ArticlePDF Available

Transdisciplinarity across the Qualitative and Quantitative Science through C.S. Peirce’s Semiotic Concept of Habit

Authors:

Abstract

This paper investigates how Peirce manages to establish a transdisciplinary fallibilist view of the sciences that is not hostile to religious spirituality viewed as a complementary fallibilist knowledge type. I focus on Peirce’s attempt to construct an alternative to classical mechanical ontology with its reversible time concept and the ontological view of absolute transcendental laws of nature. His triadic semiotic pragmaticism has empiricism in common with the logical positivists, but it shares the fallibilist critical stance with Popper, with whose critical rationalism Peirce also shares a thorough-going evolutionary approach. With Hegel and Schelling, Peirce shares a kind of evolutionary objective idealism and with Whitehead a thoroughgoing process view, and finally with Wittgenstein, he shares a pragmatic view of the meaning of words and concepts. What knits together all these apparently incompatible views is his dynamic Tychism and his Synechist field view. Together these produce a transdisciplinary irreversible view of habits as “laws” of nature, mind, and society that emerge in the development of the cosmos. Though Peirce is somehow close to Hegel’s phenomenological and dialectical view on cosmogony, a number of aspects are quite unique about his approach: the most important of these are his dynamic triadic categorically-based semiotics that makes him understand human beings as well as the universe as symbolic self-organizing developing processes. This is an interesting alternative to modern mechanical info-computationalism.
Open Information Science 2018; 2: 102–114
Søren Brier*
Transdisciplinarity across the Qualitative and
Quantitative Science through C.S. Peirce’s
Semiotic Concept of habit
https://doi.org/10.1515/opis-2018-0008
Received January 10, 2018; accepted June 5, 2018
Abstract: This paper investigates how Peirce manages to establish a transdisciplinary fallibilist view of the
sciences that is not hostile to religious spirituality viewed as a complementary fallibilist knowledge type.
I focus on Peirce’s attempt to construct an alternative to classical mechanical ontology with its reversible
time concept and the ontological view of absolute transcendental laws of nature. His triadic semiotic
pragmaticism has empiricism in common with the logical positivists, but it shares the fallibilist critical
stance with Popper, with whose critical rationalism Peirce also shares a thorough-going evolutionary
approach. With Hegel and Schelling, Peirce shares a kind of evolutionary objective idealism and with
Whitehead a thoroughgoing process view, and finally with Wittgenstein, he shares a pragmatic view of the
meaning of words and concepts. What knits together all these apparently incompatible views is his dynamic
Tychism and his Synechist field view. Together these produce a transdisciplinary irreversible view of habits
as “laws” of nature, mind, and society that emerge in the development of the cosmos. Though Peirce is
somehow close to Hegel’s phenomenological and dialectical view on cosmogony, a number of aspects are
quite unique about his approach: the most important of these are his dynamic triadic categorically-based
semiotics that makes him understand human beings as well as the universe as symbolic self-organizing
developing processes. This is an interesting alternative to modern mechanical info-computationalism¹.
Keywords: Peirce, habits
1 Introduction
C.S. Peirce, who died 100 years ago, was the father of an American pragmatism based on the logic of
semiotic relations. To distinguish it from the more superficial American pragmatism that became dominant,
he called it pragmaticism. In that, he develops a relation logic acknowledging that interaction as such is
not necessary for a relation; relation is something that arises from and continues after such interaction
has ceased. Only an irreducibly triadic relation uniting three distinct terms constitutes a “sign” formally,
is what is established by Peirce’s unique semiotic paradigm. Peirce’s basic semiotic triads are meant to
refer to the main phenomenon of all kinds of semiotic reasoning (Brier, 2015a) in nature, mind, and society.
Thus, the whole purpose of his semiotic machinery is to understand the essence of reasoning processes,
not only as internal mental human processes, but also as chains of arguments in perception, thinking, and
1 The present paper is an extended version of the long abstract published in the proceedings of the Convention IS4IS, Gothen-
burg, 2017.
Research Article
Article note: This paper belongs to the special issue on Habits and Rituals, ed. by R. Giovagnoli & G. Dodig-Crnkovic.
*Corresponding author: Søren Brier, Department for Management, Society and Communication, Copenhagen Business
School, Dalgas Have 15, 2000 Frederiksberg, Denmark; sbr.msc@cbs.dk
Open Access. © 2018 Søren Brier, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-
NonCommercial-NoDerivs 4.0 License.
Transdisciplinarity across the Qualitative and Quantitative Science through... 103
communication based on an aesthetical as well as an ethical perspective (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 6, para.
25)². The Sign in its form of an irreducible dynamic triadic process is a syllogism. One can view the major
premise as the Representamen function; the minor premise as the Object relation and, finally, view the
conclusion as producing the Interpretant. This is a dynamic transformative self-organizing process. It is not
just like a conveyor belt in a machine or an automatic algorithm in a computer. In the Peircean sign, be it in
language, paralinguistic signs, or animal communication, the information is actively interpreted from input
sensationto result in social reality, which is not just “behavior” as in behaviorism, but carries meaning.
Peirce’s view of science and religion differs from the received view of both classical dualistic science and
more modern physicalistic approaches, as he puts the signs at the center of his world - instead of matter as
in classical physicalism, energy as in relativity theory or information as in modern info-computationalism.
Though he was educated as a chemist and worked empirically as a physicist, his philosophy of science is
also based on a phenomenological philosophy through which, in a variety of qualitatively mathematical
analysis, he identified three irreducible elements of all kinds of experience. Peirce wrote:
All the elements of experience belong to three classes, which, since they are best defined in terms of numbers, may be
termed Kainopythagorean categories. Namely, experience is composed of 1st, monadic experiences, or simples, being
elements each of such a nature that it might without inconsistency be what it is though there were nothing else in all
experience; 2nd, dyadic experiences, or recurrences, each a direct experience of an opposing pair of objects; 3rd, triadic
experiences, or comprehensions, each a direct experience which connects other possible experiences.
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 528).
The categories traverse the idea of an inner and outer world, which is typical for a phenomenological point
of departure. Peirce wrote later that “three elements are active in the world, first, chance; second, law; and
third, habit-taking” (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 1, para. 409).
C.S. Peirce’s pragmaticist, triadic semiotic theory is the only paradigm that can match system science in
transdisciplinary scope, cybernetics in process dynamics, and hermeneutics in the theory of meaning and
still have a logical foundation, This is because he sees logic as semiotic (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 2, para. 227-
231) and envisages this with the new interactive embodied theory of mind as being embedded, embodied,
enacted as well as extended. It is a phenomenologically-based, natural and social scientific, process-based
vision of the mind as a complex semiotic set of activities distributed across brain, body, language, culture,
and world. Semiotics (unlike mathematics) is a positive science dealing with real relations. One of the
most important lessons to take from Peirce’s semiotics in the vast reorientation of the whole domain of
sensation, perception, logic, reasoning, thought, language, images etc. towards the chain of reasoning as
its primitive phenomenon (Stjernfelt, 2014). The point of pragmaticism is that it can be formally described,
independently of the materials in which it may be implemented. This implies that propositions are not only
entities of language or consciousness, nor do they presuppose any conscious “propositional stance”. They
are multi-aspectual real and logic is semiotic. He wrote: “Logic, in its general sense, is, as I believe I have
shown, only another name for semiotic (σηειωτικ), the quasi-necessary, or formal, doctrine of signs”
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 2, para. 227).
If science is a way of knowing the universe and how it works, then religion springs out of the
phenomenologically-based tendency to make sense of our experiences of relationship with the universe and
all the other forms of living intelligence in it. Religion springs from human beings’ religious experiences, as
Peirce argues in his “Neglected argument for the Reality of God” from 1908 (Peirce 1931-1958, Vol. 6, para.
452–467; Brier, 2014a).
