ArticlePDF Available

Cutting red tape to manage public health threats: An ethical dilemma of expediting antibiotic drug innovation

Authors:

Abstract

Antibiotic resistance, arising when bacteria develop defences against antibiotics, creates a public health threat of massive proportions. This raises challenging questions for standard notions in bioethics when suitable policy is to be characterised and justified. We examine the particular proposal of expediting innovation of new antibiotics by cutting various forms of regulatory “red tape” in the standard system for the clinical introduction of new drugs. We find strong principled reasons in favour of such lowering of the ethical standards of research and clinical introduction of new antibiotic formulas. However, this support is undermined by pragmatic challenges due to expected responses from stakeholders, creating uncertainty about what policy could actually be effectively implemented. We describe an underlying dilemma on how to rationally justify compromises between ideal ethical justification and pragmatic risks that needs to be further addressed in this light. We suggest a solution to this dilemma related to proposals of expediting antibiotic drug innovation.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
1
Cutting red tape to manage public health threats: An ethical dilemma of expediting antibiotic
drug innovation
Christian Munthe
Department of philosophy, linguistics and theory of science, and the Centre for antibiotic resistance
research, CARe, University of Gothenburg.
Christian.munthe@gu.se
Niels Nijsingh
Department of philosophy, linguistics and theory of science, and the Centre for antibiotic resistance
research, CARe, University of Gothenburg.
Abstract
Antibiotic resistance, arising when bacteria develop defences against antibiotics, creates a public
health threat of massive proportions. This raises challenging questions for standard notions in
bioethics when suitable policy is to be characterised and justified. We examine the particular
proposal of expediting innovation of new antibiotics by cutting various forms of regulatory “red
tape” in the standard system for the clinical introduction of new drugs. We find strong principled
reasons in favour of such lowering of the ethical standards of research and clinical introduction of
new antibiotic formulas. However, this support is undermined by pragmatic challenges due to
expected responses from stakeholders, creating uncertainty about what policy could actually be
effectively implemented. We describe an underlying dilemma on how to rationally justify
compromises between ideal ethical justification and pragmatic risks that needs to be further
addressed in this light. We suggest a solution to this dilemma related to proposals of expediting
antibiotic drug innovation.
Keywords
Antimicrobial resistance, health policy, legitimacy, pharmacological policy, research ethics, risk
and uncertainty
Acknowledgements
This research was supported by the UGOT Challenges Initiative of the University of Gothenburg,
and by Riksbankens Jubileumsfond, RJ (application F17-1078:1), for the project Ethics and Value
Challenges in Antibiotic Resistance Management, Policy and Research.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
2
Introduction
Antibiotic resistance
1
, arising when bacteria develop defences against antibiotic drugs, creates a
public health threat of massive proportions that is particularly difficult to manage well. The main
reason for this is that the threat results from a complex interaction of different causes that jointly
lead to a gradual accumulation of the problem, which are difficult to counter effectively in a
coordinated way. The threat is massive for well-known reasons. If pathogens continue to develop
defences against drugs, this could potentially render the medication used against common infections
worthless. Not only will this raise the risk of widespread epidemics, it will also endanger current
medical practice in several ways. Hospital infections will make inpatient care very dangerous, while
the prophylactic use of antibiotics in, for example, surgery, cancer and neonatal care will become
futile
2
.
Given such dire prospects, the antibiotic resistance challenge raises specific ethical issues about
how proportional reactions should be characterised and justified, and what that implies for standard
notions in bioethics
3
. One such issue regards to what extent the extraordinary character of the
antibiotic resistance threat justifies extraordinary measures, otherwise ruled out on ethical grounds:
Should we suspend, abandon or relax ‘normal’ requirements and standards in medicine, research
and health policy? If so, why? And to what extent? In this paper, we focus on one particular idea to
1
Resistance to other kind of drugs than antibiotics may also pose challenges. Some have therefore advocated the more
inclusive term “antimicrobial resistance”, or the more unspecific but easily understood term drug resistance, see
Mendelson, M., Balasegaram, M., Jinks, T., et al. (2017). Antibiotic resistance has a language problem. Nature.
545(7652), 23-25. As not all drug resistance gives rise to the public health challenges we focus on in the present
context, we have nevertheless chosen to restrict ourselves to antibiotic resistance.
2
World Health Organization, WHO (2014). The Evolving Threat of Antimicrobial Resistance: Options for Action.
Geneva, Switzerland: WHO; World Health Organization, WHO (2015). Global action plan on antimicrobial resistance.
Geneva, Switzerland: WHO.
3
Littmann, J. & Viens A.M. (2015). The Ethical Significance of Antimicrobial Resistance. Public Health Ethics. 8(3),
209224.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
3
this effect, namely the notion of expediting innovation
4
of new antibiotics by cutting various forms
of regulatory “red tape” that are part of the standard system for the development, testing and clinical
introduction of new drugs.
One recognised aspect of the drug resistance challenge is the lack of new antibiotic formulas. The
consequences of biological resistance development could be handled much better if there was a
regular supply of new drugs to replace the ones made inefficient through resistance
5
. However,
neither the pharmaceutical industry, nor biomedical research currently prioritize such work, which
has led to calls for policy incentives to change this course and stimulate innovation with a strong
potential to limit the threat of antibiotic resistance
6
. One group of such incentives is the idea of
“expediting” the innovation process by relaxing regulatory requirements and procedures in various
stages of the innovation process
7
. Each such stage will present ethical issues, including what level
of safety is required to move from preclinical to clinical research, what research ethical
requirements are applied in such clinical research, and what standards of proof of effectiveness and
4
In line with the FDA standard understanding, we use the term (drug) “innovation” to signify all science-based
development of new products (in this case antibiotics). This development occurs at several stages, which we explain
later in the article. See: https://www.fda.gov/drugs/developmentapprovalprocess/druginnovation/ucm592464.htm .
There exists extensive general research on the economics and policy of biomedical innovation, posing questions that we
do not currently engage with. See, e.g., Karlsson, C. (ed.) (2008). Handbook on research on innovation and clusters:
Cases and policies. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing.
5
As is generally recognized (see for example WHO (2015), op. cit. note 3, innovation would on its own be only
partially helpful. In addition, reform is needed to promote antibiotic stewardship, as well as efficient systems for
optimal access to antibiotics. However, without innovation, such actions will have only a temporary and limited effect
on the challenges resulting from antibiotic resistance.
6
WHO (2015), op. cit. note 3; Theuretzbacher, U (2017). Antibiotic innovation for future public health needs. Clinical
Microbiology and Infection. 23(10), 713-717.
7
There are also other ideas about how to stimulate industry action in this respect, such as various forms of direct
monetary incentives. See, for instance, Nijsingh, N., Larsson, D.G. J., Persson de Fine-Licht, K., Munthe, C. (2019).
