ArticlePDF Available

The Desire For Work As An Adaptive Preference

Authors:

Abstract

Many economists and social theorists hypothesize that most societies could soon face a ‘post-work’ future, one in which employment and productive labor have a dramatically reduced place in human affairs. Given the centrality of employment to individual identity and its pivotal role as the primary provider of economic and other goods, transitioning to a ‘post-work’ future could prove traumatic and disorienting to many. Policymakers are thus likely to face the difficult choice of the extent to which they ought to satisfy individual citizens’ desires to work in a socioeconomic environment in which work is in permanent decline. Here I argue that policymakers confronting a post-work economy should discount, or at least consider problematic, the desire to work because it is very likely that this desire is an adaptive preference. An adaptive preference is a preference for some state of affairs within a limited set of options formed under unjust conditions. The widespread desire for work has been formed under unjust labor conditions to which individuals are compelled to submit in order to meet material and ethical needs. Furthermore, the prevalence of the ‘work dogma’ in contemporary societies precludes nearly all individuals from seeing alternatives to work as live options.
Autonomy
The Desire For Work As An Adaptive Preference
By Michael Cholbi
A journal space for theoretical and
empirical research, aimed at critiquing
work and speculating on its future
Autonomy ISSN 2515-9852
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018
Autonomy
The Desire For Work As An Adaptive Preference
Michael Cholbi
Abstract
Autonomy
Many economists and social theorists hypothesize
that most societies could soon face a ‘post-work’
future, one in which employment and productive
labor have a dramatically reduced place in human
affairs. Given the centrality of employment to
individual identity and its pivotal role as the
primary provider of economic and other goods,
transitioning to a ‘post-work’ future could prove
traumatic and disorienting to many. Policymakers
are thus likely to face the difficult choice of the
extent to which they ought to satisfy individual
citizens’ desires to work in a socioeconomic
environment in which work is in permanent
decline. Here I argue that policymakers confronting
a post-work economy should discount, or at least
consider problematic, the desire to work because
it is very likely that this desire is anadaptive
preference. An adaptive preference is a preference
for some state of affairs within a limited set of
options formed under unjust conditions.
The widespread desire for work has been formed
under unjust labor conditions to which individuals
are compelled to submit in order to meet material
and ethical needs. Furthermore, the prevalence
of the ‘work dogma’ in contemporary societies
precludes nearly all individuals from seeing
alternatives to work as live options.
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 2
Autonomy
Many economists and social commentators
predict that coming decades will mark a
decline in work — or at least in jobs — as
we have come to know them. Automation
and the increased use of robotics; stagnating
economic growth in advanced economies;
an aging population; declines in employer
and employee loyalty; continued reductions
in the power of labour unions; continued
growth in contingent or piecework and
the gig economy; and the emergence of a
‘millennial’ generation that values flexibility,
engagement, and personal development;
all of these trends form the conditions for
an economy and culture in which fewer
individuals work, where fewer of those
who do work have traditional jobs, and
where work in general has a less prominent
role in organizing personal and social life.
Disagreement exists about the magnitude
of these developments taken individually,
as well as about the exact extent to which
work or jobs will decline in the future.
Nevertheless, there is a growing consensus
that we are headed toward a world that, in
comparison with recent decades at least,
will be ‘post-work’ — or at least ‘post-jobs’.
(Frey and Osborne 2014, Brynjolfsson and
McAfree 2014, Thompson 2014, Srnicek and
Williams 2015, Stern 2016)
The prospect of a post-work or post-jobs
future raises many critical questions
for policymakers and political leaders,
including: shall societies subsidize or
guarantee work? Shall societies reduce the
workweek or take other steps to distribute
work opportunities more broadly? Shall
income be made less dependent on work,
such as via the provision of an unconditional
basic income? In the background of each
of these policy questions, however, is an
arguably more fundamental philosophical
question regarding work and workers: to
what extent should these policy decisions
reflect individual citizens’ desire to work?
The desire to work is after all widespread
and well entrenched. Lottery winners and
retirees often continue to work despite
having virtually no need for the income
work typically provides (Arvey, Harpaz,
& Liao 1996). Few developments appear
worse for individual physical well-being,
mental health, and sense of self-worth
than continual unemployment.1 Work is a
potent source of meaning (Veltman 2016)
and identity for many people (Fryers 2006),
as work is a primary arena through which
individuals develop and manifest their skills
and character. And while job satisfaction
predictably dipped during and immediately
after the Great Recession (HITC.com 2013),
many people report being at least somewhat
satisfied with their jobs (Pew Research
Center 2016b, Society for Human Resource
Management, 2017).
Ordinarily, policymakers can and do
take individuals’ desires into account in
their decision making. By giving people
what they desire, we are likely to make
them happier, advance their interests, or
improve their quality of life. Honouring
their desires is also a way of respecting
their individual autonomy or recognizing
them as holders of certain rights. Thus, for
policymakers across the political spectrum,
one of the state’s central aims is to enable
people’s desires to be realized. But if the
aforementioned predictions concerning
1 On unemployment’s adverse effects on overall health,
see Brenner 2005, Herbig, Dragano, & Angerer 2013,
Margerison-Zilko et al. 2015. For the adverse effect of
unemployment on mental health and self-worth, see
Karsten & Moser 2009, Rutgers University Heldrich
Center for Workplace Development 2009, Goldsmith
and Diette 2012, Pharr, Moonie, & Bungum 2012, and
Calvo, Mair, & Sarkisian 2015.
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 3
Autonomy
the emergence of a post-work economy
are correct, policymakers will increasingly
struggle to satisfy citizens’ desire to work.
Full employment, so long a cornerstone of
modern economic policy, will come to be
seen as a Sisyphean pursuit. Indeed, the
confluence of the socioeconomic trends
mentioned above will make it harder for
governments to craft policies that place
work (or at least desirable or worthwhile
work) within citizens’ reach.
The question I shall therefore investigate is
whether or not the desire to work is one that
the state should help its members realize,
especially given (if the aforementioned
prognostications are correct) that
individuals will find it harder to realize this
goal, and, on a wide scale, states will find it
harder to facilitate it.
Since the 1980s, many scholars have argued
that there is a particular class of desires 2
that policymakers should not take at face
value when they consider how to craft a
just society, i.e., a class of desires that can
rightfully be discounted, or even ignored,
in policymaking. Feminist philosophers,
for example, have observed that there is
something amiss about taking desires that
women sometimes form when acculturated
within sexist or misogynist societies as
the basis for subsequent policy choices.
Imagine women in a sexist society who
(for example) are denied access to higher
education. It would not be surprising to
learn that many women in such a society in
fact have little desire for higher education,
so that its being denied them would not feel,
under these conditions, like a deprivation.
There might, hypothetically, be a resulting
indifference to whether their societies
provide women access to higher education.
But to craft education policy based on
such indifference seems suspect: a desire
for an arguably unjust state of affairs —
unequal educational access for men and
women — that individuals have in no small
measure because they have been socialized
under unjust conditions that encourage
or ratify this desire seems tainted. Such a
desire appears epistemically corrupted,
inasmuch as it does not seem to reflect
what individuals ‘really’ want. As Ann Cudd
(2006, p. 181) elaborates, “the oppressed
come to desire that which is oppressive to
them…[and] one’s desires turn away from
goods and even needs that, absent those
conditions, they would want.” We may
suspect that women in a sexist society of the
sort just described lack the desire for access
to higher education not for any reason
(or any good reason) related to higher
education or the goods or opportunities it
provides. Rather, their desire stems from
ignorance of, or an insufficient appreciation
of, those goods or opportunities. From
the policymaker’s perspective, such
desires appear uninformed, and a
policymaker would therefore be reluctant
to unproblematically treat the realization of
such desires as a policy objective.
Philosophers have come to call desires
of this sort — at a first approximation,
desires concerning some option where
the individual’s preference concerning
that option is psychologically traceable
to its having been acquired under unjust
conditions — adaptive preferences.
Adaptive preferences are an active area
of research in philosophical ethics, and
while I will here lay out what strikes me as
a credible account of adaptive preferences
and why they should not be accorded the
same respect in policymaking as other
desires are, this is intended only as a sketch,
2 “A particular class” since it is likely that there are other
classes of desires (desires rooted in addiction, say, or
sadistic desires) that also should not be given their full
due in policymaking.
