ArticlePublisher preview available

The moral standing of the dead

The Royal Society
Philosophical Transactions B
Authors:
To read the full-text of this research, you can request a copy directly from the author.

Abstract

In choosing to do certain things, we appear to presuppose that we can act in the interests the dead, and that we have a duty to do so. For example, some of us go to great lengths to carry out their final wishes. Given that the dead no longer exist, however, it seems that nothing can be good or bad for them: they lack prudential interests. In that case, it is hard to see how we could owe them anything. They seem to lack moral standing altogether. In this essay, I will rebut this line of thought. I will claim that in some cases things that happen after people die are indeed good or bad for them. Their interests can still be advanced or hindered, so the dead have moral standing. This article is part of the theme issue ‘Evolutionary thanatology: impacts of the dead on the living in humans and other animals’.
rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org
Research
Cite this article: Luper S. 2018 The moral
standing of the dead. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B
373: 20170270.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2017.0270
Accepted: 7 February 2018
One contribution of 18 to a theme issue
‘Evolutionary thanatology: impacts of the dead
on the living in humans and other animals’.
Subject Areas:
evolution
Keywords:
death, moral standing, posthumous harm,
well-being, achievementism, animal ethics
Author for correspondence:
Steven Luper
e-mail: sluper@trinity.edu
The moral standing of the dead
Steven Luper
Philosophy, Trinity University, San Antonio, TX 78212, USA
SL, 0000-0002-5992-9215
In choosing to do certain things, we appear to presuppose that we can act in
the interests the dead, and that we have a duty to do so. For example, some
of us go to great lengths to carry out their final wishes. Given that the dead
no longer exist, however, it seems that nothing can be good or bad for them:
they lack prudential interests. In that case, it is hard to see how we could
owe them anything. They seem to lack moral standing altogether. In this
essay, I will rebut this line of thought. I will claim that in some cases
things that happen after people die are indeed good or bad for them.
Their interests can still be advanced or hindered, so the dead have moral
standing.
This article is part of the theme issue ‘Evolutionary thanatology: impacts
of the dead on the living in humans and other animals’.
1. The moral standing of the dead
Must the living act on behalf of the dead? Many of us seem to think so, given
things we do after others die. For example, some of us believe that we must
carry out the final wishes of friends who have died, and go to great lengths
to do so. However, there is a strong case for concluding that the dead lack
moral standing altogether, which is to deny that the way we treat them matters
from the moral point of view. Roughly stated, the case is this. We would have
duties to the dead only if they had prudential interests. Yet they do not: nothing
can be good or bad for them. In that way the dead are like bags of sand, arm-
chairs and boulders. So we owe them nothing. In this essay, I will attempt to
rebut this argument. My main strategy will be to criticize the assumption
that the interests of people are never affected by anything that happens after
they die. Elaborating upon previous work [1], I will attempt to clarify why
this assumption seems plausible yet is false. If I am successful, it will be clear
why and in what sense the dead matter from the moral point of view: they
may have interests that are advanced or hindered by those who are still alive,
and what affects people’s interests is always relevant from the standpoint of
morality.
2. Die, dead, death and the dead
I begin with some remarks about the word ‘death’ and related terms that
feature prominently in the discussion.
The term ‘death’ is ambiguous as between dying and being dead. In what fol-
lows I will disambiguate ‘death’ when necessary by using the terms ‘dying’ or
‘being dead’. I stipulate that to die is to cease to be alive, and I assume that what
ceases to be alive ceases to exist. But what is it for you to be dead? Is it the state
you are placed into by virtue of dying? That suggests that you may be in some
state while not existing. Here is a better proposal: to say you are dead is an
abbreviated way of stating that you are dead at some given time, which, in
turn, is simply to say that you died before then. When we omit to mention
time of death, we refer implicitly to the present, so that ‘you are dead’ means
you died before now. In a similar fashion, we can use ‘the dead’ as shorthand
for ‘those who died before now’ [2].
Note, finally, that it is one thing to be harmed (or benefitted) by death and
another to be harmed (or benefitted) by something occurring after we have
&2018 The Author(s) Published by the Royal Society. All rights reserved.
... They are words and instructions that ought to be religiously adhered to. There is a moral imperative and duty to fulfil the wishes of the dead, especially if they are achievable [36]. One interviewee detailed the contents of last words of a dying person as follows; ...
... This relates to the understanding that the dead body has moral standing and moral value [36,38]. Moral standing can be based on intrinsic value. ...
