PreprintPDF Available

The Powers of Testosterone: Obscuring Race and Regional Bias in the Regulation of Women Athletes

Authors:
Preprints and early-stage research may not have been peer reviewed yet.

Abstract

Abstract Using strategies from critical race studies and feminist studies of science, medicine and the body, we examine the covert operation of race and region in a regulation restricting the natural levels of testosterone in women athletes. Sport organizations claim the rule promotes fair competition and benefits the health of women athletes. Intersectional and postcolonial analyses have shown that “gender challenges” of specific women athletes engage racialized judgments about sex atypicality that emerged in the context of Western colonialism and are at the heart of Western modernity. Here, we introduce the concept of “T talk” to refer to the web of direct claims and indirect associations that circulate around testosterone as a material substance and a multi-valent cultural symbol. In the case we discuss, T talk naturalizes the idea of sport as a masculine domain while deflecting attention from the racial politics of intra-sex competition. Using regulation documents, scientific publications, media coverage, in-depth interviews, and sport officials’ public presentations we show how this supposedly neutral and scientific regulation targets women of color from the Global South. Contrary to claims that the rule is beneficent, both racialization and medically-authorized harms are inherent to the regulation. Keywords: health / hyperandrogenism / racialization / sex and gender / science / sport / T talk / violence
1
Draft: April 25, 2018
Citation: Karkazis, Katrina and Rebecca M. Jordan-Young, “The Powers of Testosterone:
Obscuring Race and Regional Bias in the Regulation of Women Athletes,” forthcoming Feminist
Formations, summer 2018.
The Powers of Testosterone: Obscuring Race and Regional Bias in the
Regulation of Women Athletes
Katrina Karkazis and Rebecca M. Jordan-Young*
* Both authors contributed equally to this manuscript.
Katrina Karkazis, PhD, MPH
Senior Visiting Fellow
Global Health Justice Partnership
Yale University
katrina.karkazis@yale.edu
Rebecca M. Jordan-Young, PhD
Women's, Gender, & Sexuality Studies
Barnard College
3009 Broadway
New York, NY 10027
ryoung@barnard.edu
This is a draft copy of a manuscript accepted by Feminist Formations. Upon publication, the
copyright will be assigned to the publisher, the Johns Hopkins University Press.
2
Abstract
Using strategies from critical race studies and feminist studies of science, medicine and the body,
we examine the covert operation of race and region in a regulation restricting the natural levels
of testosterone in women athletes. Sport organizations claim the rule promotes fair competition
and benefits the health of women athletes. Intersectional and postcolonial analyses have shown
that “gender challenges” of specific women athletes engage racialized judgments about sex
atypicality that emerged in the context of Western colonialism and are at the heart of Western
modernity. Here, we introduce the concept of “T talk” to refer to the web of direct claims and
indirect associations that circulate around testosterone as a material substance and a multi-valent
cultural symbol. In the case we discuss, T talk naturalizes the idea of sport as a masculine
domain while deflecting attention from the racial politics of intra-sex competition. Using
regulation documents, scientific publications, media coverage, in-depth interviews, and sport
officials’ public presentations we show how this supposedly neutral and scientific regulation
targets women of color from the Global South. Contrary to claims that the rule is beneficent,
both racialization and medically-authorized harms are inherent to the regulation.
Keywords: health / hyperandrogenism / racialization / sex and gender / science / sport / T talk /
violence
3
Prelude 1: Olympic Summer Games, Rio de Janeiro, 2016
Long after the last competitor left Rio, a decidedly un-Olympic image haunted our memories.1
At the finish line of the women’s 800m final, South African runner Caster Semenya extends her
arms to fellow competitors Melissa Bishop of Canada and Lynsey Sharp of Great Britain, who
are locked in a tight embrace. Semenya has just won the gold; Sharp has placed sixth and Bishop
has taken fourth. The two disregard Semenya’s gesture, remaining closed in one another’s arms.
The photo was a sad endnote to a vitriolic media uproar that had raged intermittently for
years and especially during the month leading up to the race, sounding unfairly on Semenya’s
right to compete. For the seven years since the International Association of Athletics Federations
(IAAF) broke their own confidentiality policy and confirmed it was investigating her under its ad
hoc “gender verification” policy, Semenya has endured relentless hostility and a deluge of cruel
harassment from both the traditional and online media. Of the investigation, she has said, “I have
been subjected to unwarranted and invasive scrutiny of the most intimate and private details of
my being” (Associated Press 2010). In intervening years, the extraordinary scrutiny from
journalists and the public has persisted. A security team was reportedly provided for her in Rio
due to concerns the hostility might turn violent (Brook 2016). South Africa as a nation pushed
back with #handsoffcaster and a petition to stop bullying created by “People against racist
bullies” (Amandla Awethu 2016).