Justifying Antibiotic Resistance Interventions: Uncertainty, Precaution and Ethics. In Jamrozik, E. & Selgelid, M.
(Eds.). Ethics and Antimicrobial Resistance: Collective Responsibility for Global Public Health. Cham: Springer, in
press; Seabury, S., Sood, N. (2017). Toward A New Model For Promoting The Development Of Antimicrobial Drugs.
Health Affairs Blog: http://healthaffairs.org/blog/2017/05/18/toward-a-new-model-for-promoting-the-development-of-
antimicrobial-drugs/(accessed July 28, 2017); Morel, C.M., Mossialos, E. (2010). Stoking the antibiotic pipeline. BMJ:
British Medical Journal 340, c2115. Doi: 10.1136/bmj.c2115. In the present context, we are, however, limiting
ourselves to the expediting strategy.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
4
safety are required for clinical introduction.
8
In this paper, we present a special group of pragmatic
challenges and an underlying ethical dilemma of relevance to the analysis of these ethical issues.
We will, first, present in more detail different forms of expediting antibiotic innovation, and
formulate the ethical case in favour of such reform. Accepting that this case is strong in principle,
we then review a particular type of complicating factor, namely what in other contexts have been
termed pragmatic risks
9
: how stakeholders and key actors may respond negatively or otherwise
suboptimal to the reforms. We argue that such risks create a problematic situation for the
justification of the idea of expediting antibiotic innovation by cutting red tape, as adjustments to
accommodate for these risks tend to undermine the initial justificatory reasons. We then describe a
more general ethical dilemma of how to balance ethical reasons and pragmatic risks when
evaluating policy proposals, and suggest an answer to how this dilemma should be resolved with
regard to proposals of expediting antibiotic innovation.
Forms of expediting innovation and the case for cutting red tape
The innovation of a new drug has a long path, from basic research to actual clinical introduction.
Along this path, a number of regulatory frameworks are in effect to structure how a candidate is
reviewed and assessed in different stages of the journey. Examples of importance include rules on
patenting, criteria for assessing proof of effect and risks in research, ethical review of drug trials and
requirements applied in such settings, the licensing of a new drug based on effect and safety
standards based on trial outcomes, and decisions to include a new licensed drug in clinical
guidelines and/or subsidy systems. Part of these frameworks may differ in detail and form between
8
Fast track options, such as priority review, are not obviously riskier, but do involve taking resources away from other
type of drugs that are being developed, and may raise issues of systemic bias against more promising candidates for
new pharmaceutical treatments related to serious conditions.
9
Nijsingh et al. (2019) op. cit. note 8; Munthe C., Nijsingh N., Persson de Fine Licht K., Larsson D.G.J. Health-related
research and social value: Drug resistance intervention research and pragmatic risks, in review.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
5
states (sometimes significantly so), while others (such as those of licensing, or common scientific
standards) are increasingly harmonized across the world. But each of them offers options of what
requirements to apply and how to apply them. Authorities (or, when the regulation is informal, the
parties controlling the issue, such as a branch of the biomedical research community deciding proof
and effect-risk standards in research) may thus opt to relax some of the standards and procedures for
candidates for new antibiotic candidates, in order to ease and speed up the innovation process, as
has been done in so-called orphan areas of pharmaceutical innovation, for instance in the USA
10
.
In the following, we will include potential expediting reforms targeting all stages of the innovation
process, from the initiation of clinically relevant basic research to pre-clinical and clinical research
evaluating candidates, to decisions to license and include a new drug in clinical recommendations.
All of these stages are of importance for the actual emergence of new antibiotics available for
clinicians, and are therefore necessary to address in order to accomplish an enhanced innovation
that could have a real impact on the antibiotic resistance challenge. We are excluding any regulatory
frameworks or considerations beyond this stage, for example regarding systems of procurement by
health systems, or the clinical ethics used by medical practitioners when deciding what (among
licensed and recommended) drugs to actually use, and how to use them, in single cases.
While some have argued that, in situations of extreme hazard and threatening chaos, ethical
considerations have no place in justifying actions
11
, we consider all potentially justifying reasons
brought to bear on such actions ethical. At the same time, it is widely recognized that extreme
circumstances may present reasons to overstep standards accepted in normal situations. In the case
10
U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. (2014). Guidance for Industry. Expedited Programs for Serious
Conditions Drugs and Biologics. Washington: USDHHS. Retrieved July 7, 2017 from
https://www.fda.gov/downloads/drugs/guidances/ucm358301.pdf
11
Orend, B. (2001). Just and Lawful Conduct in War: Reflections on Michael Walzer. Law and Philosophy, 20(1), 1-30.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
6
at hand, then, the idea is that the extreme stakes presented by the antibiotic resistance threat, and the
role of drug innovation to curb it, such innovation need not be scrutinized as strictly as otherwise
required: the normal “red tape” does not apply or, at least, should be partially cut
12
. In the case of
the antibiotic resistance challenge, we find five grounds to accept this sort of reasoning, besides
simply appealing to a benefit-harm style calculus and the massive stakes:
1. Innovation speed is crucial: the antibiotic resistance challenge links to specific need of
speedier development of new compounds to “win the race” against resistant pathogens. The
notion of expedited antibiotic drug innovation targets exactly that need. Other strategies to
respond to the challenge cannot compensate if speedier innovation cannot be effected. This
argument supports not only expedited innovation, but also other kinds of interventions to
speed up drug development, such as financial incentives.
2. Inapplicability of research ethical exceptionalism: Standard ideas of benefit-safety
relationships, proof standards, et cetera, for testing and introducing new drugs assume the
presence of a decently working health system that offers solidly grounded treatments that
can be applied while awaiting the next better thing. This is the motivation of what has been
called research ethical exceptionalism
13
and why, for instance, clinical equipoise is normally
thought to be required to justify experimentation with new therapies on patients
14
. However,
the nature of how antibiotic resistance threatens to undermine (and to already be damaging)
12
This line of reasoning is common in theories of ‘supreme emergency’, such as found primarily in war ethics (see
however Sandin, P. (2009). Supreme Emergencies Without the Bad Guys. Philosophia, 37(1), 153-167.) When in 2014-
2015 the Ebola epidemic struck, similar arguments were heard. See Geisbert, T.W. (2015). Emergency treatment for
exposure to Ebola virus: the need to fast-track promising vaccines. Jama. 313(12), 1221-1222; Rid, A. & Emanuel, E.J.
(2014). Ethical considerations of experimental interventions in the Ebola outbreak. The Lancet, 384(9957), 1896-1899.
13
Wilson, J. & Hunter, D. (2010). Research Exceptionalism. American Journal of Bioethics, 10(8):45-54.
