppose again that a motorcyclist engages in reckless driving when he (1)
drives faster than 55 and (2) raises his front tire more than five inches.
This is the law in books. The law in action is 65 mph/eight inches. To
shrink this gap, the state adopts an insincere rule. It lowers the wheelie
threshold—from five inches to three inches and so on. When the threshold
reaches zero, the wheelie element evaporates. Now reckless driving is a
one-element crime rather than a two-element crime. It depends on speed
only.
Given this logic, a lawmaker calibrating an insincere rule can approach
the wheelie threshold in two ways. She can treat it as continuous,
dropping the threshold from five inches to four, two, or whatever will
elicit the best behavior. Or she can treat it as binary: the threshold stays
at five inches, or it drops to zero, meaning the element goes away. There
is no choice between.
Recall our description of Stuntz: he gestures at a multi-element, binary,
insincere rule. Now the phrase makes sense. The crimes ABC and AB are
multi-element. The crime AB is insincere. The state does not want to
punish AB; it criminalizes AB only to lower the cost of enforcing ABC.
The insincere rule is binary. The state does not lower the threshold on
element C or even contemplate doing so. It simply eliminates C.
Our work builds on Stuntz. He offered a compelling example which,
under one of his characterizations, represents an insincere rule. We
129
We assume continuous variables.
130
Equivalently, when the threshold reaches zero, the element remains, but proof of the
element becomes certain and costless.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1160 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
improve and generalize the idea. We show that insincerity works even for
one element-crimes; adding elements complicates matters without
changing the logic. We show that over-inclusiveness is a separate matter
(this line is blurry in Stuntz’s article). We show that the binary approach
Stuntz contemplated is actually an extreme and rather clumsy example of
an insincere rule. A continuous approach that fine-tunes the rule can work
better and might be more common (more on this below). We connect the
substance of the rule to the burden of persuasion in a clearer and fuller
way. Finally, we show that insincere rules can operate across enforcement
settings, not just in criminal law.
Stuntz studied “pathological politics.” The details of his argument are
beyond our scope, but here is a short summary. Legislators make more-
or-less everything a crime, and then prosecutors pick and choose whom
to prosecute among the law’s many offenders. Since more-or-less
everything is illegal, proving that any particular person has violated the
law—some law, whether minor or serious—is easy. The threat of
conviction induces guilty pleas from guilty and innocent offenders alike.
Prosecutors’ discretionary choices about enforcement determine the law
in action. Instead of legislators making law and judges adjudicating it,
prosecutors do all of the work. “Criminal law,” Stuntz wrote, is “not law
at all, but a veil that hides a system that allocates criminal punishment
discretionarily.”
131
We share Stuntz’s normative concerns with overcriminalization, and
we do not refute the descriptive accuracy of some of his claims.
Furthermore, we recognize that insincere rules could potentially
exacerbate discriminatory enforcement, as discussed above.
132
Nevertheless, we can extract insincere rules from Stuntz’s dark milieu.
Enforcement agents might exercise discretion judiciously. When they
do, insincere rules can improve rather than worsen the justice system. To
restate that point, insincere rules work especially well in systems without
discrimination in enforcement. Furthermore, our analysis pinpoints and
solves a tension in Stuntz’s analysis. He assumes the state cannot or does
not enforce crime ABC, while it can and does enforce AB—even though
AB should not be a crime. To make sense of this, Stuntz must assume that
the state overcorrects. If ABC is too costly to enforce, then AB is too
cheap. If this is what Stuntz has in mind, then the problem is not
131
Stuntz, supra note 14, at 599.
132
See supra Section III.E.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1161
insincerity per se but fine-tuning. The trick is to calibrate. Whenever
possible, the state should set the insincere rule so that the point at which
prosecutors find it worthwhile to enforce matches the point at which the
conduct becomes socially harmful. Perhaps because he focuses on the
binary case only, Stuntz does not consider this possibility.
F. Proxy Crimes
Proxy crimes are laws prohibiting behavior that is not itself harmful,
but that is associated with behavior that is harmful.
133
To give examples,
laws prohibiting open containers of alcohol in vehicles
134
and laws
prohibiting possession of burglar’s tools
135
are proxy crimes. These acts
are not harmful by themselves, but they correlate with the harmful acts of
drunk driving and burgling.
136
To analyze proxy crimes, we focus on the law forbidding open
containers of alcohol in vehicles. One way to understand this proxy crime
is as follows: the law always means what is says. It always forbids open
containers of alcohol in cars. That is what the rule-makers expect and
intend, on the theory that open containers very likely lead to harm. On
this understanding, “proxy crime” is just another term for a deliberately
over-inclusive or prophylactic rule. This kind of proxy crime differs from
insincere rules for the usual reasons: lawmakers want and expect
regulated parties to violate insincere rules. They do not want or expect
people to violate, to any degree, the prohibition on open containers in
vehicles.