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 4
Autonomy
rather than a comprehensive philosophical
treatment, of how we might vindicate the
intuition that adaptive preferences should
not enjoy the same role in policy making
as other preferences. Not everyone shares
this intuition or believes that the fact that
preferences can be adaptive provides a
compelling explanation on its own for why
they ought to be treated with suspicion in
policymaking. (Baber 2007, Bruckner 2009,
Dorsey unpublished) I do not aim to answer
fully the worries of such skeptics here, but I
hope that my discussion will introduce new
considerations into the debate and give such
skeptics food for thought.
My larger objective is to argue that the
widespread desire to work should itself
be classified as an adaptive preference,
and as such, policymakers confronting a
post-work future should not assign this
desire as much weight as they would
assign to individuals’ standard or non-
adaptive preferences. The desire to work
ought be seen as the by-product of unjust
social conditions that both enable and are
propped up by what David Frayne (2015)
has called the “work dogma.” In advancing
this thesis, I engage with an epistemic issue
that has, so far as I am aware, been largely
neglected in prior discussions of adaptive
preferences: Individuals often live under
unjust conditions and so form desires
under those conditions. But how are we to
distinguish desires merely formed under
those conditions, which presumably should
merit the ordinary amount of respect in
subsequent policymaking, from desires
shaped by the injustice present in such
conditions, which presumably should not
merit the ordinary amount of respect? An
examination of extant literature on adaptive
preferences hints that what troubles many
scholars is the fact that individuals come
to have these preferences because of prior
unjust conditions. Here I propose that
adaptive preferences have two features,
which I will call unthinkability and
underdetermination, that distinguish them
from more benign preferences formed under
unjust conditions. And because the desire
to work, having been formed under unjust
conditions, also has these two features, it
ought not be accorded the same weight as
other preferences would receive in policy
making. I conclude with some brief remarks
concerning what policies are best pursued
in relation to the prospect of a post-work
economy given that the desire to work is an
adaptive preference.
1. Adaptive preferences and unthinkable
options
Examples of adaptive preferences
have been more abundant than precise
characterizations of such preferences or of
what renders them suspect. Remaining in
abusive marriages believing that such abuse
is part of women’s lot (Nussbaum 2001a, p.
112); a willingness to tolerate a lack of clean
water supplies (Nussbaum 2001a, p. 113);
accepting wages below what members of
another gender receive for the same forms
of labor (Nussbaum 2001a, p. 113); rejecting
diagnoses of illness and thereby foregoing
needed medical care (Sen 1999a, p. 53); and
not opposing tyrannical governments (Sen
2002, p. 634); all have been put forth as
instances of adaptive preferences. Theorists
disagree about the psychological histories
of adaptive preferences, i.e., whether
they must be formed non-autonomously,
unconsciously, via habituation or
internalization, on the basis of deficient
rational reflection, etc.3 They agree, however,
that adaptive preferences are shaped by
facts about what options agents have
(or believe they have). As Rosa Terlazzo
(2015, p. 179) explains, “the idea behind the
3 See, among many discussions, Elster 1983, Nussbuam
2001b, Friedman 2003, Khader 2009, Taylor 2009, and
Colburn 2011.
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 5
Autonomy
concept of adaptive preferences is roughly
this: that when persons have limited option
sets, they can come to prefer things within
those sets that they would not prefer
otherwise” (See also Elster 1983, p. 229;
Rickard 1995, Bruckner 2009, p. 307, Dorsey
forthcoming, pp. 3-4.).
Yet this characterization does not capture
what renders adaptive preferences
troubling. For the fact that a preference is
shaped by one’s options, or the perceptions
thereof, does not render a preference
problematic. Quite the contrary: Our
preferences should adapt to our available
options. Upon learning that one’s favourite
coffee shop has closed, the yearning to dine
there might linger, but the rational response
is to relinquish that preference. The fact that
such a preference has been “formed through
adjustment to reality” hardly impugns
its credentials (Nussbaum 2001c, p. 78).
Furthermore, that a preference was formed
in response to “deprivation” or “adverse
situations” does not by itself suggest it
should be looked upon sceptically (Sen
1999a, pp. 62-63).
Thus, the fact that adaptive preferences
are adaptive in the narrow sense of being
preferences shaped by choosers’ options
does not provide a basis for concluding that
such preferences are morally or politically
problematic such that they are not entitled
to the same respect or weight in our
deliberations about what to do or how to
fashion our institutions or policies. What
further features must adaptive preferences
possess, then, in order to render them
problematic? Why, as in our earlier example,
should policymakers work to provide access
to higher education to women despite
women having no apparent desire for it?
We can home in on these further features
by considering the work of Jon Elster,
the philosopher most responsible for
introducing the concept of adaptive
preferences. Elster (1983, p. 123) used the
well- known fable of the Fox and the Grapes
to articulate the concept, so returning to
that fable can help illuminate what makes
adaptive preferences worryingly ‘adaptive’.
There are many versions of the fable. My
own favourite takes the form of a limerick by
W.J. Linton:
This Fox has a longing for grapes:
He jumps, but the bunch still escapes.
So he goes away sour;
And, ’tis said, to this hour
Declares that he’s no taste for grapes.
(Crane 1887)
We are not told whether the grapes in
question were in fact sweet and ripe, but
they were at least tempting enough to attract
the fox. Yet upon finding himself unable to
leap high enough to reach the grapes, the fox
departs, having apparently relinquished his
desire for the grapes.
As we just noted, there seems nothing
obviously troubling, irrational, etc., about
this shift in the Fox’s preferences. The Fox’s
set of options, he learns, is narrower than he
thought. And his desires (and ours) ought
to adapt to our available options. Indeed, we
may conclude that in the Fox’s case, his not
being able to reach the grapes is not itself
an irrational basis for him to relinquish his
desire for them. In terms made familiar by
economists, the Fox’s expected utility from
pursuing the grapes is in fact zero. Since
the apparent probability of his attaining
the grapes is zero, his expected utility (the
product of that probability multiplied by
the strength of his desire for the grapes) is
also zero. Rather than being an irrational
response, the Fox’s response is exactly how
a rational chooser should respond to an
option being foreclosed to her. Thus, the
fact that an adaptive preference represents a
response to one’s options being constrained
is at most a necessary condition of its being
adaptive. But it does not shed much light on
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 6
Autonomy
why it should be discounted or ignored by
policymakers.
Recall, however, that upon discovering
that the grapes are just out of reach, the
Fox not only walks away, he re-evaluates
the desirability of the grapes. What seems
troubling about his change in preferences
is that the Fox rationalizes his revised
preferences not by reference to the
impossibility of attaining the grapes but by
recalibrating his appraisal of the grapes. The
fox does not sour on the grapes because the
grapes soured. Rather, he seems to project
his frustration with his inability to reach the
grapes onto the grapes themselves. He thus
reaches a correct practical conclusion (‘I
shall not continue to pursue these grapes’)
via an unsound deliberative route (Watts
2009).
Such projection probably does not occur in
most cases of actual adaptive preferences.
Women in sexist societies probably do not
discover that higher education is off limits
to them and then become averse to pursuing
higher education, for example. Rather, those
who hold adaptive preferences are, through
the forces of socialization etc. exerted under
unjust conditions, disposed to some options
as unthinkable. To prefer some option A
within some relevant set containing A, B, C,
etc. because B, C, etc. are unthinkable is not
to literally perceive B, C, etc., as conceptually
impossible. Indeed, those with an adaptive
preference for A are probably fully aware
that others, either within their community
or outside it, prefer B, C, etc. to A. But for
those with an adaptive preference for A,
alternatives are at least ‘not for them.
4
Adaptive preferences are therefore likely to
have a strongly indexical or agent-relative
character.
That a chooser might come to find an
option intrinsically undesirable in part
because she cannot realize that option may
seem strange. But I take this to rest on the
all too common human tendency toward
optimistic self-appraisal, and in particular,
the psychological need to maintain a sense
of one’s agency as the locus of control over
significant outcomes.5 That an option is
unattainable may be understood (or in
many cases, misunderstood) as the result
of one’s own inability to attain it. Yet if the
option ‘turns out’ to have been undesirable
all along, then its unattainability represents
no threat to the agent’s self-image. Better,
or at least more emotionally tractable, to
disdain the option. Hugh Breakey provides
a vivid description of how such a process
might unfold:
As the Fox’s change of mind illustrates,
unthinkability seems to capture part of why
adaptive preferences should be treated as
suspect: Their apparent rationality conceals
the fact that one premise responsible
for their formation is false, or at least
unjustified. The Fox does not know the
grapes are sour. Indeed, he has no particular
evidence for that claim at all.