Semenya is the world’s most scrutinized and violated athlete despite having done nothing
wrong. She has neither doped nor cheated. She also has the support of the Court of Arbitration
4
for Sport (CAS), the world’s highest adjudicating body for sport (CAS 2015). A year earlier,
CAS slapped a two-year suspension on the IAAF regulation which, along with an analogous
regulation adopted by the International Olympic Committee (IOC), places a ceiling on a woman
athlete’s natural testosterone (T) level (IAAF 2011, IOC 2012).2,3 IAAF and IOC officials claim
that high T is a “male” trait, that T is the “main reason” men generally outperform women in
tests of strength and speed, and that women with high T (whom they call “hyperandrogenic”)
therefore have an “unfair” advantage over their competitors. Under the regulation, if a woman
athlete’s natural T level is deemed by the IAAF to give her “unfair” advantage, she must lower it
through surgery or drugs, or forego competing forever.
But when teenaged Indian sprinter Dutee Chand challenged the same IAAF regulation in
2015, the arbitrators at CAS ruled in her favor. They found that the IAAF had failed to
demonstrate that the policy was scientifically justified. The IAAF had not provided sufficient
evidence that female athletes with T levels in the “male range” have a performance advantage
over their peers with lower T levels that is comparable to what men have over women. The
arbitrators suspended the regulation for two years allowing the IAAF this period to return to
CAS with sufficient scientific evidence, or else the policy would be void.
Semenya was first targeted in fall 2009, fifteen months before this T regulation took
effect. The agreement between Semenya and the IAAF that allowed her to return to competition
in 2010 has never been released. Nevertheless, the ire of those unhappy with the suspension of
the regulations has been focused squarely on Semenya. She is the athlete they single out as
supposedly proving not only the need for a regulation, but T’s unparalleled role in athletic
5
performance (e.g., McRae 2016, O’Sullivan 2016). Observers have attributed her athleticism to a
single molecule—testosterone—as though it alone earned her the gold, undermining at once her
skill, preparation and achievement.
In writing of Semenya, we risk repeating the problems raised so eloquently by Neville
Hoad (2010) and Keguro Macharia (2009) including our own “participat[ion] in an ongoing
spectacularization” (Macharia). Hoad questions “broaching the topic at all. Caught in a double
demand to resist spectacularizing Semenya in the long and intractable representational history of
racialized and sexualized African bodies, and a participation in a LGBTQ praxis of freedom that
wants to render visible and celebrate gender variance (here the speed, grace, power and beautiful
butchness of Semenya), finding an ethical entry into the question of Caster Semenya becomes
difficult” (398). Feeling this double bind, in an earlier piece, we included a discussion of
Semenya that soon thereafter filled us with deep regret for our complicity in this
spectacularization (Karkazis et al. 2012). Among other harms, we made repeated references to
her “case”—a distancing, medicalizing and, ultimately, dehumanizing way to refer to her. In this
paper, we felt that no mention of her might serve as a cultural lobotomy that was equally
distancing. We thus decided to do so in a way that resists the dominant story with counter
narratives, details, and context that seek to underscore the human(s) at the core of this regulation
without recapitulating harm and without erasing what is ugly and painful here that requires
daylight.
On the eve of the 2016 Olympics, IAAF president Sebastian Coe announced that the
organization would challenge the suspension of the regulation (Guardian Sport 2016), repeating
6
this avowal just before the 800m finals with a timing that seemed specifically aimed to cast
doubt on Semenya’s right to compete. “We were surprised by the CAS decision, and I think the
IOC was too,” Coe said after a meeting of the IAAF Council. “We are looking again at this issue
and will be talking to CAS at some time over the next year” (Rowbottom 2016). Coe
immediately followed this statement with a half-hearted reminder that “these are human beings,”
likely knowing that his comments would throw into question not only Semenya’s participation
but possibly others’ too. With a tinderbox left smoldering, one breath of accusation was all that
was needed to reignite the “debate.” As if determined to maintain a veil of suspicion over these
athletes, Coe subsequently made similar pronouncements during both the 2017 Asian Athletics
Championships held in Chand’s hometown of Bhubaneswar, India and the 2017 World
Championships in Athletics held in London.
It is no surprise, then, that athletes such as Sharp, who have also worked hard and
sacrificed for their sport, seemed to feel frustrated and usurped even though they were not. Or
that in their anger, grace failed them. Poland’s Joanna Jozwik, who finished fifth between Bishop
and Sharp, bitterly called into question the three black medalists, saying: “I’m glad I’m the first
European, the second white.” It is impossible to miss the optics of this controversy—the three
black women from sub-Saharan Africa ebullient on the podium and the three white Global North
women feeling they should be there instead. These polarized perspectives reflect the racial
politics that shape the T regulation and its asymmetrical burdens and benefits.
