ArticlePublisher preview available

On Why There is a Problem of Supererogation

Authors:
To read the full-text of this research, you can request a copy directly from the author.

Abstract

How can it be that some acts of very high moral value are not morally required? This is the problem of supererogation. I do not argue in favor of a particular answer. Instead, I analyze two opposing moral intuitions the problem involves. First, that one should always do one’s best. Second, that sometimes we are morally allowed not to do our best. To think that one always has to do one’s best is less plausible, as it makes every morally best act obligatory. I argue that, despite its implausibility, this is the main ingredient in a traditional outlook I call ‘morality of law,’ which conceives of morality as impartial, impersonal, rule-based and obligation-based. My main point is that supererogation will always be seen as problematic if the background theory is a morality of law. This is because supererogation encapsulates a view of morality-outside-obligation, whereas morality of law centers upon obligation as its main instrument of curbing a supposedly natural human selfishness.
On Why There is a Problem of Supererogation
Nora Grigore
1
Received: 3 January 2018 /Revised: 31 May 2018 / Accepted: 31 October 2018 /
Published online: 14 November 2018
#Springer Nature B.V. 2018
Abstract
How can it be that some acts of very high moral value are not morally required? This is the
problem of supererogation. I do not argue in favor of a particular answer. Instead, I analyze
two opposing moral intuitions the problem involves. First, that one should always do ones
best. Second, that sometimes we are morally allowed not to do our best. To think that one
alwayshastodoones best is less plausible, as it makes every morally best act obligatory. I
argue that, despite its implausibility, this is the main ingredient in a traditional outlook I
call morality of law,which conceives of morality as impartial, impersonal, rule-based
and obligation-based. My main point is that supererogation will always be seen as
problematic if the background theory is a morality of law. This is because supererogation
encapsulates a view of morality-outside-obligation, whereas morality of law centers upon
obligation as its main instrument of curbing a supposedly natural human selfishness.
Keywords Supererogation .Morality.Obligation .Law .Virtue
1 What the Problem of Supererogation says about Morality
and Obligation
How can one explain that some morally excellent deeds are not required? The question
presupposes some degree of puzzlement, or at least of skepticism, towards the idea that
not all morally good deeds can be required. This is the problem of supererogation.
1
Philosophia (2019) 47:11411163
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-018-0045-z
1
The problem has been formulated in many ways depending on the theoretical framework used. In deontic terms,
how can one explain that some excellent moral deeds are merely permitted, not obligatory? In maximization terms
(e.g. New (1974), Dreier (2004), Scheffler (1994) and Slote (1984)). how can one explain that the moral agent is
allowed not to maximize the good in some circumstances? Raz (1975) gives one of the clearest formulations of the
problem of supererogation in terms of reasons:One important characteristic of supererogatory acts is that their
performance is praiseworthy while their omission is not blameworthy. But this creates a problem. If doing a
supererogatory act is praiseworthy there must be reason for doing it, and the reasons must outweigh any
conflicting reasons for not doing it. But if there are conclusive reasons for performing the act then not to perform it
is to act against the balance of reasons. If reason requires that the act be done then surely one ought to do it, and the
oughtis based on all the reasons which apply to the case; it is a conclusive ought. But this entails that failing to
perform the act is failing to do what one ought (conclusively) to do, so why isnt it blameworthy not to perform a
supererogatory act?(Raz 1975: 164) Also, the definition of supererogation sometimes varies from author to
author. Heyd (1982) defines supererogation as the action that is neither obligatory nor forbidden, which is not
wrong to omit, it is morally good and done voluntarily for the sake of someone elses good. I am using a
commonsensical notion of supererogation that is common among most views.
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
... All this is to support-fallibly, but ostensibly-the Good Dog picture of virtues, both intellectual and moral, that Korsgaard seems to target. duty or of supererogation, and what might be at stake in the debate, see Grigore (2019). 10 For a principled reason why thought and deed must harmonize if full rationality is presumed, see Mărăşoiu (2018). ...
... As Dreier (2004: 145) puts it, 'we take it for granted that there are supererogatory acts, and it would be incredible if the very idea of supererogation turned out to be incoherent'. Yet, the ordinary intuition encounters a theoretical challenge, known as the 'paradox of supererogation' (Archer 2013a, Dorsey 2013, Dreier 2004, Grigore 2019, Heyd 2019and Horgan and Timmons 2010. ...
