ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

Purpose There seems to exist a widespread, unquestioned and unquestionable consent, both in research and practice, that there is a moral value inherent in equality and related initiatives toward diversity and inclusion. However, this consent is primarily based on political convictions and emotional reasons, and is without any strong ethical grounding. Whilst a considerable volume of research has been carried out into different facets of the economic value of initiatives toward equality, diversity, and inclusion (EDI), comparatively little research has been undertaken into its moral value. Therefore, the purpose of this paper is to structure the moral perspectives on EDI more precisely and more critically. Design/methodology/approach After discussing the interrelation of the three concepts equality, diversity and inclusion, the authors discuss the way in which initiatives toward diversity and inclusion are justified morally in literature. The authors point out the crucial position of equality, and then, subsequently, outline how different approaches to equality try to achieve moral legitimacy. Being an important group of initiatives in this debate, the authors subsequently reflect upon the moral (il)legitimacy of affirmative action (AA). The concluding section of this paper provides a brief summary of the findings. Findings The moral evaluation of equality, diversity and inclusion remains an under-theorized field. Within the discourse on equality, diversity and inclusion, the term “justice” is largely used in an intuitive way, rather than being rooted in a specific moral philosophy. As there are several conceivable, differing moral perspectives on EDI, one cannot expect an indisputable answer to the question as to whether a given approach toward equality, diversity and inclusion is morally praiseworthy or just. However, the widespread assumption that equality is morally praiseworthy per se, and that striving for equality morally justifies any initiative toward diversity and inclusion, is untenable. Originality/value This paper addresses the lack of theorizing on the moral value of initiatives toward equality, diversity, and inclusion, such as diversity management, AA or various equal opportunity approaches. Future research could enrich the discourse on the moral evaluation of diversity management, inclusion programs and organizational equality approaches with new philosophical facets and perspectives, perspectives that might differ from those taken in the predominantly American discourse.
An indisputable holy trinity?
On the moral value of equality,
diversity, and inclusion
Thomas Köllen
Department of Organization and Human Resource Management (IOP),
University of Bern, Bern, Switzerland
Marja-Liisa Kakkuri-Knuuttila
Department of Management Studies, Aalto University School of Business,
Helsinki, Finland, and
Regine Bendl
Department of Management,
Vienna University of Economics and Business, Vienna, Austria
Abstract
Purpose There seems to exist a widespread, unquestioned and unquestionable consent, both in research
and practice, that there is a moral value inherent in equality and related initiatives toward diversity and
inclusion. However, this consent is primarily based on political convictions and emotional reasons, and is
without any strong ethical grounding. Whilst a considerable volume of research has been carried out into
different facets of the economic value of initiatives toward equality, diversity, and inclusion (EDI),
comparatively little research has been undertaken into its moral value. Therefore, the purpose of this paper is
to structure the moral perspectives on EDI more precisely and more critically.
Design/methodology/approach After discussing the interrelation of the three concepts equality, diversity
and inclusion, the authors discuss the way in which initiatives toward diversity and inclusion are justified
morally in literature. The authors point out the crucial position of equality, and then, subsequently, outline how
different approaches to equality try to achieve moral legitimacy. Being an important group of initiatives in this
debate, the authors subsequently reflect upon the moral (il)legitimacy of affirmativeaction (AA). The concluding
section of this paper provides a brief summary of the findings.
Findings The moral evaluation of equality, diversity and inclusion remains an under-theorized field.
Within the discourse on equality, diversity and inclusion, the term justiceis largely used in an intuitive way,
rather than being rooted in a specific moral philosophy. As there are several conceivable, differing moral
perspectives on EDI, one cannot expect an indisputable answer to the question as to whether a given
approach toward equality, diversity and inclusion is morally praiseworthy or just. However, the widespread
assumption that equality is morally praiseworthy per se, and that striving for equality morally justifies any
initiative toward diversity and inclusion, is untenable.
Originality/value This paper addresses the lack of theorizing on the moral value of initiatives toward
equality, diversity, and inclusion, such as diversity management, AA or various equal opportunity
approaches. Future research could enrich the discourse on the moral evaluation of diversity management,
inclusion programs and organizational equality approaches with new philosophical facets and perspectives,
perspectives that might differ from those taken in the predominantly American discourse.
Keywords Moral value, Diversity management, Morality, Equality, Affirmative action, Reverse discrimination
Paper type General review
Introduction
Equality, diversity and inclusion are three closely-related concepts. The concept of diversity
builds on the fact that there are numerous categories, often referred to as dimensions of
diversity, that can be used to describe humans, and that humans can utilize to describe
themselves. These dimensions of diversity, such as age, sexual orientation, gender,
nationality, etc., can assume different shapes or manifestations; for example, being male,
female or intersex, in terms of the dimension of gender. Every human, at a given time,
represents at least one manifestation of every dimension of diversity, within a given context.
Equality, Diversity and Inclusion:
An International Journal
Vol. 37 No. 5, 2018
pp. 438-449
© Emerald Publishing Limited
2040-7149
DOI 10.1108/EDI-04-2018-0072
Received 14 April 2018
Accepted 16 April 2018
The current issue and full text archive of this journal is available on Emerald Insight at:
www.emeraldinsight.com/2040-7149.htm
438
EDI
37,5
The vast number of shared similarities, and prevalent differences, between humans, alongside
a conceptually infinite number of dimensions, represents the diversity of, for example, a given
workforce, a nation or even of humanity as a whole. Since it is often the case, in given contexts,
that certain manifestations of specific dimensions are valued more highly than others, the
concept of equality is concerned with the way in which an individual (or group) displaying
specific manifestations (of any dimension of diversity) is related to that individuals
(or groups) (un)equal achievements, status or access to resources. Figurative terms that are
often used in this context, in order to describe the (un)equal positioning or standing of the
representatives of differing manifestations of given dimensions of diversity, are hierarchy/
hierarchizationor marginalization.In this context, the concept of inclusion refers to the
way that these differing manifestations are organized alongside, for example, societal, national
or organizational hierarchies; inclusion can also refer to the process of (de)hierarchizing these
manifestations. Most voices in the academic and practical discourse on equality, diversity and
inclusion assume that a high level of inclusion is positively related to a high level of equality
amongst the representatives of the differing manifestations of the dimensions of diversity in
question. For many, the state of equality seems to be a positive condition per se,whichis
therefore worth striving for. Thus, it seems to have become an imperative that diversity
should be handled (or managed) in a way that promotes the highest degree of inclusion and,
with it, the highest degree of equality, possible. Average group values over the specific
manifestations of each dimension of diversity often serve as an indicator for this degree.
However, it would seem that, within the discourse on equality, diversity and inclusion, it is
equality that holds a central position. It seemingly prescribes and legitimates the way in which
the inclusion of diversity should happen. The most common term for attempts toward this
inclusion is diversity management.Literature on the moral value of EDI is very scarce
(Byrd, 2018; Nkomo, 2014; Oswick and Noon, 2014; Sposato et al.,2015).
Organizational or business research on EDI, which stresses its moral value, seldom reflects
upon the specific moral perspective taken, its underlying basic assumptions, or potential
points of criticism; for the most part, an everyday understanding of what might be morally
praise- and blameworthy is applied (e.g. Jones et al., 2013). Questioning the moral value of EDI
would seem to be taboo, which supports the view held by Nietzsche; he, through Zarathustra,
compares the preachers of equalitywith secretly vengeful tarantulas,hiding behind the
word justice,whose goal is to ensure that the “‘will to equalityshall henceforth be the name
for virtue(Nietzsche, 1954, p. 100), whilst actually only serving their own will to power.
