Content uploaded by Yannick Joye
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Yannick Joye on Jul 12, 2018
Content may be subject to copyright.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
1
Nature’s Broken Path to Restoration. A Critical Look at Attention Restoration Theory
Yannick Joye1, Siegfried Dewitte2
1 University of Groningen, y.joye@rug.nl
2 University of Leuven, siegfried.dewitte@kuleuven.be
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
2
Abstract
Over the past three decades, a growing body of environmental psychology research has
demonstrated that interacting with natural environments – and especially greenspace – can have
beneficial psychological effects on human individuals. One influential and widely-cited
theoretical account to explain such effects is Attention Restoration Theory (ART). ART zooms
in on the cognitive benefits nature can yield, and assumes that when an individual’s ability to
concentrate or direct attention has become depleted, then nature is well-equipped to replenish
this capacity. Nature’s restorative potential is thought to especially derive from its soft
fascinating characteristics; these can put an individual in an effortless mode of attention, thereby
giving directed attention a relative opportunity to rest and replenish itself. Although ART has
been highly influential in the field of restoration studies and continues to inspire health
promotion interventions, with the current paper we aim to show that the framework has
important empirical and conceptual shortcomings. We specifically aim to show (a) that some of
ART’s principal theoretical notions are vague (e.g., soft fascination), have remained
underdeveloped, and lack a clear operationalization, (b) that the framework has failed to
(adequately) test its main theoretical predictions (i.e., that nature effects are recovery effects),
and (c) that there is currently little support for the ART-based assumption that restoration is – or
derives from – an ancient evolved adaptive response. We conclude our paper with discussing
four outstanding questions for ART, and make methodological suggestions that could potentially
address some of ART’s current shortcomings.
Keywords: Attention Restoration Theory, soft fascination, directed attention, criticism
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
3
Nature’s Broken Path to Restoration. A Critical Look at Attention Restoration Theory
In their influential 2008 article, Berman, Jonides and Kaplan ask their readers to
“(i)magine a therapy that had no known side effects, was readily available, and could improve
your cognitive functioning at zero cost” (Berman, Jonides, & Kaplan, 2008, 1207). The therapy
they have in mind, and for which they hope to gather empirical support, is to go out into nature.
While beliefs about nature’s healing potential are part and parcel of many current and past
cultures, and will, for many, resonate with personal experience, the last three decades a growing
body of environmental psychology research has sought to confirm this notion.
But whence this apparently unique capacity of nature to mentally invigorate and sooth us?
Is it because (being in) nature invites physical exercise, provides us with opportunities for social
contact, or reminds us of relaxing times and activities (e.g., holidays)? Is it because nature, more
so than urban and/or indoor environments, offers us fresh air and daylight? While these and other
factors have indeed been shown to contribute to nature’s salutogenic effects (for a review:
Hartig, Mitchell, de Vries, & Frumkin, 2014), environmental psychology research demonstrates
that already the direct perceptual (i.e., visual) experience of nature scenes and elements –
especially vegetation and water features – can positively impact individuals, by counteracting
stress (Ulrich et al., 1991) and facilitating the recovery from mental fatigue (Kaplan, 1995;
Berman et al., 2008). Such effects are commonly labelled as “restorative” nature experiences, as
they seemingly involve a recovery from depleted cognitive resources and/or undo negative
psychophysiological states.
In research on restorative experiences, two important theoretical frameworks have been
proposed to explain nature’s restorative effects, namely Stress Recovery Theory (SRT; Ulrich,
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
4
1983; Ulrich et al., 1991) and Attention Restoration Theory (ART; Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989;
Kaplan, 1995; Kaplan & Berman, 2010). SRT especially aims to elucidate how contact with
nature can reduce (psychophysiological) stress in individuals. Drawing on evolutionary
psychology (e.g., Tooby & Cosmides, 1992), SRT specifically assumes that the human species is
biologically prepared to rapidly display positive affect towards natural, vegetation-rich
environments (Ulrich, 1983; Ulrich, 1993; Ulrich et al., 1991; Parsons, Tassinary, Ulrich, Hebl,
& Grossman-Alexander, 1998). The argument goes that such a response was adaptive for
ancestral humans, because it facilitated their quest for food, water, and places to shelter (see
especially Ulrich, 1993). Based on the evolutionary psychology hypothesis that the modern
human brain is wired for the Stone-Age (Tooby & Cosmides, 1997), SRT assumes that in our
modern era natural settings and elements still produce positive affect in individuals, which may
consequently reduce, or even buffer psychophysiological stress.
Where SRT zooms in on people’s immediate affective responses to nature as a driver of
restoration, ART focuses on the potential cognitive benefits that can derive from interactions
with natural environments (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989; Kaplan, 1995; Kaplan & Berman, 2010). A
central notion in ART is “directed attention”, which can be defined as the effortful process to
focus or concentrate on objects or events, while at the same time blocking out distracting
stimulation. While ART considers directed attention to be a limited resource that can be depleted
after long and/or intensive use, it also claims that certain environments – especially natural
environments – are able to facilitate/support the recovery from a state of attentional depletion.
According to ART, the reason is that nature is often rife with (soft) fascinating stimuli that
capture one’s attention in an automatic, bottom-up way. This minimizes the demands on
(effortful) directed attention, and consequently allows this capacity to rest and restore itself.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
5
Over the last three decades empirical evidence for nature’s restorative benefits has been
steadily accumulating. Restoration researchers have – amongst others – attempted to chart the
positive cognitive (for a review: Ohly et al., 2016), affective (for a review: McMahan & Estes,
2015) and psychophysiological effects of nature contact (e.g., Ulrich et al., 1991; Hartig, Evans,
Jamner, Davis, & Gärling, 2003; Chang, Hammitt, Chen, Machnik, & Su, 2008; Van Den Berg
& Custers, 2011). Efforts have been made to determine the optimal dose (Barton & Pretty, 2010;
Shanahan et al., 2016) and modality (e.g., virtual versus real nature; Pals, Steg, Dontje, Siero, &
van Der Zee, 2014) of nature for restoration, while research has also demonstrated how
restorative nature effects can depend on group characteristics (e.g., elderly: Ottosson & Grahn,
2005; children: Taylor & Kuo, 2008; Ulset, Vitaro, Brendgen, Bekkhus, & Borge, 2017), on
individuals’ salient identities (e.g., Morton, van der Bles, & Haslam, 2017) or on the life stage
one is in (Scopelliti & Giuliani, 2004).
While nature restoration has occasionally been studied from a qualitative perspective – for
example by taking interviews on nature experiences and activities (cfr., Hawkins, Mercer,
Thirlaway, & Clayton, 2013) – the majority of restoration studies are quantitative. Such
quantitative studies have made use of secondary data to establish a link between restoration and
access to natural environments (White, Pahl, Ashbullby, Herbert, & Depledge, 2013), but
oftentimes nature’s restorative benefits are experimentally researched within lab or field settings,
using both subjective (i.e., self-report) and objective measures of emotional and
attentional/cognitive functioning (e.g., Joye, Pals, Steg, & Lewis-Evans, 2013). Key findings and
reviews on restoration have been published in highly prestigious academic journals (e.g.,
Science: Ulrich, 1984; Hartig & Kahn, 2016; The Lancet: Hartig & Marcus, 2006), have become
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
6
highly cited1, and have received ample media coverage – all of which testifies to the importance
of this research field, within academia and beyond.