4 This is not to preclude the possibility of options varying
in their degrees of unthinkability.
5For the introduction of the concept of locus of control, see
Rotter (1966).
What is at work here, I think, is a
colouring of mood and habituation
of thought. Emotionally, we work
up a state of dislike, hatred, disgust,
resentment orscorn (perhaps fuelled
by our incapacity toattain the object)
and we direct it at the unattainable
object itself. We smear it internally
with ugly emotive connotations.
Cognitively, we develop a habitof
stressing its defects to ourselves
whenever we consider it. In this way,
we mentally paper over the genuine
desire that remainsfor the object.
(2010, p. 32)
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 7
Autonomy
Similarly, in the case of actual adaptive
preferences, their holders do not seem to
have a good reason for them, even if their
inability to attain the objects of those
preferences might otherwise be a good
reason to hold such preferences. The
preferences in question turn pivotally on
normative or evaluative judgments for
which they lack sufficient evidence. And if
only those preferences that meet minimal
standards for rationality merit full respect by
policymakers, then adaptive preferences do
not merit such respect.
In addition, it is morally significant that
those with adaptive preferences have false
beliefs regarding the normative premises
incorporated into their practical reasoning.
Those with adaptive preferences engage,
like all agents, in practical reasoning. And
though their reasoning (again) may land on
the correct conclusion in the circumstances
(that the unattainability of B, C, etc., justifies
a preference for A), they land on those
conclusions on the basis of unjustified
normative premises. And it does seem to
be more objectionable or lamentable for
individuals to engage in practical reasoning
that rests on unjustified normative premises
— the premises concerning their goals,
ends, or values — than it does for them to
engage in practical reasoning on unjustified
non-normative or empirical premises. The
normative attitudes that constitute what Rawls
called our conception of the good form the
agenda for our practical pursuits, and so, in
this respect, have a kind of normative priority
over the non-normative attitudes on which
we rely in order to pursue our conceptions of
the good. As I argue elsewhere (Cholbi, 2017),
we have stronger reason to object to treatment
that interferes with our capacity to rationally
will ends than we have to object to treatment
that interferes with our capacity to identify
the best means to those ends (or to determine
whether there are any means sufficient to
our willed ends). Interference of this first sort
engages with those capacities with which we
more closely identify as practical agents and
so reflects greater mistrust of us as practical
agents. In the case of adaptive preferences,
those holding them have had their attitudes
manipulated so that though they reach
justifiable practical conclusions about what
they ought to do under the circumstances, they
do not appreciate how they have mistaken
the unattainable for the unthinkable. In terms
akin to those popularized by Rawls, those with
adaptive preferences have come to think that
the pursuit of certain options is unreasonable,
when in reality the unjust conditions under
which they live have made the pursuit of
certain reasonable options irrational.
We have established therefore that adaptive
preferences are preferences formed under
conditions of injustice wherein an individual
prefers some option over some set of
relevant alternatives, where alternatives
to the preferred option come to be viewed
as unthinkable. That adaptive preferences
are unthinkable in this way is a claim that
several have gestured at. Amartya Sen, for
instance, remarks that the poor may “come
to terms with their deprivation” by adjusting
“their desires and expectations to what they
unambitiously see as feasible” (Sen 1999b,
p. 30).
Still, we have not yet teased out all the salient
features of adaptive preferences. That this
is so becomes evident when we confront an
epistemological difficulty associated with
the identification of adaptive preferences.
That a preference reflects limited options,
whether in reality or in choosers’ perceptions
thereof; that the preference was formed
6 This account of adaptive preferences also needs to be
limited in one specific way: An individual living under
unjust conditions may prefer to have those conditions
overturned and view extant conditions as unthinkable.
Thus, adaptive preferences probably cannot have the
unjust circumstances themselves as their objects.
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 8
Autonomy
under unjust conditions; and that the
preference holder rules out alternatives
to her preference as unthinkable;6 even
when all of these hold true, we might still
wonder whether individuals’ preferences
satisfying these criteria have been formed
because of those individuals living under
unjust conditions. It is after all possible
that individuals have the preferences they
do for reasons unrelated to those unjust
conditions, that is, that the injustice of
the conditions is merely incidental to the
preferences having been formed under those
conditions. We thus seem to need indicators
of preferences whose ‘adaptiveness’ is due to
unjust background conditions. Fortunately,
an examination of the desire to work
highlights the evidence needed to ascertain
that an adaptive preference is due to unjust
conditions. But we must first address
whether the present day desire to work has
in fact been formed under unjust conditions.
2. Injustice and the desire to work
That the desire to work meets one of the
conditions for an adaptive preference
— that it has been formed under unjust
conditions — is no doubt contentious. All
the same, establishing such a claim does not
depend on endorsing any comprehensive
theory of justice, so long as we draw upon
considerations that nearly any such theory
would recognize as speaking in favour of
the injustice of the present-day conditions
in which the widespread desire to work has
been formed.
The considerations relevant to the desire to
work are the conditions of contemporary
work and of the workplace itself. The first
class of such considerations are broadly
material. One general way in which
these conditions can be unjust is if work
(understood primarily as paid employment)
does not offer workers a fair balance of
effort and reward. Certainly workers receive
some goods through their work – wages, at
a minimum. But the rewards for their work
are often more meagre than justice would
mandate. Thanks to stagnating wages,
recent decades have seen an explosion in
‘working poor,’ individuals whose work does
not offer adequate monetary compensation
to remove them from poverty. In the U.S., 40
percent of those in poverty work full time
(Dalaker, 2017), and three-fifths of those in
poverty in the UK live in households where
someone is employed (Butler, 2017). That a
large number of the working poor receive
public assistance only highlights how
working often fails to provide a fair reward
for workers’ efforts.
Simultaneously, we often underestimate
the burdens associated with working. The
most obvious burden is the opportunity
cost associated with time spent working.
Workers in most countries spend around
2,000 hours per year on the job, the
equivalent of working ‘24/7’ for 11 weeks.
These statistics do not include the time
spent travelling to and from work sites.
In the U.S., an average commute requires
180 hours per year (Ingraham 2016). The
time associated with working is time not
spent on leisure, social relationships, or
community activities. And what time
workers retain for themselves is increasingly
devalued by the expectation that they will
remain electronically “connected” to the
workplace through e-mail, text messaging,
etc. (Gregg 2011). This expectation results in
the fragmentation of workers’ ‘free’ time and
makes wholehearted engagement with non-
work activities more elusive.
Another neglected burden associated
with work is that it costs money to work.
Consider commuting again. In addition
to being a source of stress and ill health
(Ingraham 2016), commuting can be
costly; Vasel (2015) notes how it costs,
on average, $2,600 per worker in the US.
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 9
Autonomy
Workers can also bear monetary costs for
clothing or equipment required or expected
in the workplace, as well as costs to pay
other people to do work that one might be
able to perform oneself (child care, home
repair, house cleaning, etc.) were one not
working.
Work, then, is not all that it is cracked up to
be: often less remunerative than is needed
to provide for individuals’ basic needs and
encumbered with costs we too often ignore.
These observations make recent research
finding that unemployment is sometimes no
worse, or even better, than holding certain
jobs far less surprising (Kim and von dem
Knesebeck 2015, Chandola and Zhang 2018).
A second category of considerations,
indicating that workers today operate in
an unjust labor environment, are what we
might call moral considerations. Here it is
worth noting that most workplaces today
insist that workers submit to infringements
of their liberties in order to obtain, retain, or
maximize the value of paid employment. To
require background checks and drug testing,
to utilize visual and electronic surveillance,7
to ask employees to forego legal rights and
agree to employer-instigated arbitration
(Colvin 2017), to mandate dress codes,
to police suitable subjects of workplace
conversation (or the language in which
those conversations are conducted), or to
penalize workers for their political activities;
these Foucaultian maneuvers represent
employers infringing on employees’
freedom as a condition of their working.
Elizabeth Anderson has recently likened the
American workplace order to a communist
dictatorship, with unaccountable superiors
(management and ownership) enjoy largely
arbitrary authority to govern employees by
nearly unchecked fiat. As Anderson (2017,
p. 37ff.) observes, workers thereby appear
to tolerate their employers functioning as a
form of ‘private government’ with powers
that exceed the powers that most workers
would view it as justifiable for their elected
‘public’ government to possess.
In tandem, these material and moral
considerations imply that the widespread
desire to work has been formed under
labor and workforce conditions that are
unjust insofar as they embody an unfair
balance of burdens and benefits for workers.