There is another way to understand the proxy crime. Rule-makers do
not intend to forbid all open containers of alcohol in vehicles. In fact, they
do not care about open containers in general, they just want to forbid
drunk driving. They only expect officers to enforce the law against drunk
drivers. By eliminating some pesky elements (the vehicle was moving,
the driver was drunk), the proxy crime makes the proof process easier. On
133
See Frederick Schauer, Bentham on Presumed Offences, 23 Utilitas 363 (2011); see also
Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan, Reflections on Crime and Culpability: Problems
and Puzzles 83–92 (2018) (exploring the justifications for proxy crimes and concluding that
they “promote only mischief”); Richard H. McAdams, The Political Economy of Entrapment,
96 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 107, 156–64 (2005) (discussing how enforcement of proxy
crimes is geared towards prevention of crimes that have great social detriment).
134
McAdams, supra note 133, at 160–61.
135
Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan, Crime and Culpability: A Theory of
Criminal Law 309 (2009).
136
McAdams, supra note 133, at 160–61.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1162 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
this understanding, the “proxy crime” is something like a binary, multi-
element, insincere rule, á la Stuntz.
137
One contribution of this Article is to divide proxy crimes into two
concepts, one being conventional proxy crimes, and the other being
insincere rules. These different concepts are easily conflated, but we can
pull them apart.
Proxy crimes are often criticized for penalizing conduct that is not
blameworthy, like driving home sober with a stoppered bottle of wine.
Under the conventional conception of proxy crimes, this criticism is
inevitable. Conventional proxy crimes are deliberately over-inclusive.
But under the insincere conception of proxy crimes, this criticism is not
inevitable. If the law in action penalizes blameless conduct, the insincere
rule needs fine-tuning.
V. NORMATIVE IMPLICATIONS: COSTS, TRUTH, AND TRIALS
Insincere evidence reduces proof costs, thereby increasing the state’s
ability to punish lawbreaking, thereby improving compliance with law.
The strategy does not always work well. Remember those “good men”
and credulous enforcers? But it can work very well. And because of this,
we believe it could be common in practice.
Assuming it is used, is it laudable? Better compliance with law is a
good thing, but the way insincere evidence achieves better compliance
may raise some concerns. One involves prosecutorial discretion, which
we addressed above.
138
This Part addresses other normative concerns.
First, we consider whether the justifiability of insincere evidence depends
on the source of proof costs. Second, we consider whether insincere
evidence is too much of an affront to truth. Third, we consider whether
cost reduction is a sufficient justification for introducing insincerity into
legal standards. In every case, we argue that the categorical rejection of
insincere evidence is unwarranted.
137
Stuntz did not characterize his analysis as involving proxy crimes. In fact, he never used
the word “proxy” in his article. Others understand his analysis in terms of proxies. See
McAdams, supra note 74, at 524 (“In Stuntz’s terms, selling drugs outside undercover
operations is crime ABC, while selling drugs in undercover operations is DEF; we punish the
otherwise harmless behavior DEF because we think it is correlated with ABC. . . . [T]he
undercover offense usually does not prove an external offense beyond a reasonable doubt. Yet
that turns out to be perfectly ordinary under the proxy approach.”).
138
See supra Section IV.E.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1163
A. Are There Better Ways to Reduce Costs?
We have assumed that the costs of proof spring from straightforward
sources: officers have to testify, lawyers have to draft pleadings, and so
on. To some extent these costs are inevitable. They can, however, be
modulated by the state and other forces. This raises questions about what
kinds of proof costs the state should be permitted to offset with insincere
rules.
Suppose there are two kinds of proof costs: unavoidable costs and
avoidable costs. Putting officers on the stand and having lawyers draft
critical documents are unavoidable costs. Making officers wait for hours
at the courthouse and making lawyers draft formalistic and redundant
documents are avoidable costs. While both costs have the same effect—a
gap arises between the law in books and the law in action—the
appropriate strategy for responding to those costs might differ. Insincere
rules might be a justifiable only in response to unavoidable costs. In the
case of avoidable costs, we might prefer the state to improve the
enforcement process by shortening wait times and streamlining pleadings.
It should not simply enact a stricter rule.
We are sympathetic to this argument. The case for insincerity seems
weaker when proof costs can be mitigated in other, straightforward ways.
The point should not, however, be taken too far.