The insight that nature can make people thrive is also increasingly applied to (different
parts of) our daily lives. Based on restoration research, healthcare professionals and instances
promote contact with natural environments as a means to bolster psychological health and
wellbeing, or to reduce pain and stress during clinical interventions (Diette, Lechtzin, Haponik,
Devrotes, & Rubin, 2003; Tanja-Dijkstra et al., 2017). Contact with greenery has been found to
boost children’s cognitive performance in the classroom (Van den Berg, Wesselius, Maas, &
Tanja-Dijkstra, 2017), and to enhance workers’ mood and productivity in office settings
(Korpela, De Bloom, & Kinnunen, 2015; Steidle, Gonzalez-Morales, Hoppe, Michel, & O’Shea,
2017). In the commercial sphere, retail environments are greened up to lift the mood of
consumers, and to consequently boost their willingness to pay and/or buy (Joye, Willems,
Brengman, & Wolf, 2010; Brengman, Willems, & Joye, 2012; Rosenbaum, Otalora, & Ramírez,
2016). Based on the various psychological benefits of nature contact, in some countries
(governmental) campaigns have even been initiated to raise awareness of nature’s soothing
psychological effects (e.g., “green schoolyards” in the Netherlands).
While laudable, the search for further empirical confirmation and for promising
applications of nature’s salutogenic effects has – in our view – also come with a cost, in that the
field of restoration studies has reached a theoretical standstill. Since already three decades SRT
and ART have been standing as the main and seemingly undisputable explanatory frameworks
for restorative nature experiences, despite some striking limitations and issues. In this paper, we
1 For example, Kaplan & Kaplan (1989) receives 5915 citations on Google Scholar, whereas Ulrich (1984) receives
4422 citations (date: 6 June 2018).
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
7
aim to start overturning this theoretical status quo2. For this, we will review the main theoretical
assumptions underlying the field of restoration research, and point to a number of important
empirical and conceptual shortcomings. Note that with our critical review we will specifically
target ART, rather than SRT, as the former theory has barely received any systematic criticism
(for critiques on SRT, see e.g., Kaplan, 1995; Joye & Van den Berg, 2011).
General outline
In what follows, we critically examine the main theoretical and empirical assumptions of
ART. In a nutshell, ART states that nature’s soft fascinating characteristics (i.e., the independent
variable) can lead to a recovery of directed attention (i.e., the dependent variable), and this effect
is driven by the capacity of fascinating (natural) environments to trigger bottom-up involuntary
attention (i.e., the mediator). In the ensuing critical review, we aim to pinpoint difficulties with
all three elements of ART’s basic model. In our first two criticisms, we address the DV side of
the model, and ask whether there is currently sufficient evidence for the assumption that
restorative nature effects are recovery effects (Assumption 1), and that a particular cognitive
resource (i.e. directed attention) is replenished during this recovery process (Assumption 2).
Next, we focus on the IV side of the model, and argue that the notion of soft fascination is vague
and conceptually underdeveloped, and is currently lacking a clear operationalization
(Assumption 3 and Assumption 4). We then move on to the proposed mediator for attention
restoration, and point out that, besides being untested, it is far from even-handed that the (often
2 This theoretical standstill is probably also exacerbated by the fact that some restoration studies are only loosely
based on ART or SRT, and are not particularly interested in rigorously testing ART’s/SRT’s highly specific
assumptions.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
8
mundane) natural settings used in restoration research are able to trigger bottom-up involuntary
attention in the first place (Assumption 5). Following this, we zoom out, and question the
broader evolutionary background of ART, i.e., the assumption that natural fascinations are
restorative because they ultimately fulfilled an adaptive function in ancestral environments
(Assumption 6). We close off with some outstanding questions, such as why being in a state of
fascination is associated with cognitive effortlessness rather than effortfulness.
Assumption 1: Restorative nature effects are recovery effects
One of ART’s central assumptions is that when individuals are attentionally fatigued,
contact with natural settings can relax the demands on directed attention, thereby giving this
capacity an opportunity to recover and replenish itself (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989; Kaplan, 1995;
Kaplan & Berman, 2010). Because urban environments often contain dramatically distracting
stimulation (e.g., car horns, billboards: Berman et al., 2008), in such settings directed attention
may need to be further recruited to block out that stimulation, thereby potentially exacerbating
directed attention fatigue. Thus, in the most common theoretical characterization of ART,
restorative nature experiences are assumed to be recovery effects: nature facilitates the
replenishment of an initially depleted resource, i.e., directed attention.
Several ART-based studies are aimed at testing whether restorative environments indeed
foster a recovery from attentional fatigue (e.g., Laumann, Gärling, & Stormark, 2003; Hartig et
al., 2003; Bodin & Hartig, 2003; Berto, 2005; Berman et al., 2008; Shin, Shin, Yeoun, & Kim,
2011; Berman et al., 2012). Such studies typically start off by administering participants a task
that induces a state of attentional fatigue in them, which is then followed by an environmental
treatment (oftentimes exposure to, or immersion in natural versus urban settings), and the target
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
9
measurement of participants’ attentional/cognitive functioning. Employing this experimental
paradigm, several studies find that (fatigued) individuals who have subsequently been exposed
to, or immersed in natural/green environments (e.g., forests, parks) score better on the (target)
attentional/cognitive task than individuals exposed to urban settings (Joye & Van den Berg,
2012).
While the results of such ART-based studies are often interpreted in terms of a
(cognitive/attentional) recovery process, it is worth emphasizing that it is common practice to
fatigue all participants before environmental exposure in such studies (Beute & De Kort, 2014).
Besides notable exceptions (e.g., Hartig et al., 2003; Hartig, Böök, Garvill, Olsson, & Gärling,
1996), the vast majority of restoration studies does not include a control group of low-fatigued
individuals to compare the results of the experimental group with (see Ohly et al., 2016 for an
overview). With this paradigm, it obviously becomes impossible to determine whether superior
(cognitive/attentional) performance after seeing nature (versus urban scenes) in fatigued
individuals is diagnostic of a recovery from directed attention depletion, or whether it signals an
entirely different process, unrelated to recovery (e.g., vitalizing and energizing potential of
natural versus urban settings: Ryan et al., 2010). One of ART’s major theoretical claims thus
remains to be tested.
The absence of a control group in restoration studies, in and of itself does not disconfirm
ART’s recovery idea. That could only happen if, in one and the same study, a control group of
low-fatigued individuals were shown to benefit as much from the nature intervention as highly
fatigued individuals. While systematic and extensive research on this issue is currently lacking,
some initial evidence speaks to this idea. Beute and De Kort (2014), for example, found that
individuals were better able to self-regulate after exposure to natural versus urban scenes, and
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
10
showed that this effect occurred for (ego) depleted as well as for non-depleted participants. In
line with this finding, prominent restoration researchers propose that “restorative” nature
experiences can indeed go beyond mere (attentional resource) replenishment, and point out that
“interacting with such environments can restore and even improve directed attention abilities”
(Kaplan & Berman, 2010, 52; italics added; see also: Collado, Staats, Corraliza, & Hartig, 2017).
But how to reconcile ART with the claim that nature can boost attentional functioning?
After all, the theory explains the cognitive benefits of interacting with nature solely in terms of
facilitating a return to baseline levels of an initially depleted attentional resource (through
fascination, and other supporting restorative components). Because ART assumes that nature
does not causally intervene in the process of restoration itself, the framework seems by definition
unable to explain how nature could boost attentional performance beyond that baseline.