This leads him to the dictum: Mistrust all who talk much of their justice. [] And when they
call themselves the good and the just, do not forget that they would be pharisees, if only they
hadpower(Nietzsche, 1954, p. 100). Nietzsche exemplifies only one of many critical moral
perspectives on EDI, which hitherto have been silent within the academic discourse on EDI.
In the same way, the moral legitimacy and value of EDI is rarely expressed explicitly in this
discourse, and is rarely embedded in concrete moral philosophies.
Although there seems to be a widespread and unquestioned consent, both in research
and practice, that there is a moral value inherent in diversity and inclusion initiatives, there
is a lack of theorizing with regard to this, as well as a lack of critically linking these
initiatives and their underlying targets with specific moral philosophies. Most research in
EDI implicitly values equality as something morally good,but this is mostly borne out of a
political conviction, and without any ethical grounding. While a considerable amount of
research has been conducted on different facets of the economic value of equality, diversity
and inclusion, very little research has been undertaken on its moral value (e.g. Köllen, 2016;
van Dijk, 2017; van Dijk et al., 2012). Therefore, this paper aims at structuring the moral
perspectives in EDI more precisely and more critically.
The remainder of this introductory article for the special issue of EDI on Moral
Perspectives of Equality, Diversity, and Inclusionis structured as follows. First, we discuss
439
Moral
value of EDI
the way in which initiatives toward diversity and inclusion are justified morally in literature.
We point out the crucial position of equality, and then, second, we outline how the different
approaches to equality attempt to achieve moral legitimacy. Since it comprises an important
group of initiatives in this debate, we subsequently reflect upon the moral (il)legitimacy of
affirmative action (AA). The concluding section of this paper provides a brief summary
of the findings of this paper; it gives an overview of the contribution of the four papers of
this special issue to the discourse on moral perspectives of equality, diversity and inclusion,
and it proposes streams for future research and discussions on this issue.
Equality and the moral goodnessof Initiatives toward diversity and inclusion
Diversity management and related initiatives toward the inclusion of a diverse workforce are
currently a globally widespread practice amongst organizations and territorial authorities,
and the diffusion of such initiatives is still increasing (Martínez-Ariño et al., 2018; Vasconcelos,
2017). Besides citing business case arguments for the implementation of these practices
(Heres and Benschop, 2010; Kulik, 2014; Soltani et al., 2012), organizations tend to present
diversity management as some kind of morally praiseworthyor goodorganizational
practice in their internal and external communication. They often try to project the estimated
goodnessof these actions onto the actors themselves, aiming at giving the company
[or organization] a general label of ethical goodness’” (Köllen, 2016, p. 216). Often without
stating it explicitly, equalityis assumed to be a crucial indicator for the degree of
organizational goodness(or even justice), which therefore, for many, can be seen as the
intended, morally praiseworthy outcome of diversity management initiatives or
organizational programs of inclusionof a diverse workforce (see, e.g. Brewis, 2017).
Diversity management is, then, assumed to be socially just and morally desirable
(Lorbiecki and Jack, 2000, p. 21). Within the discourse on EDI, the propermanagement of a
diverse workforce has become something of a moral imperative(OLeary and Weathington,
2006; Vertovec, 2013). Romani et al. (2017) summarize this imperative as the principle of
representation, social responsibility, anti-discrimination and equal treatment [accomplished
by] HRM practices that seek to blur, or somewhat minimize, the differences with which
minority groups might contribute in the name of anti-discrimination and equality of treatment
(the moral imperative)(Romani et al., 2017, p. 273).
The assumed moral value that is ascribed to these management practices is
predominantly based on the same considerations that were, in the past, also referred to in
order to legitimize equal opportunity and AA (also referred to as positive action,
reservation,or employment equity) programs, and to load them morally. From the
standpoint of this morality, diversity management should aim at the same goals that equal
opportunity or AA initiatives did. One of these goals is adjusting the representation of
certain manifestations of certain dimension of diversity (which, in the AA context, are
mainly gender and race) on certain organizational levels, with regard to their representation
in society. With diversity management, an additional business perspective has entered the
discourse; however, its moral value is almost exclusively deduced from its impact
(or intention) in achieving some state of group-based equality. Though arguments based on
organizational self-interest might well be the norm amongst advocates of diversity, in
principle nothing prevents diversity being argued for as a way of serving the very same
moral ends as equal opportunity(Kaler, 2001, p. 59). Cox (1994) describes this phenomenon
in the following way:
In most organizations the representation of culture groups in the overall work population, and
especially in the most powerful positions, is highly skewed [which makes] equal opportunity
issues prominent aspects of diversity work in organizations. [] Thus for nations and organizations
that subscribe to a creed of equal opportunity, a major motive for investing in managing-diversity
initiatives is that it is morally and ethically the right thing to do. (Cox, 1994, p. 10)
440
EDI
37,5
Some actors even label their diversity approach, and with it their contribution toward
equality and inclusion, as an element of their responsibilitytoward society or humanity,
and, in doing so, bestow upon themselves the quality of moral goodness.Its moral
grounds seem to touch more directly upon inclusion (of individuals), and then, upon
equality, [] [being related to the] social responsibility of corporations [] and eventually a
more egalitarian society(Romani et al., 2017, p. 274). The category of equalityitself, then,
is not called into question, and it effectively turns into a moral value in itself.
Equality, therefore, is the (partial) goal of initiatives toward diversity and inclusion,
which is frequently assumed to be morally desirable, and which attaches moral value to the
initiatives themselves. In order to shed more light on the differing ways of attaching moral
value to equality,the different notions of equality will be discussed in the next section,
The moral legitimization of the different approaches toward equality
Equality is mostly discussed in the form of equality of opportunity (Fleurbaey et al., 2017),
equality of outcome, or, less frequently, equality of treatment (Dahlerup, 2007; Klarsfeld et al.,
2016) for all employees, regardless of their diverse demographics or backgrounds. Organizations
mostly present their attempts to work toward anyoftheseformsofequalityassomethingthat
ismorallypraiseworthyormorallygood,althoughtheyonlyrarelyaccentuatethisasbeing
their primary incentive (Barclays, 2002; Demuijnck, 2009; Guarnieri and Kao, 2008). In some
cases quite explicitly (Fujimoto et al., 2013), but mostly in an implicit way, a state of equality is
equated with a state of fairness and (social) justice (Brewis, 2017; Choi and Rainey, 2014).
Depending on the form or type of equality in question, this perceived justice can then occur in
the form of interactional justice (Bies, 2015), distributive justice (Villanueva-Flores et al., 2017), or
procedural justice (Kim and Siddiki, 2018). In this context, the moral value of equality seems to
be non-disputable and irrevocable (Frankfurt, 1987; Westen, 1982), and the moral goodness of an
organization (or at least of its values) seems to be determined by the ways in which it strives for
equality, and the intensity with which it strives.
In terms of the idealization of equality, Kaler (2001) distinguishes between three
dominant positions in the discourse on equality and diversity: weak equal opportunity,
strong equal opportunity and equal group selection.
