ArticlePDF Available

Sharing conservation burdens fairly

Wiley
Conservation Biology
Authors:

Abstract

We examined how, from the point of view of justice, the burdens of paying for conservation should be shared. I resisted simple answers to the question of who should pay for conservation that lean on a single moral principle. I identified 3 relevant principles that relate to who causes conservation challenges, who has greater capacity to carry burdens, and who stands to benefit from conservation. I argue for a distinctive pluralist framework for allocating conservation burdens that grants a proper role to all 3 principles. A multistep process can be used to put the framework into practice. First, identify cases in which conservation is necessary. Second, consider whether people knew or could have been expected to anticipate the consequences of their activities and whether they had reasonable alternatives to acting the way they did. Third, turn to facts about benefits; when no culprit for conservation challenges can be found, ask who benefits from acts of conservation. In the second and third stages, consideration must also be given to ability to pay.
Sharing Conservation Burdens Fairly
Forthcoming in Conservation Biology (2018)
Chris Armstrong
Department of Politics and International Relations
University of Southampton
Keywords: Conservation justice, distributive justice, ability to pay, contribution to the
problem, benefits, a pluralist account
1
Abstract
We examined how, from the point of view of justice, the burdens of paying for conservation
should be shared. I resisted simple answers to the question of who should pay for
conservation that lean on a single moral principle. I identified 3 relevant principles that relate
to who causes conservation challenges, who has greater capacity to carry burdens, and who
stands to benefit from conservation. I argue for a distinctive pluralist framework for
allocating conservation burdens that grants a proper role to all three principles, and describe a
multistep process for putting the framework into practice.
2
Introduction
Article 6 of the 1972 World Heritage Convention states that the natural world “constitutes a
world heritage for whose protection it is the duty of the international community as a whole
to co-operate.” That is an admirable ideal. But international schemes to pool conservation
costs are chronically underfunded (Balmford & Whitten 2003; Bruner et al 2004). In the
absence of adequate international financing, the citizens of each state are required to pay to
conserve the resources within their borders. This is regardless of their ability to meet those
costs and the fact that conservation often delivers significant benefits to outsiders. This
situation leaves many poor communities facing a tragic choice between conservation and
economic development, and conservation often takes a back seat (Sanderson & Redford
2003). At the same time, the protection of precious resources that fall outside the borders of
any state – such as those of the High Seas – often ends up being nobody’s responsibility.
Improving the international allocation of conservation costs should therefore be an
urgent priority for anyone interested in either conservation or global justice. One important
political question concerns the mechanisms that would allow humanity to make concrete
progress toward a fairer allocation of the costs of conservation. But even if that problem
could be solved, more precise moral guidance on where the costs of conservation should fall
would also be required. It is objectionable to leave conservation costs to poor communities
(Sanderson & Redford 2003). But what would a fair distribution of burdens look like?
An account of distributive justice may help identify the best moral principles for
sharing benefits and burdens (Kymlicka 2002). Elsewhere, I set out a general theory of
natural resource justice that can help guide answers to this question (Armstrong 2017). I
argue that the benefits and burdens flowing from the world’s natural resources – including the
burdens of conservation – should be shared in such a way as to reduce, rather than deepen,
global inequalities. Rather than describing this theory, here I sought to provide a diagnostic
framework for assessing how to allocate conservation costs. In practice, conservation can be
3
complex, involving overlapping challenges and multiple actors, and the effects of one’s
actions may be quite uncertain. Applying the framework to specific cases requires one to
navigate complex questions about, for instance, agents’ capacity to bear costs and their causal
contribution to ecosystem damage. Although engaging with such complexities is not easy,
being clear about the underlying principles is nevertheless essential if conservation burdens
are to be allocated fairly. I developed the framework to clarify the principles that are relevant
to sharing conservation costs and a multistep procedure for integrating them.
A clear ethical framework is important for several reasons. First, it is important for
conservation practitioners and policy makers to be clear about the ethical underpinnings of
their policies so they can make responsible decisions (Mitrani et al 2018). This requires an
informed position on the fair distribution of conservation costs. Second, cooperation with
conservation efforts is likely to be higher if it is believed that the costs of those efforts are
being shared fairly. By contrast, burdening those who can ill afford, and do not deserve, to
bear costs diminishes cooperation with vital conservation efforts. Clarity about the best
moral principles for sharing costs is therefore required. Third, those who may be prepared to
fund conservation efforts should understand the precise nature and source of their ethical
obligations. The fact that international conservation programs are chronically underfunded
often reflects a view that participation in financing these schemes is morally optional. I
considered reasons for resisting this idea. There are good grounds, in fact, for believing that
greater international sharing of conservation costs is required by justice.
Allocating Conservation Costs
Conservation is a broad category which can encompass several different types of action or
inaction (Del Corral 2015). It can involve protecting something – such as a precious resource
- from a threat which would destroy or degrade it. It can involve repairing the damage done
when some such threat comes to fruition. And, it can involve simply refraining from
4
interfering with some resource, so that it can continue to perform its function within an
ecosystem. All these varieties of conservation will lead to someone somewhere incurring
costs, whether financial or otherwise. Acts of protection and restoration – such as restoring
the balance of ecosystems or nurturing threatened species back to sustainability – sometimes
threaten to monopolize society’s attention. But often the most important thing to do with
regards to some precious ecosystem is to leave it alone. Here too someone may incur a kind
of cost: the opportunity cost involved in refraining from taking up economic opportunities
that would otherwise be open to them. These opportunity costs are sometimes marginalised in
analyses of the costs of conservation, which often focus on the direct costs of implementing
conservation schemes. But in many real-world cases opportunity costs are an absolutely
central issue, not least in a context where much of the world’s biodiversity is located in
tropical regions that are also home to endemic poverty. Our biggest international challenge, in
many cases, is how the poor’s right to develop can be protected alongside the achievement of
effective conservation (Rosales 2008).