Compounding this arguably unjust balance
of burdens and benefits is that work is
effectively compelled or coerced in most
societies. To achieve a decent lifestyle, nearly
everyone must work for a significant portion
of their lives. The aforementioned burdens of
work are thus tolerated despite the fact that
a society that essentially mandates work
places weighty constraints on what Phillippe
van Parijs calls “real freedom.” To be really
free, van Parijs proposes, an individual
must not only be able to act on her choices
without others’ interference. She must also
possess the capacities and resources to carry
out those choices and realize her objectives.
(van Parijs 1995) Being compelled to work
turns real freedom against itself: by requiring
individuals to work in order to acquire the
material resources needed to pursue their
ends, a society places significant limitations
on how individuals can effectively use their
resources, material and otherwise, in the
pursuit of their ends.
Again, I have not offered a theorization of
justice here in support of my claim that
the desire to work has been formed under
unjust labour conditions. But I imagine that
adherents of a wide range of conceptions of
justice (libertarian, communitarian, liberal,
socialist, etc.) will agree that a set of societal
arrangements into which individuals are
effectively compelled; makes extremely
extensive demands on their time, energy,
attention, and material resources;
often offers them economic rewards
7 For a useful general overview of the ethical issues raised
by workplace surveillance, see Pitesa (2012).
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 10
Autonomy
inadequate to their needs; and mandates
that they submit to violations of their
personal freedoms they would not likely
tolerate in other sectors of life, is highly
suspect from the standpoint of justice. This
conclusion should not be exaggerated:
workers, their employment situations, and
the political situations in which they work
vary, and there are many workers (the well
compensated, the skilled, the unionized,
etc.) whose work-life represents a fair
balance of benefit and burden, does not
require violations of their freedom, etc. The
conditions under which we have come to
desire work are therefore not uniformly or
homogenously unjust. Nevertheless, the
workplace and the labour market as we
know it falls well short of nearly any credible
ideal of just exchange.
3. The desire for work: Limited options,
unthinkability, and underdetermination
Having shown that the desire to work has
been formed under unjust conditions and
that the desire to work depicts alternatives
to work as unthinkable, let us now use the
desire to work to identify a final condition
on a preference being adaptive.
The desire to work is clearly ‘adaptive’
in a minimal sense. For it is a preference
for an option formed in contemporary
industrialized societies wherein the primary
alternatives to working have been foreclosed
by a combination of policy and culture.
Over the past generation or so, many
societies have increasingly insisted that
their members work, adopting ‘workfare’
policies making the receipt of various
forms of public assistance contingent
upon employment (or short of that, the
conscientious pursuit thereof) (Peck 2001,
Brodkin and Larsen 2013). And while one
might think that the central goal of politics
should be to expand human freedom or
augment human happiness, the Left and
the Right converge in supposing that the
primary goal of economic policy is to create
jobs. Evidently, once everyone is employed,
freedom, happiness, and equality take care
of themselves.
Culturally, work has a near sacred status
in most prosperous nations. The remains
of Webers ‘Protestant work ethic’ continue
to exert their power over popular attitudes
toward work, enticing individuals toward
“the identification with and systematic
devotion to waged work, the elevation
of work to the centre of life, and the
affirmation of work as an end in itself”
(Weeks, 2011, p. 46). Work is widely seen as
the mark of independence and the central
responsibility associated with citizenship.
Unsurprisingly, few events are more
psychologically traumatic than long-term
involuntary unemployment. Striving is
superior to slacking, and even in the face
of considerable evidence that hard work
and industriousness are at best necessary
and clearly far from sufficient for material
success, the belief persists in work’s capacity
to ensure such success. “Grit”, passion,
perseverance, and self-confidence are thus
the central virtues of what Frayne (2015)
has coined the “work-centred society”.
So pervasive is the belief in the necessity,
both prudential and moral, of work that
we increasingly struggle to describe
activities that are arguably not work in
terms dissociated from work. Exercising
is ‘working out’. Troubled couples need to
‘work on’ their relationships. Parenting is
‘a job’ (Malesic 2017). And while educators
may hope that education provides goods
other than improved job opportunities, to
argue that (say) public education should
not make children into “job ready” adults is
suicide in today’s political climate.
Of course, few fail to recognize that
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 11
Autonomy
refraining from, or refusing to work, is at
least conceivable. But it takes considerable
audacity to do so, since doing so labels
the non-worker as deviant, as someone
effectively removing themselves from the
essential precondition of participation in
shared public life. As Frayne (2015, pp. 2-5)
notes, the cultural power of work is such
that modern societies lack any serious
debate about the merits of work and seem
constitutively unable to imagine modes of
social organization in which work is less
prominent.
Hence, we may reasonably conjecture that
even if not working remains in some sense
an abstract possibility, it is what William
James called a “live hypothesis” for very
few. Hence, citizens of advanced societies
nowadays frequently find themselves
in a position akin to the Fox’s after the
grapes proved unattainable: They have
adapted their preferences in light of the
unavailability of economically and culturally
viable alternatives to work. And as with
other adaptive preferences, the desire
to work does not rest on a substantive
engagement with, or consideration of,
alternatives. Just as the Fox, unable to attain
the grapes, turns against them, so too have
many members of modern societies, unable
to attain (or even coherently envision) an
existence without work, turned against non-
work. The desire to work is thus a desire
forged in ignorance of relevant alternatives.
Alternatives to work are thus unthinkable
for most.
The desire to work thus satisfies the
conditions for adaptive preferences
adumbrated in section 1. Yet there is another
dimension to the desire to work that
enables us to grasp the nature of adaptive
preferences.
As noted above, an adaptive preference
will be one its holders have because of their
having acquired it under unjust conditions.
We thus need indicators of when this is so.
In the case of the desire to work, I suggest
that we see such indicators in the apparent
discord between the global or generic desire
to work and the conclusions individuals
reach regarding the specific attributes of
work. As we shall enumerate momentarily,
individuals view many aspects of work (or
at least of their work) as bad or unsatisfying
and yet retain a desire to work nonetheless.
In my estimation, this betokens the sort
of irrationality we would expect from an
adaptive preference: If one judges that X
is bad in numerous ways but nevertheless
desires X —indeed, finds not pursuing X
almost unfathomable — this suggests that
one’s overall judgments have been distorted
by socialization under unjust conditions.
When a global judgment regarding X is
thereby underdetermined by the particular
judgments relevant to that global judgment,
the judgment is likely to have been shaped
by unjust conditions. To desire work and
yet find nearly every aspect of the actual
practice of work undesirable is to have a
preference that outstrips, and is arguably
at odds with, the evidence relevant to that
preference. Only potent social conditioning,
I propose, can engender this sort of discord.
Many people desire to work and find
involuntarily not working to be painful or
distressing. These attitudes are surprising,
given how negatively individuals often
appraise the various aspects of work
that should presumably influence global
appraisals of the desirability of work. A
2008 study (Jenkins, Kopicki, Van Horn
& Zukin) found that with respect to six
main determinants of job quality (hours,
education and training, health and
medical benefits, retirement and pensions,
retirement age, and income), fewer than half
of American workers were “very satisfied”
with any of these six determinants, this
despite 51 percent reporting being satisfied
with their jobs as a whole. A similar
gap between global judgments of work
satisfaction and judgments of particular
determinants of work satisfaction has been
observed in more recent studies. A RAND
Corporation survey of over 3,000 American
workers summarized its findings as follows:
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 12
Autonomy
the American workplace is very physically
and emotionally taxing, both for workers
themselves and their families. Most
Americans (two-thirds) frequently work
at high speeds or under tight deadlines,
and one in four perceives that they have
too little time to do their job. More than
one-half of Americans report exposure
to unpleasant and potentially hazardous
working conditions, and nearly one in five
American workers are exposed to a hostile
or threatening social environment at work
(Maestas et al 2017).
The same study reports that at least
two-thirds of workers report “mismatch”
between the working conditions they desire
and the working conditions they have. Still,
the respondents’ faith in work is intact,
as four out of five respondents indicated
that their work is meaningful in some way.