Equal opportunity is about the attempt to provide ones employees with the opportunity to
compete on an equal basis for unequal rewards [, whereby the] equal basis for competition
provided by equal opportunity is selection of merit(Kaler, 2001, p. 53). The merit in question
here is ones contribution to the organizations objectives, although the matter of how these
contributions can be valued in concrete terms remains open for discussion (Liff and Wajcman,
1996). However, it is safe to assume that mere demographics, such as race, sexual orientation
or gender per se, cannot be considered as being meritorious. In case the unequal distribution of
rewards is solely due to unequal merits, the weak equal opportunity approach backs unequal
outcomes. This approach legitimizes diversity and inclusion initiatives which counteract
selections or decisions that are based on social group memberships, alongside the differing
dimensions of workforce diversity. However, if certain merits are inherent in certain group
memberships or demographics, a group related, unequal distribution of outcome is acceptable
(Kaler, 2001). Examples of meritorious characteristics are, amongst others, self-confidence, the
qualifications of individuals, commitment, aplomb, ambition and experience. Going one step
further than the mere possession of such characteristics, the strong equal opportunity
approach also takes into account the potential of the individual to acquire them, and to
develop them further. Equal opportunities for all individuals, from this perspective, would
demand that every individual had the same full potential for acquiring them.
As group-specific barriers might impede the attempts of some individuals to acquire
these characteristics, the strong equal opportunity approach backs diversity and inclusion
initiatives which exclusively support specific groups, in order to make the members of these
441
Moral
value of EDI
groups more competitive in the struggle for unequal rewards. Such group-specific barriers
are often based on, or related to, group-specific ways of being socialized, general
social stereotyping, and, especially in the case of the dimension of gender, the way in
which domestic responsibilities are traditionally distributed (Blaine and McClure Brenchley,
2018; McMillanCapehart, 2005). The strong equal opportunity approach proceeds
on the assumption that work, and the definition of work-related merits, are not
race-, gender-, sexual orientation-, etc., neutral. Since each dimension of diversity has, from
this perspective, privileged manifestations in a given context (Acker, 2006; van Dijk et al.,
2017), this approach allows remedial initiatives of diversity and inclusion. These initiatives,
then, can exclusively address and support representatives of underprivileged
manifestations of the respective dimensions of diversity; for example, black, female,
foreign or homosexual employees. The strong equal opportunity approach, therefore,
legitimizes the unequal treatment of employees, through practices that are often rhetorically
framed as AAs or positive actions. This reverse discrimination allows the provision of
certain groups of employees with resources to which others may not have access (Newton,
1973; Taylor, 1973). On an averaged group-perspective, one result of such an approach
might be the equality of outcome, but this is not perforce the primary goal of this approach.
Equality of outcome,in the form of achieving representativeness in all working areas and
on all hierarchy levels, is rather the explicit ideal/typical goal of a third approach to equality:
the equal group selection approach. Its ideal outcome is a situation in which every workforce is
more or less representative of all the social groupings available to it(Kaler, 2001, p. 53). Any
measure that is legitimized by the strong equal opportunity approach is also legitimized in this
approach, which additionally legitimizes quota systems. Focusing primarily on an individuals
demographics or group membership, instead of his or her merits (e.g. when making decisions
pertaining to recruitment and promotions) makes this approach, strictly speaking, unrelated to
equal opportunities; it is no longer about an equal competition for scarce resources.
Approaches to equality, which emphasize the goal of representativeness, are often labeled
as radicalapproaches. Approaches to equality, which put an emphasis on the merits of the
individual, are often labeled as liberalapproaches. This distinction was coined by Jewson
and Mason (1986); it is a distinction, that is often referred to as the sameness-difference
debate(Greene, 2015). Intersectional perspectives utilizing this simplistic distinction
between radical and liberal approaches partially integrate other dimensions, such as age, class
and race (e.g. Acker, 2006; Berger and Guidroz, 2010), but the academic discourse on this issue
revolves predominantly around the dimension of gender. The very influential and
oft-cited paper from Liff and Wajcman (1996) exemplifies this issue. This is why, within this
discourse, the distribution of caring responsibilities between women and men is a central
issue (Leitner, 2003); this is an issue that is non-transferable to other dimensions of
workforce diversity.
Drawing on Kalers (2001) classification of approaches to equality, it is the equal group
selection approach and, with certain qualifications, the strong equal opportunity approach
that provide legitimacy for direct intervention aiming at redistributing power and resources
between social groups. The most widely used term for these interventions, representing some
kind of positive discrimination, is AA. These actions can also include quotas for the differing
manifestations of certain dimensions of workforce diversity. However, political motivations
aside, the topic of how these actions are justifiable morally will now be discussed.
The moral (Il-)legitimacy of AAs
One group of arguments in favor of AAs, no matter whether they are labeled as such within
organizational diversity management initiatives, is related to the consequences of these
actions. Besides potentially positive economic consequences, other alleged positive
consequences of these actions are also pointed out in literature.
442
EDI
37,5
One line of argument in favor of organizational interventions toward redistributing
resources and power from over-represented groups to under-represented ones sees the
impact of role models for members of hitherto underrepresented groups as positive.
Providing these groups with such role models might motivate them to follow in their
footsteps, or, at least, it might contribute toward convincing them that their demographic
per se is not a reason for not working in a given area, or at a given level (Securius-Carr and
Rohr, 2018; Singh et al., 2006). The basic assumption of this argument is related to a second
line of argument.
This line of argument states that segregation (or exclusion)isbad.Segregation is any
state of unrepresentativeness, on whatever hierarchy level or working area, in terms of any
dimension of diversity. Overcoming it is seen as good,since that integration of racial,
ethnic, and other groups that mark significant lines of social inequality is a vital ideal for a
democratic society, necessary for its basic institutions to function successfully(Anderson,
2010, p. X). With reference to racial segregation in the US society, Anderson (2010) alleges
that if segregation is a fundamental cause of social inequality and undemocratic practices,
then integration promotes greater equality and democracy. Hence, it is an imperative of
justice. It is also a positive good. It should appeal to us as well as command us to action
(Anderson, 2010, p. 2). Therefore, for Anderson, any race-based AAs that aim at overcoming
this segregation are morally legitimate; she very much connects it with her conviction that
democracy is worth protecting and segregation might destabilize democracy.
Segregation of social groups is a principal cause of group inequality. It isolates
disadvantaged groups from access to public and private resources, from sources of human
and cultural capital, and from the social networks that govern access to jobs, business
connections, and political influence. It depresses their ability to accumulate wealth and gain
access to credit. It reinforces stigmatizing stereotypes about the disadvantaged and thus
causes discrimination. Segregation also undermines democracy(Anderson, 2010, p. 2).
These arguments are intuitively comprehensible; however,they lack a clear ethical grounding.
Furthermore, they do not resolve the conflict between the standpoint that every individual
deserves the same respect, treatment and opportunities (for whatever reason), and the fact
that these practices make the individual a prisoner of her or his demographics.
Another line of argument is less concerned with the consequences of these initiatives, but
legitimates AA as rectification for historical injustice. In the context of the USA, Jarvis
Thomson (2013) morally justifies the systematic disadvantaging of white males through AA
in two ways. First, the potential that they might have benefitted from policies that have
advantaged them in the past. Second, she derives its legitimacy from the competitive
advantage that, in her opinion, was available to white males through their higher level of
confidence, which was a product of their higher status ( Jarvis Thomson, 2013). Others take
the same line by arguing that disadvantaging certain individuals because of their
demographics or group membership is legitimate when this membership is related to certain
competitive advantages that non-members do not receive, or have not received in the past.