I considered key features of the status quo – according to which conservation costs
tend to fall on locals, if they are picked up at all - and assessed why the status quo is not just.
I propose that 3 principles play a role in guiding the allocation of conservation costs.: These
focus respectively on an agent or group of agents’ contribution to threats or damage to natural
resources; their capacity to bear costs; and the degree to which they benefit from
conservation. Advancing conservation justice means giving appropriate weight to each of
these principles. I considered how they can be integrated together to provide guidance on the
fair sharing of costs.
Why justice requires the international sharing of conservation costs
At present rates of decline, the world’s gorilla populations are seriously threatened with
extinction. The Eastern Lowland Gorilla (Gorilla beringei graueri), for instance, is critically
5
endangered; there are probably no more than 10,000 individuals living (Strindberg et al
2018). An estimated 80% of the world’s population of gorillas lives in the Democratic
Republic of the Congo, a country blighted by poverty and a legacy of civil unrest (Walsh et al
2003). If the species is to be protected and populations restored, there will be significant costs
attached. Illegal poaching must be prevented (at considerable financial cost) and habitat loss
slowed (with an opportunity cost for those who would otherwise benefit from deforestation).
But who, if anyone, should pay? Internationally, it is frequently declared that the habitat of
these gorillas must be protected. The world’s most precious natural resources have
increasingly been designated as being the “common concern of humankind,” even if they fall
within one nation’s borders (Baslar 1998). There are even a number of efforts, led by
international nongovernmental organisations, to share in the costs of protecting them. But
these efforts remain the exception rather than the norm. For the most part, it is left to locals to
pick up the costs. This is especially likely to be the case when it comes to the opportunity
costs associated with conservation (Bamford & Whitten 2003). If locals do not carry the
burdens associated with conservation, then no one will.
This practice of letting costs fall where they fall, however, generates considerable
injustice. It is not actually clear why the mere fact of geographical proximity, by itself, should
be considered relevant to the allocation of costs at all. Is there not a certain arbitrariness in
asking those who happen to live near a particular ecosystem to bear the costs of protecting it,
regardless of whether they are actually the agents responsible for endangering it in the first
place, for instance? It might be argued, in response, that even if geographical proximity in
and of itself is not morally important, there is a sound pragmatic case for leaving each nation-
state to pay the costs of conserving domestic resources. Recent developments in international
law have increased the emphasis placed on states’ duties toward natural resources, including
duties of sustainable use (Schrijver 1997). If each state is capable of funding effective
conservation, then, it might be argued, international sharing does not appear to be required.
6
One problem with such a pragmatic, state-led approach is that it would not actually
cover a range of important conservation challenges. In areas such as the High Seas,
Antarctica, and parts of the high Arctic, there is simply no local nation-state to depend upon.
Conservation must by definition, therefore, be an international effort. In cases where
migratory species that regularly cross national borders need conservation, moreover, some
kind of international coordination will be required (Mancilla 2016), and this will plausibly
involve some form of cost-sharing. In all these cases, principles for international cost-sharing
are needed.
But even in cases where precious resources fall neatly within nation-states, allowing
the inhabitants of each state to pick up the tab for conservation is surprisingly difficult to
defend. There are, I argue, 3 considerations that are morally relevant when it comes to
allocating conservation costs. But none of them has anything to do with geographical location
or national membership as such. First, who, if anyone, has caused a threat to a resource or a
species such that it requires conservation. Contribution to threats will often be morally
relevant when conservation costs are allocated. But threats to resources or ecosystems will
often arise from activities that take place outside of a nation’s borders or from activities (such
as greenhouse gas emissions) that have a truly global impact.
Second, what are the capacities of different communities to bear costs without
undergoing excessive sacrifices? The capacity to bear costs varies widely between
communities, and leaving local communities to bear conservation costs will require sacrifices
that some of them can ill afford. The Democratic Republic of the Congo, for instance, is
described by the United Nations as one of the world’s least developed countries, with a per
capita income per year of US$481 in 2018. Conservation projects must compete, here, with
the fight to escape desperate poverty, whereas other societies may have much greater capacity
to bear burdens.
Finally, who stands to benefit from acts of conservation? Sometimes, it is locals who
will benefit. But in many cases, ecosystems deliver significant benefits to outsiders too
7
(Balmford & Whitten 2003), from the role of forests in regulating the global climate to the
provision of water, oxygen, and nutrients by key ecosystems. Many of these serve as global
public goods. To require local communities to foot the bill for conservation in many cases
amounts to asking the global poor to subsidise the lifestyles of the globally wealthy. In a
highly unequal world, such a policy is hard to justify.