14
London, A.J. (2017). Equipoise in Research: Integrating Ethics and Science in Human Research. JAMA, 317(5): 525-
526.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
7
large segments of healthcare means that this assumption cannot be upheld. An exception to
the “exceptionalist” stance of standard research ethical norms may thus be justified.
3. Sustainability threats require special ethical consideration: The above reason can be
generalised into a ‘sustainability argument’, applicable to ordinary biomedical research
ethics. It may be argued to hold for any institution meant to ensure some important good,
that if this the norms governing this institution serve to undermine its future ability to
deliver this good, it is permissible (if not imperative) to set aside the norms normally
governing it. It is obvious how this kind of reason may be applied to the antibiotic resistance
threat in light of how it undermines the effectiveness of healthcare. Moreover, together with
the drastically increased risks of epidemic outbreaks, this will in practice mean that the
prospect of future biomedical innovation is undermined (as medical research and
development is much more difficult in a chaotic societal situation, and resources are usually
reserved for managing acute problems)
15
.
4. The antibiotic resistance threat activates public health ethical norms: Standard biomedical
research ethics rests on an individualistic paradigm, where protection against harm and
violation of rights of research subjects and patients is a paramount consideration. However,
the reasons 2 and 3, together with the nature of the long-term consequences if the threat is
not adequately addressed, means that the values at stake need to be considered in more
collectivist terms, moving the issue from the ordinary sector of biomedical research ethics to
a public health ethical domain
16
. In that context, innovation regulation must build on the
15
Angus Dawson has elaborated on the basis of sustainability arguments related to drug resistance in a recent
conference presentation, available on video: https://play.gu.se/media/Sustainability+and+antibiotics/0_e6qn6zsu.
16
Coggon, J. (2010). Does Public Health Have a Personality (and If So, Does It Matter If You Don’t Like It)?
Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics. 19(2): 235248. Dawson, A. (ed.) (2011). Public Health Ethics: Key
Concepts and Issues in Policy and Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Munthe, C. (2008). The Goals of
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
8
need for coordinated political action across time, as well as the public good of having access
to effective antibiotics. In that context, harm and infringements to individuals becomes
easier to justify, as long as the public health ethical aim is effectively promoted.
5. Precautionary ethics justifies the imposition of higher risks than normal when ethically
important uncertainties need to be settled. This type of argument has evolved in the area of
the ethics of risk and uncertainty of technology and the environment
17
, but more recently
been applied to bioethical issues and the antibiotic resistance challenge
18
. It builds on the
recognition of acting on good reason and evidence as an ethically important consideration,
and therefore links immediately to the ethics of regulating research and development in
areas of great ethical significance, where there is a serious lack of knowledge and the
relevant technology is under development. The antibiotic resistance challenge and its need
for drug innovation fits perfectly into this type of reasoning.
We do not claim any of these arguments to be decisive on their own, and note that they may all
attract criticism. Nevertheless, we will in the following assume that they jointly offer significant and
principled support for expediting antibiotic drug innovation, even if the implied cutting of red tape
comes at a cost in terms of more uncertain benefits and elevated risk for research subjects and
patients. We do not deny that such reform will actualise many detailed questions regarding design
Public Health: An Integrated, Multi-dimensional Model. Public Health Ethics. 1(1), 39-52; Verweij, M., Dawson, A.
(2009). Public Health Research Ethics: A Research Agenda. Public Health Ethics. 2 (1), 1-6.
17
Munthe, C. (2011). The Price of Precaution and the Ethics of Risk. Dordrecht: Springer.; Steel, D. (2014). Philosophy
and the Precautionary Principle: Science, Evidence, and Environmental Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
18
Munthe, C. (2016). Precautionary principle. In ten Have, H. (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics (pp. 2257-2265).
Cham: Springer; Nijsingh et al. op. cit. note 8.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
9
and implementation
19
, and that these will need to be addressed in further ethical assessment.
However, we do not provide such details here. We also leave open exactly how far the principled
justification that we assume leads, thus leaving for others to pursue further typical bioethical
analysis, where different ethical principles and stances are brought to bear on the issue. Instead, we
will proceed from our general assumption and address a number of pragmatic challenges that
complicate the justification of expediting antibiotic drug innovation, even in light of a strong
principled reason in its favour.
Pragmatic challenge 1: Strategical adaption from industry
No matter how lines are drawn in the research ethical argument that we leave for others to work out,
relaxing the criteria for antibiotic drug innovation involves accepting greater risk and more
uncertain benefits. At the same time, interventions that aim to diminish complex public health
threats may backfire due to responses and adapted behaviour of stakeholders
20
. One central
stakeholder in the case of cutting red tape to stimulate antibiotic drug innovation is, of course, the
pharmaceutical industry. Although it is the point of any kind of expediting reform to have industry
adapt its business decisions, they may lead to a situation where, although there are more antibiotics
on the market, the public health gain might actually be negative, due to the increase of ineffective or
harmful drugs
21
. As we have seen in programs for expediting innovation for orphan drugs and
diseases, when industry is rewarded for increasing its innovative flow in one particular domain, it
becomes rational to make as much of the innovation to fit that domain, regardless of how well this
expanded innovation fits the rationale that originally justified the cutting of the red tape. For
instance, many orphan disease programs designed for rare diseases are now being increasingly filled
19
For instance, issues about damage or risk compensation, as well as global health justice, of the sort discussed by
Anomaly and Savulescu, Krockow and colleagues, as well as Millar, in their respective contributions to this special
issue.
20
Nijsingh,et al. op. cit. note 8.
21
Floyd, J.S. and Psaty, B.M. (2014). The Potential Risks of Expedited Approval of Drugs for Acute Bacterial
Infections. JAMA internal medicine. 174(9), 1436-1437.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
10
with candidates coming out of recent “personalized medicine” or “precision medicine” efforts for
common disease areas (such as cancer). These harvest the benefits of laxer requirements while
offering uncertain benefits in terms of the rationale of the original programs
22
. The process also
creates opportunity costs in terms of alternative treatments, or treatments in other areas, that are
never developed due to the rechannelling of both public and private resources stimulated by the
expedited innovation program. Procedures and extra regulation put into place to counter these kinds
of developments add extra costs and disincentivise companies from being baited, thus undermining
the principled argument for expedited antibiotic drug innovation reform.
None of this is, of course, a result of companies being intentionally malicious, it is a result of
companies being companies. From the point of view of business, if the state makes it attractive to
launch operations in area x, it makes sense for a company to transform more and more of business
operations to fit into area x. But this transformation may then corrupt the original reason for a state
to bait companies into area x. Furthermore, it is sound strategical business behaviour to adapt the
response in such a way that maximizes the attractiveness of the bait, relative to the cost of the
innovation for the company. Such logic can force an expedited reform to cut more red tape in order
to have industry respond as desired. In both of these ways, any reform to expedite antibiotic drug
innovation may thus be undermined by quite ordinary business rationality. The result is a pragmatic
risk that more red tape is being cut for less benefits and at higher costs than assumed in the
principled argument in favour of expediting antibiotic innovation.