From this perspective, reverse discrimination seems to be justified, as being a compensation
for disadvantaging that has been experienced in the past (Boxill, 1972; Sher, 1975). Since the
group memberships in question (such as being female, white, transgender and heterosexual)
have not been chosen by their members, Lippert-Rasmussen (2017) categorizes these
arguments as innocent beneficiary argument[s] for affirmative action(LippertRasmussen,
2017, p. 74), from which its advocates derive the putative obligations of the innocent
beneficiaries of past injustice to benefit the involuntary victims of those past injustices
(Lippert-Rasmussen, 2017, p. 73). However, what is designated justicefrom this
perspective can only count for group averages, since not every individual is perforce a
victim or beneficiary of historic injustice.Disentangling the underlying beneficiary
principle (see, e.g. Butt, 2014) from the concept of luck egalitarianism, Lippert-Rasmussen
443
Moral
value of EDI
(2017) shows that affirmative action is never required by justice because of a duty for the
innocent beneficiaries of past injustice to compensate their victims(Lippert-Rasmussen,
2017, p. 77). However, from the perspective of luck egalitarianism, striving for some kind of
distributive justice, AA can be justified on the group level, but not as a duty on the
individual level (Lippert-Rasmussen, 2017).
Conclusion, this special issue and future research
Conclusion
Morally evaluating equality, diversity and inclusion remains an under-theorized field. Within
the discourse on equality, diversity and inclusion, the term justiceis predominantly used in a
more intuitive way, and is mostly not rooted in a specific philosophy. Just as there is no sound
general answer to the question is affirmative action just?’”(Lippert-Rasmussen, 2017, p. 76),
one can also not expect an indisputable answer to the question as to whether any approach
toward equality, diversity and inclusion is morally praiseworthy or just. However, much more
critical reflection and theorizing of the moral value (i.e. the moral goodnessor evilness)of
the differing approaches is required. Instead of implicitly applying prescriptive ethics, which
are mostly based on intuitive reasoning, or simple political convictions, future research could
enrich the discourse on the moral evaluation of diversity management, inclusion programs
and organizational equality approaches, with new philosophical facets and perspectives;
perspectives that might differ from those taken in the predominantly American discourse.
This special issue hopes to contribute to this endeavor through the four contributionsincluded
within it.
Articles included in this special issue
The article Ethics and intercultural communication in diversity managementby
Eila Isotalus and Marja-Liisa Kakkuri-Knuuttila demonstrates the need for a radically new
approach to diversity management, which shifts the focus in diversity management on
meanings and communication. The central role of meanings should be obvious, with the
perception that all diversity categories (such as sexual orientation, race, gender, etc.) are
loaded with contextually varying cultural meanings. Furthermore, these diversity categories
are neither ethically nor politically neutral, hence presenting the challenge of deconstructing
value hierarchies, detrimental both from the ethical and economic perspectives. To improve
the team performance and product quality, team members need to overcome stereotypical
categorizations, and get to know each others methods of thinking and acting. For the
development of the dialogical skills needed to promote healthy communication practices, the
paper introduces negotiating reality dialogue developed by Ariane Berthoin Antal and Victor
Friedman. Because putting such diversity management measures into practice presupposes
both emotional and cognitive development, its challenges are discussed in terms of
Aristotelian virtue ethics.
The article Justice as fairness in the workplace: A trajectory for managing diversityby
Pradeepa Dahanayake, Diana Rajendran, Christopher Selvarajah and Glenda Ballantyne
extends the discourse on the moral evaluation of diversity management, inclusion programs
and organizational equality approaches, by introducing conceptual tools to bridge the gap
between literature on organizational justice and diversity management, and by the empirical
analysis of two cases highlighting the significance of this approach. The conceptual
analysis consists of: first, presenting four categories of workplace justice (distributive,
procedural, interpersonal and informational justice) and four theories of justice (equity
theory, social exchange theory and John Rawls and Amartya Sens theories of social
justice); and, second, discussing their relevance to diversity management. Both of the two
cases consist of comparing diversity practices and consequences in two organizations in
Australia with the help of the conceptualization of justice and fairness as described.
444
EDI
37,5
Two organizations are compared with respect to their gender pay inequity measures; the
other two with respect to their means of coping with cultural diversity. Significant
differences between the compared organizations yield a vivid picture of the complexity of
issues linking justice and diversity management.
The article HPWS and climate for inclusion: A moral legitimacy lensby Jennifer
Harrison, Janet Boekhorst, and Yin Yu offers a conceptual model to expand the notion of
climate for inclusion (CFI) to include moral legitimacy assessments of employees on the
organizations human relations policies, specified as high-performance work systems
(HPWS). The moral legitimacy assessments of inclusion-oriented HPWS are conceptualized
through the application of Suchmans (1995) four categories: structural, procedural,
consequential and personal. In the model, the employees moral identity is offered as a factor
influencing the persons assessment of each of the four dimensions. To form a collective
evaluation of CFI, the variability of climate assessments between organizational groups,
such as majority and minority groups, is taken into account as a mediating factor between
individual- and collective-level perceptions.
Looking at the most significant international documents on disability, the article
Remarks on Disability Rights Legislationby John-Stewart Gordon and Felice Tavera-
Salyutov reviews the history of disability rights legislation. Drawing on the concept of
human rights,the authors identify patterns that in future could be crucial for the
disability movement. They describe a fully inclusive and allembracing society as a
utopian goal that it is worth striving for a goal that only can be reached when people with
impairments are fully included.
Future research
Future research could continue to derive the moral value, or question the value, of
different approaches to EDI from the perspective of specific moral philosophies. Future
research might also apply a perspective of deontological (e.g. Hegel, 1821, 1991; Kant,
1785, 2011, or others), asking whether organizations and/or individuals within these
organizations do indeed have an obligation or duty (or even responsibility) toward
approaching equality, diversity and inclusion in a certain way. The question might be
asked, from the perspective of virtue ethics (e.g. Anscombe, 1958; Aquinas, 1570; Aristotle,
2000; Plato, 1907, or others), as to whether there is a virtuous way of approaching EDI
within organizations, and, if so, what the most virtuous way might be. From a utilitarian
perspective (e.g. Bentham, 1789; Mill, 1863, or others) the question might be asked as to
how organizations, or individuals within organizations, should approach EDI in order to
maximize categories such as welfare, happiness, autonomy, etc. From these perspectives,
or from the perspective of other moral philosophies, research might question how existing
organizational or individual approaches to EDI can be evaluated morally. Another
research stream could focus on the role of the incentives of organizations or individuals in
their efforts regarding EDI. The question might be posed as to how genuine incentives
determine the moral praiseworthiness/blameworthiness of organizational approaches to
EDI (e.g. applying ethics from Hume, 1751; Schopenhauer, 1860, 2010, or others). Future
research could also examine more closely how the attribution of moral worth to different
approaches to EDI might be unmasked and deconstructed as a mere means to other ends.
Philosophical perspectives on the notional and moral worth of equality and inequality as
such could be developed further. Research could examine whether (certain) organizational
inequalities could be just,morally acceptable, or even morally praiseworthy, or even
whether equality is a moral category at all. Future research could also direct its attention
toward moral perspectives of quota systems and AAs, asking what kind of understanding
of equalitythese measures express, and how (dis)advantaging of certain groups of
employees can be evaluated morally.
445
Moral
value of EDI
References
Acker, J. (2006), Inequality regimes: gender, class, and race in organizations,Gender & Society, Vol. 20
No. 4, pp. 441-464.
Anderson, E. (2010), The Imperative of Integration, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Anscombe, G.E.M. (1958), Modern moral philosophy,Philosophy, Vol. 33 No. 124, pp. 1-19.
Aquinas, T. (1570), editio Piana, Santa Maria sopra Minerva, Rome.