The pragmatic argument for letting conservation costs fall to local citizens faces three
major challenges. It does not adequately reflect the frequent mismatch between the location
of a resource and the origin of a threat to that resource; it is ill-suited to a world in which
there are massive international inequalities in the capacity to effectively advance conservation
goals; and it neglects the frequently poor fit between those who will be asked to pay for
conservation and those who will benefit from it. Progress in sharing conservation costs
globally has been very slow in practice, but justice demands a much more systematic sharing
of conservation burdens. Whereas mere geographical proximity does not appear to track
anything of moral significance, who caused threats, who has the capacity to bear conservation
costs, and who will benefit from acts of conservation appear highly relevant.
Contribution to the problem
If the reason a species or an ecosystem is under threat is that it is being degraded or destroyed
by someone, then it makes intuitive sense to ask that person or group of people to pick up the
tab for restoring it to health. The so-called contributor pays principle places costs on the
shoulders of whoever is responsible for damaging conservation-worthy objects. We often
hold people remedially responsible for rectifying problems when they have played a
significant causal role in bringing them about (Miller 2007). The principle is familiar from
discussions of climate justice, where it is frequently argued that heavy emitters ought to bear
the lion’s share of the costs of mitigation. The argument runs along the lines of ‘you broke it,
you fix it’ (Shue 2014).
8
The contributor principle taps into the idea that humans are moral agents, capable of
making choices, and that – at least when certain conditions are in place – it makes moral
sense to hold us responsible for those choices (Dworkin 2000). There is also the question of
incentives to consider. If people are going to be held responsible for meeting the costs of
conservation efforts required by their own damaging actions, they will, one assumes, be less
likely to cause damage in the first place. But to apply the contributor pays principle to
contemporary conservation challenges, one needs to know a little more about the
circumstances in which the relevant damage has been done. It makes moral sense to hold
people responsible when they understood the possible adverse consequences of their actions
and could have acted otherwise without facing unreasonable costs. Where those conditions
are met, there are moral grounds for placing greater burdens on the shoulders of those who
have generated threats to the health of ecosystems or species. For instance, if the reason an
ecosystem is threatened is that somebody has recklessly and unnecessarily used a dangerous
pesticide nearby, the contributor pays principle will hold them responsible for any clean-up
costs.
The contributor pays principle is a very familiar moral principle, and plays a major
role in legal systems around the world. For instance, Article 32d of Switzerland’s Federal Act
on the Protection of the Environment (1983) declares that those responsible for causing
pollution are obliged to bear the costs of remediation. In cases where there is more than one
responsible actor, it continues, each should bear costs in proportion to their share of the
responsibility. The Canadian Environmental Protection Act (1999) also requires polluters to
bear clean-up costs. There are, to be sure, some cases which have a more complex structure.
One complexity concerns risks. In principle, one could hold agents responsible not only for
the consequences of their actions, but also for managing the risks of their actions. But in
many cases risks will be rather uncertain, and if they are one would need to turn to some form
of precautionary principle (Gardiner 2006). Another complexity concerns the diffuse effects
9
our actions can have. In the law, one is typically required to make good the particular damage
one has caused. But sometimes it is very hard to unpick the specific damage someone has
done. In cases where it is nevertheless certain that someone has made damage more likely, it
may make moral sense to require them to share in the costs of conservation in general.
There are, however, cases where the contributor-pays principle does not appear well
equipped to offer guidance on how to share costs (Caney 2010). First, there will be cases
where the reason conservation is required has nothing to do with human action. If the threat
in question is not anthropogenic, one will need to turn to some other principle for guidance
(and if the threat is only partly anthropogenic, the principle will give only a partial answer to
our question about conservation burdens). Second, conservation problems may have been
caused by people who are no longer alive. Perhaps past generations engaged in the most
wanton habitat destruction. If so, we cannot now make them pay the price of putting it right.
One can only ask current generations to foot the bill for what they have themselves done.
Finally, there will be cases where the people who caused the damage were not aware of the
consequences of their actions or had no reasonable alternatives to acting in the way they did.
In all these cases, one needs to turn to one of the other principles to allocate costs.
Capacity
When a community faces a common problem, it will often turn to considerations of capacity
when deciding who must bear the burdens of responding to it. The capacity- or ability-to-pay
principle suggests that whoever can bear greater sacrifices without unduly setting back their
interests should do so (Shue 2014). The principle is attractive to those who care about
equality because it asks more of those who have more and avoids putting still greater burdens
on those who are faring badly. As such, it will not intensify existing inequalities (Armstrong
2017). But it can also appeal to those who care only about poverty, insofar as it protects those
who can ill afford to contribute to dealing with shared problems. It seems particularly
10
important to keep the capacity to bear sacrifices in mind when laying burdens at one agent’s
door would compound existing disadvantage, preventing them from escaping poverty or
pushing them further into it.
Something like the capacity principle is the basis of the proportional and progressive
taxation systems operated by most contemporary states, wherein people with higher incomes
contribute more to the provision of public goods and other services. For the principle to work,
of course, some reasonable index must be provided along which to measure different levels of
capacity. Globally, for instance, some index that factors in gross domestic product per capita
or levels of human development’ could be used to identify individuals or countries that are
most able to bear conservation burdens (Moellendorf 2014). If it can, the capacity principle
can offer powerful guidance when it comes to allocating conservation burdens.