Combined with the fact that there is currently little empirical evidence for ART’s recovery idea,
it might be worthwhile – and even more parsimonious – to explore the explanatory potential of
non-depletion accounts for beneficial cognitive nature effects.
Assumption 2: Directed attention is restored
While ART identifies directed attention as the main cognitive resource that can be restored
through contact with natural environments (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989; Kaplan, 1995; Kaplan &
Berman, 2010), this capacity has not been uniformly operationalized in restoration studies (Ohly
et al., 2016). As research stands, restoration researchers have used a fairly heterogeneous and
broad set of cognitive tasks to gauge restoration (Ohly et al., 2016), including – but not limited to
– proofreading (e.g., Hartig, Mang, & Evans, 1991), the Trail Making Test (e.g., Shin et al.,
2011), the Stroop Task (e.g., Taylor & Kuo, 2008), the Sustained Attention to Response Task
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
11
(e.g., Berto, 2005), or the Digit Span Backward/Forward (e.g., Berman et al., 2008; Berman et
al., 2012).
Importantly, the foregoing tasks vary in the type of cognitive functions they primarily
capture. This poses a challenge for ART, as such functional variety makes it difficult to ascertain
whether nature effects on one or more of these tasks either reflect (restoration of) directed
attention functioning or some other cognitive functions or phenomena. Very probably, however,
executing any of the aforementioned tasks requires some directed attention capacity, merely
because one needs a good deal of focus and concentration to complete them. And if the common
denominator between the cognitive tasks used in ART studies turns out to be directed attention,
is it then not justified to conclude that nature-induced cognitive effects reflect directed attention
functioning? Not necessarily, since such cognitive effects are consistent with, and can in
principle also be diagnostic of other processes triggered by fascinating natural scenes, such as
increased vitality (Ryan et al., 2010) or task motivation (Silvia, 2008). To the best of our
knowledge, such plausible alternative explanations have not been systematically explored, nor
have they been ruled out within the context of ART.
Note furthermore that a recent meta-analysis reveals that – from the broad arsenal of
objective measures used in ART-based research – especially an overall positive significant effect
of nature exposure was found for tasks tapping working memory performance (Ohly et al., 2016;
see: Hartig & Jahncke, 2017, for a critical review of aspects of this meta-analysis). Are we
therefore to conclude that nature is especially beneficial for working memory (e.g., Digit Span
Forward), rather than for directed attention? Or, is working memory task performance one of the
best ways to capture directed attention capacity? But if so, why then are other tasks than memory
tasks being used to gauge directed attention? In its current form, and testifying to its theoretical
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
12
underdevelopment, the literature on attention restoration does not provide clear-cut answers to
these questions. What seems certain, however, is that the current available empirical evidence for
nature’s cognitive benefits does not unambiguously support the hypothesis, central to ART, that
nature especially benefits the execution of directed attention.
Assumption 3: Nature’s fascinating qualities restore directed attention
Within ART, the attention restoring capacity of natural environments is (among others)
situated in the fact that such environments are more fascinating, or contain more fascinating
elements than urban environments. Fascination assumes a central explanatory role in ART: it
implies a state of effortless bottom-up attention, through which demands on directed attention
can be relaxed, allowing this limited resource to replenish itself. Restoration researchers have
mentioned “clouds, sunsets, snow patterns, the motion of the leaves in the breeze” (Kaplan,
1992, 139), or “waterfalls, caves and fires” (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989) as typical instances of
(natural) fascinations.
Importantly, in restoration studies participants are only rarely – if ever – exposed to caves,
fires, clouds or sunsets, but they are rather typically shown, or immersed in, vegetation-rich
environments, including park-like settings, meadows or forests. While there seems to be general
agreement on the idea that the restorativeness of such greenspace is (partly) due to its fascinating
qualities, at the same time there is currently very little known about what it is about such
restorative green settings – in terms of physical/visual attributes – that makes them fascinating in
the first place (see also: Valtchanov & Ellard, 2015; Van den Berg, Joye, & Koole, 2016).
Fascination is thus put forward as one of ART’s central explanatory principles, but at the same
time the notion itself has remained remarkably underexplained. Adding to this conceptual
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
13
vagueness is the issue that it even remains to be systematically empirically verified that
fascination is indeed a crucial driver of restorative nature effects.
Assumption 4: Nature’s soft fascinating qualities restore directed attention and enable
reflection (a.k.a. “full” restoration)
According to ART “full” restoration does not solely amount to a mere recovery of directed
attention capacity; part of a restorative experience is that individuals also have an opportunity to
reflect on unsolved (life) issues (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989; Herzog, Black, Fountaine, & Knotts,
1997). Through such reflection, internal noise that could otherwise further burden directed
attention capacity can be reduced (Basu, Duvall, & Kaplan, 2018)
Importantly, not all fascinations are equally suited to reach the stage of full restoration.
Certain fascinating events or phenomena might perhaps facilitate attention restoration by
effortlessly attracting attention (e.g., attending a sports event), but they might at the same time
also be so absorbing or dramatic that they leave little place for reflection, thereby making it
difficult for individuals to attain full restoration (Herzog et al., 1997). Proponents of ART have
specified that full restoration will especially occur upon exposure to natural stimuli or
environments that trigger “soft” fascination, a notion referring to a positively valenced but less
dramatic type of fascination (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989; Herzog et al., 1997). Soft fascinating
settings attract effortless attention in a moderate and pleasant way, and thereby leave ample place
for the mind to wander, for unbidden thoughts to occur, and for serious reflection about
important (life) issues.
Despite the importance of soft fascination to reach full restoration, to our knowledge the
optimal softness level of fascination that is needed to provoke a full restorative experience has
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
14
not been clarified in ART, nor has it been explained which attributes make a fascinating stimulus
or environment soft rather than hard fascinating (e.g., size, intensity, duration of the stimulus).
Adding to this conceptual vagueness is the issue that the commonly used instruments to gauge
fascination (e.g., Perceived Restoration Scale: Hartig, Korpela, Evans, & Gärling, 1997;
Restorative Components Scale: Laumann et al., 2001) do not differentiate between hard and soft
fascination (see also: Basu et al., 2018). The theoretically predicted role of soft fascination thus
not only remains untested, the major (validated) instruments to probe fascination are not even
designed to test it.
We agree that it may be hard to define a particular point at which soft fascination turns into
hard fascination, or vice versa. But without a minimal specification of the bandwidth of optimal
softness, any stimulus could potentially be considered as soft fascinating, whereby the notion
runs the risk of becoming unfalsifiable. As long as it is not clarified how much softness is
required for full restoration to occur, we remain unable to fully understand, and explain why
exactly natural, vegetation-rich environments are generally more restorative than urban settings.
Assumption 5: Nature is restorative by virtue of bottom-up effortless attention
So far, we have discussed what is needed for restoration to occur: namely that natural
environments have softly fascinating characteristics. A next question is how (soft) fascination
facilitates restoration. As pointed out earlier, in ART fascination is assumed to be akin to
(effortless) bottom-up attention (Berman et al., 2008; Kaplan & Berman, 2010), and by
recruiting this type of attention the capacity for (effortful) top-down attention is not further
burdened, but instead given an opportunity to replenish itself. Nature is restorative by virtue of
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
15
its fascinating – and hence bottom-up – aspects, whereas urban settings command, and might
therefore further deplete, top-down attention.