Aristotle (2000), Nicomachean Ethics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Barclays (2002), Success through inclusion: equality and diversity at Barclays,Human Resource
Management International Digest, Vol. 10 No. 7, pp. 9-12.
Bentham, J. (1789), Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Thomas Payne and Son at
the Mews Gate, London.
Berger, M.T. and Guidroz, K. (2010), The Intersectional Approach: Transforming the Academy Through
Race, Class, and Gender, University of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill, NC.
Bies, R.J. (2015), Interactional justice: looking backward, looking forward, in Cropanzano, R.S. and
Ambrose, M.L. (Eds), The Oxford Handbook of Justice in the Workplace, Oxford University Press,
New York, NY, pp. 89-107.
Blaine, B.E. and McClure Brenchley, K.J. (2018), Understanding the Psychology of Diversity,
Sage Publications, London.
Boxill, B.R. (1972), The morality of reparation,Social Theory and Practice, Vol. 2 No. 1, pp. 113-123.
Brewis, D.N. (2017), Social justice lite? Using emotion for moral reasoning in diversity practice,
Gender, Work & Organization, Vol. 24 No. 5, pp. 519-532.
Butt, D. (2014), “‘A doctrine quite new and altogether untenable: defending the beneficiary pays
principle,Journal of Applied Philosophy, Vol. 31 No. 4, pp. 336-348.
Byrd, M.Y. (2018), Does HRD have a moral duty to respond to matters of social injustice?,Human
Resource Development International, Vol. 21 No. 1, pp. 3-11.
Choi, S. and Rainey, H.G. (2014), Organizational fairness and diversity management in public
organizations,Review of Public Personnel Administration, Vol. 34 No. 4, pp. 307-331.
Cox, T. (1994), Cultural Diversity in Organizations: Theory, Research and Practice, Berrett-Koehler
Publishers, San Francisco, CA.
Dahlerup, D. (2007), Electoral gender quotas: between equality of opportunity and equality of result,
Representation, Vol. 43 No. 2, pp. 73-92.
Demuijnck, G. (2009), Non-discrimination in human resources management as a moral obligation,
Journal of Business Ethics, Vol. 88 No. 1, pp. 83-101.
Fleurbaey, M., Peragine, V. and Ramos, X. (2017), Ex post inequality of opportunity comparisons,
Social Choice and Welfare, Vol. 49 No. 3, pp. 577-603.
Frankfurt, H. (1987), Equality as a moral ideal,Ethics, Vol. 98 No. 1, pp. 21-43.
Fujimoto, Y., Härtel, C.E.J. and Azmat, F. (2013), Towards a diversity justice management model:
integrating organizational justice and diversity management,Social Responsibility Journal,
Vol. 9 No. 1, pp. 148-166.
Greene, A.-M. (2015), Equal opportunities, in Schmitz, J. (Ed.), Wiley Encyclopedia of Management,
John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, London, pp. 1-6.
Guarnieri, R. and Kao, T. (2008), Leadership and CSR-a perfect match: how top companies for leaders
utilize CSR as a competitive advantage,People and Strategy, Vol. 31 No. 3, pp. 34-41.
Hegel, G.W.F. (1821), Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im
Grundrisse, Nicolaische Buchhandlung, Berlin.
Hegel, G.W.F. (1991), Elements of the Philosophy of Right, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
446
EDI
37,5
Heres, L. and Benschop, Y. (2010), Taming diversity: an exploratory study on the travel of a
management fashion,Equality, Diversity and Inclusion: An International Journal, Vol. 29 No. 5,
pp. 436-457.
Hume, D. (1751), An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, Andrew Millar, London.
Jarvis Thomson, J. (2013), Preferential hiring, in Cahn, S.M. (Ed.), The Affirmative Action Debate,
Routledge, London, pp. 35-50.
Jewson, N. and Mason, A. (1986), The theory and practice of equal opportunities policies: liberal and
radical approaches,The Sociological Review, Vol. 34 No. 2, pp. 307-334.
Jones, K.P., King, E.B., Nelson, J., Geller, D.S. and Bowes-Sperry, L. (2013), Beyond the business case:
an ethical perspective of diversity training,Human Resource Management, Vol. 52 No. 1,
pp. 55-74.
Kaler, J. (2001), Diversity, equality, morality, in Noon, M. and Ogbonna, E. (Eds), Equality, Diversity
and Disadvantage in Employment, Palgrave Macmillan, London, pp. 51-64.
Kant, I. (1785), Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, Johann Friedrich Hartknoch, Riga.
Kant, I. (2011), Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals: A German-English Edition, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Kim, J. and Siddiki, S. (2018), Linking diversity of collaborative policymaking venues with procedural
justice perceptions: a study of US marine aquaculture partnerships,The American Review of
Public Administration, Vol. 48 No. 2, pp. 159-174.
Klarsfeld, A., Ng, E., Booysen, L., Castro Christiansen, L. and Kuvaas, B. (2016), Comparative equality
and diversity: main findings and research gaps,Cross Cultural & Strategic Management,
Vol. 23 No. 3, pp. 394-412.
Köllen, T. (2016), Acting out of compassion, egoism, and malice: a schopenhauerian view on the moral
worth of CSR and diversity management practices,Journal of Business Ethics, Vol. 138 No. 2,
pp. 215-229.
Kulik, C.T. (2014), Working below and above the line: the research-practice gap in diversity
management,Human Resource Management Journal, Vol. 24 No. 2, pp. 129-144.
Leitner, S. (2003), Varieties of familialism: the caring function of the family in comparative
perspective,European Societies, Vol. 5 No. 4, pp. 353-375.
Liff, S. and Wajcman, J. (1996), “‘Samenessand differencerevisited: which way forward for equal
opportunity initiatives?,Journal of Management Studies, Vol. 33 No. 1, pp. 79-94.
LippertRasmussen, K. (2017), Affirmative action, historical injustice, and the concept of beneficiaries,
Journal of Political Philosophy, Vol. 25 No. 1, pp. 72-90.
Lorbiecki, A. and Jack, G. (2000), Critical turns in the evolution of diversity management,British
Journal of Management, Vol. 11 No. S1, pp. S17-S31.
McMillanCapehart, A. (2005), A configurational framework for diversity: socialization and culture,
Personnel Review, Vol. 34 No. 4, pp. 488-503.
Martínez-Ariño, J., Moutselos, M., Schönwälder, K., Jacobs, C., Schiller, M. and Tandé, A. (2018), Why
do some cities adopt more diversity policies than others? A study in France and Germany,
Comparative European Politics, pp. 1-22 (in press).
Mill, J.S. (1863), Utilitarianism, Parker, Son & Bourn, London.
Newton, L.H. (1973), Reverse discrimination as unjustified,Ethics, Vol. 83 No. 4, pp. 308-312.
Nietzsche, F. (1954), Thus Spoke Zarathustra: A Book for None and All, Penguin Books,
Harmondsworth.
Nkomo, S.M. (2014), Inclusion: old wine in new bottles?, in Ferdman, B.M. and Deane, B.R. (Eds),
Diversity at Work: The Practice of Inclusion, Wiley, New York, NY, pp. 580-592.
OLeary, B.J. and Weathington, B.L. (2006), Beyond the business case for diversity in organizations,
Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal, Vol. 18 No. 4, pp. 283-292.
447
Moral
value of EDI
Oswick, C. and Noon, M. (2014), Discourses of diversity, equality and inclusion: trenchant
formulations or transient fashions?,British Journal of Management, Vol. 25 No. 1, pp. 23-39.