... On this analysis, the dead would have moral standing. Their final value would be based on the extrinsic value of respect of human life [36]. Indeed, to the Basoga, this reflection is on the basis that in spite of death, robbing them of a living person, the body remains a dignified creation of Kibumba [32,33]. ...
Article
Full-text available
Numerous studies on death in African societies with no doubt have been successfully conducted though their preoccupation has been with the religious and spirituality perspectives. There has been a great deal of theologizing about the spiritual connection between the life here and life after death. Most studies in the humanities have zeroed on burial rituals and rites as means of transition to the spiritual world. Others have concentrated on how different societies cope with the misfortune of death; through grieving, mourning, choosing an heir or heiress and the succession disputes that are always part and parcel of such a culturally acknowledged process. Death is largely constructed as a challenge and misfortune, and many a scholar in the humanities are concerned with how different societies define, perceive, handle and cope with this catastrophe. Most scholarly works have paid a deaf ear to the social value that comes with the demise of an individual. One such social value is the definition and shaping of moral order in society, in which death occurs. Busoga traditional society of Uganda is used as the case study. Busoga is both a geographical reality and cultural entity, found in the eastern part of Uganda. The authors argue that rather than militating life, death promotes and perpetuates moral values on one hand and discourages vices that destabilize society on the other.
... 24 For the skeptical view see, for example, Partridge (1981) and Callahan (1987). 25 See Feinberg (1984), Pitcher (1984), Fisher (2001), Ridge (2003), Meyer (2004), Luper (2018), andStemplowska (2020). 26 Here again it should be noted that de-extinction is not an apparent choice. ...
Article
Full-text available
While anthropogenic species extinctions can be considered morally problematic for a range of reasons, they can also be described as a problem of interspecies justice. That is the focus of this paper in which we argue that human-caused species extinctions can be integrated within a non-anthropocentric account of reparative justice that is significantly similar to how reparation is understood within political theory at large. An account such as this faces a series of difficulties, such as how to make right past injustices against victims that do not exist any longer and which belonged to species now extinct. For that purpose, we offer an argument in favour of symbolic forms of reparation in the form of, amongst other things, the preservation and restoration of habitat to materially repair the interspecies justice relationship; as well as monuments and education to honour the nonhuman dead.
... In some respects, anonymization can be regarded as a way of protecting the sensibilities of the family and/or friends of body donors, as well as upholding the inherent dignity of the living while disrespecting the dead (e.g., through the practice of "cutting" and dissection of the deceased) is thought to jeopardize. While some argue that once dead the body donor can no longer be harmed as they have no interests, 42,43 others argue that we can be harmed posthumously, [44][45][46] as is attested by the lengths we go to respect the final wishes of loved ones who have died, as well as the legal standing given to wills. So, while the consent of body donors remains both a moral and legal imperative, a broader appreciation of how donors would like to be represented to students (anonymized or personalized) would support a more meaningful account of what 'respecting their wishes' entails. ...
Article
Full-text available
Clinical anatomy education is meant to prepare students for caring for the living, often by working with the dead. By their nature many clinical anatomy education programs privilege topographical form over the donor's humanity. This inbalance between the living and the dead generates tensions between the tangible and the spiritual insofar as semblances of the humanity of donors endure even in depictions and derivatives. This article argues that considering the relevance of spirituality, and what endures of a donor's humanity after death, would enhance contemporary anatomy education and the ethical treatment of human body donors (and derivatives). In developing this argument, we (the authors) address the historical connection between spirituality and anatomy, including the anatomical locations of the soul. This serves as a basis for examining the role of the mimetic—or imitative—potential of deceased human donors as representations of the living. We deliberate on the ways in which the depersonalization and anonymization of those donating challenge the mimetic purpose of human body donors and the extent to which such practices are misaligned with the health care shift from a biomedical to a biopsychosocial model. Weighing up the risks and opportunities of anonymization versus personalization of human body donors, we propose curricula that could serve to enhance the personalization of human donors to support students learning topographical form. In doing so, we argue that the personalization of human donors and depictions could prevent the ill effects of digital representations going “viral,” and enhance opportunities for donors to help the general public learn more about the human form.