A UK survey likewise found that half of
British workers find their work meaningful
(Dahlgreen/YouGov 2015).8 This same
pattern — positive global appraisals of
work alongside largely negative appraisals
of the factors on which those global
appraisals ought to be based — recurs in a
Pew Research Group (2016b) study of US
workers. Again, only a small fraction (15
percent) report being at least somewhat
dissatisfied with their jobs, and about half
report that their jobs offer them a sense of
identity. But underneath the surface, anxiety
and dissatisfaction loom: A majority report
that they do not receive the ongoing training
or education needed to succeed in the job
market, that desirable jobs are increasingly
hard to find, and that their wages are not
adequate to ensure themselves a decent
retirement. Meanwhile, both hours worked
per week and weeks worked per year have
climbed over the past generation. In sum,
“many Americans think jobs in the U.S. are
less secure, more pressured, less rewarding
in terms of benefits, and less built on worker
loyalty to employers than in the past.” The
vast majority expect such conditions to
worsen over coming decades (Pew Research
Center 2016a). Studies of European
workers have reached similar conclusions
(Eurofound, 2017).
A number of caveats are in order here.
Societies and workplaces vary, and
unsurprisingly, workers with higher
levels of income, education, workplace
autonomy, and job benefits view their work
more positively, both globally and in the
particular. Moreover, much of what workers
find undesirable in their work is contingent,
set by employer or government policies
that, if reformed, might improve working
conditions.
Nevertheless, it is hard to deny that, on
balance, today’s labourers seem to love
work in principle or in the abstract but
seem to find their actual work conditions
disappointing, even worthy of resentment.
Their global judgments regarding work’s
desirability are thus underdetermined by
their judgments of the particular factors
on which such global judgments are
presumptively based. This, I suggest, is
what we would anticipate if the desire to
work were maintained by an aversion to
alternatives such that those alternatives
have become unthinkable thanks to the
baleful influence of social conditioning
under unjust conditions. Getting individuals
to acknowledge that their living conditions
could be inherently unjust works against
the deep seated human tendency to view
the world as just by nature (Furnham 2003).
At the same time, workers’ attitudes toward
the particular facets of their work suggest
that they would not, upon full reflection,
conclude that they work under just
conditions. The most viable way to reduce
this tension — to reduce the cognitive
dissonance between work as it should be
in a just society and work as it is in most
actual societies — is for the desire to work
to be psychologically and epistemically
cordoned off from the evidence relevant to
it. That is to say, it is necessary for many
people to successfully desire work very
8 Intriguingly though, 37% of British workers in that
same survey said their jobs do not make any meaningful
contribution to the world.
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 13
Autonomy
much against the tide of evidence against its
desirability under present day conditions.
Only if the value of work has been elevated
to a dogmatic ideology can it plausibly be
immune to the abundant counterevidence
offered by the contemporary workplace.
4. Conclusion: Policymaking and the desire
for work in a post-work future
We have seen, then, how the desire to
work is an adaptive preference: a desire
formed under, and in response to, unjust
circumstances of work and labour wherein
many in modern societies to view (a) work
as indispensable, despite often viewing
their own work as unsatisfactory, even
meaningless, and (b) alternatives to work as
essentially unthinkable.
If I am correct and work is an adaptive
preference, then as we approach the
possibility of an increasingly ‘post-work’
future, policymakers ought not to be as
fixated on satisfying individuals’ desires to
work as they are now. To aim at satisfying
this desire may not only be fruitless, it
is also to satisfy a preference that is in a
fundamental sense a preference for an
unjust state of affairs, namely, one in which
limiting one’s work efforts, or refraining
from work altogether, is neither materially
viable nor socially sanctioned.
An obvious rejoinder to this conclusion
is ‘easier said than done.’ The emergence
of post-work economies could result
in widespread moral distress. As large
numbers of individuals become incapable
of accessing work, they are likely to be
deprived of sources of meaning or identity
and may feel guilt or resentment at their
inability to fulfil their perceived obligation
to materially contribute to the larger society
through their work efforts. In democratic
societies, only a very brave elected official is
likely to challenge her constituents’ desire
for work.
Policymakers facing a post-work future
thus confront a difficult balancing act:
having recognized that the desire to work
is an adaptive preference, they should be
hesitant to craft policies aimed at satisfying
that desire (even assuming that they could
manage to craft policies that can withstand
the tide of trends making its satisfaction
harder), while at the same time attending to
the adverse psychological and eudaimonic
consequences of the emergence of the post-
work society. Policymakers must engineer
a soft landing, one in which individuals can
‘un-adapt’ from the work-centered society
and begin to adapt to a post-work society. As
Serene Khader (2011, p. 42) observes, adaptive
preferences, while often deeply entrenched,
can be dislodged if individuals are exposed
to alternative possibilities that foster their
scrutiny of those preferences. A central pillar
in preparing us for a post-work future will
be to steadily acclimatise individuals to a
society in which work is more peripheral.
This can be achieved through an array of
reforms including de-emphasizing vocational
goals in the educational process; lowering
retirement ages; reducing the length of the
work week and/or work year; validating
(rather than shaming) adolescents who
engage in self-exploration and delay entry
into the workforce; and detaching public
welfare initiatives from conditions related to
work or the seeking thereof. By dissociating
work from social status, such reforms would
expose the adaptive preference for work to
greater scrutiny and invite individuals to take
work reduction or refusal more seriously as
Millian ‘experiments in living.’ Obviously, the
reforms needed to mitigate the moral distress
that would likely accompany the emergence
of the post-work economy are profound. But
the slow dislodging of entrenched attitudes
regarding work is clearly preferable to ignoring
the likely detrimental consequences that such
attitudes will lead to should the predicted
post-work world materialize.9
9 My thanks to my colleagues Alex Madva, Katie
Gasdaglis, and Peter Ross, and to my students in my
winter 2018 seminar “The Ethics and Politics of Work”,
for feedback on earlier versions of this essay.
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 14
Autonomy
Anderson, E 2017, Private government: How
employers rule our lives (and why we don’t talk
about it, Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Arvey, RD, Harpaz, I, & Liao, H 1996, ‘Work
centrality and post-award work behavior of lottery
winners,’ Journal of Psychology, vol. 130, no. 5, pp.
404-420.
Baber, HE 2007, ‘Adaptive preference,’ Social
Theory and Practice, vol. 33, no. 1, pp. 105-126.
Breakey, H 2010, ‘Adaptive preferences and
the Hellenistic insight, “Australian Journal of
Professional and Applied Ethic, vol. 12, no. 1, pp.
29-39.
Brenner, MH 2005, ‘Commentary: Economic
growth is the basis of mortality rate decline in the
20th century—experience of the United States
1901–2000,’ International Journal of Epidemiology,
vo. 34, no. 6, pp. 1214–1221.
Brodkin, EZ, & Larsen, F 2013, ‘Changing
boundaries: The policies of workfare in the U.S.
and Europe,’ Poverty and Public Policy, vol. 5, no.
1, pp. 37-47.
Bruckner, DW 2009, ‘In defense of adaptive
preferences,’ Philosophical Studies, vol. 142, no. 3,
pp. 307-324.
Butler, P 2017, ‘Record 60% of Britons in poverty
are in working families – study,” The Guardian,
retrieved 25 August 2017 https://www.theguardian.
com/society/2017/may/22/record-britons-in-work-
poverty-families-study-private-rented-housing
Brynjolfsson, E & McAfee, A 2014, The second
machine age: Work, progress, and prosperity in a
time of brilliant technologies, Norton, New York.
Calvo, E, Mair, CA, & Sarkisian, N 2015 ‘Individual
troubles, shared troubles: The multiplicative effect
of individual and country-level unemployment on
life satisfaction in 95 nations (1981-2009),’ Social
Forces, vol. 93, no. 4, pp. 1625-1653.
Chandola, T, & Zhang, N 2018, ‘Re-employment,
job quality, health and allostatic load markers:
Prospective evidence from the UK household
longitudinal study,’ International Journal of
Epidemiology, vol. 47, no.1, pp. 47-57.
Cholbi, M 2017, ‘Paternalism and our rational
powers,” Mind, vol. 126, no. 501, pp. 123-153.
Colburn B 2011, ‘Autonomy and adaptive
preferences,’ Utilitas, vol. 23, no. 1, pp. 52–71.
Colvin, AJS 2017, ‘The growing use of forced
arbitration,’ Economic Policy Institute
(Washington D.C.) report, 27 Sept 2017 <epi.
org/135056>.
Crane, W 1887, Baby’s own Aesop, G. Routledge and
Sons, London.
Cudd, A 2006, Analyzing oppression, Oxford
University Press, New York.
Dahlgreen, W & YouGov, 2015, ‘37% of British
workers think their jobs are meaningless,”
12 August 2015. https://yougov.co.uk/
news/2015/08/12/british-jobs-meaningless/
Dalaker, J 2017, ‘Poverty in the United States in
2015: In brief,’ Congressional Research Service,
retrieved 25 August 2017 https://fas.org/sgp/crs/
misc/R44644.pdf
Dorsey, D forthcoming. ‘Adaptive preferences
are a red herring,” Journal of the American
Philosophical Association.