Plato (1907), Platonis Opera, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Romani, L., Holck, L., Holgersson, C. and Muhr, S.L. (2017), Diversity management and the
Scandinavian model: illustrations from Denmark and Sweden, in Özbilgin, M. and Chanlat, J.-F.
(Eds), Management and Diversity, Emerald Publishing Limited, Bingley, pp. 261-280.
Schopenhauer, A. (1860), Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik, F.A. Brockhaus, Leipzig.
Schopenhauer, A. (2010), The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Securius-Carr, C. and Rohr, R. (2018), Educating for inclusive diversity, in Gertz, S.K., Huang, B. and
Cyr, L. (Eds), Diversity and Inclusion in Higher Education and Societal Contexts: International
and Interdisciplinary Approaches, Springer International Publishing, Cham, pp. 97-118.
Sher, G. (1975), Justifying reverse discrimination in employment,Philosophy & Public Affairs,
pp. 159-170, doi: 10.1057/s41295-018-0119-0.
Singh, V., Vinnicombe, S. and James, K. (2006), Constructing a professional identity: how young female
managers use role models,Women in Management Review, Vol. 21 No. 1, pp. 67-81.
Soltani, E., Syed, J., Liao, Y.-Y. and Shahi-Sough, N. (2012), Tackling one-sidedness in equality and
diversity research: characteristics of the current dominant approach to managing diverse
workgroups in Iran,Asia Pacific Journal of Management, Vol. 29 No. 1, pp. 9-37.
Sposato, M., Feeke, S., Anderson-Walsh, P. and Spencer, L. (2015), Diversity, inclusion and the
workplace-equality index: the ingredients for organizational success,Human Resource
Management International Digest, Vol. 23 No. 5, pp. 16-17.
Taylor, P.W. (1973), Reverse discrimination and compensatory justice,Analysis, Vol. 33 No. 6,
pp. 177-182.
van Dijk, H. (2017), (Managing) diversity, in Poff, D.C. and Michalos, A.C. (Eds), Encyclopedia of
Business and Professional Ethics, Springer International Publishing, Cham, pp. 1-4.
van Dijk, H., Meyer, B., van Engen, M. and Loyd, D.L. (2017), Microdynamics in diverse teams:
a review and integration of the diversity and stereotyping literatures,Academy of Management
Annals, Vol. 11 No. 1, pp. 517-557.
van Dijk, H., van Engen, M. and Paauwe, J. (2012), Reframing the business case for diversity: a values
and virtues perspective,Journal of Business Ethics, Vol. 111 No. 1, pp. 73-84.
Vasconcelos, A.F. (2017), Organizational diversity commitment: a web-based investigation,
Management & Marketing, Vol. 12 No. 3, pp. 474-499.
Vertovec, S. (2013), Diversityand the social imaginary,European Journal of Sociology, Vol. 53 No. 3,
pp. 287-312.
Villanueva-Flores, M., Valle, R. and Bornay-Barrachina, M. (2017), Perceptions of discrimination and
distributive injustice among people with physical disabilities: in jobs, compensation and career
development,Personnel Review, Vol. 46 No. 3, pp. 680-698.
Westen, P. (1982), The empty idea of equality,Harvard Law Review, Vol. 95 No. 3, pp. 537-596.
About the authors
Thomas Köllen is Faculty Member at the Department of Organization and Human Resource
Management, at University of Bern, Switzerland. Prior to that, he was Assistant Professor at the
Institute for Gender and Diversity in Organizations (Department of Management), Vienna University of
Economics and Business (WU), Austria. In 2017, he has finished his postdoctoral lecture qualification
(habilitation) at WU Vienna. He has studied in Germany (Friedrich Schiller University, Jena), Italy
(Università di Torino) and Austria (WU Vienna). He was a Doc Team Fellow of the Austrian Academy
of Sciences (200609) and a Visiting Scholar at Goethe University Frankfurt, Germany (2007) and
Universidade Federal Fluminense (UFF) in Niteroi, Brazil (2012). In 2016, he was a Visiting Professor at
Rowe School of Business, Dalhousie University, Halifax, Canada. Dr Köllens academic research
interests include business ethics; issues of gender, gender identity and sexual orientation in
448
EDI
37,5
management and organizations; and national identities and nationalism in the workplace. He has
published articles on these topics in journals such as the International Journal of Human Resource
Management,Journal of Business Ethics,German Journal of Human Resource Management,Philosophy
of Management and Management Research Review. In 2016, he has edited the book Sexual Orientation
and Transgender Issues in Organizations: Global Perspectives on LGBT Workforce Diversity (Springer).
Thomas Köllen is the corresponding author and can be contacted at: thomas.koellen@iop.unibe.ch
Marja-Liisa Kakkuri-Knuuttila is Professor in Philosophy of Management, emerita, Aalto
University School of Business, Helsinki, Finland. She has taught courses on various fields of
philosophy for business students, such as logic, the history of philosophy, the philosophy of social
science, rhetoric and feminist philosophy. Her research into ancient philosophy deals with the structure
of the Socratic dialogue in Plato and Aristotle, and Aristotles methodology of philosophical inquiry.
Research on contemporary issues in the philosophy of social sciences covers, for instance, the nature of
causation and explanation in qualitative research, in particular, and the relevance of Aristotelian
methodology to epistemological debates, and in John Rawlss methodology of reflective equilibrium.
Her present research focuses on ethical commitments in dialogue, and she is active in promoting
dialogical skills and practices in Finland.
Regine Bendl is Professor and the Head of the Institute for Gender and Diversity in Organizations
at WU Vienna. She was Visiting Research Fellow at the Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, Oxford
University and Auckland University of Technology. She got several national and international awards
for her research. Her research and teaching interests include gender and diversity in organizations,
organizing and managing diversity, intersectionality and queer perspectives and subtexts in
organization theories.
449
Moral
value of EDI
... Additionally, our work contributes to the literature by moving past the business case for diversity (Roberson, 2019). That is, we address the lack of theory regarding the moral aspects of diversity (Köllen et al., 2018) by considering how token levels of diversity enable groups to feel credentialed as non-discriminatory. ...
... We argue that moral licensing theory is an appropriate perspective for theorizing about homosocial reproduction because ethical and moral foundations are a fundamental aspect of societal and organizational imperatives to consider and increase diversity within groups and organizations. Organizations pursue diversity for different reasons, including the pursuit of higher levels of performance (Köllen et al., 2018;Roberson, 2019). However, beyond this 'business case' for diversity, organizations have shifted to consider the moral aspects of diversity and have begun to present their diversity practices as morally good and praiseworthy to internal and external stakeholders (Köllen et al., 2018). ...
... Organizations pursue diversity for different reasons, including the pursuit of higher levels of performance (Köllen et al., 2018;Roberson, 2019). However, beyond this 'business case' for diversity, organizations have shifted to consider the moral aspects of diversity and have begun to present their diversity practices as morally good and praiseworthy to internal and external stakeholders (Köllen et al., 2018). Additionally, fostering diversity may be important 'for achieving benefits associated with the symbolic processes of representation and access to power' (Milliken and Martins, 1996, p. 421). ...