While being one of ART’s central theoretical theses, the assumption that fascinating nature
recruits bottom-up attention remains to be empirically verified. What is more is that there seems
to be a seeming misfit between this theoretical notion and the particular characteristics of the
natural environments used in restoration studies. Specifically, it is well known that bottom-up
attention is typically activated by stimuli that stand out and inadvertently attract attention: think
for example of a bright red bird in a green tree canopy, the sudden flash of a lightning bolt
(Corbetta & Shulman, 2002), or as Stephen Kaplan (1995, 170) mentions “… wild animals,
danger, caves, blood…”. Note, however, that in restoration experiments participants often have
to passively watch visuals (e.g., videos, photographs) of, or to walk in fairly unspectacular,
mundane natural settings (e.g., urban park), seemingly devoid of things that truly stand out3.
When turning to the urban perspective, it has been noted that “… urban environments are
filled with stimulation that captures attention dramatically” (Berman et al., 2008, 1207), and that
directed attention fatigue can ensue, or is exacerbated, when top-down attention is required to
block out this dramatic stimulation. Also this theoretical assumption is not evidently reflected in
the stimuli that are used: in numerous restoration studies participants have to watch
images/videos of fairly ordinary streetscapes, which clearly lack any of the “dramatic” features
that might cause or worsen attentional fatigue. Note that even if the urban scenes would display
dramatic stimulation, it is unsure whether – at least in a lab setting – participants would
3 It might be argued that nature recruits bottom-up attention mainly because of the evolutionary significance of
natural settings, and not so much because of salient visual characteristics (Awh, Belopolsky, & Theeuwes, 2012).
We refer to our discussion of Assumption 6, where we address this point.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
16
experience a need to overcome that stimulation, given the passive viewing setup characteristic of
such restoration studies.
Restoration has been claimed to result from the workings of effortless bottom-up attention
(or: fascination) recruited by nature, and effortful top-down attention (or: directed attention)
commanded by urban settings (Berman et al., 2008; Kaplan & Berman, 2010; Berman et al.,
2012). However, the fact that beneficial nature effects occur using fairly mundane exemplars of
both stimulus categories not only suggests that ART does not strictly test what it theoretically
predicts, but it also challenges the notion that those nature effects are to an important extent
driven by the interplay between bottom-up and top-down attention. If anything, it seems that the
stimulation that is thought to underlie the depleting aspects of urban environments (Kaplan &
Berman, 2010) – e.g., car horns, billboards, or any other dramatic stimulation – fits the
description of typical input of bottom-up attention much better than the natural scenes used in
restoration research (Corbetta & Shulman, 2002).
Assumption 6: Fascination with natural settings has an evolved origin
For ART’s sixth theoretical assumption, we turn away from the proposed proximate to
the ultimate mechanism for attention restoration, and focus on the idea – made by prominent
restoration researchers – that restorative nature experiences are ultimately rooted in our shared
evolution in natural settings (cfr., Kaplan, 1977; Hartig et al., 1996; Van den Berg, Hartig, &
Staats, 2007; Staats, 2012; Collado et al., 2017). This view is for instance expressed by Stephen
Kaplan who claims that because “…our ancestors evolved in a nature-filled environment…
[nature] should feel more comfortable, more relaxed, more like home. It’s not a big leap between
that and being more competent, less distracted” (Kaplan cited in Jaffe, 2010). Kaplan’s
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
17
acknowledgment of the evolved origins, and possibly adaptive function(s) of our positive
(cognitive and emotional) responses to nature, resonates with Edward O. Wilson’s biophilia
hypothesis (1984; Kellert & Wilson, 1995), as well as with the tenets of SRT (Ulrich, 1983;
Ulrich et al., 1991; Ulrich, 1993), both of which consider mankind’s affective bond with nature
as an (adaptive) remnant of our evolutionary past in natural settings.
ART’s evolutionary theorizing starts off from the idea that “…much of what was
important to the evolving human – wild animals, danger, caves, blood, to name a few examples –
was (and still is) innately fascinating…” (Kaplan, 1995, 170). From this perspective, one of the
ultimate functions of fascination – the central driver of attention restoration – was thus to
selectively attend to stimuli of evolutionary significance, including possible threat cues (e.g.,
predators), as well as cues signalling reward value (e.g., food, mates). The view that natural
stimuli/characteristics can be innately attention grabbing, receives support from empirical
research hinting at an evolved propensity to display selective attention towards animate motion
(Pratt, Radulescu, Guo, & Abrams, 2010), as well as to certain biological kinds (Yorzinski,
Penkunas, Platt, & Coss, 2014).
If especially green environments/elements grab attention, generate (aesthetic) interest, and
have restorative potential, then this of course raises the question what the evolutionary
significance was of selective attention to such settings/elements. Proponents of ART have argued
that, inasmuch as “(w)ater, trees, and foliage are all indicators of the habitats in which human
survival is more likely” (Kaplan 1987, 25), an aesthetic interest/fascination could guide and
facilitate the process of finding a safe retreat that contained life-sustaining elements, such as food
and water. When individuals are nowadays exposed to nature, and specifically to greenery and
foliage, then this still effortlessly draws attention (i.e., fascination), with a number of
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
18
downstream effects, including restoration from directed attention fatigue (Van den Berg et al.,
2007). The upshot is that “… people will restore better in environments that have characteristics
that were relevant for survival during early evolution” (Collado et al., 2017, 129).
Given the idea that the adaptive function of fascination with green settings was to guide
humans to “good habitats”, one would expect fascination – and hence restoration – to especially
occur for green settings/elements that actually provided food, water and safety for ancestral
humans, or at least contained specific cues diagnostic of these. Based on this, researchers
studying evolved responses to landscapes have argued (Orians, 1980; Orians & Heerwagen,
1992; Heerwagen & Orians, 1993; Coss, 2003) that individuals should be particularly drawn to
trees with broad canopies (offering protection against adverse weather conditions) and short
trunks (making them easily climbable), and by verdant, fruit-bearing vegetation (indicating the
nearness of water and food).
While there is some (mixed) evidence for an aesthetic preference for savanna-type
settings and trees (Balling & Falk, 1982; Sommer & Summit, 1995; Summit & Sommer, 1999;
Lohr & Pearson-Mims, 2006; Falk & Balling, 2010), to the best of our knowledge, there is still a
dearth of research that systematically tests the fascinating qualities, and superior restorative
qualities of green settings that can afford resources and protection. More importantly, and in
seeming contrast to the view that selective attention to such settings is an adaptive response,
studies show that restoration occurs towards green settings/elements in general (Velarde, Fry, &
Tveit, 2007), many of which lack obvious indicators of a high-quality habitat (i.e., cues of food,
water and refuge). ART has thus posited the existence of an adaptive response, but this response
also appears to occur for environments that do not evidently solve the problem for which this
adaptation presumably has been designed for by natural selection (Joye & Van den Berg, 2011).
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
19
In view of this, it remains very unsure whether a general fascination with foliage and greenery
could have promoted our ancestors’ fitness.
Outstanding issues
Our critical review suggests that ART faces substantial conceptual and empirical issues,
which call for further theoretical development of the framework, and point to the importance of
additional empirical verification of central theoretical assumptions. Below, we list four further
outstanding issues/questions, which – we feel – have not been adequately or explicitly addressed
and/or clarified within ART.