Elster, J 1983 Sour grapes: Studies in the
subversion of rationality, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge UK.
Eurofound 2017, Sixth European working
conditions survey – Overview report (2017 update),
Publications Office of the European Union,
Luxembourg. https://www.eurofound.europa.
eu/sites/default/files/ef_publication/field_ef_
document/ef1634en.pdf)
References
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 15
Autonomy
Frayne, D 2015, The refusal of work: The theory and
practice of resistance to work, Zed, London.
Frey, CB & Osborne, MA 2014, ‘The future of
employment,” Oxford Martin School Working
Paper.
Friedman, M 2003, Autonomy, gender, politics,
Oxford University Press, New York.
Fryers, T 2006, ‘Work, identity and health,’ Clinical
Practice and Epidemiology in Mental Health,
vol. 2, no. 12, retrieved 11 January 2018
<https://cpementalhealth.biomedcentral.com/
articles/10.1186/1745-0179-2-12>.
Furnham, A 2003, “Belief in a just world: Research
Progress over the past decade,” Personality and
Individual Differences, vol. 34, no. 5, pp. 795–817.
Goldsmith, A, & Diette, T 2012 ‘Exploring the
link between unemployment and mental
health outcomes,’ The SES Indicator, American
Psychological Association, April 2012.
Gregg, M 2011, Work’s intimacy, Wiley, New York.
Herbig, B, Dragano, N, and Angerer, P 2013,
‘Health in the long-term unemployed,’ Deutsches
Ärzteblatt International, vol. 110, nos. 23-24, pp.
413–419.
HITC.com 2013, ‘Global survey reveals staggering
results on job satisfaction,” retrieved 18 September
2017 http://www.hitc.com/en-gb/2013/09/18/nearly-
half-of-global-employees-unhappy-in-jobs-survey/
Ingraham, C 2016, ‘The astonishing human
potential wasted on commutes,’ Washington
Post, retrieved 25 August 2017 <https://www.
washingtonpost.com/news/wonk/wp/2016/02/25/
how-much-of-your-life-youre-wasting-on-your-
commute/?utm_term=.7048b95c2b79>.
Jenkins, K, Kopicki, A, Van Horn, C & Zukin, C
2008, ‘The anxious American worker,’ WorkTrends,
summer 2008 (Rutgers University Heldrich Center
for Workplace Development) http://heldrich.
rutgers.edu/sites/default/files/products/uploads/
Work_Trends_August_2008.pdf
Karsten, IP, & Moser, K 2009 ‘Unemployment
impairs mental health: Meta-analyses,’ Journal of
Vocational Behavior, vol. 74, no. 3, pp. 264-281.
Khader, S 2009, ‘Adaptive preferences and
procedural autonomy,’ Journal of Human
Development and Capabilities, vol 10, no. 2, pp.
169-187.
—— 2011, Adaptive preferences and women’s
empowerment, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Kim, TJ, & von dem Knesebeck, O 2015, ‘Is an
insecure job better for health than having no job
at all? A systematic review of studies investigating
the health-related risks of both job insecurity and
unemployment,” BMC Public Health, vol. 15, p.
985.
Maestas, N, Mullen, KJ, Powell, D, von Wachter,
T, & Wenger JB 2017, ‘Working conditions in
the United States: Results of the 2015 American
working conditions survey,’ RAND Corporation
https://www.rand.org/content/dam/rand/pubs/
research_reports/RR2000/RR2014/RAND_RR2014.
pdf
Malesic, J 2017, ‘Parenting is not a ‘job,’ and
marriage is not ‘work’’ New Republic 9 August
2017. <https://newrepublic.com/article/144254/
parenting-not-job-marriage-not-work>.
Margerison-Zilko, C, Goldman-Mellor, S, Falconi
A, & Dowing, J 2016, ‘Health impacts of the Great
Recession: A critical review,’ Current Epidemiology
Reports, vol. 3, no. 1, pp. 81–91.
Nussbaum, M 2001a ‘Adaptive preferences and
women’s options,’ Economics and Philosophy, vol.
17, no. 1, pp. 67-88.
—— 2001b, Women and human development: The
capabilities approach, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge UK.
—— 2001c, ‘Symposium on Amartya Sen’s
philosophy: 5 Adaptive preferences and women’s
options’, Economics and Philosophy 17 (2001), p.
78.
Peck, J 2001, Workfare states, Guilford, New York.
Pew Research Center 2016a, ‘The state of American
jobs 2016,” retrieved 15 July 2017 http://www.
pewsocialtrends.org/2016/10/06/the-state-of-
american-jobs/
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 16
Autonomy
Pew Research Center 2016b, ‘How Americans
view their jobs,’ retrieved 15 July 2017, http://www.
pewsocialtrends.org/2016/10/06/3-how-americans-
view-their-jobs/
Pharr, JR, Moonie, S, & Bungum, TJ 2012,
‘The impact of unemployment on mental
and physical health, access to health care and
health risk behaviors,’ ISRN Public Health 2012,
doi:10.5402/2012/483432, accessed 1 December
2017 https://www.hindawi.com/journals/
isrn/2012/483432/
Pitesa, M 2012, ‘Employee surveillance and the
modern workplace,’ Business Ethics: A Critical
Approach: Integrating Ethics Across the Business
World, 206-219, Research Collection Lee Kong
Chian School Of Business retrieved 16 February
2018 < http://ink.library.smu.edu.sg/lkcsb_
research/5031>
Rickard, M 1995, ‘Sour grapes, rational desires, and
objective consequentialism,’ Philosophical Studies,
vol. 80, no. 3, pp. 279-303.
Rotter, JB 1966 ‘Generalized expectancies for
internal versus external control of reinforcement,
Psychological Monographs: General and Applied,
vol. 80, no. 1, pp. 1-28.
Rutgers University Heldrich Center for
Workforce Development 2009, ‘The anguish
of unemployment,” Work Trends, retrieved 12
November 2017 http://heldrich.rutgers.edu/sites/
default/files/products/uploads/Heldrich_Anguish_
of_Unemployment.pdf
Sen, A 1999a, Commodities and capabilities,
Oxford University Press, Oxford.
—— 1999b, Development as freedom, Anchor: New
York.
—— 2002, Rationality and freedom, Belknap,
Cambridge UK.
Society for Human Resource Management 2017,
‘2017 employee job satisfaction and engagement,’
retrieved Decemer 21 2017, https://www.shrm.
org/hr-today/trends-and-forecasting/research-
and-surveys/pages/2017-job-satisfaction-and-
engagement-doors-of-opportunity-are-open.aspx
Srnicek, N & Williams, A 2015, Inventing the future:
Postcapitalism and a world without work, Verso,
London.
Stern, A 2016, Raising the floor, Public Affairs, New
York.
Taylor, JS 2009, Practical autonomy and bioethics,
Routledge, New York.
Terlazzo, R 2015, ‘Adaptive preferences: Merging
political accounts and well-being accounts,’
Canadian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 45, no. 2, pp.
179-196.
Thompson, D 2015, ‘A world without work,” The
Atlantic, July/August 2015, retrieved 22 October
2017,https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/
archive/2015/07/world-without-work/395294/
Van Parijs, P 1995, Real freedom for all: What
(if anything) can justify capitalism?, Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Vasel, K 2015, ‘We spend $2,600 a year commuting
to work,” CNN Money, retrieved 25 August 2017
<http://money.cnn.com/2015/06/17/pf/work-
commute-time-and-money/>.
Veltman A 2016, Meaningful work, Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Watts, M 2009, ‘Sen and the art of motorcycle
maintenance: Adaptive preferences and higher
education,’ Studies in Philosophy and Education,
vol. 28, no. 5, pp. 425-436.
Weeks, K 2011, The problem with work, Duke
University Press, Durham US
Autonomy Research Limited
info@autonomyinstitute.org
@Autonomy_UK
Autonomy: 04 : July 2018 17
Autonomy
... De voorkeur voor nuttig werk, zo stelt Michael Cholbi, kan ook gezien worden als een adaptive preference: een voorkeur gevormd in een onderdrukkende samenleving en bij gebrek aan alternatieven. 54 Anderzijds stelt Marcuse ook dat we lage en hoge vormen van genot kunnen onderscheiden. In sociaal noodzakelijke arbeid kunnen we hooguit een lage, valse vorm van genot ervaren. ...