Benefiting from conservation
The final principle for allocating conservation burdens suggests that those who benefit from
conservation should pay more of the costs. It is widely accepted that when one consumes
public goods, one develops an obligation to share in the costs of their production. This
argument can be qualified in light of people’s different capacities to bear costs: those on low
incomes are typically, and rightly, exempted from paying for many public services. But
people who happily consume public goods and then refuse to bear any of the costs – even
though they are perfectly able to - are regularly condemned for being free-riders. A similar
argument can be made in the case of conservation. Often, the protection of vital ecosystems
means that important ecosystem services continue to be used both locally and globally. If so,
then people can be described as free-riders if they refuse to share in the costs involved in
protecting those ecosystems.
Some political philosophers argue that one cannot be obliged to pay for benefits one
has not asked for or does not even want (Nozick 1974). The argument that people should pay
is much easier to make in cases where they need the services in question (Klosko 1987) and
11
someone is inevitably going to incur costs in producing or protecting them. This is certainly
true in the case of ecosystem services that are vital to human survival and the broader
ecosystems in which people live. One important example would be the role of the world’s
forests in sequestering carbon. When communities take steps to conserve forests, they allow
people to emit more carbon dioxide than they otherwise could, assuming that one wants to
preserve a safe climate. If the sink capacity of the forests were lost, the transition away from
carbon would have to happen much faster and would likely be much more costly. If
protecting forests from various threats means someone will have to carry costs, then it
appears that those who benefit from carbon-intensive activities ought to share in those costs
and that high emitters of greenhouse gases ought to bear greater costs than low emitters. For
outsiders to refuse to share in these burdens simply because the forests in question fall within
someone else’s national borders, is to free-ride on states with forests (Armstrong 2016).
Against a simple approach
The difficulty for those concerned with the fair or just allocation of conservation costs is that
all 3 principles appear to be powerful and important. If so, it appears unlikely that a fair
allocation of costs can be guided by any one principle alone. Such simple approaches have
been suggested. For instance, it has been argued that those who benefit from conservation
should be the ones who pay for it (Bamford & Whitten 2003). This is in many ways an
attractive principle on its face. In practice global conservation efforts often involve people in
poor countries being asked to protect resources that then deliver ecosystem benefits to people
living in wealthy countries – who are not required to pay. Contributions to the conservation
costs incurred in poor countries are basically voluntary in nature, and hence international
sharing is patchy at best. The rich may sometimes feel they ought to share in conservation
costs, but if they prefer not to, they are not obliged to do so. If conservation nevertheless
occurs, they can continue to enjoy these benefits for free. The claim that from the point of
12
view of justice, beneficiaries of conservation should share in conservation costs is quite
powerful in such a context.
But the moral picture is a little more complex. Consider the following two examples
that combined show why the question of who benefits from conservation cannot be the entire
story. Consider a country such as Somalia, one of the world’s least developed countries.
Somalia initially depends on sustainable artisanal fishing for the livelihood of thousands of
people and the nutrition of many thousands more. Fish stocks in its Exclusive Economic
Zone collapse, however, due to illegal and unreported fishing carried out by boats from
better-off countries. The local state, unfortunately, lacks the capacity to enforce restrictions
on fishing so that stocks can recover. Now imagine that some (hypothetical) international
agency steps in and drives out illegal fishing. Who should pay for its efforts? According to
the principle that the beneficiaries of conservation efforts should pay, Somalia would carry
the costs because conservation will secure the livelihoods of its fishers. It will be, that is, the
chief, and perhaps the only, beneficiary of conservation. But this conclusion is morally
troubling because it is not the Somali fishers who caused the collapse of the stocks. In this
case, justice suggests that those who contributed to the problem – the perpetrators of illegal
overfishing - should be the ones to pay. And, this is so even if they will not benefit from
conservation themselves. An approach that focuses on benefits from conservation alone,
wrongly neglects facts about contributions to the problem.
In the second example, a country establishes a network of nature reserves. As well as
providing benefits to wildlife, these are enjoyed by residents who live nearby. According to
the idea that the beneficiaries of conservation ought to pick up the tab, these residents should
share in the costs of maintaining the reserves. In practice, however, when states fund such
schemes, they do not require all citizens to pay, whether directly or through taxation. The
elderly, children, and the unemployed are frequently excused from paying anything on the
basis that they do not have the capacity to bear those costs. From the point of view of justice,
13
this is quite right. An approach that focuses only on benefits wrongly neglects facts about
capacity, which can also be highly relevant to the allocation of conservation costs.
Although I focused on the idea that the beneficiaries of conservation should pay,
similar things could be said about the idea that it is those who contribute to damage to
ecosystems who ought to pay for their conservation. In some cases, that judgement appears
highly plausible. But in other cases, people damage ecosystems because they are desperately
poor and lack reasonable alternatives. It should be a priority of global justice to alleviate the
tension between conservation and pro-poor development, for instance by opening up
opportunities for economic diversification that are less environmentally destructive
(Armstrong 2017). But in the meantime, it makes no sense to require the very poor to pay for
the damage they do because doing so would jeopardize their most basic interests. In this case,
facts about ability to pay modify the conclusions one would otherwise reach on the basis of
facts about contribution to ecosystem damage. What seems required, in sum, is some way of
accommodating facts about contribution and benefits and capacity to make sacrifices. Any
satisfactory answer to the question about how conservation costs should be allocated must
rest on some combination of all 3 of these principles.