If our internal experiential world and the material outer world are two sides of the same coin, then the
coin is us, not the universe itself, and it raises the problem of whom or what we are. Not only personal but
as groups connected through a language and a culture. Humans seem divided into a rational materially
optimizing Homo economicus and a Homo religious driven by a hermeneutic meaning-seeking aspect.
Knowing, not at least scientific knowing, seems to be the key to connecting our two aspects. It seems that
2 Peirce’s Collected papers (often referred to as CP) where the first number refers to volume and the next to paragraph. It is now
freely available on the net https://colorysemiotica.files.wordpress.com/2014/08/peirce-collectedpapers.pdf
104  S. Brier
economical system thinking lacks a theoretical foundation in the phenomenological and hermeneutical
aspects of communication, because it is often based on statistical concepts of information and views
communication as information transfer. Thereby analysis of the aspects of signification and interpretation
is left to common sense, leaving out important philosophical dimensions of worldviews, historical situation,
cultural horizon, and the relation between rationality, logic, and meaning. Thus, business communication
is often based primarily on the rationality executed by economic paradigms of game theory, control theory,
and artificial intelligence blended with common sense practical rationality.
Our civilizations were originally organized around religious meaning. Science was something developed
much later as another type of searching for the truth. From the development of the natural sciences,
quantitative empirically based modeling using mathematics became the core of quantitative science from
which, the mechanical physicalistic ontology of the Cosmos as something governed by absolute laws,
sprang. So did the logical positivist reductionist view, which was crystallized in social science. Today, this
philosophy of science seems to be a hindrance to integrating qualitative theories of quale consciousness
and social theories of meaningful communication with the natural sciences. It is a problem because, ever
since Darwin’s theory of evolution was accepted, we have been forced to find a way to unite evolutionary
and historical sciences into our scientific - often mechanically dualist based - worldview in order to better
understand ourselves and our culture’s relation to its ecological foundation.
It seems that we need to produce a non-reductionist unity of science that will integrate the quantitative
and the qualitative sciences in some kind of transdisciplinary framework as exemplified by Cybersemiotics
(Brier, 2008). To do that we will have to develop our ontological and epistemological view of humans
and the possible function of our knowing process in the universe in a philosophy that is able to include
phenomenology. It is within the experiential mind that meaning, philosophy, and religion is generated. An
aspect of our body can be described by biological science in an physiological, evolutionary and ecological
scientific framework; and here it already seems that we are at the limits of the mechanical philosophy of
science and have to use thermodynamics to found our models and has been at odds with a purely mechanical
paradigm (Prigogine, Stengers, 1984). The deep problem is whether we are related to the universe in other
ways than material, energetic and informational sciences has thus far described. Peirce attempted to create
an alternative semiotic process worldview. Peirce views the life of signs as a self-organizing and developing
process. Like a virus, signs self- organize and reproduce through their tokens, without signs being themselves
fully embodied living creatures. Yet, signs are embodied by humans, through our thinking and imagining.
In Peirce’s triadic semiotics, symbols grow by nature and are supported by the tendency to take habits, be
this in human biology, mind, or culture. This explains Peirce’s view of how the tendency to take habits,
combined with symbolic dynamics, is the driving force across the realms of physics, chemistry, biology,
psychology, sociology, and religion!
When Peirce was not applying the categories to the special sciences, like physics or psychology, he started
to call those categories Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness. These quasi-mathematical terms fit very well into
the logic of relations he developed. In the 1903 “Syllabus”, he defines them in the following way:
Firstness is that which is such as it is positively and regardless of anything else. Secondness is that which is as it is in a
second something’s being as it is, regardless of any third. Thirdness is that whose being consists in its bringing about a
Secondness.”
(Peirce 1931-1958, Vol. 5, para. 66).
Peirce makes mathematics and mind converge through his three-category-based semiotics, where logic is
semiotic. This is a fundamentally different way of looking at logic. Semioticians doubt that reality is a
deterministic algorithm playing itself out. Our progress in physics that has led to quantum mechanics and
quantum field, which support the idea that it is necessary to create new non-mechanical ontologies that
can encompass evolution as well as the free will of humans. One of the reasons is that quantum mechanical
experiments are tied to the free will choice of a measurement, as Wheeler (1994) points out. Thus, analysis
of awareness and free will seems necessary to establish a new philosophy of transdisciplinary science.
Therefore Peirce uses “categories” and “elements” in reference to his phenomenological triad. The concept
Transdisciplinarity across the Qualitative and Quantitative Science through... 105
of elements, he used to signify the non-decomposable parts of the phaneron. His use of the term categories
was not about classification of phenomena, but about analysis of the elements of which they are composed.
Finding the elements that are always present in the phaneron. The phaneron being that, which is everything
one can think.
This makes it possible for Peirce to do what the logical positivists were not able to do: namely, to
produce a philosophical framework for uniting the natural, human, and social sciences and to stop the
war over which type of science is most true and useful. This can only be done by changing some basic
ontological and epistemological viewpoints about mind, matter, law, scientific truth, evolution, and the
reality of meaning.
Before we enter into a discussion of his central concept of habit, let us take a look at how Peirce views
the connections between mind and matter: “(W)hat we call matter is not completely dead, but is merely
mind hidebound with habits. It still retains the element of diversification; and in that diversification there
is life” (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 6, para. 158). Thus, Peirce did not support the idea of classic natural science
that the world is built from elementary particles only, governed by universal laws driven by purely material
forces and energy. He called his alternative view synechism, which (coming from the Greek synechés
meaning “continuous”, cf. 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 565) is “that tendency of philosophical thought which
insists upon the idea of continuity as of prime importance in philosophy and, in particular, upon the
necessity of hypotheses involving true continuity” (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 6, para. 169). The consequence
of this view is a rejection of ultimate elements, or the view of atoms as “Das Ding an sich”, ultimate things
(without an interior science can access). Peirce has always – in spite of his great admiration for Kant and his
work - objected to this idea of ‘the thing in itself’ as it poses an unacceptable postulate of an ultimate limit
of knowledge using the inexplicable as an explanation. Peirce wrote:
Synechism is not an ultimate and absolute metaphysical doctrine; it is a regulative principle of logic, prescribing what sort
of hypothesis is fit to be entertained and examined. The synechist, for example, would never be satisfied with the hypothesis
that matter is composed of atoms, all spherical and exactly alike. If this is the only hypothesis that the mathematicians are
as yet in condition to handle, it may be supposed that it may have features of resemblance with the truth. But neither the
eternity of the atoms nor their precise resemblance is, in the synechist’s view, an element of the hypothesis that is even
admissible hypothetically. […]. So the synechist will not believe that some things are conscious and some unconscious,
unless by consciousness be meant a certain grade of feeling. He will rather ask what are the circumstances which raise
this grade; nor will he consider that a chemical formula for protoplasm would be a sufficient answer. In short, synechism
amounts to the principle that inexplicabilities are not to be considered as possible explanations; that whatever is supposed
to be ultimate is supposed to be inexplicable; that continuity is the absence of ultimate parts in that which is divisible;
and that the form under which alone anything can be understood is the form of generality “, which is the same thing as
continuity.”
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 6, para. 173).
Peirce did not believe in ultimate limits of knowledge. One can also call his view a special kind of holism
insisting that the whole is always more than the sum of the parts. He explained the consequences of his
synechist view on the continuum this way:
A true continuum is something whose possibilities of determination no multitude of individuals can exhaust. Thus,
no collection of points placed upon a truly continuous line can fill the line so as to leave no room for others, although
that collection had a point for every value towards which numbers, endlessly continued into the decimal places, could
approximate;”
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 6, para. 170).
Thus, synechism views the universe as a continuous whole consisting of all its parts! It is a holism, meaning
that explanations by way of ultimate structures is not possible as synechism is “the doctrine that all that
exists is continuous” (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 1, para. 172).