We have assumed, up to this point, that lawmakers act as benevolent
and informed shepherds motivated by the desire to improve efficiency and
social order under the law. This assumption—which we make in common
with nearly all of the law and economics literature on enforcement
139
largely obviates the source-of-cost issue. A benevolent lawmaker
optimizes all proof costs, not just those reachable by an insincere rule. Put
another way, we have assumed that lawmakers will only enact an
insincere rule if the benefits outweigh the costs. The benefits, in this
framework, will be low if the state can costlessly achieve the same results
through streamlined pleadings and better docketing. Conversely, if these
reforms are themselves costly to implement, the argument against
insincere rules becomes less compelling. The seemingly sharp distinction
between avoidable and unavoidable costs can thus be seen as simply
139
See, e.g., Garoupa & Klerman, supra note 33, at 116 (“Previous analyses [in the law and
economics literature on enforcement] have assumed that the government aimed to maximize
social welfare.”); id. at 117 (“In the law enforcement literature, the optimal policy is usually
derived by maximizing social welfare, which is assumed to be the government’s objective
function.”).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1164 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
another part of the cost-benefit analysis surrounding the adoption of an
insincere rule.
B. Is This an Affront to Truth?
Another potential concern is that the production of insincere evidence
rests on the introduction of systematic falsehoods into law. The strategy
reduces proof costs by substituting a disingenuous fact-finding exercise
for the genuine questions around which trial would otherwise revolve.
Rather than proving the fact of the sincere infraction (whether the
defendant violated the speed limit by 1 mph), trial is made to focus on the
insincere infraction (whether the defendant violated the speed limit by 11
mph). This is in more than a little tension with a core legal value: truth.
It is often said that trials are about nothing but the search for truth. This
applies equally to the institution of trial
140
and the rules that govern it.
141
At its most extreme, the Supreme Court has said that “[t]he fundamental
basis upon which all rules of evidence must rest—if they are to rest upon
reason—is their adaptation to the successful development of the truth.”
142
In a similar vein, it has referred to the “very nature” of trial as “a search
for truth.”
143
140
See David W. Peck, The Complement of Court and Counsel 9 (1954) (“The object of a
lawsuit is to get at the truth and arrive at the right result. That is the sole objective of the judge,
and counsel should never lose sight of that objective in thinking that the end purpose is to win
for his side.”); Marvin E. Frankel, Search for Truth: An Umpireal View, 123 U. Pa. L. Rev.
1031, 1033 (1975) (“Trials occur because there are questions of fact. In principle, the
paramount objective is the truth.”); Charles R. Nesson, Incentives to Spoliate Evidence in
Civil Litigation: The Need for Vigorous Judicial Action, 13 Cardozo L. Rev. 793, 793 (1991)
(describing “the ideal of the trial as a search for truth”); Robert S. Summers, Formal Legal
Truth and Substantive Truth in Judicial Fact-Finding–Their Justified Divergence in Some
Particular Cases, 18 Law & Phil. 497, 497 (1999) (“Some natural scientists, some social
scientists, some philosophers, and many others regularly assume that truth finding is the only
important function of trial court procedures and the rules of evidence.”).
141
See Chris William Sanchirico, Evidence Tampering, 53 Duke L.J. 1215, 1220 (2004)
(“Most analyses of evidence law take litigation’s prime object to be the discovery of truth
about past events.”); William Twining, Evidence and Legal Theory, 47 Mod. L. Rev. 261, 272
(1984) (“There is undoubtedly a dominant underlying theory of evidence in adjudication, in
which the central notions are truth, reason and justice under the law.”); Jack B. Weinstein,
supra note 66, at 246 (“In case of conflict, the court’s truth-finding function should receive
primary emphasis except when a constitutional limitation requires subservience to some
extrinsic public policy.”).
142
Funk v. United States, 290 U.S. 371, 381 (1933).
143
Nix v. Whiteside, 475 U.S. 157, 166 (1986); see also id. at 174 (describing the lawyer as
an “officer of the court and a key component of a system of justice, dedicated to a search for
truth(emphasis added)); Lloyd v. Am. Exp. Lines, Inc., 580 F.2d 1179, 1186 (3d Cir. 1978)
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1165
This may seem problematic for insincere rules. It is odd to think that a
system so focused on truth may be improved through the introduction of
falsehoods. But the situation is not so black and white.
First, even if trials were exclusively devoted to the search for truth, it
would not necessarily follow that insincere evidence would be counter to
this goal. The truth of what has happened is sought the same under either
a sincere rule or an insincere rule. In the driving example, the state seeks
to prove that a driver was going 56 mph (a truth in the world) regardless
of the sincerity or insincerity of the law. All that differs between the
sincere and insincere rule is the legal standard to which this behavior is
compared.
Second, there are reasons to question just how immutable truth-seeking
really is. There are philosophic reasons to doubt whether trials ever
uncover truth in an absolute sense of the term.
144
Litigants do not typically
have duties, or even incentives, to develop fully truthful records at trial.
145
Reasonable arguments can be made that fact-finding is basically a
functional concept: “legal truth,” as opposed to a substantive or platonic
truth.
146
This creates space for legal truths defined relative to insincere
rules.
Third, the rules of evidence and procedure already include many
examples of laws that frustrate truth-seeking. The most obvious is the
requirement of proof beyond a reasonable doubt in criminal cases. This
(“Any fact-finding process is ultimately a search for truth and justice, and legal precepts that
govern the reception of evidence must always be interpreted in light of this.”).