A pluralist framework for fair burden sharing
From the point of view of justice, the best way to accommodate these competing principles is
to adopt a multistep procedure. First, identify cases in which conservation is necessary, for
instance because valuable resources have become threatened or damaged. Second, consider
whether anyone can be held morally responsible for the threat or damage. In some cases, no
human being will be causally responsible for any damage (as when forests are damaged by
volcanic activity). In other cases, someone will be responsible for the conservation challenge
coming into existence. But the fact that they are causally responsible does not yet establish
that they must be held remedially responsible (i.e., that they have a duty of justice to repair
14
the damage). In this step, one must also consider whether they knew or could have been
expected to anticipate the consequences of their activities. One must also assess whether they
had any reasonable alternatives to acting in the way they did. If they did know the possible
consequences and if they could reasonably have been expected to act otherwise, then the
culprit, from the point of view of justice, stands in line to bear conservation costs. If, for
instance, the reason a large predatory species is endangered is that it has been knowingly
overhunted for reasons other than subsistence, then when it comes to allocating the costs of
restoring the species, those who engaged in that pastime are responsible. Those who
avoidably and knowingly emit disproportionate amounts of greenhouse gases, thereby
contributing to the acidification of the oceans and the emergence of severe weather patterns,
ought to bear the burdens of responding to coral bleaching and climate-related habitat loss.
There are, however, many cases where people cannot be held responsible for
conservation threats – either because they have left the scene, did not know what they were
doing, or had no reasonable alternative options open to them. In such cases, identifying
causal contribution to the problem does not help assign costs. In such cases, one must engage
in a third and final step. This initially involves turning to facts about benefits. When no
culprit for conservation challenges can be found, one must ask who will benefit from acts of
conservation. In principle, people ought to share in the costs of important public goods from
which they benefit, and this includes the crucial ecosystem services they garner when
resources and habitats are protected for posterity. And, again in principle, those who benefit
more should pay more. This explains why it should be high-emitting countries – or, perhaps
better, high-emitting individuals – who bear most of the costs involved in protecting the
world’s forests or other carbon sinks. But, as I have argued, it makes no moral sense to
require individuals or countries to share in conservation costs when they are desperately poor.
Considerations of ability to pay are relevant here too and once more allow one to specify a
15
crucial threshold below which people will not be asked to contribute even if they are major
beneficiaries of conservation efforts.
In this framework, all three principles play a key role, often in a sequence. In many
cases, those who contribute to damage should be the ones to pay for its repair. But this is not
always the case, and one reason for forgiving people for the damage they do is that they are
desperately poor and have no better options for escaping poverty than to engage in
destructive development. In this sense, considerations of ability to pay establish a critical
threshold below which facts about contribution to ecosystem damage become less relevant.
When culprits cannot be identified, one must then turn to facts about who will benefit
from conservation. In principle, those who benefit from conservation should share in the
costs involved in protecting or restoring precious resources, but not always. Once more,
considerations of ability to pay allow one to set a critical threshold below which people
should not be asked to contribute. Just as governments in the developed world do not ask the
poor, sick, or unemployed to contribute to the cost of maintaining key public goods, so the
international community should not require the poor of the world to share in the costs of
conservation – even if those poor themselves are among the key beneficiaries of conservation
projects.
The pluralist framework I have outlined is undoubtedly more complex than simple
approaches that would lean on one simple principle. Although simplicity is often a virtue,
when it comes to justice the search for one single principle capable of regulating the
distribution of benefits and burdens can lead conservationists seriously astray. Focusing on
benefits alone, for instance, wrongly ignores the fact that people are sometimes responsible
for conservation challenges, and this must matter when it comes to allocating conservation
burdens. It also ignores the fact that, in a highly unequal world, people have hugely varying
capacities to absorb sacrifices. Some people, from the point of view of justice, should be
exempted from carrying any conservation costs. The pluralist framework I argue for shows
how contribution, capacity, and benefits can all matter to the allocation of conservation costs
16
and illustrates how the 3 principles can be integrated into a multistep procedure for allocating
conservation burdens.
Conclusions
The fair sharing of conservation burdens is one of the most pressing challenges our world
faces. The present skewed allocation of costs is unfair on its face, not least because it often
holds very poor people responsible for conserving resources that are of benefit to all and to
future generations. It also makes effective conservation less likely, precisely because it leaves
conservation burdens to those who are struggling against desperate poverty. Though many
people share the intuition that the current allocation of burdens leaves a lot to be desired, a
clear positive account of how these burdens should be shared is still needed. As I have shown,
there is no simple answer to this question, and 3 moral principles are relevant. These concern
who caused conservation challenges, who can best afford to bear the costs, and who stands to
benefit from conservation projects. Because all three principles are relevant, simple accounts
that give a role to 1 or 2 of these principles must be rejected. Instead, a pluralist framework is
required that puts each principle in its proper place.
Literature Cited
Adams VA, Pressey RL, Naidoo R. 2009. Opportunity costs: who really pays for
conservation? Biological Conservation 143: 439-448.
Armstrong C. 2016. Fairness, free riding and rainforest protection. Political Theory 44:
106-130.