This means that synechism accords with the view that continuity of being is a condition for
communication (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 572); Peirce underlines that continuity, according to his
view, means that all phenomena are of one character, consisting of a mixture of freedom and constraint.
106  S. Brier
Thus, Kant’s idea of Nature as being determinist, ruled by law and freedom, as only belonging to humans,
is a hidden way of repeating Descartes’ dualism. Thus, meaning and reason is not only being for humans
or to the living being but to all of existence, because of the deep, partly phenomenologically-based
process philosophy on which his cosmogony is based; the consequence of which is that the universe, in
a teleological manner, tends to increase reasonableness through its development (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7,
para. 570; Brier, 2015a).
This view is foundational in Peirce’s philosophy and intrinsically connected to his concept of habit,
which is again explicable from a synthesis of pragmaticism and his process philosophy’s other foundational
concept, namely tychism. Tychism is another break with the classical mechanical concept of the universe -
although much closer to modern quantum field theory - as it is the belief that spontaneous chance events
are real events at the most fundamental levels of physical reality. By making chance part of his philosophical
framework, Peirce makes possible a unity between the quantitative and qualitative sciences.
Synechism also has interesting philosophy of science consequences as it leads Peirce to embrace the
fallibilist view that the results of science are continually subject to revision. Thus, like Karl Popper, Peirce
was a fallibilist opposing the logical positivistic epistemology of verificationism with regard to scientific
theories and models. No absolute atoms – understood as indivisible things in themselves - and laws are to
be found, and the end of research for a certified truth is an ideal that is far away in the future.
Another controversial viewpoint of Peirce’s in respect of the objective stance associated with the
verificationalism of the logical positivistic view of science is that, as a consequence of synechism’s
fallibilism, there exists no ultimate boundary between science and religion (understood as spirituality).
This view opens up a way to integrate the existential, ethical, and aesthetical aspects of knowledge with
the scientific ones and, in Peirce’s metaphysics, the normative sciences, such as ethic, aesthetics and logic,
play an important role. He viewed logic as an investigation of the role of good and consistent reasoning.
The problem of the role of values in the scientific search for truth is one that not only exists between
science and religion, but which is already immanent in the schism between the natural and the social and
cultural sciences. Peirce simply wrote that synechism is “a purely scientific philosophy [that] may play a
part in the onement of religion and science” (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 578). Furthermore, as mentioned
earlier, Peirce was not a proponent of physicalistic material mechanicism, but a process philosopher and
an evolutionary synechist closer to a position of objective idealism. This makes his approach similar to
Emerson and the transcendentalists, with whom his family were acquainted – as well as to Hegel and
Schelling, as earlier mentioned.
Peirce’s evolutionary and synechist process view made him focus on vague beginnings for many
phenomena in the world instead of absolute laws and indivisible atoms. He wrote:
There is a famous saying of Parmenides, [. . .] ‘being is, and not-being is nothing.’ This sounds plausible, yet synechism
flatly denies it, declaring that being is a matter of more or less, so as to merge insensibly into nothing
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 569).
This strongly suggests that he thought that mind and matter are connected in a continuum and that matter
therefore had some internal living qualities, because he did not believe that the world consisted in inert matter
ruled by absolute and precisely determinable laws; nor did he support the idea that such laws and matter
could somehow pre-exist the manifest universe in time and space came. Like modern quantum field physics’
positing of a vacuum field, Peirce’s scientific philosophy of science led him to an emptiness ontology:
I may mention that my chief avocation in the last ten years has been to develop my cosmology. This theory is that the
evolution of the world is hyperbolic, that is, proceeds from one state of things in the infinite past, to a different state of
things in the infinite future. The state of things in the infinite past is a chaotic emptiness, tohu bohu, the nothingness of
which consists in the total absence of regularity. […] I believe the law of habit to be purely psychical. But then I suppose
matter is merely mind deadened by the development of habit. While every physical process can be reversed without
violation of the law of mechanics, the law of habit forbids such reversal.
(Brier 2014b; Peirce, 1931- 1958, Vol. 8, para. 317-318).
Transdisciplinarity across the Qualitative and Quantitative Science through... 107
Thus, his ontology did not need to be built from atoms, energy, and bits only.
A further problem with the mechanicism of classical physics was that the concept of time in Newton’s
theory of motion was reversible. Time had no arrow. By contrast, in Peirce’s cosmogony change is
fundamental in that Firstness is imbued with the tendency to take habits: consequently, time has an arrow
and is irreversible, which is why laws became manifest as the universe developed. This was unthinkable
from a mechanical point of view and is probably one of the reasons why Peirce was not really acknowledged
in classical science. However, Prigogine and Stengers (1984) in their development of non-equilibrium
thermodynamics based on Boltzmann’s probability interpretation of thermodynamics, managed to get
irreversibility accepted as the basic process in physical ontology in the shift from mechanicism to an
evolutionary view based on thermodynamics. Nevertheless, it was very difficult for classically trained
physicists to embrace. But then, in 2013, the recognized physicist Lee Smolin published the book Time
Reborn (2013), in which he accepted Peirce’s as well as Prigogine’s views on the nature of time, change,
and law and embraced the big change with regard to the foundational conception of physics that this view
brings. Peirce had concluded that: “Hence…the laws of the universe have been formed under a universal
tendency of all things toward generalization and habit-taking.” (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 515). He
also wrote that “A law is in itself nothing but a general formula or symbol” (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 5, para.
107). But of course, in contrast to Smolin and Prigogine, as well as to cybernetics and systems theory,
Peirce also grounds his philosophical framework in phenomenology: “Normative science rests largely on
phenomenology and on mathematics; Metaphysics on phenomenology and on normative science.” (Peirce,
1931-1958, Vol. 1, para. 186). A further development of his thought on the difference between empiricism and
phenomenology can be found in an undated manuscript included in the Collected Papers:
Logic is a branch of philosophy. That is to say it is an experiential, or positive science, but a science which rests on no special
observations made by special observational means, but on phenomena which lie open to the observation of every man,
every day and hour. There are two main branches of philosophy, Logic, or the philosophy of thought, and Metaphysics, or
the philosophy of being. Still more general than these is High Philosophy which brings to light certain truths applicable
alike to logic and to metaphysics. It is with this high philosophy that we have at first to deal.
What is the experience upon which high philosophy is based? For any one of the special sciences, experience is that which
the observational art of that science directly reveals. This is connected with and assimilated to knowledge already in our
possession and otherwise derived, and thereby receives an interpretation, or theory. But in philosophy there is no special
observational art and there is no knowledge antecedently acquired in the light of which experience is to be interpreted.
The interpretation itself is experience. Even logic, however, the higher of the two main branches of philosophy, draws a
distinction between truth and falsehood. But in high philosophy, experience is the entire cognitive result of living, and
illusion is, for its purposes, just as much experience as is real perception […] it is to be remarked that I use the word
“experience” in a much broader sense than it carries in the special sciences..”
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 526-538).
Thus, Peirce makes phenomenology – as it is called in Europe - one of the primary sources of philosophy.
Though Peirce was inspired by German idealism and Naturphilosophie, especially Hegel and Schelling,
he also has affinities with empiricism as he worked with physical measurements. This makes him a kind
of process objective idealist, albeit a very special one. In the tradition of Aristotle, Hegel, and Kant, he
worked out a system of basic categories that had a deep impact on his cosmogony (Brier 2014b). There are
many statements in which Peirce tries to explain these basic categories. They are his development of the
categories that Aristotle, Kant, and Hegel worked with in their philosophies. Here is one of his descriptions:
Actuality is something brute. There is no reason in it. I instance putting your shoulder against a door and trying to force
it open against an unseen, silent, and unknown resistance. We have a two-sided consciousness of effort and resistance,
which seems to me to come tolerably near to a pure sense of actuality. On the whole, I think we have here a mode of being
of one thing which consists in how a second object is. I call that Secondness. Besides this, there are two modes of being
that I call Firstness and Thirdness. Firstness is the mode of being which consists in its subject’s being positively such as
it is regardless of aught else. That can only be a possibility. For as long as things do not act upon one another there is no
sense or meaning in saying that they have any being, unless it be that they are such in themselves that they may perhaps
come into relation with others. The mode of being a redness, before anything in the universe was yet red, was nevertheless
a positive qualitative possibility. And redness in itself, even if it be embodied, is something positive and sui generis. That
108  S. Brier
I call Firstness. [….] Now for Thirdness. Five minutes of our waking life will hardly pass without our making some kind
of prediction; and in the majority of cases these predictions are fulfilled in the event. Yet a prediction is essentially of a
general nature, and cannot ever be completely fulfilled. To say that a prediction has a decided tendency to be fulfilled, is to
say that the future events are in a measure really governed by a law.