... These circumstances include increasing precarity of employment and social insecurity, decreasing remuneration and benefits, increased encroachments on their non-work time, and a pervasive lack of control over what jobs they have to take up and their performance of these jobs (Horgan, 2021). Under such circumstances, which render talk of social reciprocity or fairness vacuous, the desire for work that many people 6 feel and the widespread belief that all have a duty to work are together best viewed as an 'adaptive preference', an irrational accommodation by workers to a situation they should instead refuse (Cholbi, 2018a(Cholbi, , 2018b). ...
Chapter
Full-text available
The ‘postwork’ perspective represents a complex of theoretical and empirical claims not held by every postwork theorist, but which taken together can be viewed as offering a thoroughgoing critique of our capitalist ‘work society’ and the ‘work ethic’ underpinning it. The work ethic can take many forms, but at its core is the belief that work is in some way fundamental to human life, serving needs, generating key aspects of identities, and thus providing a locus of individual and social meaning underpinning communities in fundamental ways. For postwork critics, however, the work ethic has consistently granted work a centrality it ought not to have, with the result that other human activities are devalued, and has functioned as a legitimating ideological cover for practices that undermine our freedom and are exploitative and unjust. Here we offer an interrogation of this postwork critique. We contend that in responding to the issues posed by contemporary work we need to still insist on work’s social centrality, not reject it. As we see it, one error of the postwork stance is that, in its rejection of work’s centrality, it targets an overly restricted notion and experience of work. A further problem is its failure to properly register the individual and social goods people can and do attain through work. This is compounded by a failure to realize that the movement towards a more free and just society in fact requires the endorsement of a work ethic, albeit one different from earlier forms and alive to the dangers of its being harnessed by regressive forces.
... On the other hand, however, it opens up the possibility of imagining a society after work society, as Weeks for instance does when she advocates utopian thinking with regard to work, again as a way of defamiliarising the present (2011,. Michael Cholbi similarly argues that the desire for work is not an inherently human desire but rather what he terms an adaptive preference, given that working is an economic necessity for most people at the moment and culturally privileged in our society (Cholbi 2018). Only once paid work is no longer a necessity would it then emerge what kinds of other activities people might wish to pursue. ...
... It significantly structures not only the use of one's time but one's very identity. When philosophers approach work as a topic of philosophical interest, it is typically from an ethical or economic perspective (e.g., Anderson, 2017;Cholbi, 2018;Gilabert, 2018). To my knowledge, there have been few if any attempts to examine work from an agentic perspective, that is, in terms of what sort of actions we are engaged in when we are at work and how we conceptualize what we are doing when we work. 1 I suggest that understanding work as a species of complex activity permits novel insights into human agency and self-understanding. ...
Article
Technological developments have led to the digitization of certain sectors of the economy, and this has many authors looking ahead to the prospects of a post-work society. While it is valuable to theorize about this possibility, it is also important to take note of the present state of work. For better or worse, it is what we are currently stuck with, and as the COVID-19 pandemic has ensured, much of that work is now taking place online. Though a ‘return to normalcy’ is on the horizon, part of that normalcy involves online work, which is itself a significant change in the lives of many workers. Here I develop an account of work on which work is teleologically structured. This gives the result that working is something we can fail at doing, even when we try, and we can also be unsure of whether we've succeeded or failed. The shift of certain work from in-person to online modes generates a persistent uncertainty for workers in affected professions. Because our ability to work is something we typically value, this uncertainty has significant negative consequences for a worker's self-conception. Indeed, it is analogous to disorders of agency and generates a kind of alienation.
... They note that many jobs in fact produce deleterious outputs, to the self, to others, to society and to the environment, either directly (see Frayne's "working pains" in 2015: 46-66;Cholbi 2018a), or more generally because the work ethic is tied to a productivist mindset that ignores its devastating consequences (Gorz 2018). Indeed, working implies costs and burdens that are often not taken into account (Cholbi 2018b). Having a job today in no way ensures that an individual is able to sustain their material well-being, both because wages are under continuous downward pressure and full-time employment in well-paid occupations tends to become the exception rather than the norm (Gorz 1980(Gorz : 3, 1989 Srnicek and Williams 2015: 67). ...
Article
Full-text available
In recent years, theorists have contended that we should move to a mode of social organisation where work and the values attached to it are no longer central, a ‘post-work society’. For these theorists, the modern ideology of work is intrinsically unjust, even irrational and no longer suited to the challenges of our time. The article presents an alternative response to the problems of work and employment. Rather than moving to a ‘post-work’ society, the article argues that we should transform the world of work, precisely by keeping in view why working is important to individuals and the community. In fact, it is not realistic to believe that human societies could ever do without work. Because human societies are by necessity work societies, and work, if organised correctly, entails many goods, we cannot really, and we should not, wish work away.
... Existing field studies can tell us a limited amount regarding UBI's potential effects on different labour market groups, but the lack of long-term studies means we can extrapolate little. For example, the fact that existing studies suggest people do not generally give up work in response to receiving a UBI (Forget, 2011;Salehi-Isfahani & Mostafavi-Dehzooei, 2018) does not mean that they would not do so under a long-term UBI programme, which could shape adaptive preferences (Cholbi, 2018). ...
Book
The unconditional basic income (UBI) has attracted renewed attention in academia, as well as in public discussions in recent years, and much has been written on the possible consequences of a UBI. However, this is the first book focusing on the UBI in Europe that offers empirical research findings. It includes a survey on preferences for a UBI in the EU; an assessment of the political feasibility of a UBI in the EU; field studies in the Netherlands and Scotland; and the findings of laboratory experiments. Presenting contributions from Dutch and international researchers, this book provides scientific answers to the question of whether a UBI is desirable and feasible in Europe.
... Existing field studies can tell us a limited amount regarding UBI's potential effects on different labour market groups, but the lack of long-term studies means we can extrapolate little. For example, the fact that existing studies suggest people do not generally give up work in response to receiving a UBI (Forget, 2011;Martinelli, 2017;Salehi-Isfahani & Mostafavi-Dehzooei, 2018) does not mean that they would not do so under a long-term UBI programme, which could shape adaptive preferences (Cholbi, 2018). ...
Chapter
A basic income policy, whereby individuals receive unconditional, regular payments regardless of their income, wealth or economic activity, has been a long-held goal for many. Increasing discussions among a variety of stakeholders and evidence of concrete actions in many European states suggest its time may have come. Yet there is also resistance, and the feasibility of such a policy is subject to significant constraints, both in terms of implementation and achievement of desired outcomes. We use data on campaigns, political support and pilot studies from a variety of sources to assess the likely feasibility of a basic income policy in the European Union. The emerging pilots and other concrete actions suggest that there have been important, if fragile, steps forward. We suggest that while discussion and public statements of support are still a long way from a realisable basic income policy, the pressures for radical and innovative reforms of the welfare state mean that basic income will remain a relevant solution for elements of current and future labour market challenges.
... For an exploration of how the desire to work is shaped by contemporary economic and ideological conditions, seeCholbi (2018). 5 For a helpful elaboration of Christian attitudes toward work prior to the emergence of the Protestant work ethic, seeLis and Soly (2012). ...
Article
Full-text available
Most advanced industrial societies are ‘work-centered,’ according high value and prestige to work. Indeed, belief in an interpersonal moral duty to work is encoded in both popular attitudes toward work and in policies such as ‘workfare’. Here I argue that despite the intuitive appeal of reciprocity or fair play as the moral basis for a duty to work, the vast majority of individuals in advanced industrialized societies have no such duty to work. For current economic conditions, labor markets, and government policies entail that the conditions for a reciprocity-based argument to apply to most workers are not usually met. More specifically, many workers fail to provide valuable goods through working or their working does not result in net social benefit. Concurrently, many workers do not receive adequate benefits from working in that they neither have their basic needs met or do not even enjoy an improvement in welfare thanks to working. Hence, workers neither provide nor receive the benefits needed for a reciprocity-based duty to work to apply to them. Furthermore, these conditions are conditions over which workers themselves have very little control. Most workers therefore could not fulfill their ostensible duty to work even if they made conscientious efforts to do so. In most cases, a person who fails to work morally wrongs no one, and in the case of any particular individual or worker, the defeasible presumption ought to be that she has no duty to work.