Armstrong C. 2017. Justice and natural resources. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Bamford A, Whitten T. 2003. Who should pay for tropical conservation, and how could
the costs be met? Oryx 37: 238-250.
Baslar K. 1998. The concept of the common heritage of mankind in international law.
Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague.
Bruner AG, Gullison RE, Bamford A. 2004. Financial costs and shortfalls of managing
and expanding protected-area systems in developing countries. BioScience 54: 1119-1126.
17
Caney S. 2010. Climate change and the duties of the advantaged. Critical Review of
International Social and Political Philosophy 13: 203-228.
Del Corral M. 2015. Respect, protection and restoration: preservation as a negative or a
positive duty. Ethics, Policy & Environment 18: 268-70.
Dworkin R. 2000. Sovereign virtue. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Massachusetts.
Gardiner S. 2006. A core precautionary principle. Journal of Political Philosophy 14: 33-
60.
Klosko G. 1987. Presumptive benefit, fairness, and political obligation. Philosophy &
Public Affairs 16: 241-259.
Kymlicka W. 2002. Contemporary political philosophy, second edition. Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Mancilla A. 2016. Shared sovereignty over migratory natural resources. Res Publica 22:
21-35.
Miller D. 2007. National responsibility and global justice. Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Mitrani DS, Justus J, Huffaker B. 2018. The crucial but underrepresented role of
philosophy in conservation science curricula. Conservation Biology (forthcoming).
Moellendorf D. 2014. The moral challenge of dangerous climate change. Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Nozick R. 1974. Anarchy, state and utopia. Blackwell, Oxford.
Rosales J. 2008. Economic growth, climate change, biodiversity loss: distributive justice
for the global north and south. Conservation Biology 22: 1409-1417.
Sanderson SE and Redford KH. 2003. Contested relationships between biodiversity
conservation and poverty alleviation. Oryx 37: 389-390.
Schrijver J. 1997. Permanent Sovereignty over Natural Resources: Balancing Rights and
Duties. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Shue H. 2014. Climate justice: vulnerability and protection. Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Strindberg S et al 2018. Guns, germs and trees determine density and distribution of
gorillas and chimpanzees in Western Equatorial Africa. Science Advances 4: 2964.
Walsh PD et al 2003. Catastrophic ape decline in western equatorial Africa. Nature 422:
611-614.
18
... Previous research has considered the allocation of responsibilities for managing several other pressing environmental and public health challenges, including climate change (Caney, 2010;Knight, 2011;Moellendorf, 2012;Page, 2012), ecosystem conservation (Armstrong, 2018), lack of access to medicines in the developing world (Barry and Raworth, 2002;Malmqvist, 2016) and pollution from drug manufacturing (Nijsingh et al., 2019;Malmqvist and Munthe, 2020). By contrast, how responsibilities for managing pharmaceutical pollution from human use should be allocated remains an unexplored yet critical issue . ...
... They characterize this application of PPP both as fair, because it assigns responsibility where it is due (to the polluters), and as effective, because it encourages upstream actors to avoid or reduce polluting behaviour (e.g. by developing 'green' pharmaceuticals and adopting sustainable drug prescription, consumption and disposal practices) (Deloitte, 2020;EurEau, 2020). This echoes two widely acknowledged general advantages of PPP and the underlying moral responsibility principle (Miller, 2001;Moellendorf, 2012;Armstrong, 2018). First, PPP is sensitive to how harms that need to be addressed come about, reflecting a 'you broke it, you fix it' logic that is intuitively appealing and familiar from various moral and legal practices. ...
... This represents an advantage over PPP, which, as argued in the preceding section, lacks precisely this feature. Also, APP has a certain egalitarian appeal as it tends to assign greater burdens to the better off than to the worse off (Armstrong, 2018). On the other hand, APP lacks the features that make PPP attractive. ...
Article
Full-text available
Human consumption of pharmaceuticals often leads to environmental release of residues via urine and faeces, creating environmental and public health risks. Policy responses must consider the normative question how responsibilities for managing such risks, and costs and burdens associated with that management, should be distributed between actors. Recently, the Polluter Pays Principle (PPP) has been advanced as rationale for such distribution. While recognizing some advantages of PPP, we highlight important ethical and practical limitations with applying it in this context: PPP gives ambiguous and arbitrary guidance due to difficulties in identifying the salient polluter. Moreover, when PPP does identify responsible actors, these may be unable to avoid or mitigate their contribution to the pollution, only able to avoid/mitigate it at excessive cost to themselves or others, or excusably ignorant of contributing. These limitations motivate a hybrid framework where PPP, which empha- sizes holding those causing large-scale problems accountable, is balanced by the Ability to Pay Principle (APP), which emphasizes efficiently managing such problems. In this framework, improving wastewater treatment and distributing associated financial costs across water consumers or taxpayers stand out as promising responses to pharmaceutical pollution from human use. However, sound policy depends on empirical considerations requiring further study.
... However, despite the importance of addressing objective constraints (e.g. time, poverty, costs, incentives), recent studies also increasingly highlight that material services alone do not entirely explain how individuals participate in conservation programs: participation is also motivated by a range of subjective constraints (Fig. 1), such as social cohesion and a strong sense of place (Yuliani et al., 2022); the reflection of locally held relational values (Lliso et al., 2022); allegiance to new governance structures created by the conservation intervention (Silva and Mosimane, 2014); institutional and interpersonal trust among project stakeholders (Young et al., 2016), and fairness in the distribution of costs and benefits (Sommerville et al., 2010, Armstrong, 2019 and in decision-making (Kennedy et al., 2022). These non-material barriers can be binned into 'subjective constraints' to participation (Fig. 1). ...