Prelude 2: Marseilles, France, IAAF Specialist Reference Center
7
The scrutiny aimed at Semenya was achingly personal for her, but not unique. Other women
from the Global South have also been subject to physical and psychological invasions under this
regulation. In 2013, doctors affiliated with the IAAF published a report that gives insight into
what happens when women are investigated under this regulation.
Four young women, aged 18-21 and from “rural and mountainous regions of developing
countries,” were identified through various means as having high T, and were each sent to the
IAAF-approved specialist reference center in southern France for a work-up to see whether they
were intersex (Fenichel et al. 2013).4 A large, multi-disciplinary team of clinicians conducted
extensive investigations aimed at assessing sex-linked biology, beginning with endocrine,
karyotype, and genetic analyses. They also inspected the women’s breasts, genitals, body hair
patterns, internal reproductive organs, and basic body morphology in detail, and interviewed
them as to gender identity, behavior, and sexuality. From these exams, the doctors determined
that these women had testes and high functional testosterone levels. By using the term
“functional T,” the authors signal that the women’s bodily tissues respond to T and thus that they
do not have any condition that renders their tissues insensitive to the hormone. Although the
doctors acknowledged that leaving the women’s testes intact “carries no health risk,” they also
told the women that gonadectomy would “allow them to continue elite sport in the female
category.” But the medical team aimed for more than lowering T. The doctors’ “proposed” the
surgical and medical interventions long practiced for gender normalization of people with
atypical sex-linked biology (intersex), including “a partial clitoridectomy with a bilateral
8
gonadectomy, followed by a deferred feminizing vaginoplasty and estrogen replacement
therapy” (Fenichel et al., E1057).
The genital surgeries described in the report suggest that something beyond T and athletic
performance motivates the regulation, and indicate that it’s not just compliance with the T
regulation that drives the interventions. Martin Ritzén, a pediatric endocrinologist specializing in
children with atypical sex-linked biology (intersex), who was a key architect of the IAAF
regulation, was reportedly “furious” about the genital surgeries, declaring that they were “against
the rules of the IAAF” (de Visser 2013). Although the report on the four women was co-authored
by Stéphane Bermon, the IAAF’s then medical director, the paper’s publication nevertheless
angered other IAAF officials. Interviewed for a Dutch newspaper, an unnamed IAAF official
said of the publication, “This is a flagrant violation of professional secrecy” (de Visser)
indicating that the IAAF had violated its own “principle” of “respect for confidentiality in the
medical process and the need to avoid public exposure of young females with hyperandrogenism
who may be psychologically vulnerable” (IAAF 2011, 1). An IAAF official interviewed by Lisa
Bavington in 2013 called the publication “unfortunate” and said that had he did not know about
its existence “until it was too late for the authors to withdraw the paper,” adding that “[s]o far,
you seem to be the only one to pick up this issue, and I hope that no media will try to identify
them” (2016, 154).
The paper violates the athletes’ privacy and confidentiality and should not have been
published. It sheds light, however, on an implementation process that is otherwise kept under
wraps, and further highlights whom this regulation burdens. Sport authorities, through public
9
talks, publications, and interviews, have consistently indicated that the women investigated for
high levels of naturally occurring T are exclusively from the Global South, and all indications are
that they are black and brown women.5 Because race is not a biological category, a biological
criterion such as T levels should be race-neutral, applying to women irrespective of ethnoracial
categorization. So why is there racial and regional bias in the regulation’s effects? How are race
and region connected to the problem of “unfair advantage” that this regulation is purportedly
designed to prevent?
Framework
We use critical race theories and feminist studies of science, medicine and the body to examine
the covert operation of race and region in the putatively neutral T regulation. Following scholars
such as Holloway (2011) and Ticktin (2011), who combine critical race studies with feminist
intersectional studies of medicine, we show how this supposedly neutral and scientific regulation
targets women of color from the Global South. Contrary to claims that the rule is beneficial, both
racialization and medically-authorized harms are inherent to the regulation.