Pragmatic challenge 2: Negative professional response
22
Rodriguez-Monguio, R., Spargo, T., Seoane-Vazquez, E. (2017). Ethical imperatives of timely access to orphan
drugs: is possible to reconcile economic incentives and patients’ health needs? Orphanet Journal of Rare Diseases. 12,
1. Doi: 10.1186/s13023-016-0551-7
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
11
Other obvious and important stakeholders in the case of the antibiotic resistance challenge are
biomedical researchers and health professionals. Just as any reform to expedite antibiotic drug
innovation depends on appropriate response from the pharmaceutical industry to serve its purpose,
it and its consequences for research and clinical practice need to enjoy sufficient support among
involved professionals in order for this reform to be implemented and work as intended. But if
researchers and clinicians find these consequences unacceptable, they are likely not to act as they
need to act for the reform to produce the desired outcome. They may, for instance, decline to
participate in trials they find unethical due to elevated risk levels and more uncertain prospects for
future benefits. Similarly, clinical professionals may refuse to recommend a new drug coming out
of an expedited process due to the similar reasons. This, of course, holds entirely independent of if
such opinions are justified or not (we are presently assuming they are not): professional legitimacy
is a key feature of any feasible antibiotic resistance intervention.
This prospect has led some commentators to argue in favour of revisions of the ethics underlying
clinical guidelines, so that higher risks and more uncertain benefits for patients are judged more
acceptable if they come out of actions to effectively manage the antibiotic resistance challenge
23
,
and such notions may be extended also to the realm of research ethics
24
. However, while such
proposals may be supported by sound theoretical argument
25
, it is likely that such changes to
clinical and research ethical orthodoxy will be resisted, if only because the individualist stance of
these well-established frameworks are strongly entrenched in the training of researchers and
clinicians, as well as systems set up to monitor and review activities in this light. Contrary to this,
23
Littmann, J., Rid, A., Buyx, A. (2018). Tackling anti-microbial resistance: ethical framework for rational antibiotic
use. European Journal of Public Health. 28(2), 359363.
24
See the contribution of Anomaly & Savulescu to the present special issue for one example.
25
This, to our mind, remains to be shown, as it may very well be thought to be of great importance that clinical
researchers and practitioners continue to prioritise the needs of their individual patients before other considerations,
even in the light of the good reasons for expediting antimicrobial innovation.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
12
some recent developments have indeed introduced changes to central policy documents that seem to
give room for less individualist considerations, such as the notion of “social value” as the ultimate
goal of health-related research in the revised CIOMS guidelines for research ethical review
26
. But
individualism nevertheless still holds its grip over traditional clinical ethics and the central research
ethical document of biomedical research, The Declaration of Helsinki
27
.
A way out of this challenge would be if the reasons to cut research ethical red tape, and thereby
expedite antibiotic drug innovation, could be plausibly formulated in terms of the traditional
individualist (biomedical research and clinical) ethos. While not ruling this possibility out entirely,
we harbour serious doubt about the feasibility of this way forward. Expediting antibiotic drug
innovation unavoidably elevates risks and uncertainties for identifiable and existing individuals.
The balancing act of trading off these risks against benefits is not only about a trade-off between
individual and collective outcomes, but also about the long-term securing of public goods and the
sustainability of health systems, and the latter may be plausibly argued to be about the good of
individuals as well. However, these potential benefits of expediting antibiotic drug innovation by
exposing current research subjects and patients to elevated risk and uncertainty all lie in an
uncertain future, where the (possible) beneficiaries are currently non-existing and unidentifiable.
This means that those arguing in favour of cutting red tape will have to accept both
instrumentalisation of present patients and research subjects, where these are sacrificed to the
benefit of an unclear mass of future people – as well for collective goods – and a particular and
controversial type of view on the ethics of future generations, where the possible aggregated needs
26
Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences, CIOMS. (2016). International Ethical Guidelines for
Health-related Research involving Humans. Geneva: CIOMS.
27
World Medical Association, WMA. (2013). WMA Declaration of Helsinki Ethical Principles for Medical Research
Involving Human Subjects. Ferney-Voltaire: WMA.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
13
of the future are put before the actual needs of patients today
28
. While normative ethical arguments
to this effect may indeed be formulated, we doubt that these arguments can easily be fitted into
current individualist orthodoxy of the ethics of biomedical research and clinical practice.
Pragmatic challenge 3: Adverse popular and political response
Expediting antibiotic drug innovation may not only be strategically counterproductive and
professionally illegitimate but may also set off destructive dynamics among the broadest group of
stakeholders, people in general (and, indirectly, political decision-makers). First, there is an inherent
paradox in the message that risks and uncertainties of antibiotic drug development and therapy need
to increase in order to protect future antibiotic efficiency, as the reasons that people and policy
makers will see for the latter aim are thereby weakened: the public good that is supposed to be
protected by cutting research ethical red tape is being devaluated by the very same reform. Second,
just as professionals may be unwilling to participate in the implementation of reforms to expedite
antibiotic drug innovation, patients and potential research subjects may rationally respond with
reduced clinical adherence and research participation, both of which will work against the aim of
cutting the red tape. While reduced research enrolment is straightforward and easily understood,
reduced clinical adherence may take various forms. One is elevated consumption of prescribed
antibiotics where the effect is seen as more uncertain. Another is reduced consumption of
prescribed drugs due to perceived elevated risks, so that the therapy becomes inefficient,
necessitating repeated treatment and, in the end, elevated antibiotic consumption (as well as
sustained ill-health). A third is that patients turn to alternative sources, such as online clinics and
pharmacies, to get their hands on what they believe are more safe and efficient antibiotic drugs,
leading to risks of elevated consumption that drives resistance (as the drugs acquired may be ones
28
This aspect may be argued not to regard patients in life threatening circumstances and where there are no feasible
treatment options. However, such patients are a rarity, and effective enhancement of innovation will have to include
many more patients than this exclusive group.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
14
that need to be heavily rationed to manage the resistance threat), inefficient treatment (due to the
lack of control of products sold on the shade side of the global drug market), and/or undermined
motivation to innovate from industry (as the demand for their novel antibiotic products declines).