How do fleeting episodes of bottom-up attention support restoration?
Attention restoration is commonly interpreted as a process that needs time to unfold (e.g.,
Hartig et al., 1996), and that is triggered by, and ascribed to (natural) environments in their
entirety (cfr., “Natural environments, such as parks, gardens, and lakefronts, are able to capture
involuntary attention…”, Kaplan & Berman, 2010, 48), whereas bottom-up involuntary attention
is well-known to be short-lived and triggered by constituent scene elements (Corbetta &
Shulman, 2002). Given these outspoken differences in terms of temporal and spatial resolution
between the explanandum (i.e., restoration via nature contact) and explanans (i.e., bottom-up
attention), the question arises of how exactly seemingly fleeting and “local” episodes of
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
20
involuntary attention can mutually combine or connect, so as to support a full-blown restorative
experience towards an entire environment or scene4.
Why does hard fascination preclude reflection?
ART suggests that because soft fascinating scenes are only moderately distracting, they
leave ample room for reflection about important life issues, and thereby enable individuals to
reach full restoration (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989; Kaplan & Berman, 2010). But why should soft
(rather than hard) fascination be a necessary requirement for reflection? Research on individuals’
responses to awe-inspiring nature (Keltner & Haidt, 2003), for example, suggests that deeply
fascinating natural settings and phenomena (e.g., the Grand Canyon) can be mind-fulling, but at
the same time also make individuals reflective and mindful about themselves, their lives, and
their place in the world, by virtue of their profoundly attention grabbing qualities (Jefferies &
Lepp, 2012; Pearce, Strickland-Munro, & Moore, 2017)5. By inducing a sense of self-
4 While we are aware that Kaplan and Kaplan (1989) point out that a restorative environment needs to have extent,
whereby disparate fascinating elements become connected (to a larger framework), this still leaves us with the
question as to how exactly such connectedness is reached.
5 There can, of course, be differences between reflective episodes stemming from encounters with soft fascinating
settings versus reflection originating from hard fascinating, awe-evoking environments. For instance, reflection in
hard fascinating (natural) environments probably occurs only after, and not during the fascinating experience. In
addition, reflection in soft fascinating environments is probably due to mind-wandering, while in the case of awe-
evoking settings it might result from the realization of one’s own insignificance in the larger scheme of things (Piff
et al., 2015). In ART, it has however not been specified that the exact moment of reflection, the kind of reflection, or
the pathway through which reflection is reached are diagnostic for the reflective episode of a restorative experience.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
21
diminishment vis-à-vis the world (Piff, Dietze, Feinberg, Stancato, & Keltner, 2015), and self-
transcendence (Stellar et al., 2017), such hard fascinating environments might very well promote
the “self-distanced perspective taking”, which certain ART researchers assume to be crucial for
reflection on life issues (Kaplan & Berman, 2010). The experience of such hard fascinating
nature – and the reflective mindset it may promote – is far from uncommon, which makes us
wonder whether the theoretical distinction between hard and soft fascination is adequate and
necessary to explain full restoration.
Why is soft fascination required for ART?
Soft fascination is triggered by pleasantly distracting visual information that puts
individuals in an effortless mode of attention (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989; Kaplan, 1995; Kaplan &
Berman, 2010). However, given the fact that within ART attention restoration is regarded as an
autonomous and self-replenishing process, it is unclear why soft fascination should be a
necessary theoretical component of the framework, as prominent ART researchers suggest (cfr.,
“Fascination is a necessary, but not sufficient basis for recovering directed attention”, Kaplan,
1995, 172). Does the recovery of directed attention not merely require a process/stimulus that
does not further burden directed attention capacity? And if so, could numerous other non-
fascinating stimuli/processes not offer such relief as well (e.g., visually minimalist
environments), or does soft fascination provide an exclusive and superior pathway to attention
restoration? Perhaps the theoretical necessity of soft fascination derives partly from the fact that
it is crucial for reaching full restoration (cfr., Herzog et al., 1997), where the aesthetic pleasure
This means that there is no a priori reason to discount reflection resulting from exposure to hard fascinating awe-
evoking natural scenes as a “proper” instance of nature-induced reflection.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
22
derived from soft fascinating stimuli can offset the pain that can accompany reflection about life
issues. But then again, does this not show that especially the pleasurable aspect of soft
fascination facilitates full restoration, rather than fascination itself?
Why are fascinating stimuli relatively effortless rather than effortful?
Although ART has focused on the effortless attention component of fascination as the main
driver of attention restoration, it seems that effortless attention is – at least partly – recruited by
virtue of the fact that fascinating stimuli are often novel, complex or unpredictable (Silvia,
2008). Especially the idea of complexity as determinant of fascination clearly speaks from the
often used Perceived Restorativeness Scale (Hartig et al., 1997), where highly fascinating scenes
are assumed to be scenes where there is “a lot going on” (consider the items “My attention is
drawn to many interesting things” or “There is much to explore and discover here”). The upshot
is that while the process of attracting attention (i.e., fascination) might indeed be automatic and
relatively low on cognitive resources, processing the actual stimulus that attracts attention (i.e.,
natural setting) seems – given its complexity – also to require considerable cognitive resources
(Eng, Chen, & Jiang, 2005). Implicit to ART is the idea that the effortlessness of the process of
being attracted by fascinating stimuli, trumps the effortfulness associated with the attracting
stimulus, leading to an overall better performance on cognitive tasks after exposure to nature.
But why should that be the case? After all, in ART the distractive component of restorative
environments is considered to be moderate (cfr., “soft” fascination), and does this not suggest
that attending to such environments is not completely effortless?
Discussion
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
23
While an extensive body of empirical literature has sought to confirm the notion that
exposure to nature settings can have beneficial psychological effects, with our critical review we
hope to have shown that one of the most widely adopted theories on these benefits – i.e., ART
(Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989; Kaplan, 1995; Kaplan & Berman, 2010) – has important empirical and
conceptual limitations. While numerous researchers in the field share our belief in the
importance of criticism and of theoretical expansion of ART (e.g., Ohly et al., 2016; Hartig &
Jahncke, 2017), paradoxically, we also observe that in major contemporary theoretical reviews
(Hartig et al., 2014; Collado et al., 2017) and in handbooks on environmental psychology
(Clayton, 2012; Steg, Van den Berg, & De Groot, 2012), ART is often still upheld as one of the
main canons for (attention) restoration.
To reiterate, we have three general concerns with ART: (a) some of ART’s central
theoretical notions are vague, remain conceptually underdeveloped (e.g., soft fascination), and
still await a systematic and adequate (experimental) operationalization (e.g., soft fascination), (b)
ART’s central theoretical assumptions still need to be corroborated, especially the proposed
mechanism for attention restoration (i.e., bottom-up attention), and (c) experimental studies often
do not accurately or adequately test what ART predicts. Based on this, we doubt whether – in its
current form – ART can provide an accurate theoretical description of how nature might restore
and/or improve cognition and attention in individuals.
Note that, although our discussion especially focused on the notion of fascination, we are
aware that additional components have been claimed to be important for the process of attention
restoration, such as “being away”, “extent”, and “compatibility” (Kaplan & Kaplan, 1989;
Kaplan, 1995). The rationale for focusing on fascination, however, is that this notion is
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
24
considered to be the central driver of attention restoration, whereas the other components provide
(moderating) conditions under which attention restoration optimally takes place.