... Similar to motivations to participate, reasons for nonparticipation can be associated with diverse subjective and objective factors, often mediated by structural conditions of the intervention: a sense of resentment, fear of lost access (Bennett and Dearden, 2014), conflicting values, different perceptions over time and priority for allocation, or negative legacies of past interaction with conservation institutions (Jim and Xu, 2002) are other possibilities (Fig. 1). Research also shows that disparities in the sharing of costs and benefits derived from conservation interventions can influence adverse behaviors and attitudes by local communities and individuals with livelihood heterogeneity (Mehta and Heinen, 2001;Jim and Xu, 2002;Armstrong, 2019;Newton et al., 2012). Notably, lack of clear communication about the conservation intervention and its potential impact can result in misunderstandings about the intervention and unwanted outcomes; for example, a fear of losing access to resources in the future can increase current resource extraction and degradation (Jim and Xu, 2002). ...
... In addition, conservation, restoration, revitalization and remediation efforts are increasingly examined in terms of equity and environmental justice (Armstrong, 2019;Garcia et al., 2021;Tyner & Boyer, 2020). Broadly, the concern is to ensure that restoration efforts-and the accompanying federal spending-are fairly distributed among regions and communities according to socio-economic status, race and gender (Angradi et al., 2019;Armstrong, 2019;Breslow et al., 2016;Wells et al., 2021), without causing negative impacts like 'green gentrification' or displacement of low-income or renter communities (Gould & Lewis, 2012;Rigolon et al., 2019). ...
... In addition, conservation, restoration, revitalization and remediation efforts are increasingly examined in terms of equity and environmental justice (Armstrong, 2019;Garcia et al., 2021;Tyner & Boyer, 2020). Broadly, the concern is to ensure that restoration efforts-and the accompanying federal spending-are fairly distributed among regions and communities according to socio-economic status, race and gender (Angradi et al., 2019;Armstrong, 2019;Breslow et al., 2016;Wells et al., 2021), without causing negative impacts like 'green gentrification' or displacement of low-income or renter communities (Gould & Lewis, 2012;Rigolon et al., 2019). For example, the Remediation to Restoration to Revitalization (R2R2R2) framework proposed by Williams and Hoffman (2020) and research by Nixon et al. (2022) highlight the local links between restoration actions and the socio-economic and well-being changes that drive revitalization. ...
Article
Full-text available
Traditionally, ecosystem restoration has focussed on standard ecological indicators like water or habitat quality, species population abundance or vegetation cover to determine success. However, there is growing interest in how restoration might impact people and communities. For example, researchers have documented positive socio-ecological links between restoration and human well-being indicators like property value, natural hazard mitigation, recreation opportunity and happiness. Furthermore, public health benefits from restoration have been linked to public support for programmes. Drawing from this research, the United Nations declared 2021–2030 the ‘Decade of Ecosystem Restoration’ and set a goal to promote more socio-ecological goals in ecosystem restoration. Nonetheless, there is still a lack of information on the extent to which restoration practitioners consider well-being because many granting programmes only require ecological goals and monitoring. To explore how restoration practitioners design, implement and measure the success of their projects, we used the federally funded Great Lakes Restoration Initiative (GLRI) as a case study. Since 2010, GLRI has awarded over $3.5 Billion to over 5300 projects across the midwestern United States, but it does not presently require human well-being considerations. We performed an online survey targeting project managers with a sample of GLRI projects (N = 1574). We received 437 responses and found that almost half set a human well-being goal, and more than 70% of those who did believe they reached it. In comparison, 90% of project managers believed they met their ecological goals. These documented perceptions of positive impacts for both people and nature suggest that restoration may already transcend traditional indicators and monitoring for socio-ecological metrics could capture many ‘unseen’ benefits. Therefore, we recommend that ecosystem restoration programmes adopt a socio-ecological lens to document the full extent of their restoration outcomes.
... For example, they do not ensure the representativity of species diversity in different areas or provide su cient replication to reduce extinction risk 29 . Further, developing global-scale prioritisations could exacerbate the conservation burden for countries in the Global South 30 . While country-scale planning could solve some of these issues, it is more costly and could still miss other aspects of conservation. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Climate change and anthropogenic activities threaten biodiversity and ecosystem services. Climate-smart conservation plans address these challenges by focusing protection in climate-resilient areas. However, integrating climate change in the design of conservation plans is often deemed too expensive, as it may require larger networks or protecting more costly sites. Using mangroves as a case study, we evaluated the efficiency of protecting mangroves in climate-smart versus climate-naïve reserve networks. We found that climate-smart conservation plans could provide sizable benefits for relatively small increases in protected area. Moreover, transboundary plans, involving cooperation among countries, require less area and protect more climate-resilient mangroves than nation-by-nation plans. Implementing these strategies would improve the current network of protected areas for mangroves, which currently has poor climate resilience. These findings could also be applied in other ecosystems.