On top of this, people in general, just as professionals, may, of course, find the costs of cutting
research ethical red tape unacceptable, creating political pressure on policy makers not to go
forward with reforms to expedite antibiotic drug innovation. Attitudes of distrust towards the
motives of pharmaceutical companies may further fuel such resistance. Depending on the force of
such popular response, the resulting political backlash may very well be substantial, and may
threaten the political feasibility of effective action to manage the antibiotic resistance challenge for
a long time. In addition, the uncertainty created by the strategy to cut the red tape of drug
innovation means that there is a risk of creating a false sense of security: believing in the effect of
the expedited program to provide a continuous supply of new antibiotic formulas that can keep the
resistance threat at bay, we can be expected to discount both the reduced effectiveness of these
drugs and the need to work on the resistance challenge from different angles. This dynamic will
likely occur to a greater extent when the promise of a new therapy is elevated, such as in the case of
‘golden ticket’ solutions, such as phage therapy
29
. When the actual outcome is then disappointing,
this could lead to further dismay, feeding the negative policy pragmatics created by all of the
challenges 1-3.
Pragmatic challenge 4: Rhetorical negative feedback
29
This is one of several high risk (in terms of very uncertain prospect for a useful product at the end of the innovation
process), high gain antimicrobial innovation options that has been used to strongly advocate expedited innovation
reform. See Thiel, K. (2004). Old Dogma, New Tricks21st Century Phage Therapy. Nature Biotechnology. 22(1): 31-
36, as well as the petition at https://www.change.org/p/janet-woodcock-m-d-urge-the-fda-to-loosen-restrictions-on-
bacteriophage-therapies-as-antibiotics
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
15
An obvious way for policy makers to respond to the challenges 2 and 3, is to add to the expedited
innovation reform itself a rhetorical narrative that aims to create a support that compensate for the
risk of lost legitimacy. We have expressed some doubt about this prospect with regard to challenge
2, and convincing members of the public to support a system that will provide them with less safe
and less effective healthcare is a challenge that needs recognition. In both cases, what seems to be
required is a distinctly moral tale of what the drug resistance challenge is about and the implied
need for speedier antibiotic drug innovation that can make them change their present priorities.
But this rhetorical add-on to the expedited innovation reform also adds a further layer of pragmatic
risk. For what if the public and professionals don’t buy the story, but on the contrary find it
repugnant? If, for example, the rhetoric endeavour is viewed by the public as an attempt to coax
them into accepting increased risks to patients and research subjects for the benefit of large
corporations, not only may political backlash be reinforced, basic trust in state institutions may be
undermined. It does not take much imagination to see how a rhetorical move in favour of cutting
research ethical red tape may create a breeding ground for a toxic relationship between key
stakeholders and the state that can require a long time to repair.
Conclusion: a further dilemma and a suggestion
There are strong principled reasons in favour of expediting antibiotic drug innovation, and thus to
accept a lowering of ethical standards of research and clinical introduction of new antibiotic
formulas. However, this support is weakened by the four pragmatic challenges we have described.
It is, of course, at this point an open question just how likely to occur the scenarios we have
sketched are
30
. Whether or not all or any of them arises as a response to the relaxing of specific
30
Perhaps with exception for the first challenge of strategic adapted industry response. As this phenomenon has been
observed in relation to expedited programs for orphan disease treatments, there some empirical support of such response
to be expected also in the antibiotic case.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
16
standards with regard to the various stages of antibiotic drug development, depends on a lot of
factors, not the least of which is how extensive the expediting measures are. Their uncertainty,
however, is no reason to simply disregard them
31
. In the worst case, these challenges threaten us
with costly counterproductive reforms that lack the legitimacy necessary to be implementable or
politically feasible. This may create long-term political backlash against policies in response to the
antibiotic resistance challenge, as well as undermining basic trust in institutions necessary for any
such policy to be effective. Such stakes create a reason to adapt reform proposals to appease key
stakeholders in order to create legitimacy and institutional effectiveness.
However, this conclusion leaves us to face a new dilemma, which is of a more general nature,
illustrated by image 1:
Image 1
31
Nijsingh et al. op. cit. note 8.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
17
As an effective justified action, assessed to be so on a valid ethical basis, becomes infeasible due to
negative stakeholder response (marked in red) policy makers are forced to reconsider (red feedback
arrow). They first create a rhetoric for having stakeholders view the action in a more favourable
light
32
. If luck wins the day, this will resolve the pragmatic challenge, but if not (as we have argued
is not an unlikely outcome in the case of reform to expedite antibiotic drug innovation), the negative
response will accumulate, again forcing reconsideration. This process will then have policy makers
adapt by weakening the force of the action (to have less of the objectionable effect) in order to
finally win acceptance, but at the cost of simultaneously weakening the original ethical justification
of the action. Alternatively, they may resist adaption and pressing on to have the action
implemented (typically, using force), in which case the risks of severe political blocking of effective
policy increases. This type of dilemma is relevant for many serious public health threats, one of
which is that of antibitic resistance, as these usually require drastic action and controversial
revisions of public policy and practice. Recently, the ethical dimension of such ‘wicked problems’
of health policy implementation have been lifted as a major gap in biomedical research ethics
33
.
We suggest that the importance of securing the functionality of basic institutions and of avoiding
long-term blocking of political action in response to the antibiotic resistance challenge means that
policy avenues actualising this secondary dilemma should often be abandoned. They should be
pursued only if they can be made to win necessary stakeholder acceptance at a fair distance from
the point where they are either having their original justification undermined, or where real political
blocking becomes a viable possibility. We are not certain where this leaves the notion of expediting
antibiotic drug innovation in response to the antibiotic resistance threat. However, we do believe
32
It is also possible to consider further actions to secure acceptance, such as stakeholder or community engagement
programs. See King, K.F., Kolopack, P., Merritt, M.W., Lavery, J.V. (2014). Community engagement and the human
infrastructure of global health research. BMC Medical Ethics 15, 84. Doi: 10.1186/1472-6939-15-84.
33
Lavery, J.V. (2016). ‘Wicked problems’, community engagement and the need for an implementation science for
research ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics 44(3): 163-164.
This is a ”preprint”, the authors manuscript of an article after peer review but before the final editorial changes, published in the scientific
journal Bioethics, Early view, doi: 10.1111/bioe.12605. Citation should refer to the published version, available here:
https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12605
18
that this is not the only action exposed to this kind of complication among the many policies in the
quickly growing toolbox of suggested responses to fight the threat of resistance to antibiotics.
... Second, ethical preparedness is not a solutionist approach: even if an individual (or group of individuals) are ethically prepared, ethical decisionmaking is still fraught with difficult and complex decisions with often no correct 'answer' . Finally, even if an individual, group of individuals or organisation does have the capability, opportunity and motivation to make a particular ethically considered decision, this act of decisionmaking may cause changes to the macro layers of the system (e.g., there could be a backlash from stakeholders, key actors and/or the public about the decision), which will, in turn, have implications on the capability, opportunity and motivation of the decision [48]. This creates the need for an iterative process of behavioural and ethical analysis and highlights the importance of recognising the temporality of decision making, and the dynamic relationship between the decision-making and changes in the capability, opportunity and motivation over time. ...