We and others have previously demonstrated that the anxieties about “unfair advantage”
codified in this regulation and rehearsed through its application are blatant conflicts over the
boundaries between women and men (Karkazis et al. 2012, Cooky and Dworkin 2013, Karkazis
and Jordan-Young 2015, Henne 2015, Bavington 2016, Browning 2016, Pieper 2016). Sport
officials insist that the T regulation is not “sex testing,” and some of the public controversy over
the regulation has focused on resolving the question of whether it is or is not.6 Here we are
10
primarily concerned with showing that the regulation is indeed yet another version of “sex
testing,” accomplished by racializing sex and by associating “failures” of dichotomous sex with
failures of modernity characteristic of countries or regions outside the industrialized West. Other
scholars have drawn on intersectional and postcolonial analyses to show how discourses on
Semenya’s eligibility engage racialized judgments regarding sex atypicality and non-conformity
that emerged in the context of Western colonialism and that are at the heart of Western
modernity (Nyong’o 2010, Hoad 2010, Munro 2010, Schuhmann 2010, Schultz 2011, Cooky,
Dycus & Dworkin 2013, Doyle 2013, Adjepong and Carrington 2014, Magubane 2014).
Many of these scholars have noted that “sex testing” of women athletes has rested on
invasive genital and physical inspections that are both hauntingly reminiscent and a continuation
of the prurient European gaze directed at black women’s bodies. The experience of Saartjie
Baartman, a black South African Khoikhoi woman, is the quintessential example of European
exploitation and commodification of African women, often enacted under the guise of scientific
progress. Brought to Europe in the early 1880s under false pretenses by a British doctor,
Baartman was displayed mostly naked and often caged before huge crowds in London and Paris,
and in private homes where observers could touch her. In a stunning example of dehumanization,
the renowned naturalist Georges Cuvier arranged for Baartman to be studied by zoologists and
other scientists, and he pronounced her to be “a link between animals and humans.” After her
death, her preserved body parts including her genitals remained on display in Paris’ Musée de
l’Homme until 1974 (SAHO 2017).
11
Munro traces the inspections of women athletes to a “familiar prurient/Enlightenment
will-to-know” which, she notes, works in tandem with racialized ideals about women’s bodies to
construct women who do not fit the ideal as ‘‘pre-modern’’ and “reinforce a post-imperial sense
of the ‘natural’ global order.” Munro argues that in this context “the untamed, ‘simple’ African
body is one that has not yet been streamlined into ‘modern’ norms.” Locating the problem not in
the women’s bodies, but in systems that figure their bodies as problematic or unintelligible,
Doyle observes, “What makes their stories catastrophic are the terrorizing systems that take the
fact of these women’s existences — rather than racism, sexism, or homophobia —as a conflict
that must be resolved” (423).7
While the racial politics of “sex testing” in sport have been critiqued extensively, the
question of how and why black and brown women from the Global South come to be the
exclusive targets of the supposedly new, neutral, and scientific T regulation remains
unanswered.8 Scholars calling attention to the racial and regional politics of this regulation have
pointed out how historic associations of hegemonic femininity with whiteness continue to bring
women of color under particular scrutiny (Karkazis et al. 2012, Cooky and Dworkin 2013, Pieper
2014). In this paper, we go further by examining in detail the systems this regulation participates
in and concretely show how the racialization of gender and national or regional tropes of “the
modern West” are operationalized via this regulation.
“T talk” is a term we developed to signal a web of direct claims and indirect associations
that circulate around testosterone both as a material substance and as a multi-valent cultural
symbol. In the sections that follow, we show how, via T talk, sex biology is reshaped from messy
12
distributions into clean dimorphism, which is re-introduced as the natural state of human
biology; a racialized aesthetic of gender is made to appear “normal/natural” and biological, not
cultural; “sex testing” is disavowed and repackaged as a health intervention “for the good of the
athlete”; and the operations of power and harm in the regulation are inverted—the least
advantaged are figured as “unfairly advantaged,” and the extraordinary harms of interventions
are framed as beneficial.
T talk seamlessly weaves together folklore and science, as scientific claims about T
seemingly validate cultural beliefs about the structure of masculinity and the “natural”
relationship between women and men. T talk includes and goes beyond the “sex hormone”
concept, which has been extensively critiqued by biologists and other feminist scholars for both
shaping the way that scientific information is gathered and interpreted about T, and also actively
blocking the recognition and acceptance of scientific evidence that does not fit the model of
“male” and “female” hormones (Oudshoorn 1994, van den Wijngaard 1997, Fausto-Sterling
2000, Nehm and Young 2008). One indication that the sex hormone concept is still powerful is
that T is constantly coded as “the male sex hormone,” which invites multiple inaccurate
assumptions. For example, tagging T as male signals that T is restricted to men and is dangerous
or a “foreign substance” in women’s bodies, though women also produce T and require it for
healthy functioning. Tagging T as a “sex hormone” signals that T’s functions are restricted to sex
and sex differences, though T is required for a broad range of functions that are common to all
humans and are unrelated to reproductive structures and physiology, such as liver function. With
the sex hormone concept, T and its “partner” estrogen have been framed as a heteronormative
13
pair: binary, dichotomous, and exclusive, with each “belonging” to one sex or the other. They are
viewed as both complementary and antagonistic, locked into an inevitable and natural “war of
the sexes.”