(Peirce 1931-1958, Vol. 1, pp. 24-26).
These are the three necessary categories Peirce derives from his qualitative mathematical analysis of
the phaneron in the sense of what is common to all human immediate and conscious experience. These
basic categories of perception, thinking, and communication are at the basis of his philosophy and its
development into a pragmaticist semiotics. Compared to his predecessors he manages to boil matters down
so that only three categories are necessary for developing all possible dynamic forms by combination. In that
respect he is close to Hegel’s dialectical developmental building on thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, which
was further developed in dialectical materialism’s ideas of evolution in nature, human culture, and power-
distribution in society. However, Peirce has another philosophical foundation and his connection with
empirical modern science was advantaged compared to Hegel and his connections to the phenomenological
and hermeneutical aspect of communication as well as in comparison to dialectical materialism. It is from
this phenomenological tri-categorical, synechist and tychist foundation that Peirce builds his process view
of the triadic sign function, which he calls semiosis, across nature and culture. Here is one of his many
definitions that underline his views on the way signs have a real dimension as part of the reality in which
we live and breathe and search for the truth:
A sign is connected with the ‘Truth,’ i.e. the entire Universe of being, or, as some say, the Absolute, in three distinct ways.
In the first place, a sign is not a real thing. It is of such a nature as to exist in replicas. Look down a printed page, and
every the you see is the same word, every e the same letter. A real thing does not so exist in replica. The being of a sign is
merely being represented. Now really being and being represented are very different. Giving to the word sign the full scope
that reasonably belongs to it for logical purposes, a whole book is a sign; and a translation of it is a replica of the same
sign. […] Every sign that is sufficiently complete refers to sundry real objects. All these objects, even if we are talking of
Hamlet’s madness, are parts of one and the same Universe of being, the “Truth.” But so far as the “Truth” is merely the
object of a sign, it is merely the Aristotelian Matter of it that is so. In addition however to denoting objects, every sign
sufficiently complete signifies characters, or qualities. We have a direct knowledge of real objects in every experiential
reaction, whether of Perception or of Exertion (the one theoretical, the other practical). These are directly hic et nunc. But
we extend the category, and speak of numberless real objects with which we are not in direct reaction. We have also direct
knowledge of qualities in feeling, peripheral and visceral. But we extend this category to numberless characters of which
we have no immediate consciousness. All these characters are elements of the “Truth.” Every sign signifies the ‘Truth.’ But
it is only the Aristotelian Form of the universe that it signifies
(Peirce, 1998, pp. 303-304).
Signs consist of an invisibly triadic form, carrying and producing processes that manifest themselves through
the production of tokens. We see here Peirce’s categorical and semiotic foundation for his transdisciplinarity.
Peirce considered it his primary task to develop a metaphysical and epistemological architectonics, in the
framework of which his new theory of triadic categorical theory could be understood, and connected to a
dynamic triadic web of semiotics. This semiotic dynamics was viewed in terms of the processes of objective
mind (Raposa, 1989) with the advances over materialism to be based upon an emptiness ontology (Prigogine,
Stengers, 1984). This combination of emptiness ontology and the principle of continuity (synechism) is in
some respects close to Buddhism and, in other respects, to the vacuum field in modern quantum field
physics (Brier, 2014a, pp. 300–324; Peirce, 1998, pp. 303–304), again bridging science and spirituality in a
new philosophy (Brier, 2017b). Peirce was influenced by Aristotle’s concept of form, but his evolutionary
cosmogony was inspired by a combination of Hegel’s and Schelling’s perspectives on the matter as well as
by early 20th century scientific worldviews. Consequently, according to Peirce, a sign is a medium for the
communication of a form or the way a habit is embodied in the constraint of an object on the interpretant in
order to constrain the interpreter’s behavior as specifically as possible (Peirce, 1998, p. 544).
Through his triadic semiotics, Peirce regards the universe as an abstract symbolic process which,
through a process of self-development, unfolds its laws in the manifestation of signs and habits. What may
help to solve the deep problem of quantum dynamic views concerning the birth of the universe from the
Transdisciplinarity across the Qualitative and Quantitative Science through... 109
vacuum field filled with potential energy and particles to a world filled with sentient beings is the semiotic
dynamics of evolution. Peirce developed a most astonishing and novel view on the dynamics of the universe
as a series of symbols, all of which works through a so-called type-token process, with signs manifesting
themselves in the form of tokens and through habits as part of a huge semiotic process of transformation.
Here the symbolic sign plays a central role in how the Cosmos arises and develops from emptiness:
A symbol is something which has the power of reproducing itself, and that essentially, since it is constituted a symbol
only by the interpretation. This interpretation involves a power of the symbol to cause a real fact; and although I desire to
avoid metaphysics, yet when a false metaphysics invades the province of logic, I am forced to say that nothing can be more
futile than to attempt to form a conception of the universe which shall overlook the power of representations to cause real
facts. What is the purpose of trying to form a conception of the universe if it is not to render things intelligible? […] If we
are to explain the universe, we must assume that there was in the beginning a state of things in which there was nothing,
no reaction and no quality, no matter, no consciousness, no space and no time, but just nothing at all. Not determinately
nothing. For that which is determinately not A supposes the being of A in some mode. Utter indetermination. But a symbol
alone is indeterminate. Therefore, Nothing, the indeterminate of the absolute beginning, is a symbol. That is the way in
which the beginning of things can alone be understood.
(Houser, Kloesel, 1992, p. 322).
This emptiness cosmogony is something Peirce, surprisingly shares with modern physics in the sense that
the Tychistic idea of an inherent chance activity in emptiness is similar to the vacuum field, a theory to
be developed only after his death. The respect in which Peirce differs from modern physics is in how he
conceptualizes the ontological nature of what, in physics, is described as the spontaneous activity of virtual
particles. Here, Peirce’s inherent notion of chance activity in Tychism can serve to explain spontaneous
activity, whereas classical physics tends to work with a mechanical universe and therefore encounters
problems with explaining the emergence of consciousness in a mechanical - even though it is a quantum-
mechanical – world. This view has changed significantly in the last 50 years. John A. Wheeler’s “It from bit”
philosophy (Wheeler 1994) is a good, and maybe the most visionary example of this. As in Peirce’s semiotics
and as in general system theory, central to Wheeler’s perspective is a self-organizing process. Though much
cybernetics and systems theory operates with an observer, it is not an embodied and phenomenologically
grounded observer. It is here that Peirce’s triadic semiotic and pragmaticist philosophy is able to produce
an alternative model based on his concept of the symbol as a general force of habit in nature, humans, and
culture. From the passage just quoted, Peirce continues:
What logically follows? We are not to content ourselves with our instinctive sense of logicality. That is logical which comes
from the essential nature of a symbol. Now it is of the essential nature of a symbol that it determines an interpretant,
which is itself a symbol. A symbol, therefore, produces an endless series of interpretants. […] There can, it is true, be no
positive information about what antedated the entire Universe of being; because, to begin with, there was nothing to have
information about. But the universe is intelligible; and therefore it is possible to give a general account of it and its origin.