Article
Full-text available
Background Public health scholars have long called for preparedness to help better negotiate ethical issues that emerge during public health emergencies. In this paper we argue that the concept of ethical preparedness has much to offer other areas of health beyond pandemic emergencies, particularly in areas where rapid technological developments have the potential to transform aspects of health research and care, as well as the relationship between them. We do this by viewing the ethical decision-making process as a behaviour, and conceptualising ethical preparedness as providing a health research/care setting that can facilitate the promotion of this behaviour. We draw on an implementation science and behaviour change model, COM-B, to demonstrate that to be ethically prepared requires having the capability (ability), opportunity, and motivation (willingness) to work in an ethically prepared way. Methods We use two case examples from our empirical research—one pandemic and one non-pandemic related—to illustrate how our conceptualisation of ethical preparedness can be applied in practice. The first case study was of the UK NHSX COVID-19 contact tracing application case study involved eight in-depth interviews with people involved with the development/governance of this application. The second case involved a complex case regarding familial communication discussed at the UK Genethics Forum. We used deductive qualitative analysis based on the COM-B model categories to analyse the transcripbed data from each case study. Results Our analysis highlighted that being ethically prepared needs to go beyond merely equipping health professionals with skills and knowledge, or providing research governance actors with ethical principles and/or frameworks. To allow or support these different actors to utilise their skills and knowledge (or principles and frameworks), a focus on the physical and social opportunity is important, as is a better understanding the role of motivation. Conclusions To understand ethical preparedness, we need to view the process of ethical decision-making as a behaviour. We have provided insight into the specific factors that are needed to promote this behaviour—using examples from both in the pandemic context as well as in areas of health research and medicine where there have been rapid technological developments. This offers a useful starting point for further conceptual work around the notion of being ethically prepared.
... The promise of better diagnostics cannot be fulfilled without access to subsequent care. On top of the implementation barriers for diagnostics, crucial bottlenecks continue to remain in drug development: a challenge encountered elsewhere in precision medicine [123] and that can present new ethical dilemmas in AMR [124]. The well-documented economic obstacles to establishing a reliable AM drug development pipeline is increasingly taking on social and moral significance [125]. ...
Article
Full-text available
The precision health era is likely to reduce and respond to antimicrobial resistance (AMR). Our stewardship and precision efforts share terminology, seeking to deliver the “right drug, at the right dose, at the right time.” Already, rapid diagnostic testing, phylogenetic surveillance, and real-time outbreak response provide just a few examples of molecular advances we dub “precision stewardship.” However, the AMR causal factors range from the molecular to that of global health policy. Mirroring the cross-sectoral nature of AMR science, the research addressing the ethical, legal and social implications (ELSI) of AMR ranges across academic scholarship. As the rise of AMR is accompanied by an escalating sense of its moral and social significance, what is needed is a parallel field of study. In this paper, we offer a gap analysis of this terrain, or an agenda for “the ELSI of precision stewardship.” In the first section, we discuss the accomplishments of a multi-decade U.S. national investment in ELSI research attending to the advances in human genetics. In the next section, we provide an overview of distinct ELSI topics pertinent to AMR. The distinctiveness of an ELSI agenda for precision stewardship suggests new opportunities for collaboration to build the stewardship teams of the future.
... Recent literature has stressed that, amongst other challenges, ABR raises serious ethical ones, which require justifiable ethical principles to be formulated and applied [37,53,54]. In addition, however, people's actual normative and evaluative commitments, such as those found in this study, need to be understood to ensure feasibility of policies based on such principles [38,55]. In terms of concrete measures tackling specific obstacles, lack of trust in healthcare institutions and perceived low individual self-efficacy, if confirmed in quantitative investigations, could be addressed in adequately framed communication campaigns as well as in doctor-patient communication, as suggested also by other research [32,51,52]. ...
Article
Full-text available
Background Antibiotic resistance is a complex phenomenon heavily influenced by social, cultural, behavioural, and economic factors that lead to the misuse, overuse and abuse of antibiotics. Recent research has highlighted the role that norms and values can play for behaviours that contribute to resistance development, and for addressing such behaviours. Despite comparatively high antibiotic consumption in Greece, both at the community and healthcare level, Greeks have been shown to be relatively aware of the connection between antibiotic overuse and antibiotic resistance. This suggests that Greeks’ non-judicious use cannot simply be explained by lack of awareness but may relate to other factors specific to Greek society. The present study aimed to explore attitudes, perceived norms, and values in relation to antibiotics, in order to improve understanding of socio-cultural determinants of antibiotic resistance in Greece. Methods Data were collected through online focus group discussions in 2021. Twenty Greeks were recruited through purposive sampling, aiming for as heterogeneous groups as possible regarding gender (12 women, 8 men), age (range 21–55, mean 33), and education level. Interview transcripts were analysed inductively using thematic content analysis. Results Participants considered antibiotic overconsumption as a consolidated habit influenced by ease of access, social expectations and, more generally, cultural practices. While critical of such norms and practices, participants opposed stewardship measures that would prioritize the societal interest in maintaining antibiotic effectiveness over individual needs. Participants considered responsibility for antibiotic resistance to be shared by the whole society, but the role of government actors and health professionals as well as of food producers was emphasized. Notably, scepticism about the prospect of effectively managing antibiotic resistance in Greece was commonly expressed. Conclusions The study makes explicit attitudes, perceived norms and values that, besides limited awareness, may contribute to non-judicious antibiotic use in Greece. These socio-cultural determinants of antibiotic resistance warrant further research and should be considered when designing measures aimed to mitigate this problem.
... Secondly, (semi-) mandatory approaches may in some cases even create perverse incentives, for example when people are motivated to "chase immunity" in order to escape the burdens of the app. Any attempt to encourage or mandate CT apps is then likely to worsen the situation, by creating backlash effects that cause CT technology to lose support of large parts of the population (Munthe and Nijsingh 2019). It is precisely because of the potential benefit of being able to trace the spread of the virus more easily and pervasively than with the labour intensive method of contacting people personally that we may expect the chances of these kinds of effects to rise. ...
Article
Full-text available
The COVID-19 pandemic presents unprecedented challenges to public health decision-making. Specifically, the lack of evidence and the urgency with which a response is called for, raise the ethical challenge of assessing how much (and what kind of) evidence is required for the justification of interventions in response to the various threats we face. Here we discuss the intervention of introducing technology that aims to trace and alert contacts of infected persons—contact tracing (CT) technology. Determining whether such an intervention is proportional is complicated by complex trade-offs and feedback loops. We suggest that the resulting uncertainties necessitate a precautionary approach. On the one hand, precautionary reasons support CT technology as a means to contribute to the prevention of harms caused by alternative interventions, or COVID-19 itself. On the other hand, however, both the extent to which such technology itself present risks of serious harm, as well as its effectiveness, remain unclear. We therefore argue that a precautionary approach should put reversibility of CT technology at the forefront. We outline several practical implications.