T talk goes beyond the sex hormone concept in at least two ways. First, as a domain of
folklore, T talk is not bound by formal logics or demands for consistency. “T makes men
athletically superior to women” feels like a truth, despite the fact that millions of men the world
over have vastly more T than do ninety-five percent of elite women athletes, yet are not as fast or
as strong as those women. While we have the semi-joking language of “testosterone poisoning”
to naturalize bad behavior in men, testosterone is viewed as actually poisonous only to women.
“Too much T,” medicalized as “hyperandrogenism,” is a concept that does not apply to men,
whereas women whose T values fall outside the typical range are by default assumed to have a
medical problem (even if the woman has no known functional problems).
Second, while T is a synecdoche for masculinity, T can also symbolize biology or nature
in general, as well as science and the associated values of precision and objectivity. Because T is
coded as natural and in the realm of biology, T talk fundamentally serves scientism, which
elevates scientific values, evidence, and authority above all others, even as it paradoxically
obviates the need for evidence. Scientism equates scientific knowledge with knowledge itself,
especially valorizing the natural sciences. Scientism thus lends added weight and substance to
the scientific arguments about the regulation. For example, in the CAS decision, the arbitrators
read a 2012 paper in which we criticized the regulation on both ethical and scientific grounds.
They judged our analysis of ethical principles (e.g., fairness, eligibility and notions of normal;
14
health treatment and the question of medical need; confidentiality leaks and whisper triggers) not
only to be utterly outside the relevant evidence for judging the regulation, but as outside the
purview of “knowledge” itself, calling it “sociological opinion, which does not equate to
scientific and clinical knowledge and evidence” (134).
Following Stephen Colbert, we might say that T lends truthiness to the rationale for the
regulation: unburdened by the factual, the ubiquitous common-sense notion of T as an
overwhelming “super substance” not only substitutes for evidence, but makes calling for
concrete, empirical details about what T actually does for women athletes seem puzzling or
obtuse. In the same 2012 paper that CAS dismissed as irrelevant, we pointed out the lack of
reliable and pertinent data to support the regulation’s grandiose claims about what high T does to
and for women athletes. This paper led to numerous media interviews, many of which were
perplexing to us because interviewers had a difficult time grasping, or perhaps believing, that
there was so little evidence linking high T to exceptional athleticism. Short of repeating our full
critique of the evidence on T and athleticism here, a few key points merit attention. Studies in
sports science overwhelmingly confirm that T, while relevant to athleticism, is far from
determinant: T levels cannot predict athletic performance; better-performing athletes do not have
higher T levels (baseline or pre-competition); individual variability in response to T is enormous.
While higher T has been linked to greater strength, speed, and muscle size at the group level, at
the individual level these relationships are inconsistent. Some athletes get little or no benefit
from increased levels of T, while others get considerable benefits. These facts fly in the face of
received wisdom, while the IAAF’s and IOC’s claims fit T folklore neatly. As a result,
15
interviewers often had a hard time accepting our arguments, even when they were accompanied
by concrete scientific references. As a consequence, several interviewers repeatedly questioned
why T is not a good proxy for athleticism.
T talk has both enabled this regulation and has been increasingly elaborated as a post hoc
justification for it. T talk obscures the fact that this regulation is still “sex testing,” T talk also
deflects attention away from the racial politics of intra-sex competition in women’s sport and
diverts attention from structural arrangements and how the regulation under question is about
power asymmetries not only between athletes, but between nations. It is difficult to frame the
harms of the regulation in terms of T: invasion of athletes’ privacy, humiliation, loss of career,
and medically unnecessary surgeries must be discussed on other grounds. Thus, in relation to the
regulation, T talk succeeds in a range of obfuscations and distortions.
T talk is rarely directly about race or about global power relations, which makes this story
challenging to tell. The gender politics of this regulation can be read directly from the texts that
introduce, explain, and justify it, but identifying its co-occurring politics of race and region
requires a different sort of work. Logic and rationality are inadequate guides. Moreover, racial
hierarchies are often not explicit nor are they rational and ordered; they are chaotic and
camouflaged, but operate foundationally. Thus, we must look to the way that the T regulation
and its enforcement alchemizes ideas about gender, race, and “advantage” through sideways
moves, indirect logics, resonances, reinforcements, and disavowals, relying on images and
aesthetics as much as words, and on the wide circulation of unspoken tropes of gender, race, and
16
modernity or civilization (barely hidden within references to nation or region), especially as they
are entangled.