This general account is a symbol; and from the nature of a symbol, it must begin with the formal assertion that there was
an indeterminate nothing of the nature of a symbol. […].
(Peirce, 1998, pp. 322-324).
This view of the dynamics of the emergence of the universe, as of the nature of the dynamics of a general
symbolic, is unique for Peirce’s semiotic pragmaticism, showing just how much it develops a new ontology
for its synechist and fallibilist theory of science. It offers an alternative to mechanical thinking. That even
includes the quantum field version. It also differs from general system’s theory of self-organization on an
organicist basis and its theory of emergence, that is still questionable.
General system theory was originally formulated (von Bertalanffy, 1976/68) without Maturana and
Varela’s theory of autopoiesis. Luhmann only integrated this second order cybernetic theory of life later on
in his triple autopoietic system theory. It was carried out in a fashion criticized by Maturana and Varela,
because Luhmann extended their concept beyond the cybernetic biological realm in the frames of which it
was originally produced as a theory of the nature of the organization of living systems (Mingers, 1995, pp.
82-86). However, in the Peircean framework, manifestation in the form of tokens constitutes the intrinsic
110  S. Brier
nature of the symbolic function in nature as well as in culture. In Peircean semiotics, of course, symbols
need to be understood as something much more general than the way they are defined in linguistics. They
break out of language, so to speak, into a semiotic world where signs are as real as elementary particles.
Peirce develops his theory of the drive to be represented further in the same text:
As a symbol it produced its infinite series of interpretants, which in the beginning were absolutely vague like itself. But
the direct interpretant of any symbol must in the first stage of it be merely the tabula rasa for an interpretant. Hence
the immediate interpretant of this vague Nothing was not even determinately vague, but only vaguely hovering between
determinacy and vagueness; and its immediate interpretant was vaguely hovering between vaguely hovering between
vagueness and determinacy and determinate vagueness or determinacy, and so on, ad infinitum. But every endless series
must logically have a limit. […] Herein is a real effect; but a symbol could not be without that power of producing a real
effect. The symbol represents itself to be represented; and that representedness is real owing to its utter vagueness. For
all that is represented must be thoroughly borne out. [...] And the regularity is the symbol. Reality, therefore, can only be
regarded as the limit of the endless series of symbols. A symbol is essentially a purpose, that is to say, is a representation
that seeks to make itself definite, or seeks to produce an interpretant more definite than itself. […] By virtue of this, the
original replica animates the Interpretant, or by the sign it contains, with the power of representing the true character
of the object. That the object has at all a character can only consist in a representation that it has so,—a representation
having power to live down all opposition. In these two steps, of determination and of correction, the interpretant aims at
the object more than at the original replica and may be truer and fuller than the latter. The very entelechy of being lies in
being representable. A sign cannot even be false without being a sign and so far as it is a sign it must be true. A symbol is
an embryonic reality endowed with power of growth into the very truth, the very entelechy of reality. […] And the first of all
logical principles is that the indeterminate should determine itself as best it may. A chaos of reactions utterly without any
approach to law is absolutely nothing; and therefore pure nothing was such a chaos.
(Houser, Klosel, 1992, pp. 323-234).
Thus, Peirce provides, as an alternative to the classical mechanistic model of the universe, the self-
organizing dynamics of a symbol that endlessly produces its best possible representamens and by this goes
even further than the systems and cybernetics evolutionary idea of self-organization through dissipative
systems. It is a very anti-foundationalist view that avoids all sorts of scientism or fundamentalist religion.
However, it also provides a model of how to understand the emergence of life and consciousness in what
we usually consider to be a physical world of inert matter consisting of elementary particles driven by
absolute laws, but which in Peirce’s pragmaticist semiotic philosophy is viewed as a symbolically self-
organizing world. In this way, he manages to circumvent the mechanical view of nature that has isolated
physics from the life sciences and an understanding of embodied cognition and communication. Thus,
mind emerges from the self-organizing capacity of real sign dynamics and their tendency to aggregate into
greater complexes. Peirce wrote:
Consider then the aggregate formed by a sign and all the signs which its occurrence carries with it. This aggregate will itself
be a sign; and we may call it a perfect sign, in the sense that it involves the present existence of no other sign except such
as are ingredients of itself. Now no perfect sign is in a statical condition: you might as well suppose a portion of matter to
remain at rest during a thousandth of a second, or any other long interval of time. The only signs which are tolerably fixed
are non-existent abstractions. We cannot deny that such a sign is real; only its mode of reality is not that active kind which
we call existence. The existent acts, and whatsoever acts changes […]
Every real ingredient of the perfect sign is aging, its energy of action upon the interpretant is running low, its sharp edges
are wearing down, its outlines becoming more indefinite.
On the other hand, the perfect sign is perpetually being acted upon by its object, from which it is perpetually receiving
the accretions of new signs, which bring it fresh energy, and also kindle energy that it already had, but which had lain
dormant.
In addition, the perfect sign never ceases to undergo changes of the kind we rather drolly call spontaneous, that is, they
happen sua sponte but not by its will. They are phenomena of growth.
Such perfect sign is a quasi-mind.
(Houser, Klosel, 1992, p. 545).
The formation of habit through Thirdness is considered as the basic process of our reality in nature,
experience, cognition, and communication. Habit-taking is of course also basic to all kinds of magic and
religious rituals, but people often forget that they themselves are bundles of habits and thus subject to
progressive change too.
Transdisciplinarity across the Qualitative and Quantitative Science through... 111
For Peirce, the self is a symbol that grows with our life experience. Human beings find themselves
in a world perfused with habit-taking tendencies, themselves being bundles of habits because, as Peirce
explained, a habit is nothing other than the following:
… a specialization, original or acquired, of the nature of a man, or an animal, or a vine, or a crystallisable chemical
substance, or anything else, that he or it will behave, or always tend to behave, in a way describable in general terms
upon every occasion (or on a considerable proportion of the occasions) that may present itself of a generally describable
character.
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 5, para. 538).
As the laws are rather vague tendencies in the beginning that become more and more rigid habits as the
universe unfolds, Peirce’s crucial point is that we do not have any absolute knowledge. Knowledge develops
all the time - as in dialectical views, be they those held by Hegel, Marx, or Engels. This ontology creates
room for life and the evolution of mind. Peirce’s vision of the universe developing from emptiness - which
we have stressed is not much different from the vacuum field in modern quantum field physics, i.e. a
spontaneous chaos of all possibilities (Brier, 2014a) - is part of his semiotic vision that sees matter as effete
mind and the universe as a symbol in development of a grand argument (Peirce, 1998, p. 1853). As he also
points out in the relevant passage, a symbol “produces an endless series of interpretants,” and reality “can
only be regarded as the limit of the endless series of symbols. A symbol is essentially a purpose, that is to
say, is a representation that seeks to make itself definite, or seeks to produce an interpretant more definite
than itself.”
This is pretty close to general systems theory with its process ontology of the Self-organizing Universe
(Jantsch, 1980); but it adds the dynamics of the three categories, which is again similar to Hegel’s
dialectics, but developed into a semiotics. Thus, cosmogony and evolution are explained in terms of a
dynamic interaction between the three categories. Neither of the categories can be reduced to the other,
but cosmogonically viewed, they are derived from each other. Since Firstness is a state of absolute
possibility and radical indeterminacy as close to nothingness as possible, it is an absolute permissibility
with no cause outside itself. From here, Secondness emerges as one of many possibilities like difference,
otherness, individuality, limit, force, and will. Thirdness is the mediating habit-taking aspect of evolution
that contributes to the creation of an emergent semiotic order based on habits in matter as well as mind
and culture, which is somewhat different from Hegel’s dialectical evolution of objective Mind, as well
as different from the dialectical materialism of Friedrich Engels’ Dialectics of Nature of 1893. In contrast
to Engels, Peirce’s categories also have a phenomenological aspect to them; in contrast to Hegel, Peirce
introduces the category of Secondness, which creates the empirical connection to reality and as such the
possibility of falsification, which was later to become so important in Karl Popper’s philosophy of science.