144
See generally Jerome Frank, Courts on Trial: Myth and Reality in American Justice 80–
102 (First Princeton Paperback ed. 1973) (critiquing the notion that the adversarial process
leads to the general discovery of truth); Sean P. Sullivan, Challenges for Comparative Fact-
Finding, 23 Int’l J. Evid. & Proof 100 (2019) (questioning when, if ever, a proposition of fact
could be proven true by any empirical method).
145
See Frank, supra note 144, at 81–89 (illustrating ways in which trial attorneys are
incentivized to conceal, rather than develop truthful testimony); Frankel, supra note 140, at
1032 (“My theme, to be elaborated at some length, is that our adversary system rates truth too
low among the values that institutions of justice are meant to serve.”). This is not to say that
proposals to address this have not been voiced. See id. at 1052–59 (proposing reform efforts
that would impose such duties). To date, however, there seems to be little movement toward
such an overhaul of the adversarial system.
146
See Summers, supra note 140, at 498 (“I define as ‘formal legal truth’ whatever is found
as fact by the legal fact-finder (judge or lay jurors or both), whether it accords with substantive
truth or not.”); cf. Edmund Morris Morgan, Some Problems of Proof Under the Anglo-
American System of Litigation 128 (1956) (“[T]he trial is a proceeding not for the discovery
of truth as such, but for the establishment of a basis of fact for the adjustment of a dispute
between litigants. Still it must never be forgotten that its prime objective is to have that basis
as close an approximation to the truth as is practicable.”).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1166 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
standard is manifestly not facilitating truth-seeking.
147
It is aimed at an
important collateral objective: reducing the chances of wrongful
conviction when the stakes are high.
148
The reasonable doubt standard is
a prominent illustration, but it is hardly the only example.
Trials and evidence law serve many objectives,
149
and sometimes these
outweigh truth-seeking.
150
One example is the exclusion of relevant
evidence in order to incentivize desired behavior. Thus, subsequent
remedial measures are inadmissible to prove negligence in order to
incentivize the rapid remedy of potentially dangerous conditions.
151
Offers to pay medical expenses are inadmissible to show liability for an
injury in order to encourage the early payment of these expenses.
152
Exclusionary rules concerning statements made in settlement talks and
plea discussions prohibit the introduction of potentially damning
admissions in order to facilitate and encourage the settlement of
disputes.
153
Privileges are to the same effect. The attorney-client privilege
frustrates the discovery of truth in order to facilitate open communications
147
Frankel, supra note 140, at 1037 (“[I]n the last analysis truth is not the only goal. . . .
[T]he question is not at all ‘guilt or innocence,’ but only whether guilt has been shown beyond
a reasonable doubt.”); Weinstein, supra note 66, at 236 (describing requirements such as proof
beyond a reasonable doubt as “conscious distortions in the fact-finding process”).
148
See, e.g., In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 372 (1970) (Harlan, J., concurring) (“I view the
requirement of proof beyond a reasonable doubt in a criminal case as bottomed on a
fundamental value determination of our society that it is far worse to convict an innocent man
than to let a guilty man go free.”).
149
Summers, supra note 140, at 499–500 (“[T]rial court procedures and the rules of
evidence, though generally directed at substantive truth, are also designed to serve other ends
that actually come into play in a particular case.”); Weinstein, supra note 66, at 241 (“Even
were it theoretically possible to ascertain truth with a fair degree of certainty, it is doubtful
whether the judicial system and rules of evidence would be designed to do so. Trials in our
judicial system are intended to do more than merely determine what happened.”).
150
Monroe H. Freedman, Judge Frankel’s Search for Truth, 123 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1060, 1065
(1975) (“[I]n a society that respects the dignity of the individual, truth-seeking cannot be an
absolute value, but may be subordinated to other ends, although that subordination may
sometimes result in the distortion of the truth.” (footnote omitted)); Weinstein, supra note 66,
at 236 (“The law mandates many conscious distortions in the fact-finding process in order to
gain some supposed social advantage.”).
151
Fed. R. Evid. 407.
152
Fed. R. Evid. 409.
153
Fed. R. Evid. 408 (concerning compromise negotiations); Fed. R. Evid. 410 (concerning
plea discussions).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1167
by a person seeking legal counsel.
154
The doctor-patient privilege,
155
the
priest-penitent privilege,
156
the marital confidence privilege,
157
and the
spousal testimonial privilege
158
all incentivize some form of behavior or
communication that is deemed sufficiently beneficial to warrant distorting
the discovery of truth.
Other privileges and exclusionary rules operate in reverse:
manipulating the proof process to disincentivize socially undesirable
behavior. Rule 37 of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure gives judges
flexibility to declare certain facts “true” or “false” as a way of penalizing
and thus deterring failures to comply with discovery orders.