Article
Despite significant knowledge on the demographic composition of workgroups, the literature lacks group-level theory that addresses the tendency of work groups with token levels of diversity to maintain their demographic imbalance over time. We explain this phenomenon by extending moral licensing theory to the group level, arguing that a token level of racial or gender diversity leads to the development of a collective moral credential. This credential provides psychological permission for groups to relax their moral strivings, such that they are less likely to question the influence of bias in group member selection decisions, and thus more likely to make subsequent homogenous group member additions. Additionally, we argue that the diversity climates within which groups are embedded can either magnify (i.e., in fairness-focused diversity climates) or mitigate (i.e., in synergy-focused diversity climates) the development of a collective moral credential. Further, we suggest that the effect of token levels of diversity on the development of a collective moral credential can be affected by the prevailing social norms for diversity. Finally, we theorize that the effects of this process can be accentuated by group use of a majority decision rule and attenuated by group use of a unanimous decision rule.
... • Diversity refers to the degree of difference between people in a group, and in the context of DEIB, it is meant to refer to groups of people who are from historically excluded groups and share an identity (e.g., LGBTQ+, BIPOC, religious minorities, Neurodivergent, etc.) (Bernstein et al., 2020;Köllen et al., 2018). • Equity is a means towards achieving equality, through the examination and changing of oppressive and exclusionary systems (Bernstein et al., 2020;Espinoza, 2007;Köllen et al., 2018;MacKenzie, 2020, Stewart, D-L, 2020. ...
... • Diversity refers to the degree of difference between people in a group, and in the context of DEIB, it is meant to refer to groups of people who are from historically excluded groups and share an identity (e.g., LGBTQ+, BIPOC, religious minorities, Neurodivergent, etc.) (Bernstein et al., 2020;Köllen et al., 2018). • Equity is a means towards achieving equality, through the examination and changing of oppressive and exclusionary systems (Bernstein et al., 2020;Espinoza, 2007;Köllen et al., 2018;MacKenzie, 2020, Stewart, D-L, 2020. Equality distributes resources evenly, whereas equity aims to distribute resources based on proportion of need and in consideration of the impacts of both historical and modern-day societal disparities (Bernstein et al., 2020;Espinoza, 2007;Köllen et al., 2018;MacKenzie, 2020). ...
... • Equity is a means towards achieving equality, through the examination and changing of oppressive and exclusionary systems (Bernstein et al., 2020;Espinoza, 2007;Köllen et al., 2018;MacKenzie, 2020, Stewart, D-L, 2020. Equality distributes resources evenly, whereas equity aims to distribute resources based on proportion of need and in consideration of the impacts of both historical and modern-day societal disparities (Bernstein et al., 2020;Espinoza, 2007;Köllen et al., 2018;MacKenzie, 2020). • Inclusion is a means towards achieving belonging and is comprised of the actions an organization takes to ensure individuals feel they are a part of the organization (Bernstein et al., 2020;Ozkazanc-Pan, 2019). ...
Article
Full-text available
In thinking about institutional advancement in higher education, one can often point to the strengths of advancement organizations: advancement practitioners excel at creating and sustaining relationships with alumni and donors; and, have seen great success in fundraising for billions of dollars annually in the United States. Alumni and donors are partners and give back in ways that are meaningful for them. However, through the following research into practice brief, we present a new organizational change model, the ABCS model. This model utilizes change management theory and research along with the tenets of diversity, equity, inclusion, and belonging (DEIB) scholarship and practice to push the field of advancement into a space of deeper understanding and action in the engagement of historically minoritized groups. As advancement organizations make commitments to diversity, equity, inclusion, and belonging, our model moves organizations from a space of "checking the DEIB box" to a sincere and intentional commitment to listening, co-creating, action, and assessment.
... The current knowledge of what is working to address inequality and diversity is lacking with the term "justice" used intuitively rather than rooted in a specific philosophy (Holck 2016;Kollen et al 2018). Galea et al. (2015) argues poor design, weak implementation, or a lack of active maintenance and revision leads to ineffectual diversity processes. ...
Conference Paper
The aim of this study was to examine gender equality and diversity initiatives (GEDI) and the beliefs of those who design, implement and use them, or do not, in male-dominated organizations. Male-dominated industries continue to have the poorest record of gender inclusivity. A qualitative method was selected to investigate the phenomenon in depth, aiming to capture the nuanced experiences and perceptions of individuals from diverse levels, roles, and backgrounds within male-dominated industries, namely construction, engineering, and property development. Male-dominated industries were chosen due to the limited nature of research in the area of equity and the poor numbers of women across most levels and roles. In-depth interviews with twenty-eight (28) men and women were conducted. We performed the content analysis of interview data to determine major constructs and individual and group perceptions. Findings indicate men and women are treated differently in male-dominated organizations and the process of accessing flexibility initiatives offers new challenges for everyone regardless of gender. Moreover, the research highlights a limitation in the type and approach of individual GEDI, signalling a need for a more expansive and inclusive approach. The recognition of the pivotal role of leadership emerged as a key theme, with employees across all levels acknowledging its significance. The study highlights varied expectations from different leadership levels, emphasizing the importance of tailored approaches to leadership in fostering gender equality and diversity. This insight and proposition-style theorizing contribute to the growing discourse on effective GEDI design and implementation within male-dominated industries.
... Knowledge of what works to address inequality is lacking, with the term 'justice' used intuitively rather than rooted in a specific philosophy (Holck, 2016;Kollen et al., 2018). Galea et al. (2015) argues poor design, weak implementation, and a lack of active maintenance and revision leads to ineffectual equity processes. ...
Article
The persistent underrepresentation of women at work questions the value and use of a gender strategy and gender equality and diversity initiatives (GEDI). This study explores equality and equity perceptions of men and women working in male-dominated project-based organizations (PBOs) about their organization's values, behaviors, treatment of employees, and GEDI use. Drawing on an interpretivist paradigm, in-depth interviews from five PBOs were conducted. Findings indicate gendered organizations are not implementing a full range of GEDI, due to their gendered culture and structure. This study identifies important contributions required of leaders in the design and implementation choices for effective GEDI.
... Clearly, people of certain demographic groups were (and are) subject to systematic discrimination, while others have traditionally enjoyed a privileged, higher status. Indeed, the guiding values for alternative organizing-autonomy, solidarity and responsibility-harbor the potential to foster diversity, in particular by supporting the moral rather than the business case (Köllen et al., 2018;Robinson & Dechant, 1997;van Dijk et al., 2012). Hence, alternative organizations must today consider a range of subject positions of diversity such as gender, age, ethnicity, sexual orientation, religious beliefs or disability. ...
Article
Full-text available
Reflecting current debates on ‘organizational virtues’ as going beyond the capitalocentrist bias of contemporary economies and to see diversity as ‘ethical responsibility,’ this article explores ‘ethical organizing’ at the intersection of alternative organizations and diversity. Our interest in a diversity-oriented analysis of alternative organizations stems from the assumption that those which question taken-for-granted notions of existing economies and follow alternative values of autonomy, solidarity, and responsibility might also be likely to challenge existing diversity relations and, thus, potentially open up new avenues for ethical organizing. Discussing our findings in terms of Lewis and Simpson’s (in)visibility vortex, our study shows that even though organizations position themselves discursively as ‘alternative,’ this positioning is not related to diversity issues. We conclude that a shift is needed to fully constitute ethical organizing, namely the establishment of a strong connection between alternative organizations’ virtues with, e.g., the feminist, anti-racist, queer, and disability rights movements.