... In particular, the combination of a problem that is difficult to observe, interventions that come at a cost for individual persons and experts that may potentially benefit from these interventions (directly or indirectly by attracting more attention to 'their' field of specialisation) is potentially a recipe for mistrust. Worse still, attempts to enhance trust may backfire and end up exacerbating the problem: such attempts may even be perceived to be manipulative [9]. Lack of epistemic trust may severely hinder effective cooperation needed in order to address multifactorial problems, such as ABR [8]. ...
Article
In this perspective, we discuss non-experts’ beliefs about the complex and ‘messy' problem of antibiotic resistance (ABR). First, we explain what we mean by complex and messy problems and why ABR fits that description. We then suggest that the attitudes of non-experts are particularly relevant to these problems. This gives rise to social epistemic risks; risks that involve the collective and social aspects of the formation of epistemic attitudes. Steering these epistemic attitudes as a way of handling these risks can take the form of creating what we call ‘epistemic architecture’. That is, a planned design of the structure within which the formation of epistemic attitudes takes place. This entails risks of its own, which leads us to conclude that there is an important responsibility for experts to take these social epistemic risks into account when communicating on messy problems, such as ABR.
Article
Methicillin-resistant Staphylococcus aureus (MRSA) has become a rising clinical problem as its occurrence has increased due to the overuse and misuse of antibiotics. In this work, upconversion nanoparticles@AgBiS2 core-shell were produced with enhanced photothermal transformation efficiency and ability to produce reactive oxygen species for synergistic photodynamic photothermal and photodynamic antibacterial performance. The nanoparticles exhibit good antibacterial effects in vitro and satisfactory therapeutic performance on healing MRSA-infected wounds in vivo experiments. RNA-sequencing technique has been used to investigate and reveal that photothermal-photodynamic therapy using the nanoparticles can interfere with metabolic processes such as galactose metabolism in MRSA bacteria, destroy the transport system on the surface of MRSA, and affect quorum sensing to hinder the formation of biofilms to achieve effective antibacterial efficacy. It was demonstrated that this work presents an alternative near-infrared photoactive multimodal nanostructure for antibacterial applications.
Article
Full-text available
Antibiotic resistance is widely recognized as a major threat to public health and healthcare systems worldwide. Recent research suggests that pollution from antibiotics manufacturing is an important driver of resistance development. Using Sweden as an example, this paper considers how industrial antibiotic pollution might be addressed by public actors who are in a position to influence the distribution and use of antibiotics in high-income countries with publicly funded health systems. We identify a number of opportunities for these actors to incentivize industry to increase sustainability in antibiotics production. However, we also show that each alternative would create tensions with other significant policy goals, necessitating trade-offs. Since justifiable trade-offs require ethical consideration, we identify and explore the main underlying normative issues, namely, the weighing of local versus global health interests, the weighing of present versus future health interests, and the role of individualistic constraints on the pursuit of collective goals. Based on this analysis, we conclude that the actors have weighty principled reasons for prioritizing the goal of addressing pollution, but that translating this stance into concrete policy requires accommodating significant pragmatic challenges.
Article
Full-text available
Effectiveness is a key criterion in assessing the justification of antibiotic resistance interventions. Depending on an intervention’s effectiveness, burdens and costs will be more or less justified, which is especially important for large scale population-level interventions with high running costs and pronounced risks to individuals in terms of wellbeing, integrity and autonomy. In this paper, we assess the case of routine hospital screening for multi-drug-resistant Gram-negative bacteria (MDRGN) from this perspective. Utilizing a comparison to screening programs for Methicillin-Resistant Staphylococcus Aureus (MRSA) we argue that current screening programmes for MDRGN in low endemic settings should be reconsidered, as its effectiveness is in doubt, while general downsides to screening programs remain. To accomplish justifiable antibiotic stewardship, MDRGN screening should not be viewed as a separate measure, but rather as part of a comprehensive approach. The program should be redesigned to focus on those at risk of developing infections with MDRGN rather than merely detecting those colonised, as the carrier rate is steadily increasing, and the overall risk of actual infection may be very low in otherwise healthy carriers. …
Preprint
Full-text available
Antibiotic resistance is widely recognized as a major threat to public health and healthcare systems worldwide. Recent research suggests that pollution from antibiotics manufacturing is an important driver of resistance development. Using Sweden as an example, this paper considers how industrial antibiotic pollution might be addressed by public actors who are in a position to influence the distribution and use of antibiotics in high-income countries with publicly funded health systems. We identify a number of opportunities for these actors to incentivize industry to increase sustainability in antibiotics production. However, we also show that each alternative would create tensions with other significant policy goals, necessitating trade-offs. Since justifiable trade-offs require ethical consideration, we identify and explore the main underlying normative issues, namely, the weighing of local versus global health interests, the weighing of present versus future health interests, and the role of individualistic constraints on the pursuit of collective goals. Based on this analysis, we conclude that the actors have weighty principled reasons for prioritizing the goal of addressing pollution, but that translating this stance into concrete policy requires accommodating significant pragmatic challenges.
Preprint
Effectiveness is a key criterion in assessing the justification of antibiotic resistance interventions. Depending on an intervention’s effectiveness, burdens and costs will be more or less justified, which is especially important for large scale population-level interventions with high running costs and pronounced risks to individuals in terms of wellbeing, integrity and autonomy. In this paper, we assess the case of routine hospital screening for multi-drug-resistant Gram-negative bacteria (MDRGN) from this perspective. Utilizing a comparison to screening programs for Methicillin-Resistant Staphylococcus Aureus (MRSA) we argue that current screening programmes for MDRGN in low endemic settings should be reconsidered, as its effectiveness is in doubt, while general downsides to screening programs remain. To accomplish justifiable antibiotic stewardship, MDRGN screening should not be viewed as a separate measure, but rather as part of a comprehensive approach. The program should be redesigned to focus on those at risk of developing infections with MDRGN rather than merely detecting those colonised, as the carrier rate is steadily increasing, and the overall risk of actual infection may be very low in otherwise healthy carriers.
Chapter
Full-text available
This chapter charts and critically analyses the ethical challenge of assessing how much (and what kind of) evidence is required for the justification of interventions in response antibiotic resistance (ABR), as well as other major public health threats. Our ambition here is to identify and briefly discuss main issues, and point to ways in which these need to be further advanced in future research. This will result in a tentative map of complications, underlying problems and possible challenges. This map illustrates that the ethical challenges in this area are much more complex and profound than is usually acknowledged, leaving no tentatively plausible intervention package free of downsides. This creates potentially overwhelming theoretical conundrums when trying to justify what to do. We therefore end by pointing out two general features of the complexity we find to be of particular importance, and a tentative suggestion for how to create a theoretical basis for further analysis.