... Our findings highlight the urgent need to distribute the net costs of conservation fairly, considering both benefits received and ability to pay of different stakeholder groups (Kremen et al. 1979;Fisher and Christopher 2007;Armstrong 2019). Given the fine balance of national gains and losses from conservation ( Fig. 3c and Fig. 4 subplots), addressing net local costs will -for the foreseeable future -require financial transfers from elsewhere. ...
Article
Full-text available
A billion rural people live near tropical forests. Urban populations need them for water, energy and timber. Global society benefits from climate regulation and knowledge embodied in tropical biodiversity. Ecosystem service valuations can incentivise conservation, but determining costs and benefits across multiple stakeholders and interacting services is complex and rarely attempted. We report on a 10-year study, unprecedented in detail and scope, to determine the monetary value implications of conserving forests and woodlands in Tanzania’s Eastern Arc Mountains. Across plausible ranges of carbon price, agricultural yield and discount rate, conservation delivers net global benefits (+US8.2Bpresentvalue,20yearcentralestimate).Crucially,however,netoutcomesdivergewidelyacrossstakeholdergroups.Internationalstakeholdersgainmostfromconservation(+US8.2B present value, 20-year central estimate). Crucially, however, net outcomes diverge widely across stakeholder groups. International stakeholders gain most from conservation (+US10.1B), while local-rural communities bear substantial net costs (-US1.9B),withgreaterinequitiesformorebiologicallyimportantforests.OtherTanzanianstakeholdersexperienceconflictingincentives:tourism,drinkingwaterandclimateregulationencourageconservation(+US1.9B), with greater inequities for more biologically important forests. Other Tanzanian stakeholders experience conflicting incentives: tourism, drinking water and climate regulation encourage conservation (+US72M); logging, fuelwood and management costs encourage depletion (-US$148M). Substantial global investment in disaggregating and mitigating local costs (e.g., through boosting smallholder yields) is essential to equitably balance conservation and development objectives.
Article
Full-text available
This essay argues that we have a duty to protect biodiversity hotspots, rooted in an argument about the wrongful imposition of risk and intergenerational justice. State authority over territory and resources is not unlimited; the state has a duty to protect these areas. The essay argues that although biodiversity loss is a global problem, it can be tackled at the domestic level through clear rules. The argument thus challenges the usual view of state sovereignty, which holds that authority over territory, resources, and migration (all of which are connected to the protection of biodiversity hotspots) is unlimited.
Article
The United Nations Fish Stocks Agreement requires states to recognise the special requirements of developing countries and to ensure that conservation and management measures do not place a disproportionate burden on developing countries. The aim of this article is to assess what policy arrangements are required to reduce the identified disproportionate burden. We developed a policy pathway that would allow members of tuna regional fisheries management organisations (tRFMOs) to strengthen their efforts to meet their duty to share conservation burdens more equitably. This pathway consists of policy options that were developed by using policy analysis, which is an innovative approach that provides actionable outcomes that can be used by tRFMO member states. Despite the global attention to reducing disproportionate conservation burdens, developing states are still suffering. The results of this article provide novel and timely policy options that have the potential to reduce the conservation burden carried by developing states.
Article
Full-text available
Article impact statement: Normative scientists must be trained in current thinking of the philosophy that underlies their fields, an issue not fully realized in conservation.
Article
Full-text available
We present a range-wide assessment of sympatric western lowland gorillas Gorilla gorilla gorilla and central chimpanzees Pan troglodytes troglodytes using the largest survey data set ever assembled for these taxa: 59 sites in five countries surveyed between 2003 and 2013, totaling 61,000 person-days of fieldwork. We used spatial modeling to investigate major drivers of great ape distribution and population trends. We predicted density across each taxon’s geographic range, allowing us to estimate overall abundance: 361,900 gorillas and 128,700 chimpanzees in Western Equatorial Africa—substantially higher than previous estimates. These two subspecies represent close to 99% of all gorillas and one-third of all chimpanzees. Annual population decline of gorillas was estimated at 2.7%, maintaining them as Critically Endangered on the International Union for Conservation of Nature and Natural Resources (IUCN) Red List. We quantified the threats to each taxon, of which the three greatest were poaching, disease, and habitat degradation. Gorillas and chimpanzees are found at higher densities where forest is intact, wildlife laws are enforced, human influence is low, and disease impacts have been low. Strategic use of the results of these analyses could conserve the majority of gorillas and chimpanzees. With around 80% of both subspecies occurring outside protected areas, their conservation requires reinforcement of anti-poaching efforts both inside and outside protected areas (particularly where habitat quality is high and human impact is low), diligent disease control measures (including training, advocacy, and research into Ebola virus disease), and the preservation of high-quality habitat through integrated land-use planning and implementation of best practices by the extractive and agricultural industries.
Book
In modern international law, permanent sovereignty over natural resources has come to entail duties as well as rights. This study analyses the evolution of permanent sovereignty from a political claim to a principle of international law, and examines its significance for a number of controversial issues such as people's rights, nationalization and environmental conservation. Although political discussion has long focused on the rights arising from permanent sovereignty, Dr Schrijver argues that this has been at the expense of the consideration of the corollary obligations it also entails. His book thus identifies directions sovereignty over natural resources has taken in an increasingly interdependent world and demonstrates its relevance to debate on foreign-investment regulation, the environment and sustainable development.
Book
Seventeen articles written by Henry Shue between 1992 and 2014 on ethical issues about climate change.