There is not just one story here, but a linked and enmeshed series of distinct and related
narratives. There’s a story about T and advantage, a story about health, a story about ethnic and
regional variations in hyperandrogenism, among others. One common thread in all these stories
is a scientific rationale for and driver of the regulation. Sport officials and other proponents of
the regulation insist that it is only and thoroughly a scientific matter, a domain in which only
explicit language, direct logic, scientific evidence, and deliberate and intended meanings register
as “real.” This piece works in a different register—one of affect, of images, of slips in logic, of
how stories brush up against each other and generate new meanings. Together, the narratives
activate off-stage relationships and assumptions that create strong but implicit associations with
race, a relationship we’ve referred to elsewhere as “race as a ghost variable” (Jordan-Young and
Karkazis 2017).
Two recent feminist studies (Holloway 2011, Ticktin 2011) offer further insight into how
we can understand medically-authorized harms of this regulation as the predictable effect of
power relations, rather than as “accidental” or “incidental” failures of the regulation that
ironically has been promoted as a vehicle for fairness and health. Specific harms are inherent to
the regulation, which was developed within and amplifies the “matrix of domination” (Collins
1990) that distributes power hierarchically along axes of race, sex/gender, and geopolitical
region. In this paper, we show that what happened to the young women described in Prelude 2 is
what Karla Holloway (2011) would call a “predictable failure,” a concept she uses to analyze
17
medical and legal scenarios where, despite a formal right to privacy, particular people are
systematically subject to humiliations and intrusions. These “failures” of privacy are utterly
predictable in light of the specific social location of the individuals involved and the material
scaffolding that supports the supposedly generalized right to privacy. Privacy is not, then, a
general right, but a specific form of privilege that is reserved for those with favored racial,
gender, sexual, class, or national status. This regulation makes some women athletes’ bodies
permanently available for surveillance and public “reading,” probing, and coercion. Our analysis
of this regulation shows that the concept of “predictable failures” applies to other protections,
such as fairness or health, which are constructed around the needs of those who already enjoy
privilege.
To understand how the language of medical benevolence is used to justify surveilling and
intervening on women athletes who have high T, we also draw on Miriam Ticktin’s (2011)
critique of the humanitarianism which perversely enables the harsh, anti-immigrant policies of
contemporary France. While France generally blocks legal status for refugees, migrant laborers,
and other immigrants, humanitarian “exceptions” are extended to those who are recognized as
having undergone “exceptional” suffering, which is medicalized. For example, scars may be
examined and validated by medical personnel as being consistent with having endured torture;
the absence of such scars may make it difficult to be taken seriously as a refugee from violence.
The context of the T regulation is different from the situation Ticktin analyzes in important ways.
Notably, women athletes do not actively seek to be seen as “sick,” but resist it. Nevertheless,
several elements of her analysis serve as a guide for seeing the effects of invoking “care” for the
18
same people who are targeted with special surveillance and intervention, such as the claim that
“suffering” is an objective matter to be judged by medical science, the coupling of bodily
pathology with cultural pathology, and the way in which what she calls “regimes of care” depend
upon a toggling of perspective, such that “suffering victims” are rapidly refigured as dangerous
or delinquent.
The T regulation can be understood as similar to other “regimes of care” in that those
who are targeted for “care” are “visible as victims … and hence in need of help, rescue—not
equal rights” (4-5). As we show, women athletes with high T are not considered to be part of the
group of athletes whose need for “fairness” is supposedly served by this regulation. Framing
interventions to lower T as medical need activates what Ticktin calls a “moral imperative to act”
that justifies practices that can be read as violence done in the name of care. Consequently,
“regimes of care end up reproducing inequalities and racial, gendered, and geopolitical
hierarchies” (Ticktin, 5).
For our larger project, we draw on regulation documents, scientific publications in which
officials describe and defend the regulation, media coverage, and in-depth interviews with
policymakers, athletes, and scientists from 2012 through 2016. Our analysis here leans heavily
on two presentations made by sport officials about this regulation at the 2012 International
Convention on Science, Education and Medicine in Sport (ICSEMIS), the official scientific
conference that accompanies the Olympic Games (Ljungqvist and Bermon 2012). Unlike the
relatively terse text of the IOC regulation and the IAAF’s regulation and explanatory notes, the
presentations were expansive, including both images and information about regulation
19
development and implementation that has never been published. Thus, these presentations make
the “ghost connections” among the regulation, gender, race, and region explicit in a way that
documents alone do not, and show how they exist not in the abstract as formal rules, but how
they intersect with material conditions to produce distinctive effects on specific people.