Article
Full-text available
In this paper, I offer an account of social alienation, a genre of alienation engendered by contemporary work that has gone largely overlooked in the ethics of labor. Social alienation consists in a corruption of workers’ relations to their social life and the people that make it up. When one is socially alienated, one’s sociality and close relations exist as a mere afterthought or break from work, while labor is the central activity of one’s life. While one might think that existing solutions to alienated labor would resolve this social alienation, I suggest that such solutions at best leave the problem intact and may in fact contribute to it by giving labor the place of priority in workers’ lives. Resolving social alienation, I suggest, requires rethinking the amount of time we commit to work, the rigidity of the work schedule, and most crucially, the value that we attribute to work as the primary source of purpose in our lives.
Article
Full-text available
Adaptive preferences are preferences formed in response to circumstances and opportunities – paradigmatically, they occur when we scale back our desires so they accord with what is probable or at least possible. While few commentators are willing to wholly reject the normative significance of such preferences, adaptive preferences have nevertheless attracted substantial criticism in recent political theory. The groundbreaking analysis of Jon Elster charged that such preferences are not autonomous, and several other commentators have since followed Elster’s lead. On a second front, Capability Theorists Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen have objected that adaptive preferences lead people away from objective goods and constitute an impediment to progressive change in developing countries. In this paper I argue that the criticisms of Elster, Sen and Nussbaum fail on the one hand to take into account what may be positively said in favour of this type of preference formation, and fail on the other hand to distinguish between different types of psychological changes – with the result that many of the critiques offered have a narrower purview than is currently allowed. My analysis of adaptive preferences, even in their most ideal form, is however not entirely positive; I adduce reasons why we can be cautious about allowing adaptive preferences to play certain types of roles in political processes, even as we accept those very preferences as normative and autonomous for the agent holding them.
Article
Full-text available
Background: There is little evidence on whether becoming re-employed in poor quality work is better for health and well-being than remaining unemployed. We examined associations of job transition with health and chronic stress-related biomarkers among a population-representative cohort of unemployed British adults. Methods: A prospective cohort of 1116 eligible participants aged 35 to 75 years, who were unemployed at wave 1 (2009/10) of the UK Household Longitudinal Study, were followed up at waves 2 (2010/11) and 3 (2011/12) for allostatic load biomarkers and self-reported health. Negative binomial and multiple regression models estimated the association between job adversity and these outcomes. Results: Compared with adults who remained unemployed, formerly unemployed adults who transitioned into poor quality jobs had higher levels of overall allostatic load (0.51, 0.32-0.71), log HbA1c (0.06, <0.001-0.12), log triglycerides (0.39, 0.22-0.56), log C-reactive protein (0.45, 0.16-0.75), log fibrinogen (0.09, 0.01-0.17) and total cholesterol to high-density lipoprotein (HDL) ratio (1.38, 0.88-1.88). Moreover, physically healthier respondents at wave 1 were more likely to transition into good quality and poor quality jobs after 1 year than those who remained unemployed. Conclusions: Formerly unemployed adults who transitioned into poor quality work had greater adverse levels of biomarkers compared with their peers who remained unemployed. The selection of healthier unemployed adults into these poor quality or stressful jobs was unlikely to explain their elevated levels of chronic stress-related biomarkers. Job quality cannot be disregarded from the employment success of the unemployed, and may have important implications for their health and well-being.
Article
Full-text available
According to rational will views of paternalism, the wrongmaking feature of paternalism is that paternalists disregard or fail to respect the rational will of the paternalized, in effect substituting their own presumably superior judgments about what ends the paternalized ought to pursue or how they ought to pursue them. Here I defend a version of the rational will view appealing to three rational powers that constitute rational agency, which I call recognition, discrimination, and satisfaction. By appealing to these powers, my version of the rational will view can rank the wrongfulness of paternalistic acts in terms of (a) the extent to which such acts amount to supplanting the paternalized individual’s identity as a rational agent with that of the paternalist, and (b) the degree of mistrust in the paternalized individual's rational agency shown by the paternalistic act. My rational powers account thus provides a more complete account of why paternalism is a powerful, but not decisive or absolute, objection to an act or policy. My rational powers account also provides powerful explanations of why rational suasion deflects charges of paternalism; why consenting to intercessions in one’s rational agency negates paternalism; why strong paternalism is generally more objectionable than weak paternalism; and why hard paternalism is generally more objectionable than soft paternalism.
Article
Current literature in moral and political philosophy is rife with discussion of adaptive preferences. This is no accident: while preferences are generally thought to play an important role in a number of normative domains (including morality, the personal good, and political justice), adaptive preferences seem exceptions to this general rule—they seem problematic in a way that preference-respecting theories of these domains cannot adequately capture. Thus, adaptive preferences are often taken to be theoretically explanatory: a reason for adjusting our theories of the relevant normative domains. However, as I shall argue here, the relentless focus on the phenomenon of preference adaptation is a mistake. While I do not take a stand on whether typical examples of adaptive preferences are or are not problematic, I argue here that if they are problematic, it cannot be because they are adaptive.
Book
Paid work is absolutely central to the culture and politics of capitalist societies, yet today s work-centred world is becoming increasingly hostile to the human need for autonomy, spontaneity and community. The grim reality of a society in which some are overworked, whilst others are condemned to intermittent work and unemployment, is progressively more difficult to tolerate. In this thought-provoking book, David Frayne questions the central place of work in mainstream political visions of the future, laying bare the ways in which economic demands colonise our lives and priorities. Drawing on his original research into the lives of people who are actively resisting nine-to-five employment, Frayne asks what motivates these people to disconnect from work, whether or not their resistance is futile, and whether they might have the capacity to inspire an alternative form of development, based on a reduction and social redistribution of work. A crucial dissection of the work-centred nature of modern society and emerging resistance to it, The Refusal of Work is a bold call for a more humane and sustainable vision of social progress.
Article
The severity, sudden onset, and multipronged nature of the Great Recession (2007–2009) provided a unique opportunity to examine the health impacts of macroeconomic downturn. We comprehensively review empirical literature examining the relationship between the Recession and mental and physical health outcomes in developed nations. Overall, studies reported detrimental impacts of the Recession on health, particularly mental health. Macro- and individual-level employment- and housing-related sequelae of the Recession were associated with declining fertility and self-rated health, and increasing morbidity, psychological distress, and suicide, although traffic fatalities and population-level alcohol consumption declined. Health impacts were stronger among men and racial/ethnic minorities. Importantly, strong social safety nets in some European countries appear to have buffered those populations from negative health effects. This literature, however, still faces multiple methodological challenges, and more time may be needed to observe the Recession’s full health impact. We conclude with suggestions for future work in this field.
Article
Women have historically been prevented from living autonomously by systematic injustice, subordination, and oppression. The lingering effects of these practices have prompted many feminists to view autonomy with suspicion. This book defends the ideal of feminist autonomy. The book proposes that behavior is autonomous if it accords with the wants, cares, values, or commitments that the actor has reaffirmed and is able to sustain in the face of opposition. By this account, autonomy is socially grounded yet also individualizing and sometimes socially disruptive, qualities that can be ultimately advantageous for women. The book applies the concept of autonomy to domains of special interest to women. It defends the importance of autonomy in romantic love, considers how social institutions should respond to women who choose to remain in abusive relationships, and argues that liberal societies should tolerate minority cultural practices that violate women's rights so long as the women in question have chosen autonomously to live according to those practices.
Article
This book presents a new, integrated theory of social oppression, which tackles the fundamental question that no theory of oppression has satisfactorily answered: if there is no natural hierarchy among humans, why are some cases of oppression so persistent? The book argues that the explanation lies in the coercive co-opting of the oppressed to join in their own oppression. This answer sets the stage for analysis throughout the book, as it explores the questions of how and why the oppressed join in their oppression. The book argues that oppression is an institutionally structured harm perpetrated on social groups by other groups using direct and indirect material, economic, and psychological force. Among the most important and insidious of the indirect forces is an economic force that operates through oppressed persons' own rational choices. This force constitutes the central feature of analysis, and the book argues that this force is especially insidious because it conceals the fact of oppression from the oppressed and from others who would be sympathetic to their plight. The oppressed come to believe that they suffer personal failings and this belief appears to absolve society from responsibility. While in the book's view oppression is grounded in material exploitation and physical deprivation, it cannot be long sustained without corresponding psychological forces. The book examines the direct and indirect psychological forces that generate and sustain oppression. It discusses strategies that groups have used to resist oppression and argues that all persons have a moral responsibility to resist in some way. The concluding chapter proposes a concept of freedom that would be possible for humans in a world that is actively opposing oppression, arguing that freedom for each individual is only possible when we achieve freedom for all others.