But what is new compared to all other philosophies is his view of the universe as a developing symbol,
creating new habits of meaning as well as an endless stream of interpretants that make its reasoning powers
grow (Brier, 2014b) and extend into our cultures (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 1, para. 615).
Thus, for Peirce, habit, mediation, and reasoning power make up the basic character of reality,
proceeding from (what we call) dead nature, through living nature, mind, and culture all the way up to our
cultural and religious symbols. This is where synechism has other consequences. Peirce writes:
But, further, synechism recognizes that the carnal consciousness is but a small part of the man. There is, in the second
place, the social consciousness, by which a man’s spirit is embodied in others, and which continues to live and breathe
and have its being very much longer than superficial observers think […]
Nor is this, by any means, all. A man is capable of a spiritual consciousness, which constitutes him one of the eternal
verities, which is embodied in the universe as a whole. This as an archetypal idea can never fail; and in the world to come
is destined to a special spiritual embodiment.
A friend of mine, in consequence of a fever, totally lost his sense of hearing. He had been very fond of music before his
calamity; and, strange to say, even afterwards would love to stand by the piano when a good performer played. So then,
I said to him, after all you can hear a little. Absolutely not at all, he replied; but I can feel the music all over my body.
Why, I exclaimed, how is it possible for a new sense to be developed in a few months! It is not a new sense, he answered.
Now that my hearing is gone I can recognize that I always possessed this mode of consciousness, which I formerly, with
112  S. Brier
other people, mistook for hearing. In the same manner, when the carnal consciousness passes away in death, we shall at
once perceive that we have had all along a lively spiritual consciousness which we have been confusing with something
different.
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 575-577).
For Peirce, there is a growth of love and reasonableness in what he calls agapism (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 6,
para. 205). All of this is also part of our reasoning about nature and about our life and about how they are
connected and to what purpose.
Peirce’s semiotics is a general theory of all kinds of sign systems. Those systems include, as special
cases, all natural languages and all versions of formal logic. The idea that logic is semiotic is essential to
Peirce’s semiotic philosophy. What we usually call logic is only the limited formal side of the whole system,
which is a normative science for correct thinking based on signs. This is why the nature of signs and their
way to refer to and represent forms of reality are essential to fully understand logic. Evolution is a growth
in reasonableness (Stjernfelt, 2014), as well as in habit and order, and therefore tends towards goodness
or the summum bonum (Potters, 1997). Reverting to chaos and randomness cannot be a common good or
something anyone would desire. Reasonableness must be viewed as progress (Peirce, 1931-35, 5.4.). Peirce’s
Synechism is opposed to any kind of duality, be it between matter and mind, nature and culture, or between
science and religion. Still, Peirce considers this progress in reasonability as a metaphysical principle in the
philosophy of science and knowing that he calls pragmaticism (Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 7, para. 578). Peirce
wrote:
A widely current opinion during the last quarter of a century has been that reasonableness is not a good in itself, but only
for the sake of something else. Whether it be so or not seems to be a synthetical question, not to be settled by an appeal to
the principle of contradiction -- as if a reason for reasonableness were absurd. Almost everybody will now agree that the
ultimate good lies in the evolutionary process in some way. If so, it is not in individual reactions in their segregation, but
in something general or continuous. Synechism is founded on the notion that the coalescence, the becoming continuous,
the becoming governed by laws, the becoming instinct with general ideas, are but phases of one and the same process of
the growth of reasonableness. This is first shown to be true with mathematical exactitude in the field of logic, and is thence
inferred to hold good metaphysically. It is not opposed to pragmatism in the manner in which C.S. Peirce applied it, but
includes that procedure as a step.”
(Peirce, 1931-1958, Vol. 5, para. 4).
For Peirce, life, mind, logic, and semiosis are different concepts based in the actions of signs. Life emerges
from the dynamics of signs. Biosemiotics is fundamentally the study of symbols as living signs organizing
matter, energy and information. Semiosis is thus, in Peirce, naturalized to explain mental and living
processes, which are considered to be of the same nature as symbols (Romanini, 2014). Modern science has
the challenge of understanding the mental world in terms of the physical world described on a material and
energetic basis driven by absolute law. We now know that we have not come to the end of our knowledge
of matter and energy, since we are inventing new types of both, like dark matter and energy. If we want a
sort of monism – even if it is a triadic process one, we need to find a way to connect mind and matter. Info-
computationalism proposes that this can be done through the concept of information. Yet, so far, no-one
has found a scientific theory explaining how quale based consciousness could emerge from information
(Brier, 2017a; Brier, 2015b; Searle, 1989).
One way to attempt this is through Peirce’s and Aristotle’s ontological field view, which sees matter
and mind as part of a non-reducible continuity. This has the consequence of viewing matter as having an
“inside” that is somehow alive as a sort of Firstness: it has a spontaneous dynamics similar to what we have
found in the quantum physics idea of virtual particles spontaneously moving around in the vacuum field.
This idea of an inner movement of matter as a spontaneous evolutionary drive was already part of Engels
nature dialectics inspired by Hegel’s evolution of the spirit, but we can see a similar idea in Bertalanffy’s
general system theory because of its organicist basis. Bertalanffy was educated as a biologist. An important
difference between dialectical materialism and systems theory on the one hand and Peirce’s semiotic
pragmatism on the other is that none of these had a foundation in phenomenology as we find it in Hegel
Transdisciplinarity across the Qualitative and Quantitative Science through... 113
and Peirce (Ransdell, 2017). Hegel is the typical example of objective idealism. Peirce usually accepts that
term for his philosophy (Peirce, 1932-1958, Vol. 6, para. 25). However, it is the philosophy’s semiotic process
dynamics and pragmaticism that make it stand apart from all the other approaches.
By making nature symbolic and letting signs have their own self-organizing abilities, Peirce created
a philosophy of habits of nature that reveals a deep connection between our natural and socio-cultural
mental thinking and communication through symbols and stories to the effect that aesthetics, ethics, and
logics converge synergistically in the summum bonum (Brier, 2014b; Potters, 1997). It is my view that Peirce
needs to be updated with reference to modern quantum field theory, but that his philosophical framework
can encompass the developments in this area (Brier, 2013). His view can be enlarged and updated by
integrating Luhmann’s triple autopoietic system theory in order both to incorporate modern information
and communications theory as well as a more developed theory of social dynamics. This is the reason for
my creation of the Cybersemiotic framework (Brier, 2017b), a modernized version of Peirce’s pragmaticism
(cf. Apel, 1981).
Brian Josephson (forthcoming 2018) has recently been inspired by Peircean biosemiotics and by Karen
Barad’s development of Niels Bohr’s complementarity philosophy into an agential realism (Barad, 2017),
that makes the biological level of reality as – or even more – fundamental than the physical and thereby
clearly steps out of a mechanical ontological view of nature. From a Peircean view, this is a step in the right
direction of reflections on the ontological presumptions of modern natural science towards a more semiotic
and process-oriented understanding of reality.
Cybersemiotics takes a step further and suggests that the natural, life, social-hermeneutical, and
mental-phenomenological sciences are equally ontological fundamental, as one cannot be reduced to any
of the others (Brier, 2013). It is in harmony with the quantum physicist Nicolescu’s (2014) definition of
transdisciplinarity based on a holistic non-hierarchical ontology of levels, where it is impossible to point
out any of them as being most fundamental and the project of reducing one to the other must be given up
in order to produce a true transdisciplinary ontology and epistemology
Acknowledgements: Thanks to Raffaela Giovagnoli suggesting this topic, organizing and chairing the
session and further publication. Many thanks go to Alina Therese Lettner for her relentless efforts to help me
express my thoughts in proper English. Any shortcomings left in this paper are my own responsibility and
finally thanks to the department of Management, Society and Communication for covering the expenses
connected to producing this publication.