Article
We argue that permissibility-based solutions to the paradox of supererogation encounter a nested dilemma. Such approaches solve the paradox by distinguishing moral and rational permissions. If they do not also include a bridge condition that relates these two permissions, then they violate a very plausible monotonicity condition. If they do include a bridge condition, then permissibility-based solutions either amount to rational satisficing or they collapse back into the classical account of supererogation and fail to resolve the paradox.
Book
The term ‘consequentialism’ refers to a class of moral theories that rank states of affairs from an impersonal standpoint and require agents to produce the best states of affairs they can. Many philosophers have criticized and rejected consequentialist theories, but Scheffler wishes to reconsider the rejection of consequentialism. He begins by discussing two objections to consequentialism, one having to do with the integrity of agents and the other with distributive justice. From there, he outlines a hybrid moral theory that avoids these two objections. Scheffler's hybrid theory agrees with consequentialism in so far as it always permits agents to produce the best states of affairs, but it departs from consequentialism by including an ‘agent‐centred prerogative’, allowing each agent to assign greater weight to his own interests than to those of others. Scheffler argues that this prerogative rests on a principled rationale—namely, that it is a rational strategy for taking into account the independence of the personal point of view. But this rationale does not support ‘agent‐centred restrictions’—norms that sometimes forbid agents from doing what would have the best outcome overall. Scheffler searches for, but does not find, a separate rationale for agent‐centred restrictions.
Chapter
Introduction I will argue that rational satisficing and ethical satisficing suffer from the same problem, namely, that they are in danger of making no sense because their conceptions of the good cannot be made out independently of a conception of the proper aim of actions.1 In the case of rational satisficing, the main argument comes from the foundations of decision theory. In the case of ethical satisficing, I borrow an argument from Philippa Foot. In the end it turns out that ethical satisficing survives the problem, whereas rational satisficing does not. I will motivate the distinction by appealing to an intuitive feature of commonsense morality, namely, supererogation. Rational Satisficing The literature on rational satisficing is loaded with interesting examples, but none of them has ever struck me as an example of rational satisficing. They always appear to be examples of something else, not always of the same thing, but always of something that defenders of maximizing could accommodate within their theory.Oneof these is the example of Hannah. Suppose Hannah has put her house on the market, and naturally she wants the best price for it. Because she can’t wait indefinitely for bids to come in, she decides to accept the first bid that comes in above a certain satisfactory price that she chooses in advance. Suppose she picks $200,000 as her threshold. If someone offers her $205,000 the first day the ad appears in the local real estate listings, she’ll take it. © Cambridge University Press 2004 and Cambridge University Press, 2010.
Chapter
Traditional virtue-oriented approaches to ethics suppose that acquiring relatively stable character traits, such as courage and compassion, is crucial in addressing the question of how to be. However, recent psychological studies cast doubt on the idea that people develop such traits. In light of this pessimism, the paper raises the question: what is left of virtue theory? It argues that much remains once one shifts from a traditional understanding of virtues to one of cognitive/affective "if...then" dispositions that form a person's character. The central proposal is to understand such dispositions as "habitudes" - habitual ways of thinking, feeling, and acting that are acquired by example and repetition, and that enable one to competently react to varying situations one confronts. The resulting model of ethical comportment represents a psychologically realistic understanding of virtue. Furthermore, this account fits well with what we learn from the field of positive psychology about subjective well-being, thus helping to vindicate eudaimonism.
Article
I develop and defend the following neo-Aristotelian account of supererogation: an action is supererogatory if and only if it is overall virtuous and either (a) the omission of an overall virtuous action in that situation would not be overall vi-cious or (b) there is some overall virtuous action that is less virtuous than it and whose performance in its place would not be overall vicious. I develop this ac-count from within the virtue-ethical tradition. And I argue that it is intuitively defensible and fully compatible with the doctrine of the mean.