Article
Full-text available
We consider the implications for the ethical evaluation of research programs of two fundamental changes in the revised research ethical guideline of the Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences. The first is the extension of scope that follows from exchanging “biomedical” for “health-related” research, and the second is the new evaluative basis of “social value,” which implies new ethical requirements of research. We use the example of antibiotic resistance interventions to explore the need to consider what we term the pragmatic risks of such interventions to evaluate the so- cial value of certain kinds of health-related research. These (pragmatic) risks severely threaten the social value of interventions in every area where human and social re- sponses significantly impact on their effectiveness. Thus, the social value of health-re- lated research needed to demonstrate its effectiveness depends on the successful management of such risks. Research designed to take into account pragmatic risks also gives rise to similar types of risks, and the potential for social value in light of those risks needs to be considered in ethical reviews based on the new guidelines. We argue that, to handle this new expanded task, the international system of research ethical review addressed by the guidelines needs institutional development. In particular, we consider lifting research ethical review to a level closer to actual health policy making.
Article
Full-text available
In this paper, we provide a state-of-the-art overview of the ethical challenges that arise in the context of antimicrobial resistance (AMR), which includes an introduction to the contributions to the symposium in this issue. We begin by discussing why AMR is a distinct ethical issue, and should not be viewed purely as a technical or medical problem. In the second section, we expand on some of these arguments and argue that AMR presents us with a broad range of ethical problems that must be addressed as part of a successful policy response to emerging drug resistance. In the third section, we discuss how some of these ethical challenges should be addressed, and we argue that this requires contributions from citizens, ethicists, policy makers, practitioners and industry. We conclude with an overview of steps that should be taken in moving forward and addressing the ethical problems of AMR.
Article
Full-text available
While promoting population health has been the classic goal of public health practice and policy, in recent decades, new objectives in terms of autonomy and equality have been introduced. These different goals are analysed, and it is demonstrated how they may conflict severly in several ways, leaving serious unclarities both regarding the normative issue of what goal should be pursued by public health, what that implies in practical terms, and the descriptive issue of what goal that actually is pursued in different contexts. A basic conflict of perspective is handled by integrating the ideas of public health striving for health-related autonomy and equality, resulting in a prioritarian oriented population approach to health-related autonomy. This integrated goal is demonstrated to constrain itself in several ways attractive from the point of view of the classic goal, but several serious problems remain. For this reason, a model where all of the three goals are integrated into one coherent structure where they can be assigned varying degrees of importance relative to the level of population health is described. It is argued that this model avoids the problems set out earlier, and is actually normatively preferable to the classic goal alone. It is furthermore argued that the model may be employed as a useful tool for descriptive ethics, as well as a vehicle for international harmonisation of public health policies. A number of practical implications regarding, e.g., the importance of respecting autonomy and the allocation of public health resources are noted, as are a battery of questions for further research.
Article
A failure to use words clearly undermines the global response to antimicrobials' waning usefulness.
Article
The principle of equipoise states that, when there is uncertainty or conflicting expert opinion about the relative merits of diagnostic, prevention, or treatment options, allocating interventions to individuals in a manner that allows the generation of new knowledge (eg, randomization) is ethically permissible.¹,2 The principle of equipoise reconciles 2 potentially conflicting ethical imperatives: to ensure that research involving human participants generates scientifically sound and clinically relevant information while demonstrating proper respect and concern for the rights and interests of study participants.
Book
Public health ethics is a discipline concerned with the health of the public or a population as a whole, rather than focusing on the individual. This book introduces a number of this new field's central concepts and explores the key and controversial issues arising. Topics covered include the nature of public health ethics, the concepts of disease and prevention, risk and precaution, health inequalities and justice, screening, vaccination and disease control, smoking and issues relating to the environment and public health. With insightful contributions from leading experts, Public Health Ethics presents thought-provoking reviews of these topics, at the same time as encouraging and identifying areas for future discussion in this emerging discipline. This is a valuable addition to the library of anyone working in the fields of public health, health policy, ethics, philosophy and social science.
Article
Each year, about 23 000 people in the United States die from antibiotic-resistant infections. For many of these infections, safe and effective treatments are lacking. To address this problem, the US Food and Drug Administration (FDA) has updated several expedited approval programs for new antibacterial therapies, some of which alter the evidentiary standard for drug approval.¹,2 For instance, a drug may be eligible for “accelerated approval” if it “has an effect on a surrogate end point that is reasonably likely to predict clinical benefit.”² Since 1992, the accelerated approval program has been available for drugs likely to offer a therapeutic benefit over available treatments for serious or life-threatening diseases. Now, the program’s scope has been expanded to include drugs with marginal ancillary benefits, such as a novel mechanism of action without improvements in safety or efficacy. These well-intentioned new standards for drug approval have increased the risk that the FDA will approve antimicrobial therapies that are less effective or more harmful than available treatments.
Chapter
Following the statement in the United Nations' Rio Declaration of 1992 that countries should apply a “precautionary approach” in policymaking on environmental and technological issues, the notion of a precautionary principle (PP) has gained ground in worldwide policymaking and regulation, thus catching the interest of ethics scholars. Although seldom explained in much detail, and resulting in quite different policy results in different countries and areas (O'Riordan et al. 2001; Sandin 1999; Trouwborst 2002; Zander 2010), PP is generally understood as a norm urging or permitting policymakers to take preventive action in the face of unknown, uncertain, or probable dangers, motivated by the experience of how seemingly valuable and promising practices may lead to seriously adverse consequences in spite of lack of solid evidence to this effect (Sandin 1999). In ethics debate, this idea has been applied not only to matters regarding the large-scale introduction and use of technology (e.g., regarding energy production, transport and communication, nano- or biotechnology, and so on) (see Biotechnology; Nanotechnology, Ethics of) with possible ensuing impact on the natural environment connecting to the notion of sustainability (see Sustainability), but also, for example, to abortion (see Abortion), medical genetics, embryo experimentation (see Embryo Research), the treatment of animals (see Animal Experimentation), terrorism (see Terrorism), and general research ethics (see Research Ethics) (Munthe 2011). Many of these applications advocate strong conclusions in spite of the fact that PP or its normative justification have not been made very clear. At the same time, PP has been the subject of criticism, much of which boils down to three points: lack of clarity, lack of practicality, and/or ethical implausibility. Curiously, these critical points have often been made in conjunction, in spite of the fact that a clear sense of what PP means seems necessary for backing up the other two objections. Keywords: bioethics; environmental regulation; ethics; global warming; medicine; normative ethics; philosophy; practical (applied) ethics; uncertainty