Despite the speculative character of the ART, and the fact that there is a current lack of
insight into how exactly nature restoration works, nature is nonetheless integrated in different
spheres of human life (e.g., ranging from clinical to school settings) where it seemingly succeeds
in bettering the lives of people and bringing out the best of them (Kaplan & Kaplan, 2003).
Might we therefore not just be satisfied with the idea that nature interventions work, laying aside
critical questions about the possible “ingredients” or mechanism(s) that underlie nature’s
efficacy? We think that theory development and critique matter, because they can help to
develop and optimize applications (cfr., “biophilic” architecture; Joye, 2007), and to identify
relevant target groups in a cost-effective way.
How to progress from here? Below we list a number of straightforward methodological
steps that could address some of the issues we have discussed in our review.
• In addition to deliberately fatiguing individuals, efforts should be made to include a
control group of participants that has not undergone a fatigue manipulation, to verify
whether nature actually recovers from mental fatigue. If a deliberate fatigue induction
would prove difficult, natural variations in fatigue between individuals could also be
exploited. One could, for example, take a baseline measure of fatigue, and test whether
restorative nature effects will be most pronounced for participants that display higher
(versus lower) levels of baseline fatigue.
• Standardize the method(s) for inducing attentional fatigue in participants prior to
environmental exposure, and for measuring directed attention capacity after
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
25
environmental exposure. Use the same pre- and post-measures, to enable within-subjects
comparison.
• Test what the particular physical input conditions of soft fascination are, and, based on
this, develop an instrument to measure soft-fascination that is able to differentiate it from
hard fascinating stimuli.
• Test whether the bottom-up attentional aspects of natural fascinations mediate the effect
of natural versus urban environments on attentional functioning.
• Test whether people in a soft fascinating environment think and resolve more life issues
than in hard fascinating settings.
• Because urban and natural environments differ on so many (confounding) dimensions
(i.e., visual, symbolic, goal aspects) other than the factors proposed for restoration, it
might be valuable to create a controlled and validated stimulus-set of urban and natural
simulations.
• Create a set of non-urban and non-natural control images to identify where environmental
effects are situated, enabling one to pinpoint whether urban scenes worsen, or nature
ameliorates directed attention capacity (or both simultaneously). These control images
should be neutral on dimensions that are thought to affect attention restoration, i.e., in
terms of attentional aspects and valence (cfr., Lang, Bradley, & Cuthbert, 1995).
• While it might be difficult to test whether fascination with nature is indeed an evolved
adaptive response, some ancillary assumptions of this evolutionary hypothesis might still
be put to the test. One could for example look at which natural settings are perceived as
affording safety and resources (or cues thereof), and subsequently examine whether those
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
26
settings are also more restorative than natural and urban areas seemingly devoid of these
(perceived) affordances.
While we are aware that there might be individual cases of research where the foregoing
steps have already been taken, we hope that they will be applied more systematically in
restoration research. We mainly see these suggestions as a goal for the broad literature, and
realize that individual restoration studies might well disregard some of them, depending on
particular research objectives and questions (e.g., when comparing the restorativeness of
different nature types, a “neutral” control condition may not be required).
In addition to systematically implementing the aforementioned steps, it might also prove
useful to explore alternative, more parsimonious explanations for beneficial nature effects than
ART. One promising avenue for future research might be to examine whether the motivational
component of fascination could play a role in restorative nature effects. Specifically, research
into the positive emotion of interest reveals that it is associated with approach motivation, thus
spurring exploration, focused attention, and task persistence (Silvia, 2008). Inasmuch as
fascination is a form of interest (Kaplan, 1992), superior performance on cognitive tasks after
exposure to nature (versus urban) settings might well be the result of increased task
motivation/persistence due to nature’s fascinating features. Note that such an account would be
firmly grounded in current emotion research, and avoids having to posit the existence of a
depletable cognitive resource (whose existence is currently hotly debated, e.g., Friese,
Loschelder, Gieseler, Frankenbach, & Inzlicht, 2018). At the same time, however, it builds
further on a central notion of ART, namely fascination. Of course, this illustrative proposal only
zooms in on one very particular aspect and type of restoration (i.e., “cognitive” restoration), and
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
27
we look forward to research that further maps and tests additional pathways to restoration,
possibly involving different adaptive resources (Hartig & Jahncke, 2017).
Conclusion
ART has been invaluable in drawing attention to the importance of natural environments
in restoring and ameliorating human wellbeing and cognitive functioning, which has paved the
way for a rich and societally-relevant empirical research literature. But should we still consider
ART itself as viable descriptive and theoretical framework for how nature can yield these
cognitive and emotional benefits? We hope that our critical review will have sparked some
scepticism in restoration researchers, and that it will stimulate renewed interest in theoretical
enrichment and development in the field of restoration research.
Acknowledgments: Thanks to Maja Fischer, Jan Willem Bolderdijk and Bob Fennis for useful
comments on this paper.
References
Awh, E., Belopolsky, A. V., & Theeuwes, J. (2012). Top-down versus bottom-up attentional
control: A failed theoretical dichotomy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16, 437-443.
Balling, J. D., & Falk, J. H. (1982). Development of visual preference for natural
environments. Environment and Behavior, 14, 5-28.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
28
Barton, J., & Pretty, J. (2010). What is the best dose of nature and green exercise for improving
mental health? A multi-study analysis. Environmental Science & Technology, 44, 3947-
3955.
Basu, A., Duvall, J., & Kaplan, R. (2018). Attention Restoration Theory: Exploring the Role of
Soft Fascination and Mental Bandwidth. Environment and Behavior, 0013916518774400.
Berman, M. G., Jonides, J., & Kaplan, S. (2008). The cognitive benefits of interacting with
nature. Psychological Science, 19, 1207–1212.
Berman, M. G., Kross, E., Krpan, K. M., Askren, M. K., Burson, A., Deldin, P.J., … Jonides, J.
(2012). Interacting with nature improves cognition and affect for individuals with
depression. Journal of Affective Disorders, 140, 300-305.
Berto, R. (2005). Exposure to restorative environments helps restore attentional
capacity. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 25, 249-259.
Beute, F., & de Kort, Y. A. W. (2014). Natural resistance: Exposure to nature and self-
regulation, mood, and physiology after ego-depletion. Journal of Environmental
Psychology, 40, 167-178.
Bodin, M., & Hartig, T. (2003). Does the outdoor environment matter for psychological
restoration gained through running? Psychology of Sport and Exercise, 4, 141-153.
Brengman, M., Willems, K., & Joye, Y. (2012). The impact of in-store greenery on
customers. Psychology & Marketing, 29, 807-821.
Chang, C. Y., Hammitt, W. E., Chen, P. K., Machnik, L., & Su, W. C. (2008).
Psychophysiological responses and restorative values of natural environments in
Taiwan. Landscape and Urban Planning, 85, 79-84.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
29
Clayton, S. D. (Ed.). (2012). The Oxford handbook of environmental and conservation
psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Collado, S., Staats, H., Corraliza, J. A., & Hartig, T. (2017). Restorative environments and
health. In G. Fleury-Bahi E. Pol, & O. Navarro (Eds.), Handbook of environmental
psychology and quality of life research (pp. 127-148). Cham: Springer International
Publishing.
Corbetta, M., & Shulman, G. L. (2002). Control of goal-directed and stimulus-driven attention in
the brain. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3, 201-215.