In the sections that follow, we show how, via T talk, sex biology is reshaped from messy
distributions into clean dimorphism, which is re-introduced as the natural state of human
biology; a racialized aesthetic of gender is made to appear “normal/natural” and biological, not
cultural; “sex testing” is disavowed and repackaged as a health intervention “for the good of the
athlete”; and the operations of power and harm in the regulation are inverted—the least
advantaged are figured as “unfairly advantaged,” and the extraordinary harms of interventions
are framed as beneficial.
Perfect and Modified Phenotypes: T is the Key
The T regulation was officially unveiled a week prior to the 2012 London Olympics just 400
miles north in Glasgow at the ICSEMIS conference. ICSEMIS is an international sport science
conference that stemmed from a 2006 agreement between the IOC and the International
Federation of Sports Medicine (FIMS) among other organizations to put on “one large multi-
disciplinary, professional conference” around the Olympics (ICSEMIS 2016). Designed to bring
together international experts “in professional and academic sectors linked to sports science and
education,” the unveiling of the regulation here, of all places, lent it a scientific air, even if what
followed was far from scientific.
20
One of the two presenters, Stéphane Bermon, a member of the IAAF Medical and Anti-
Doping Commission since 2006, has been the IAAF’s lead player in developing, promoting, and
implementing the regulation. Bermon presented the rationale for banning women with high T,
and in his presentation, we saw T talk in action, especially the opening segment that relied on a
visual argument about male and female forms.
He began with a slide titled “Men and Women: Different Phenotypes” consisting of two
side-by-side images. On the left was Francisco Goya’s late 18th-century masterpiece La Maja
Desnuda, an idealized Venus of a woman: sensual, curved, nude, her opaline skin lustrous [see
figure 1].9 In contrast to that milky complexion is a small thatch of dark pubic hair. Her cheeks
are rosy and her brown hair falls in curly tendrils. She reclines, arms raised behind her head, eyes
looking straight at the viewer: she is so luxuriously sedentary, she looks as though she may never
move from her velvet divan.
The photo on the right could not present a starker contrast. With his oiled, dark brown
skin stretched tight over superhumanly developed muscles, Kenneth “Flex” Wheeler smiles at
the viewer [see figure 2]. The bodybuilder, whom Arnold Schwarzenegger called “one of the
greatest,” stands in a “front lat spread,” a banana-colored Speedo just covering his genitals: fists
on his narrow waist, arms bent at a right angle, pectorals pushed up and protruding out, elbows
pivoting forward, thighs and biceps bulging, with stomach sucked in. Every inch of him is dense,
striated, and rippled. A sculpted, comic book hero with approximately zero body fat, Wheeler is
the very image of power.
21
We do not think we were alone in our surprise when La Maja Desnuda was the image
Bermon displayed as “the female phenotype” in a talk about elite women athletes, nor that he
paired it with that of a 20th century ‘roided out male bodybuilder. Though Bermon
acknowledged that he “took some extreme examples,” even alluding to Wheeler’s myostatin-
inhibiting gene mutation (which allows for nearly unlimited muscle growth), he hewed closely to
these two images as evidence of what should be considered “normal male and female.”
Meanwhile, the ideal female phenotype Bermon presented was not a woman per se, but an
artistic interpretation of one. His choice of Wheeler as the archetypal normal male was also
ironic given that Wheeler is widely known to have doped for nearly two decades, but hardly
surprising since a photo of a pot-bellied man would not have served his visual argument.
Sweeping his own disclaimer aside, Bermon plowed on. “This difference in phenotype of
course explains the difference in performances, because as you know, men are much more
slender, tall, and strength (sic) than female and it’s very easy to be convinced about that.” With a
brisk review of sex differentials in various world records in track and field, Bermon offered an
explanation for men’s consistent dominance: “androgenic levels,” which he explained are ten
times higher in males than females. “So, you clearly see that what we call normal male and
female, we should not have any overlap in testosterone concentration, as well as you do not have
any overlap in world best performances, whatever the event considered.”
Reference to testosterone is all it took to transform a conversation about stereotyped
cultural images into a supposedly scientific presentation. In a series of moves so familiar they
can be hard to see, Bermon built up an argument about sexual dimorphism—the idea that the
22
sexes represent two distinct, non-overlapping forms—and the possibility of reading not just
athleticism but T from the body’s superficial appearance. If high T is what causes Flex
Wheeler’s muscles to bulge and strain, low T must be responsible for La Maja’s lack of
muscular definition, her eroticized softness, her pose that relishes in its own idleness. But what
does T have to do with her whiteness?