... In our view, one promising idea is this: In treating a human corpse inappropriately, a person reveals an attitude of dishonoring and disrespecting human dignity in a symbolic sense. To illustrate this, take an example discussed within the philosophy of violence: There is a huge difference 8 Some authors argue that an interest-based account of well-being is not able to cover posthumous harm while an account of harm based on the achievement of some goals might cover the intuitions behind the possibility of posthumous harm [40][41][42] But these adaptations of the Feinberg-Pitcher account do not rebutt the objection that the dead are beyond harm for there is nobody anymore that cares about those important goals or life-projects. between throwing some stones at a tool shed's window and throwing some stones at a synagogue's, a mosque's, or a church's window. ...
Article
Full-text available
In dealing with human corpses, notions of dignity play a decisive role, especially within legal texts that regulate a corpse’s handling. However, it is quite unclear how the claim “Treat human corpses with dignity!” should be understood and justified. Drawing upon examples and problems from forensic medicine, this paper explores three possible lines of interpreting such demands: (a) positions that closely link the dignity of the human corpse to the dignity of the former living persons and (b) accounts that derive the dignity of the dead from consequentialist considerations. We argue that both lines heavily rely on contestable metaphysical claims and therefore propose an alternative account for the dignity of the dead. Our proposal (c) focuses on action-guiding attitudes and the symbolic value of the dead. Such a conception allows for a variety of morally appropriate groundings of individual attitudes. It avoids metaphysically troublesome premises and, at the same time, allows to classify certain actions and manners of acting as clearly inappropriate and blameworthy.
... 37 It is important to notice that most authors accord to think that at least some critical interests of a person extend after his or her death. 34,[38][39][40][41][42] So the duty of the relatives is to protect and honour not only the body of their loved one but also his or her interests and values. ...
Article
Full-text available
Background Even in countries with an opt-out or presumed consent system, relatives have a considerable influence on the post-mortem organ harvesting decision. However, their reflection capacity may be compromised by grief, and they are, therefore, often prone to choose refusal as default option. Quite often, it results in late remorse and dissatisfaction. So, a high-quality reflection support seems critical to enable them to gain a stable position and a long-term peace of mind, and also avoid undue loss of potential grafts. In practice, recent studies have shown that the ethical aspects of reflection are rarely and often poorly discussed with relatives and that no or incomplete guidance is offered. No review of the literature is available to date, although it could be of value to improve the quality of the daily practice. Objectives The objective was to review and synthesize the main concepts and approaches, theories and practices of ethical reflection support of the relatives or surrogates of potential post-mortem organ donors. Research design A narrative review was performed in the medical, psychological and ethical fields using PubMed, PsycArticles and Web of Science databases (1980–2020). Results Out of 150 papers, 25 were finally retained. Four themes were drawn: the moral status of the potential post-mortem organ donor, the principlistic approach with its limits and critics, the narrative approach and the transcendental approach. Discussion This review suggests an extension of psychological support towards ethical reflection support. The process of helping relatives in their ethical exploration of post-mortem organ donation is psychologically and morally characterized. The need for specialized professionals educated and experienced both in clinical psychology and in health ethics to carry out this task is discussed. Practical impact This review could contribute to optimize the quality of the ethical reflection support by initiating an evolution from an empirical, partial and individual-dependent support to a more systematized, professionalized and exhaustive support.
... Perhaps the most profound indication that most societies believe-if unconsciously-in some kind of continued agency of the dead, is their persistence in the moral systems of the living. Luper [25] provides a philosophical treatment of the moral issues surrounding our treatment of the dead, asking if the dead have moral standing. By demonstrating that events that happen after an individual's death can indeed be good or bad for them (despite the fact that they are dead)-and thus by affecting their prudential interests it is possible for us to benefit or harm them posthumously-the dead can be argued to have moral standing. ...
Article
Full-text available
Societies, including those of humans, have evolved multiple ways of dealing with death across changing circumstances and pressures. Despite many studies focusing on specialized topics, for example necrophoresis in eusocial insects, mortuary activities in early human societies, or grief and mourning in bereavement, there has been little attempt to consider these disparate research endeavours from a broader evolutionary perspective. Evolutionary thanatology does this by adopting an explicit evolutionary stance for studies of death and dying within the sociological, psychological and biological disciplines. The collection of papers in this themed issue demonstrates the value of this approach by describing what is known about how various nonhuman species detect and respond to death in conspecifics, how problems of disposing of the dead have evolved in human societies across evolutionary time and also within much shorter time frames, how human adults' understanding of death develops, and how it is ultimately reflected in death-related language. The psychological significance and impact of death is clearly seen in some species' grief-like reactions to the loss of attachment figures, and perhaps uniquely in humans, the existence of certain psychological processes that may lead to suicide. Several research questions are proposed as starting points for building a more comprehensive picture of the ontogeny and phylogeny of how organisms deal with death. This article is part of the theme issue ‘Evolutionary thanatology: impacts of the dead on the living in humans and other animals’.