Conflicts of Interest: The author has no conflict of interest to declare.
References
Apel, K. O. (1981). Charles S. Peirce:from pragmatism to pragmaticism. Boston, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.
Barad, K. (2017). Meeting the universe halfway: quantum physics and the entanglement of matter and meaning, Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
von Bertalanffy, L. (1976/68). General System Theorie. Foundations, development, applications, New York, NY: Braziller.
Brier, S. (2013). Cybersemiotics: why information is not enough, Toronto: Toronto University Press.
Brier, S. (2014a). Pure zero. In T. Thellefsen & B. Sørensen (Eds.), Charles Sanders Peirce in His Own Words-100 Years of
Semiotics, Communication and Cognition (pp. 207–212). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.
Brier, S. (2014b). The riddle of the sphinx answered: on how C.S. Peirce’s transdisciplinary semiotic philosophy of knowing
links science, spirituality and knowing; death and anti-death, Ann Arbor, MI: Ria University Press; Volume 12, pp. 47–130.
Brier, S. (2015a). Cybersemiotics and the reasoning powers of the universe: Philosophy of
information in a Semiotic-Systemic Transdisciplinary Approach. Green Lett. Stud. Ecocriticism. doi:10.1080/14688417.20
15.1070684.
Brier, S. (2015b). Can biosemiotics be a “science” if its purpose is to be a bridge between the natural, social and human
sciences? Progress in Biophysics & Molecular Biology, 119, 576-587.
Brier, S. (2017a). How to produce a transdisciplinary information concept for a universal theory of information, In: M. Burgin,
W. Hofkirchner (Eds.). Information studies and the quest for transdisciplinarity: unity through diversity, World Scientific
Series in Information Studies: Volume 9, Singapore: World Scientific.
114  S. Brier
Brier, S. (2017b). How Peircean semiotic philosophy connects Western science with Eastern emptiness ontology. Progress in
Biophysics and Molecular Biology. 131, 22-107.
Houser, N., Kloesel, C. (Eds.) (1992). The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University
Press, Vol. 1.
Jantsch, E. (1980). The Self-Organizing Universe; New York, NY: Pergamon Press.
Josephson, B. D. (forthcoming 2018). Biological organization as the true foundation of reality, In: R. L. Amoroso, L. H.
Kauffman, P. Rowlands (Eds.), Unified Field Mechanics II: 10th International Symposium in Honor of Mathematical
Physicist Jean-Pierre Vigier, Singapore: World Scientific Publishing.
Mingers, J. (1995). Self-producing systems: implications and applications of autopoiesis, New York and London: Plenum Press.
Nicolescu, B. (2014). From modernity to cosmodernity: science, culture and spirituality, Albany, NY: State University of New
York Press (S U N Y Series in Western Esoteric Traditions).
Peirce, C. S. (1931-1958). Collected papers. C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss (Eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 8 vols.
[Past Masters CD-ROM version]
Peirce, C.S. (1998). The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, Volume 2.
Potters, V. G. (1997). Charles S. Peirce: on norms & ideals; New York, NY: Fordham University Press.
Prigogine, I., Stengers, I. (1984). Order Out of Chaos; New York, NY: Bantam Books.
Ransdell, J. (2017). Is Peirce a phenomenologist?. Cybernetics & Human Knowing. 24, 69–81. (This paper appeared in print in a
French translation by André Detienne (1989) as “Peirce est-il un phénoménologue?” in Ètudes Phénoménologiques, 9-10,
51-75. This English-language version is the original translated into French and has never been published in paper before
2017).
Raposa, M. L. (1989). Peirce’s philosophy of religion; Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Romanini, V. (2014). Semiosis as a living process, In V. Romanini & E. Fernández (Eds.), Peirce and biosemiotics: a guess at the
riddle of life (pp. 215–239). Dordrecht: Springer.
Searle, J. (1989). Minds, brains and science. London: Penguin Books.
Smolin, L. (2013). Time Reborn, London: Alan Lane.
Stjernfelt, F. (2014). Natural Propositions; Boston, MA: Docent Press.
Wheeler, J. A. (1994). At home in the universe, Woodbury, NY: AIP Press.
... The indicator that appears is to look for relevant signs. This is in accordance with the opinion (Arzarello & Sabena, 2011;Brier, 2018) which states that images are signs that represent trueto-life properties with their own simple nature. Where simple means that these properties are relevant to the original nature. ...
Article
Full-text available
Playing mathematics in early childhood based on semiotics gives children the opportunity to identify objects, look for signs and interpret signs so that they can solve problems in games. This study aims to describe semiotic based early childhood mathematics play activities. The research was conducted at the PAUD Lab School, Muhammadiyah University of Jember. The research subjects were 5 children from group B. The results showed that the activities of playing mathematics in early childhood based on semiotics were (1) collecting information related to semiotic-based math games, (2) looking for objects that matched the game and counting the number of objects found, (3) looking for relevant signs and signs. that are relevant to the number of objects found, (4) associated with signs of knowledge that have been previously possessed and look for all signs according to the objects found, (5) the child retells the play that has been done
Chapter
ch. 13 in Carlos Vidales and Søren Brier (Eds.) CYBERSEMIOTICS: A TRANSDISCIPLINARY PERSPECTIVE. Dordrecht: Springer (Biosemiotics 21), pp. 317-398. Preview (Abstract, Appendices and References) available on https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-030-52746-4_13 For the first two pages of the introduction see the upload in the entry just above! The aim of this chapter is to set out the basic coordinates of a cybersemiotic philology of Buddhist knowledge forms in order to further develop the non-anthropocentric dimensions and process-philosophical potential of both Buddhism and Peircean semiotics. This is also meant to lay the foundations for an interculturally and philologically enriched cybersemiotics. Proceeding from the logical conception of philosophical categories and their philological explication, the transdisciplinary model of a semiotic philology of thought forms (Lettner, diss. thesis, forthc.) develops an intercultural explication of “thought forms” with regard to the three interdependent pillars of philosophy (epistemological “knowledge forms”), philology (textualised “language forms”) and cultural studies (“life forms” as culture-related practices). In a first step, the reconstruction of paradigmatic modes of knowledge representation will be exemplified with regard to the approaches of Aristotelian philosophy, various positions of premodern Indian Buddhism as well as the paradigms of modern science and postclassical physics. In the second step of a cybersemiotic interpretation, Peirce’s synechistic understanding of habit will serve us to enlarge the culture-specific notion of life forms as pragmatically grounded thought forms by making it converge with the ethologically informed, biosemiotic notion of “life forms” embraced by cybersemiotics. Exploring cybersemiotics as developed by Brier (2008) from the perspective of Indian Buddhist philosophy intends to work out the phenomenological purport of Peirce’s approach, with its move of locating agency in the process of semiosis, by comparing it to the Buddhist psycho-ontological view of agency expressed in the fundamental principle of “dependent arising” (pratītyasamutpāda). In view of such synergies, we can bring the cybersemiotic interest in the unfolding of knowledge “from our bio-psycho-socio-linguistic conscious being” (Brier 2008) to bear upon the Buddhist notion of “no self” (anātman/ anattā). Thus, Kant’s transcendental subject, whose unity of apperception was dynamised by Peirce’s semiotic transformation of the categories, can now “go intercultural” by further desubstantialising signification in terms of a Buddhist cybersemiotics. Such a deconstruction of the supposed stability of “objects” and “concepts” as exemplified by the substance-philosophical belief in an ontological priority of “objects” will be accomplished in view of 1. the Buddhist explanation of unitary, stable objects existing “in name only” (prajñaptisat) with regard to “apperception” (saṁjñā) and the famous criticism of “conceptual construction” (kalpanā) by the epistemologist Dignāga (ca. 480–540) and 2. the cybersemiotic view of “objects and concepts as cognitive invariants” (Brier 2008) inspired by von Foerster’s second-order cybernetics and the creation of self-organised Umwelten (in the sense of Uexküll).