159
In criminal
prosecutions, similar reasoning applies to the exclusion of evidence
obtained without a warrant, without a proper Miranda warning, or subject
to other procedural defects.
160
These rules frustrate the discovery of truth
in order to deter police misconduct.
154
See generally 1 McCormick on Evidence §§ 87–97 (Kenneth S. Broun ed., 7th ed. 2013)
(discussing the history, justifications, and scope of the attorney-client privilege in evidence
law).
155
See generally id. §§ 98–105 (discussing the history, justifications, and scope of the
physician-patient confidentiality).
156
See Trammel v. United States, 445 U.S. 40, 51 (1980) (“The priest-penitent privilege
recognizes the human need to disclose to a spiritual counselor, in total and absolute
confidence, what are believed to be flawed acts or thoughts and to receive priestly consolation
and guidance in return.”).
157
See generally Mikah K. Story, Twenty-First Century Pillow-Talk: Applicability of the
Marital Communications Privilege to Electronic Mail, 58 S.C. L. Rev. 275, 277–82 (2006)
(discussing the history and future of the marital communications privilege).
158
See generally R. Michael Cassidy, Reconsidering Spousal Privileges After Crawford, 33
Am. J. Crim. L. 339, 355–64 (2006) (discussing the origins, purposes, and evolution of the
spousal testimonial privilege).
159
See Fed. R. Civ. P. 37(b)(1)(A) (“If a party . . . fails to obey an order to provide or permit
discovery, . . . the court where the action is pending may issue further just orders. They may
include the following: (i) directing that the matters embraced in the order or other designated
facts be taken as established for purposes of the action, as the prevailing party claims; (ii)
prohibiting the disobedient party from supporting or opposing designated claims or defenses,
or from introducing designated matters in evidence . . . .”).
160
See, e.g., Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436, 444 (1966) (“[T]he prosecution may not use
statements, whether exculpatory or inculpatory, stemming from custodial interrogation of the
defendant unless it demonstrates the use of procedural safeguards effective to secure the
privilege against self-incrimination.”); Escobedo v. Illinois, 378 U.S. 478, 491 (1964) (holding
that evidence is excluded when obtained by a violation of the constitutional right to
representation); Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S. 643, 659–60 (1961) (finding the need to exclude ill-
gotten evidence incorporated against the states).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1168 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
The implications for insincere evidence are transparent. To the extent
that the behavioral benefits are sufficiently important, there is ample and
accepted precedent for frustrating truth to achieve that end.
C. Is Cost Reduction Enough?
A response to the previous argument might be that while truth-seeking
is sometimes frustrated to achieve important social ends, it isn’t clear that
cost reduction constitutes an important social end. Insincerity about the
actual normative content of law simply to economize on legal expenses is
unseemly.
Is it? Substantive laws often aim to encourage or deter certain
behaviors.
161
That effort is futile if the proof process gets in the way.
162
If
the proof needed to establish a violation of law were always prohibitively
costly, then the substantive law would never achieve its aim.
163
Even if
proof costs were only sometimes prohibitively costly, it would make
sense for lawmakers to try to reduce these frictions.
164
If the cost-reducing
effects of insincere evidence improves compliance with law, then—far
from unseemly—the use of insincerity serves the same laudatory ends as
the substantive law itself.
165
161
See Sanchirico, supra note 141, at 1220 (“When it comes to analyses of the ‘substantive
law,’ the idea that legal rules set incentives for everyday behavior—incentives to perform as
contracted, to disclose accurate financial information, to take reasonable precaution, to adopt
a safe product design, to eschew physical violence—occupies a central position.”).
162
See Summers, supra note 140, at 497–98 (“[W]ithout findings of fact that generally
accord with truth, the underlying policy goals or norms of the law could not be served. For
example, a rule designed to secure safety on the highways by setting a speed limit of 70 mph
and by punishing those who exceed it can not effectively serve its purpose if fact finders fail
to find the true facts as to the speed of actual offenders and so let speeders go free of penalty.”).
163
Weinstein, supra note 66, at 242 (“A system for determining issues of fact very accurately
in all tribunals might permit a few adjudications a year of almost impeccable precision. But
the resulting inability of the courts to have time to adjudicate the thousands of other pending
litigations would mean that justice would be frustrated; people could flout the substantive law
with relative impunity, knowing that the likelihood of being brought to trial was remote; and
plaintiffs would be forced to avoid litigation because of its extraordinary expense and delay.”).
164
See Chris William Sanchirico & George Triantis, Evidentiary Arbitrage: The Fabrication
of Evidence and the Verifiability of Contract Performance, 24 J.L. Econ. & Org. 72, 72 (2008)
(“The design of legal obligations, whether by a public body such as a legislature or by private
contract, should anticipate the enforcement process that induces compliance.”); see also id. at
73 (“Anticipating the judicial resolution of future disputes, contracting parties are likely to be
interested in the likelihood or cost of judicial truth-finding only to the extent that the court’s
ability to discern the truth efficiently improves contract incentives and the gains from trade.”).