Coss, R. G. (2003). The role of evolved perceptual biases in art and design. In E. Voland & K.
Grammer (Eds.), Evolutionary aesthetics (pp. 69-130). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Diette, G. B., Lechtzin, N., Haponik, E., Devrotes, A., & Rubin, H. R. (2003). Distraction
Therapy With Nature Sights and Sounds Reduces Pain During Flexible Bronchoscopya: A
Complementary Approach to Routine Analgesia. Chest, 123, 941-948.
Eng, H. Y., Chen, D., & Jiang, Y. (2005). Visual working memory for simple and complex
visual stimuli. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 12, 1127-1133.
Falk, J. H., & Balling, J. D. (2010). Evolutionary influence on human landscape
preference. Environment and Behavior, 42, 479-493.
Friese, M., Loschelder, D. D., Gieseler, K., Frankenbach, J., & Inzlicht, M. (2018). Is ego
depletion real? An analysis of arguments. Personality and Social Psychology Review. In
press.
Hartig, T., Böök, A., Garvill, J., Olsson, T., & Gärling, T. (1996). Environmental influences on
psychological restoration. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 37, 378-393.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
30
Hartig, T., Evans, G. W., Jamner, L. D., Davis, D. S., & Gärling, T. (2003). Tracking restoration
in natural and urban field settings. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 23, 109-123.
Hartig, T., & Jahncke, H. (2017). Letter to the editor: Attention restoration in natural
environments: Mixed mythical metaphors for meta-analysis. Journal of Toxicology and
Environmental Health, Part B, 20, 305-315.
Hartig, T., & Kahn, P. H. (2016). Living in cities, naturally. Science, 352, 938-940.
Hartig, T., Korpela, K., Evans, G. W., & Gärling, T. (1997). A measure of restorative quality in
environments. Scandinavian Housing and Planning Research, 14, 175-194.
Hartig, T., Mang, M., & Evans, G. W. (1991). Restorative effects of natural environment
experiences. Environment and Behavior, 23, 3-26.
Hartig, T., & Marcus, C. C. (2006). Essay: Healing gardens—places for nature in health
care. The Lancet, 368, S36-S37.
Hartig, T., Mitchell, R., de Vries, S., & Frumkin, H. (2014). Nature and health. Annual Review of
Public Health, 35, 207–228.
Hawkins, J. L., Mercer, J., Thirlaway, K. J., & Clayton, D. A. (2013). “Doing” gardening and
“being” at the allotment site: exploring the benefits of allotment gardening for stress
reduction and healthy aging. Ecopsychology, 5, 110-125.
Heerwagen, J.H. & Orians, G.H. (1993), Humans, Habitats, and Aesthetics. In S. R. Kellert & E.
O. Wilson (Eds.), The Biophilia Hypothesis (pp. 138-172). Washington: Island Press.
Herzog, T. R., Black, A. M., Fountaine, K. A., & Knotts, D. J. (1997). Reflection and attentional
recovery as distinctive benefits of restorative environments. Journal of Environmental
Psychology, 17, 165-170.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
31
Jaffe, E. (2010). This side of paradise. APS Observer, 23(5). Retrieved from:
https://www.psychologicalscience.org/observer/this-side-of-paradise
Jefferies, K., & Lepp, A. (2012). An investigation of extraordinary experiences. Journal of Park
and Recreation Administration, 30, 37 – 51.
Joye, Y. (2007). Architectural lessons from environmental psychology: The case of biophilic
architecture. Review of General Psychology, 11, 305 – 328.
Joye, Y., & Van den Berg, A. E. (2011). Is love for green in our genes? A critical analysis of
evolutionary assumptions in restorative environments research. Urban Forestry & Urban
Greening, 10, 261-268.
Joye, Y., & Van den Berg, A. E. (2012). Restorative environments. In E. M. Steg, A. E. Van den
Berg, & J. De Groot (Eds.), Environmental Psychology: An Introduction (pp. 57-66).
London: Wiley-Blackwell.
Joye, Y., Pals, R., Steg, L., & Evans, B. L. (2013). New methods for assessing the fascinating
nature of nature experiences. PloS one, 8(7), e65332.
Joye, Y., Willems, K., Brengman, M., & Wolf, K. (2010). The effects of urban retail greenery on
consumer experience: Reviewing the evidence from a restorative perspective. Urban
Forestry & Urban Greening, 9, 57-64.
Kaplan, R. & Kaplan, S. (1989), The Experience of Nature: A Psychological Perspective.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kaplan, S. (1977). Tranquility and challenge in the natural environment. In Northeastern Forest
Experiment Station (Ed.), Children, nature, and the urban environment (USDA Forest
Service General Technical Report NE-30) (pp.181-185). Upper Darby, PA: Author.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
32
Kaplan, S. (1987). Aesthetics, affect, and cognition: Environmental preference from an
evolutionary perspective. Environment and Behavior, 19, 3-32.
Kaplan, S. (1992). The restorative environment: Nature and human experience. In D. Relf (Ed.),
The role of horticulture in human well-being and social development (pp. 134-142).
Portland, OR: Timber Press.
Kaplan, S. (1995). The restorative benefits of nature: Toward an integrative framework. Journal
of Environmental Psychology, 15, 169–182.
Kaplan, S., & Berman, M. G. (2010). Directed attention as a common resource for executive
functioning and self-regulation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5, 43-57.
Kaplan, S., & Kaplan, R. (2003). Health, supportive environments, and the reasonable person
model. American Journal of Public Health, 93, 1484-1489.
Kellert, S. R., & Wilson, E. O. (Eds.). (1995). The Biophilia Hypothesis. Washington: Island
Press.
Keltner, D., & Haidt, J. (2003). Approaching awe, a moral, spiritual, and aesthetic
emotion. Cognition & Emotion, 17, 297-314.
Korpela, K., De Bloom, J., & Kinnunen, U. (2015). From restorative environments to restoration
in work. Intelligent Buildings International, 7, 215-223.
Lang, P. J., Bradley, M., & Cuthbert, B. (1995). International Affective Picture System:
Technical manual and affective ratings. Gainesville FL: Center for Research in Psycho-
physiology, University of Florida.
Laumann, K., Gärling, T., & Stormark, K. M. (2001). Rating scale measures of restorative
components of environments. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 21, 31-44.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
33
Laumann, K., Gärling, T., & Stormark, K. M. (2003). Selective attention and heart rate responses
to natural and urban environments. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 23, 125–134.
Lohr, V. I., & Pearson-Mims, C. H. (2006). Responses to scenes with spreading, rounded, and
conical tree forms. Environment and Behavior, 38, 667-688.
McMahan, E. A., & Estes, D. (2015). The effect of contact with natural environments on positive
and negative affect: A meta-analysis. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 10, 507-519.
Morton, T. A., van der Bles, A. M., & Haslam, S. A. (2017). Seeing our self reflected in the
world around us: The role of identity in making (natural) environments restorative. Journal
of Environmental Psychology, 49, 65-77.
Ohly, H., White, M. P., Wheeler, B. W., Bethel, A., Ukoumunne, O. C., Nikolaou, V., &
Garside, R. (2016). Attention restoration theory: A systematic review of the attention
restoration potential of exposure to natural environments. Journal of Toxicology and
Environmental Health, Part B, 19, 305-343
Orians, G.H. (1980), Habitat selection: general theory and applications to human behaviour. In J.