Chapter
After Thomas Sebeok’s proposal of global semiotics in the 70s, an attempt to move beyond anthroposemiotics to the realm of zoosemiotics, phytosemiotics, endosemiotics, and, ultimately, to the all-encompassing realm of biosemiotics was made. Semiotics was then established as a serious candidate as the transdisciplinary base of science and humanities –particularly from the triadic and pragmaticist semiotic proposal of C. S. Peirce. However, the semiotic attempt to explain the fundamental aspects of living systems from the standpoint of meaning production and reproduction demonstrate that in order to explain the meaning-making process in living organisms a systemic, biological, cybernetic and informational approach was also needed. The integrative visions have discovered some basic similarities among these theoretical perspectives from which it has been possible to recognize complementarities among them. At the same time, it also made possible to identify variations at the very bottom of each approach, which resulted in a complex task of theoretical integration. Thus, in order to uncover these tensions and complementarities, I will focus my attention in the process of communication in an attempt to move from cybernetics to semiotics and further on to cybersemiotics considering some aspects of biosemiotics, first and second-order cybernetics, Peircean semiotics, and information theory. The goal of this chapter is to overcome the problem of defining the limits and boundaries of communication as a physical, biological, and social phenomena and its nature as an academic field by proposing communication as a transdisciplinary concept from the point of view of cybersemiotics (Vidales, Commun Soc 30:45–67, 2017b), from which it is also possible to address the process of communication, explained in what Brier (Cogn Semiotics 4:28–63, 2009) considers to be the levels of cybersemiotics, and the consequences it may have for the explanation of meaning-making processes in living systems.
Chapter
Full-text available
This text proposes a conceptual model to understand and study the communicative phenomenon. It does this by understanding communication as a phenomenon of life, so that it can be conceptualized as an expressive behavior that results in an expressive act within the framework of the theory of evolution, which makes the expression as a unit viable of primary observation of communication. Although it is based on a concept of communication slightly different from that assumed in the cybersemiotic program, we consider that the biophenomenological proposal of the communication presented here can serve as an articulation for the development of at least three of the arms proposed by Brier in his Star Cybersemiotics, so that it contributes to the development of this ambitious and necessary transdisciplinary program.
Chapter
Full-text available
The presumptions underlying quantum mechanics make it relevant to a limited range of situations only; furthermore, its statistical character means that it provides no answers to the question ‘what is really going on?’. Following Barad, I hypothesise that the underlying mechanics has parallels with human activities, as used by Barad to account for the way quantum measurements introduce definiteness into previously indefinite situations. We are led to consider a subtle type of order, different from those commonly encountered in the discipline of physics, and yet comprehensible in terms of concepts considered by Barad and Yardley such as oppositional dynamics or ‘intra-actions’. The emergent organisation implies that nature is no longer fundamentally meaningless. Agencies can be viewed as dynamical systems, so we are dealing with models involving interacting dynamical systems. The ‘congealing of agencies’ to which Barad refers can be equated to the presence of regulatory mechanisms restricting the range of possibilities open to the agencies concerned.
Article
Full-text available
To follow the transdisciplinary ambition in much information science and philosophy leading to cognitive science we need to include a phenomenological and hermeneutical ground in order to encompass a theory of interpretative meaning and signification to achieve a transdisciplinary theory of knowing and communication. This is also true if we start in cybernetics and system theory that also have transdisciplinary aspirations for instance in Batesons ecological concept of information as a difference that makes a difference and in Luhmann’s triple autopoietic communication-based system theory. Charles Sanders Peirce’s pragmaticist semiotics integrates logic and information in interpretative semiotics. But although Peirce’s information theory is built on meaningful signs and he connects information to the growth of symbols, his information theory is empirically based in a realistic worldview, which in the development to modern biosemiotics include all living systems.
Article
Charles S. Peirce occupies a secure and significant position in the annals of American intellectual history. His impact on contemporary philosophy, logic, semiotic, literary theory and communication studies has been enormous. Nevertheless, only a handful of theologians and philosophers of religion have looked to his writings as an important resource; very few of his commentators have paid to the religious dimension of his thought the attention that it deserves.^ The purpose of this dissertation is to underscore the role that religious ideas played in shaping Peirce's philosophy, and to provide a systematic account of his philosophy of religion. There is a hermeneutical difficulty here; very few of Peirce's writings are devoted explicitly to religious topics. I contend, however, that Peirce's interest in and perspective on such topics are manifested throughout his corpus, in scientific and mathematical papers, as well as in his writings on metaphysics, cosmology and the normative sciences. I conclude that Peirce's religious ideas are continuous with and integral to his reflections on these other issues, so that they must be identified and understood if his work as a whole is to be interpreted properly. And I suggest that his writings ought to be considered an important resource for contemporary scholars of religion, briefly indicating at the end of my study those of his ideas that might be most fruitfully entertained and developed.^ Peirce's most famous essay in the philosophy of religion, "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God," provides a useful sketch of his general religious perspective. I use the argument there to organize my study; an extended commentary on that essay comprises my fifth, penultimate chapter.
Article
In recent articles in this journal I have discussed why a traditional physicalist and mechanist, as well as an info-computationalist, view of science cannot fulfil the goal of building a transdisciplinary science across Snow's two cultures. There seems to be no path proceeding from mechanistic physicalism to views that encompass phenomenological theories of experiential consciousness and meaning-based cognition and communication. I have suggested, as an alternative, the Cybersemiotic framework's integration of Peirce's semiotics and Luhmann's autopoietic system theory. The present article considers in greater depth the ontological developments necessary to make this possible. It shows how Peirce avoids materialism and German idealism through his building on a concept of emptiness similar to modern quantum field theory, positing an indeterminist objective chance feeding into an evolutionary philosophy of knowing based on pure mathematics and phenomenology that is itself combined with empirically executed fallibilism. Furthermore, he created a new metaphysics in the form of a philosophical synechist triadic process philosophy. This was integrated into the transcendentalist view of process view of science and spirituality developed from Western Unitarianism by Emerson (agapism), and featuring a metaphysics of emptiness and spontaneity (tychism) that are also essential for the Eastern philosophies of Buddhism and Vedanta.
Book
A growing field of inquiry, biosemiotics is a theory of cognition and communication that unites the living and the cultural world. What is missing from this theory, however, is the unification of the information and computational realms of the non-living natural and technical world. Cybersemiotics provides such a framework. By integrating cybernetic information theory into the unique semiotic framework of C.S. Peirce, Søren Brier attempts to find a unified conceptual framework that encompasses the complex area of information, cognition, and communication science. This integration is performed through Niklas Luhmann’s autopoietic systems theory of social communication. The link between cybernetics and semiotics is, further, an ethological and evolutionary theory of embodiment combined with Lakoff and Johnson’s ’philosophy in the flesh.’ This demands the development of a transdisciplinary philosophy of knowledge as much common sense as it is cultured in the humanities and the sciences. Such an epistemological and ontological framework is also developed in this volume. Cybersemiotics not only builds a bridge between science and culture, it provides a framework that encompasses them both. The cybersemiotic framework offers a platform for a new level of global dialogue between knowledge systems, including a view of science that does not compete with religion but offers the possibility for mutual and fruitful exchange.
Chapter
Peirce’s theory of signs is not easy to grasp and there are a number of reasons for that. The most important is that it is unfinished. For nearly 40 years, Peirce actively worked on his system of logic he regarded to be the same as semeiotic. In these four decades, Peirce produced dozens of different definitions for the term “sign” and its fundamental aspects (which he called respects, probably meaning that they were always respective to one another, as in CP 8.343). The simple ones are quite similar because they involve only the three basic aspects and their correlation. So we can say without fear of mistake that a sign is anything that represents its object as to produce an effect, which is its interpretant.