165
Weinstein comes close to making this exact point. Weinstein, supra note 66, at 243
(“Unless we are to assume that the substantive law is perverse or irrelevant to the public
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1169
In fact, this concern may be close to a strawman. Including cost
considerations among the social concerns of the legal system is not a new
proposition.
166
Alongside the discovery of truth, the Federal Rules of
Evidence list the elimination of “unjustifiable expense and delay” as one
of their core objectives.
167
The same phrase appears in the Federal Rules
of Criminal Procedure.
168
The Federal Rules of Civil Procedure provide
that they are to be construed “to secure the just, speedy, and inexpensive
determination of every action and proceeding.”
169
Practicality has never
compelled that cost considerations be ignored in promulgation of laws or
the structure of the legal process.
And if proof costs are included in the balancing of social interests
served by laws and the litigation system, then we are back to the same
cost-benefit analysis. So long as the benefits of insincere evidence
outweigh the costs, the frustration of truth is justifiable. An English court
made essentially this same observation nearly 200 years ago:
The discovery and vindication and establishment of truth are main
purposes certainly of the existence of Courts of Justice; still, [these
objectives,] however valuable and important, cannot be usefully
pursued without moderation . . . . Truth, like all other good things, may
be loved unwisely—may be pursued too keenly—may cost too much.
170
VI. CONCLUSION
In this Article, we have analyzed the ability of insincere evidence to
reduce proof costs. We have connected this effect to burdens of
persuasion and other legal concepts. We have also considered various
welfare, then its enforcement is properly the primary aim of litigation; and the substantive law
can be best enforced if litigation results in accurate determinations of facts made material by
the applicable rule of law.”). Here, however, it is not the accurate determination of facts, but
the cost of doing so, that determines the degree to which the litigation process will achieve the
substantive objectives of law.
166
See id. at 241 (stating that other objectives of the evidence system include “economizing
of resources, inspiring confidence, supporting independent social policies, permitting ease in
prediction and application, adding to the efficiency of the entire legal system, and tranquilizing
disputants”).
167
Fed. R. Evid. 102; see also Fed. R. Evid. 403 (including “undue delay” and “wasting
time” among the balancing factors on which a judge may exclude an otherwise relevant item
of evidence).
168
Fed. R. Crim. P. 2 (“These rules are to be interpreted to provide for the just determination
of every criminal proceeding . . . and to eliminate unjustifiable expense and delay.”).
169
Fed. R. Civ. P. 1 (emphasis added).
170
Pearse v. Pearse (1846) 63 Eng. Rep. 950, 957; 1 De G. & Sm. 11, 28–29.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1170 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
qualifications to the effectiveness and desirability of insincere evidence.
Rather than summarizing that work, we conclude by sketching some open
questions and pathways for future research.
For one thing, insincere lawmaking complicates the notion of
legislative intent.
171
To reduce proof costs through insincerity, legislators
must drive a wedge between what they consider to be socially optimal
behavior for society (their sincere intent) and what they publicly say to
better effect outcomes (insincerity in the text of a statute and, possibly, in
the legislative history that accompanies it). The idea that legislators would
bluster during floor debates is not shocking, but the idea that they might
exaggerate their sincere preferences in the substance of law is less
familiar. The more one thinks insincere lawmaking occurs in practice, the
less compelling it becomes to equate legislative intent with traditional
sources like statutory text and legislative history.
The same tensions are magnified when agencies need to justify
exercises of their rulemaking authority. Under the Administrative
Procedure Act, as part of the rulemaking process, an agency must produce
“a concise general statement of [the] basis and purpose [of the adopted
rule].”
172
While this statement need not be exhaustive, the expectation is
that it will indicate the policy questions at issue as well as the agency’s
reason for choosing its rule.
173
Judges often focus on this explanatory
statement in deciding whether agency action should be set aside as
arbitrary and capricious.
174
Though deferential, that review is not
toothless.
175
Again, the use of insincerity complicates matters. Suppose,
for example, that a regulatory agency faced the speed limit problem we
have discussed. The need to explain itself would seem like an obstacle to
171
Of course, legislative intent is already complicated. See, e.g., Kenneth A. Shepsle,
Congress Is a “They,” Not an “It”: Legislative Intent as Oxymoron, 12 Int’l Rev. L. & Econ.
239 (1992).
172
Administrative Procedure Act, 5 U.S.C. § 553(c) (2012).
173
See, e.g., Indep. U.S. Tanker Owners Comm. v. Dole, 809 F.2d 847, 852 (D.C. Cir. 1987)
(“[S]uch a statement should indicate the major issues of policy that were raised in the
proceedings and explain why the agency decided to respond to these issues as it did,
particularly in light of the statutory objectives that the rule must serve.”).