Chapter
Meaningful lives are often thought to be lives that are in some way “important”, but it is unclear what importance actually consists in. In this chapter Hauskeller puts the idea to the test by looking at the role that among other things football plays in the lives of many fans and the different ways in which things can become important in people’s lives. It turns out that while people often seek and gain importance through extraordinary achievements, what makes their life meaningful is not their achievements as such, but the importance those achievements have for them through the role they play in their life. The chapter concludes with a critical examination of the common assumption that our lives can become more meaningful through events taking place after our death, such as the posthumous recognition we receive for our achievements.
Chapter
This chapter shifts the focus to the relational dimension of moral consideration, juxtaposing it with properties-based views. It first explores purely relational approaches to moral consideration that prioritize extrinsic relations over intrinsic properties. The chapter argues against these relational perspectives by highlighting their implausible implications in cases of social isolation and their tendency toward moral relativism, among other issues. As an alternative, it proposes a middle ground that integrates both properties and relations into moral consideration. This hybrid approach recognizes the importance of properties such as sentience and sapience, while also acknowledging that one can come to possess intrinsic value through certain morally significant relationships. By embracing this approach, the chapter seeks to account for the moral significance of sentient and sapient beings while addressing concerns of moral underinclusion associated with “properties-only” views.
Article
In this article, I sort through some of the confusion surrounding what constitutes the controversial notion of a “good death” for children. I distinguish, first, between metaphysical and practical disagreements about the notion of a good death, and, second, between accounts of a good death that minimally and maximally promote the dying child’s interests. I propose a narrowed account of the dying child’s interests, because they differ from the interests of non-dying children. Importantly, this account illustrates how disagreements at the end of a child’s life are sometimes the result of a shift from a future to a present-oriented understanding of the child’s interests on the part of some stakeholders but not others, and sometimes the result of a values-based disagreement about how different interests should be weighted. This brings into sharper focus the questions of for whom, and in what way, a child’s death might be considered good.
Article
This chapter examines the concept of the so-called retroactive harms and wrongs related to death, explaining the principle of the immunity thesis which holds that nothing that happens after we are dead harms or benefits us. It presents a case against the existence of proactively harmful postmortem events and argues that an action taken after people die may wrong them retroactively by harming them or by interfering with their desires while they are alive.
Article
I take the view that dying is bad for those who otherwise would have lived well, and good for those who otherwise would have fared badly, but also that never existing is neither good nor bad for people. The latter claim I refer to as the indifference thesis. I review discussions in the literature concerning the indifference thesis, almost all of them critical. Then I offer a fresh defense of that thesis. My claim is that events (or states of affairs) that help us to acquire the capacities involved in faring well or ill help make it possible for events to harm or benefit us, but are themselves neither good nor bad for us. Coming into existence is one of these events.
Chapter
What is death? How is it related to the existence of living things? Is it possible for something to continue its existence while dead? In this chapter I will attempt to answer these questions. I will begin by arguing that death is the loss of life. I will then consider whether living things could cease to exist without dying, and whether they could die yet continue existing. Finally, I will discuss some ways my conclusions bear on creatures like you and me.
Article
The Philosophy of Death is a discussion of the basic philosophical issues concerning death, and a critical introduction to the relevant contemporary philosophical literature. Luper begins by addressing questions about those who die: What is it to be alive? What does it mean for you and me to exist? Under what conditions do we persist over time, and when do we perish? Next, he considers several questions concerning death, including: What does dying consist in; in particular, how does it differ from ageing? Must death be permanent? By what signs may it be identified? Is death bad for the one who dies? If so why? Finally he discusses whether, and why, killing is morally objectionable, and suggests that it is often permissible; in particular, (assisted) suicide, euthanasia and abortion may all be morally permissible. His book is a lively and engaging philosophical treatment of a perennially fascinating and relevant subject.
Article
Article
Rejetant la these de l'independance selon laquelle le mal est independant des personnes, l'A. defend l'idee qu'un evenement ne peut affecter quelqu'un que s'il concerne son corps ou son esprit. Soulevant la question de l'experience antemortem et de l'experience postmortem, l'A. distingue les notions de personne et existence, interet personnel et interet impersonnel, prejudice et echec.