Article
Full-text available
Purpose This article examines the organizational learning processes of multinational corporations (MNCs) regarding diversity equality and inclusion (DEI) practices as they aim to implement them across borders. Design/methodology/approach Drawing on 22 semi-structured interviews with managers responsible for DEI in MNCs, we adopt a qualitative inductive research approach. Findings We adopt an organizational learning lens to unpack the continuous learning processes that consist of an interrelated mix of sharing insights, transferring successful practices and adapting initiatives to fit local realities. These processes take place within an entity (intra-organizational), between entities (inter-organizational) and in interaction with external bodies (extra-organizational) taking the form of transactive memory systems and online learning communities to tap into lived experience and local knowledge. Originality/value Our findings contribute to the literature on organizational learning in MNCs and global diversity management by revealing the complex, multi-directional nature of learning processes in implementing global DEI initiatives.
Chapter
Artificial Intelligence (AI) seems omnipotent and ubiquitous in the workplace, but managers and employees have mixed views about its merits in practice. In this chapter, the opportunities and constraints of AI-driven management policy and practices are critically discussed, through an in-depth review of both conceptual research and empirical study, drawing on three theoretical perspectives (i.e., job replacement, psychological contract, and demands-resources theories). Following the theories-informed analyses, four meaningful discoveries are revealed. These are: (i) a manager’s experiences, attitude, and understanding of AI are highly influential, which in turn may affect the design and implementation of AI-driven management policies; (ii) the utility of AI-driven management policies does not necessarily guarantee productivity and should not be treated as an elixir to fix poor employee performance; (iii) managers are liable to learn AI and understand its characteristics prior to the implementation of AI-driven management policies; where applicable, a dry-run or pilot practice should be arranged in advance; and (iv) managers should remain cautious of AI’s influence in their managerial practices, as AI has the potential to become a job-demand or job-resource, affecting their employees either psychologically or behaviorally. In conclusion, the current chapter aims to offer new unique insights to AI-driven management literature, hence advancing knowledge in the field of AI policymaking and managerial practices. Limitations and suggestions for future studies are also discussed.
Article
Full-text available
An increasing sociocultural heterogeneity of populations and vocal demands for the recognition of diversity have become common features of, in particular, cities in Western Europe. Do cities reshape policies in response to such developments? And to what extent do they implement policies that accommodate difference? We use data from an original survey of urban policy actors in the twenty largest cities of France and Germany to identify city-level diversity policy instruments. In both countries, such instruments are widespread, contradicting assumptions of dominant assimilationist paradigms. And yet, the degree of adoption across cities varies. Drawing on institutionalist theory, we investigate what might explain differing adoption rates. The main finding is that key determinants at the urban level differ between the two countries. In France, the political constellation is crucial; higher numbers of diversity policies are associated with centre-left dominance. In contrast, in German cities, political consensus around diversity policies seems to prevail and higher adoption rates are associated with higher population diversity. Our findings provide a first wide-ranging account of the adoption of diversity policy instruments in European cities. They demonstrate that such policies exist at a relevant scale. They further help explain why the adoption of diversity policy instruments is uneven.
Article
Full-text available
In this paper we propose different criteria to rank income distributions according to equality of opportunity. Different from existing ones, our criteria explicitly recognize the interplay between circumstances and effort. We characterize them axiomatically and we compare them with existing criteria; then we propose some scalar measures. We show that our ex post criteria are mostly obtained from “seemingly” ex ante properties. In the second part of the paper we apply our new criteria to measuring inequality of opportunity in Germany. We illustrate our ex-post inequality of opportunity approach based on classes by means of the German Socio-Economic Panel (SOEP) for the first decade of the 2000s.
Article
Full-text available
The purpose of this study is to examine organizational held values and beliefs related to diversity, particularly derived from the corporate websites of the best companies to work for in Brazil, that is, an annual edition published by Época magazine along with the Great Place to Work® Institute (GPTW). Therefore, this study focuses on how these companies are addressing the themes of diversity, inclusion, and discrimination through their organizational discourses. More specifically, it draws exclusively on the statements and corporative documents posted on their websites. Overall, findings indicated that barely 57 (43.8%) of the 130 companies awarded by GPTW-Época 2014’s list showed some interest in providing a discourse toward diversity/inclusion issues in their websites. Moreover, no more than 31 firms (54.4% of the sample) depicted a compelling or somewhat acceptable diversity discourse (i.e., an indication that this issue has been addressed, yet it requires additional measures). Taken as a whole, results suggest that diversity appears to be a topic of low status in the most of the best organizations to work for in Brazil. In general, multinational corporations tend to put aside desirable aspects on their statements, even so they enact better diversity, inclusion, and anti-discrimination discourses than Brazilian firms.
Chapter
Full-text available
Article
Full-text available
Purpose This study examines whether disabled workers perceive negative workplace experiences in terms of discrimination. The purpose of this paper is to study the effects of perceived distributive injustice at work, regarding three dimensions – job assignment, compensation and career development opportunities – on perceived discrimination and explore the mediation role of perceived discrimination in the relationship between perceived distributive injustice and the job dissatisfaction. Design/methodology/approach Research hypotheses are tested with a questionnaire administered to 107 disabled employees working in public and private Spanish organisations. Findings The results indicate that physically disabled people perceive distributive injustice and discrimination at work regarding job assignment, compensation and career development opportunities in Andalusian organisations, and this perception of discrimination leads to feel dissatisfaction. This study confirms the triple dimensionality of two of the variables studied: perceived distributive injustice at work and perceived discrimination at work. Originality/value Few studies have focussed on disability-related issues from a human resource management viewpoint. This study focusses on job assignments, compensation and career development and shows that the perception of discrimination mediates the relation between the perception of distributive injustice at work, and job dissatisfaction. That is, perceived distributive injustice in the organisation leads physically disabled employees to compare their situation with that of their non-disabled peers and thus to perceive discrimination regarding job assignment, compensation and career development opportunities. As a result, they become dissatisfied with their jobs. The results obtained allow us to extend the organisational justice framework, achieving a more thorough understanding of the perception of both injustice and discrimination.
Chapter
Charlotte Securius-Carr and Reiner Rohr discuss the efforts of the German-American Fulbright Commission to promote educational and cultural exchange between Germany and the United States in this chapter on inclusive diversity. They present the inception of the Commission’s focus on inclusive diversity; the new program initiatives promoted by the U.S. Department of State, with the support of the German Foreign Office and the German Government’s Transatlantic Program through ERP funds of the Federal Ministry for Economic Affairs and Energy; and their various successful attempts to launch transatlantic dialogues. After more than ten years, they have been able to establish, both at the Commission and among German higher education partners, a firm awareness of and appreciation for the importance of diversity in higher education exchanges.
Chapter
Equal opportunities (EO) is a label for policies and practices in employment based on a principle of non-discrimination. It is commonly used in the UK, and is directly comparable to Equal Employment Opportunity in the USA, and Employment Equity in Australia. The identity groups usually covered are women, black, and minority ethnic people, disabled people, lesbian and gay people, and younger and older people (under 25 and over 45 years). The liberal and radical models of EO are presented, distinguishing between approaches based around sameness or difference, groups or individuals, and equality of opportunity or outcome. Various associated policy formations are discussed including positive action, affirmative action, and positive discrimination. The main debates within the literature offering a critique of EO are also highlighted.
Article
The purpose of this article is to question whether or not social injustice should matter to human resource development (HRD). The goal is to invoke a sense of moral agency and responsiveness within the HRD community for having more candid and open conversations about social injustice and the lived experiences of marginalized individuals. In this article, a social justice paradigm will be suggested as a dedicated platform for studying social justice as a necessary outcome of social injustice. Organizational social justice will be introduced as a progressive workplace norm that envisions an equal balance of social justice outcomes for all members in organizations and places of work.