174
Administrative Procedure Act, 5 U.S.C. § 706(2)(A) (2012) (requiring a reviewing court
to “hold unlawful and set aside agency action . . . found to be . . . arbitrary, capricious, an
abuse of discretion, or otherwise not in accordance with law”).
175
See Motor Vehicle Mfrs. Ass’n v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 463 U.S. 29, 43 (1983)
(endorsing fairly exacting hard look review of agency rulemaking); Citizens to Pres. Overton
Park, Inc. v. Volpe, 401 U.S. 402, 415 (1971) (explaining that a presumption of regularity “is
not to shield [agency] action from a thorough, probing, in-depth review”).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1171
using an insincere rule. Can the agency say to a court that it intentionally
adopted a too-strict rule to improve enforcement? Maybe not. On the
other hand, if the point of delegation to the agency was to achieve a given
enforcement outcome, and if the agency better achieves that outcome with
an insincere rule, then invalidation of the rule by the reviewing court
would undermine the intent of the legislature in empowering the agency
in the first place.
Before concluding, we should say something about the rule of law.
That divine, contested concept lurks in the background of every page.
176
One might wonder whether insincerity undermines the rule of law,
especially its accessibility. Law, the argument goes, must be publicized
and intelligible so that people can understand it.
177
To the extent that
insincere rules are adequately publicized, we do not see an obvious
tension. But perhaps they cut against accessibility. Perhaps when
deployed by judges, insincere rules could cut against norms of candor.
178
We do not work through these questions here.
We will, however, address a point about the perception of the rule of
law. That perception, one might argue, would suffer if people discover
the state to be deliberately misrepresenting its desired behavior. We are
not sure this is right. Perception of the rule of law probably depends on
both the law in books and the law in action. If people perceive the law in
books to be too harsh, perceptions may suffer. But if people perceive the
law in action to be about right, perceptions may improve. Insincere rules
have both effects. How the scales of perception balance is yet unknown.
176
See Brian Z. Tamanaha, On the Rule of Law: History, Politics, Theory 3–4 (2004)
(noting widespread support for the “rule of law,” but also substantial ambiguity and even
disagreement about what exactly this concept entails); Jeremy Waldron, The Rule of Law,
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (June 22, 2016), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rule-
of-law/ [https://perma.cc/GNX2-P2LH] (surveying disagreements about the desirability and
definition of rule of law under the headings of “The Contestedness of the Rule of Law,”
“Opposition to the Rule of Law,” and “Controversies about Application”).
177
See, e.g., Paul Gowder, The Rule of Law and Equity, 32 Law & Phil. 565, 582–85 (2013)
(discussing publicity of law as one uncontroversial aspect of rule of law concepts); Waldron,
supra note 176, § 2 (“[L]aw should be epistemically accessible: it should be a body of norms
promulgated as public knowledge so that people can study it, internalize it, figure out what it
requires of them, and use it as a framework for their plans and expectations and for settling
their disputes with others.”).
178
Cf. Micah Schwartzman, Judicial Sincerity, 94 Va. L. Rev. 987 (2008) (arguing for the
importance of sincerity and candor in judicial opinions).
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1172 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
TECHNICAL APPENDIX
The main text of this Article provides an intuitive explanation of our
theory of insincere evidence. Here, we extend that theory with a modest
formalization. The only unusual aspect of this model is its reliance on
likelihood concepts instead of posterior probabilities. One of us (Sullivan)
has elaborated elsewhere on the superiority of likelihood analysis as a
model of legal persuasion.
179
Among other things, our reliance on
likelihoods allows this model to avoid the always awkward problem of
specifying the prior distribution of violations in the population.
180
Suppose the state seeks to regulate some privately beneficial but
socially costly activity. Let
$ % &
be the level of activity a given
individual chooses to undertake. All else equal, this person prefers higher
levels of
$
. Let
' % &
be the legal limit that state lawmakers have adopted
for this activity. Activity levels
$ ( '
are illegal and subject to
punishment by the state.
Suppose that state agents can perfectly observe a person’s choice of
$
,
but cannot credibly disclose this information to the tribunal. Perhaps the
agents cannot credibly disclose their knowledge because the fact-finder
correctly predicts that they would exaggerate the extent of the observed
violation if given the chance. Instead, the state is limited to proving a
violation of law by objective evidence—a noisy signal of the actual
activity level. For sake of clarity, assume that the combined weight of the
objective evidence is distributed according to a normal distribution,
centered on the true activity level, and dispersed according to an
exogenous noise parameter,
) ( *
, such that the evidence draw in a given
case is
+,-.$/ )01
.
181
Agents of the state do not draw from the evidence
distribution until after the costs of trial have already been borne.
182
179
Sullivan, supra note 60.
180
Cf. Davis, supra note 66 (noting the complexities that population distributions (i.e., prior
probabilities) have in a probability-based model of the trial process).
181
The following generalizes in an obvious way to other evidence distributions.