S. Lockard (Ed.), The evolution of human social behaviour (pp. 49-66). New York:
Elsevier.
Orians, G.H. & Heerwagen, J.H. (1992), Evolved Responses to Landscapes. In J. H. Barkow, L.
Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The Adapted Mind. Evolutionary Psychology and the
Generation of Culture (pp. 555-574). New York: Oxford University Press.
Ottosson, J., & Grahn, P. (2005). A comparison of leisure time spent in a garden with leisure
time spent indoors: on measures of restoration in residents in geriatric care. Landscape
Research, 30, 23-55.
Pals, R., Steg, L., Dontje, J., Siero, F. W., & van Der Zee, K. I. (2014). Physical features,
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
34
coherence and positive outcomes of person–environment interactions: A virtual reality
study. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 40, 108-116.
Parsons, R., Tassinary, L. G., Ulrich, R. S., Hebl, M. R., & Grossman-Alexander, M. (1998). The
view from the road: Implications for stress recovery and immunization. Journal of
Environmental Psychology, 18, 113-140.
Pearce, J., Strickland-Munro, J., & Moore, S. A. (2017). What fosters awe-inspiring experiences
in nature-based tourism destinations? Journal of Sustainable Tourism, 25, 362-378.
Piff, P. K., Dietze, P., Feinberg, M., Stancato, D. M., & Keltner, D. (2015). Awe, the small self,
and prosocial behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 108, 883 – 899.
Pratt, J., Radulescu, P. V., Guo, R. M., & Abrams, R. A. (2010). It’s alive! Animate motion
captures visual attention. Psychological Science, 21, 1724-1730.
Rosenbaum, M. S., Otalora, M. L., & Ramírez, G. C. (2016). The restorative potential of
shopping malls. Journal of Retailing and Consumer Services, 31, 157-165.
Ryan, R. M., Weinstein, N., Bernstein, J., Brown, K. W., Mistretta, L., & Gagne, M. (2010).
Vitalizing effects of being outdoors and in nature. Journal of Environmental
Psychology, 30, 159-168.
Scopelliti, M., & Giuliani, M. V. (2004). Choosing restorative environments across the lifespan:
A matter of place experience. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 24, 423-437.
Shanahan, D. F., Bush, R., Gaston, K. J., Lin, B. B., Dean, J., Barber, E., & Fuller, R. A. (2016).
Health benefits from nature experiences depend on dose. Scientific Reports, 6, 28551.
Shin, W. S., Shin, C. S., Yeoun, P. S., & Kim, J. J. (2011). The influence of interaction with
forest on cognitive function. Scandinavian Journal of Forest Research, 26, 595-598.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
35
Silvia, P. J. (2008). Interest—The curious emotion. Current Directions in Psychological
Science, 17, 57-60.
Sommer, R., & Summit, J. (1995). An exploratory study of preferred tree form. Environment and
Behavior, 27, 540-557.
Staats, H. (2012). Restorative environments. In S. Clayton (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of
environmental and conservation psychology (pp. 445-458). New York: Oxford University
Press.
Steg, L., van den Berg, A. E., & De Groot, J. I. (Eds.). (2012). Environmental psychology: An
introduction. London: Wiley-Blackwell.
Steidle, A., Gonzalez-Morales, M. G., Hoppe, A., Michel, A., & O’shea, D. (2017). Energizing
respites from work: a randomized controlled study on respite interventions. European
Journal of Work and Organizational Psychology, 26, 650-662.
Stellar, J. E., Gordon, A. M., Piff, P. K., Cordaro, D., Anderson, C. L., Bai, Y., …. Keltner, D.
(2017). Self-transcendent emotions and their social functions: Compassion, gratitude, and
awe bind us to others through prosociality. Emotion Review, 9, 200-207.
Summit, J., & Sommer, R. (1999). Further studies of preferred tree shapes. Environment and
Behavior, 31, 550-576.
Tanja-Dijkstra, K., Pahl, S., White, M. P., Auvray, M., Stone, R. J., Andrade, J., … Moles, D.R.
(2017). The Soothing Sea: A Virtual Coastal Walk Can Reduce Experienced and
Recollected Pain. Environment and Behavior, in press.
Taylor, A., & Kuo, F. E. (2009). Children with attention deficits concentrate better after walk in
the park. Journal of Attention Disorders, 12, 402-409.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
36
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (1992), The Psychological Foundations of Culture. In J. H. Barkow, L.
Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind. Evolutionary psychology and the
generation of culture (pp. 19-136). New York: Oxford University Press.
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (1997). Evolutionary Psychology: a Primer. Retrieved from:
http://www.cep.ucsb.edu/primer.html
Ulrich, R.S. (1983), Aesthetic and affective response to natural environment. In I. Altman & J. F.
Wohlwill (Eds.), Human Behavior and Environment, Volume 6 (pp. 85 – 125). New York:
Plenum Press.
Ulrich, R. (1984). View through a window may influence recovery. Science, 224, 224-225.
Ulrich, R.S. (1993), Biophilia, Biophobia, and Natural Landscapes, In S. R. Kellert & E. O.
Wilson, E.O. (Eds.), The Biophilia Hypothesis (pp. 73 – 137). Washington: Island Press.
Ulrich, R. S., Simons, R. F., Losito, B. D., Fiorito, E., Miles, M. A., & Zelson, M. (1991). Stress
recovery during exposure to natural and urban environments. Journal of Environmental
Psychology, 11, 201-230.
Ulset, V., Vitaro, F., Brendgen, M., Bekkhus, M., & Borge, A. I. (2017). Time spent outdoors
during preschool: Links with children's cognitive and behavioral development. Journal of
Environmental Psychology, 52, 69-80.
Valtchanov, D., & Ellard, C. G. (2015). Cognitive and affective responses to natural scenes:
effects of low level visual properties on preference, cognitive load and eye-
movements. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 43, 184-195.
Van den Berg, A. E., & Custers, M. H. (2011). Gardening promotes neuroendocrine and
affective restoration from stress. Journal of Health Psychology, 16, 3-11.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
37
Van den Berg, A. E., Hartig, T., & Staats, H. (2007). Preference for nature in urbanized societies:
Stress, restoration, and the pursuit of sustainability. Journal of Social Issues, 63, 79-96.
Van den Berg, A. E., Joye, Y., & Koole, S. L. (2016). Why viewing nature is more fascinating
and restorative than viewing buildings: A closer look at perceived complexity. Urban
Forestry & Urban Greening, 20, 397-401.
Van den Berg, A. E., Wesselius, J. E., Maas, J., & Tanja-Dijkstra, K. (2017). Green walls for a
restorative classroom environment: a controlled evaluation study. Environment and
Behavior, 49, 791-813.
Velarde, M. D., Fry, G., & Tveit, M. (2007). Health effects of viewing landscapes–Landscape
types in environmental psychology. Urban Forestry & Urban Greening, 6, 199-212.
White, M. P., Pahl, S., Ashbullby, K., Herbert, S., & Depledge, M. H. (2013). Feelings of
restoration from recent nature visits. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 35, 40-51.
Wilson, E. O. (1984). Biophilia. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.
Yorzinski, J. L., Penkunas, M. J., Platt, M. L., & Coss, R. G. (2014). Dangerous animals capture
and maintain attention in humans. Evolutionary Psychology, 12, 534 – 548.
Running head: A CRITICAL LOOK AT ART
38