182
This setup is an easy way to think about the situation, but it is not the only way to
understand the model. Alternatively, the regulator could be understood as having no direct
ability to observe
$
, but instead having access to an unbiased signal of
$
. Subject to some
complications around the possible communication of asymmetric information by the
individual, results in this alternative specification of the model seem much the same as in the
above specification. Another approach would be to interpret the state as having access to all
available evidence of the regulated party’s activity level, but subject to uncertainty about how
the fact-finder will weigh this evidence at trial. Again, this approach would seem to result in
largely the same model as the above specification.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1173
Violations of law are established by producing enough evidence to
convince the fact finder that
$ ( '
by the applicable burden of persuasion.
While it might seem natural to model this persuasion process in terms of
the posterior distribution
2.$3+1
, this would require us to assume a prior
distribution
2.$1
, which we do not do. Instead, we model the proof
process via likelihood reasoning. Intuitively, the likelihood approach
involves an iterative comparison of pairwise likelihood-ratio tests in order
to determine whether
$ ( '
has been established. The end result is that
proof of
$ ( '
under any given burden of persuasion requires an evidence
draw,
+
, such that the following condition is met:
456
789: ;.+3$</ ) 01
456
78=: ;.+3$</ )01( >/
where
;.+3$</ ) 01
is the probability density of the normal distribution,
evaluated at the observed evidence draw, under the assumed centrality
parameter,
$<
. The
>
term in this likelihood ratio is a numeric
representation of the applicable burden of persuasion. Sullivan has argued
that
> ? @
corresponds to preponderance of the evidence; that something
like
@ A > A @*
represents clear-and-convincing evidence; and that
something like
> ( @*
represents proof beyond a reasonable doubt.
183
In the case of evidence draws distributed according to the normal
distribution, it can be shown that the above general condition for proof of
$ ( '
by any arbitrary burden of persuasion requires an evidence draw,
+
, such that
+ ( ' B
C
D)0EFG >/
with all variables as defined above.
184
At the point where
$
is known but
+
is not known, then for a given choice of legal limit,
'
, and for given
183
Sullivan, supra note 60, at 26–37.
184
Here is an informal proof. Since
> H @
in every interesting application, a necessary
condition for the state to win at trial is
+ ( 'I
For the preponderance of the evidence standard,
this condition is both necessary and sufficient. For higher burdens of persuasion, assuming
+ ( '
, the maximum likelihood estimator of
$
is simply
+
, and the constrained maximum
likelihood estimator on the assumption that
$
J '
is simply
'
. As such, sufficient evidence
of violation has been produced whenever
;
.
+
3
+/ )0
1
( ;
.
+
3
'/ )0
1
K >
. Simplifying and
solving this expression for
+
leads to the stated condition.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
1174 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1115
levels of the burden of persuasion,
>
, and noise parameter,
)
, the
probability of successfully proving a violation of law for activity level
$
is
2
.
$/ '/ >
1
? @ L M
N
' B
C
D)0EFG >
O
$/ )0
P
/
with
M
.
Q
3
$/ )0
1 the normal cumulative distribution function.
With this definition of the probability of
2
.
$/ '/ >
1, we can
operationalize the remainder of the model. While we would ideally focus
on the state’s optimal choice of legal limit and enforcement strategy, the
assumptions needed to do so are more than we wish to defend at this
point.
185
To obtain tractable results without limiting our approach, we
characterize how the choice of
'
affects the necessary condition for non-
strategic enforcement of laws.
A necessary condition for the rational enforcement of any law is that
the expected marginal cost of attempting to prove a violation of law
should not outweigh the expected marginal benefit. Formalizing this
necessary condition requires only modest assumptions. Specifically, we
assume the existence of a known functional form for the cost of trying to
prove a violation of law:
R
.
$/ '
1
( *
. We also assume a known functional
form for the benefit of successfully proving a violation of law by any
given choice of activity level. This is a reduced-form expression for
whatever benefit society gets from the (unmodeled) marginal deterrence
arising from successful punishment of a given level of violation:
S.$/ '1
.
Combining these terms with the probability of successful proof at trial,
the necessary condition for the state to attempt to prove a violation of law
is
S
.
$/ '
1
K 2
.
$/ '/ >
1
( R
.
$/ '
1
I
185
For example, these assumptions would include precise specification of the welfare
implications of different choices of
'
; specification of individuals’ exact preferences over all
possible combinations of activity level, penalty, and probability of incurring a penalty,
including any variation in this preference, in risk tolerance, or in strategic type; and
specification of the game-theoretic equilibrium strategies individuals adopt in deciding when
to violate laws, and that both individuals and the state adopt in deciding when to litigate
disputed violations of law.
COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION
2019] Insincere Evidence 1175
As we explain in the Article, this necessary condition is more
conveniently illustrated with the probability term on the cost side of the
inequality:
S
.
$/ '
1
(R.$/ '1
2.$/ '/ >1I