Bermon did not make the explicit claim that T is what caused Flex’s darkness, nor lack of
T La Maja’s lightness. But insisting that T is what drives the difference in the male and female
phenotype, and presenting these as black and white, respectively, nonetheless attaches T to a
package of existing associations about race and gender. While Bermon probably did not
consciously or deliberately choose the image of a white woman for this presentation, it could
hardly have been an accident, either: whiteness is an essential part of the traditional image of
ideal femininity in the West. Similarly, the choice of a black male bodybuilder to show the
“extreme phenotype” of masculinity ties into longstanding associations of black men with
hypermasculinity, and blackness in general with athleticism. Keep these pictures in mind as we
follow the rest of Bermon’s presentation.
The next section of Bermon’s talk was an argument about sex dimorphism. To start, he
said that women and men are dimorphic not just in phenotype, but also in sport performance and
in T levels. To make this argument he began with a table comparing women’s and men’s world
records in track and field events, showing that these differed by ten to fifteen percent “in favor of
the male of course,” and then extending this difference to all other sports. Second, he painted T
as the “fundamental” dimorphism, the characteristic that causes both sex-specific phenotypes and
23
sport performances. The message he drove home was that there was a “lack of overlap” in
females and males: in testosterone, in sport performances, and in “normal” phenotype. It was the
lack of overlap in T, he said, that is “one of the main explanations” for the lack of overlap in
“world best performances.” Sounds simple, but dimorphism in athletes’ T levels is contested, and
relies on manipulating which women and men are included in analysis (Healy et al. 2014,
Karkazis and Jordan-Young 2015).
From there, Bermon’s presentation took an odd turn as he created potent associations
between doping and naturally-occurring high T. Implicitly referring to the hyper-distinct “male”
and “female” phenotypes he had just shown, he said these phenotypes can be “modified” by
“exogenous administration of androgen or anabolic hormones.” In other words, doping. As he
spoke, he showed a slide featuring the same photo of Flex Wheeler, but this time paired with a
female bodybuilder with remarkably bulging and striated muscles under taut skin, her right arm
curled for maximum definition of her biceps and upper pecs, her right leg extended to show off
her magnificent quadriceps. Compared with La Maja Desnuda, this steroid-pumped woman
bodybuilder, like Flex, may as well have been not only from a different century and context but
of a different species. The visual argument this slide offered was that the normal dimorphism had
been breached. Her slicked back, bleached blond hair and light eyes notwithstanding, the overall
impression given by her physique and her deeply bronzed skin was not so different from that of
Flex.
Bermon’s only other comment on this slide was to say that the only time you see
“overlap” in women’s and men’s T levels is in doping and in naturally high T, calling both
24
“hyperandrogenism (HA).” Calling doping “exogenous hyperandrogenism” (meaning high T
from an external source) was idiosyncratic in the extreme; the term “hyperandrogenism” is never
used for doping. Bermon immediately reiterated this opportunistic usage by heading another
slide with the text “Exogenous HA: Doping.”
The viewer not only compares the woman bodybuilder to her fellow bodybuilder, Flex,
but also to La Maja, whose image she has replaced on one half of the slide. The bodybuilder is
not only abnormally “masculinized”— pictured as both a hormonal and an aesthetic problem in
contrast with La Maja—she is a cheat.
Beyond linking naturally high T and doping, Bermon’s sequence of slides strategically
triggered a series of associations that would resonate through the rest of the presentation.
Combining cultural tropes of masculinity, femininity, power, fairness and race, Bermon set up a
link between feminine, natural/honest, weak, and pale, on the one hand, and masculine,
unnatural/cheating, powerful, and dark, on the other. There are several senses in which the
female bodybuilder is not, like La Maja, the “fair” member of the pair. She has “modified” her
phenotype with banned substances (unfair), while La Maja is the stand-in for the universal,
“natural” woman. Neither the body nor the pose of the bodybuilder channel any of the attributes
of the “fair sex” that are evident in the feminine La Maja (delicacy, availability, softness,
sensuality). Finally, the bodybuilder’s skin is dark, like Flex, not light, like La Maja. The double
comparison of the woman bodybuilder to Flex (alike) and to La Maja (different) makes an
obvious argument about the breach of sexual dimorphism, but it also extends the association of
masculinity with dark, muscular, power that was invoked by Flex’s image in the first place.
25
These slides build up associations by using words and images that have powerful “off-stage”
meanings. Alone, the images of Flex, La Maja Desnuda, and the woman bodybuilder do not
constitute an argument about race and hyperandrogenism. But they put in play elements that
would be available to increase the resonance of other words and images that followed and which
also have racial associations.
The Rebranding of “Sex Testing”
Bermon, the IAAF’s point person on the regulation, was followed by Arne Ljungqvist, who has
strong ties both to the IAAF and the IOC. He spoke that morning from his position as chair of the
IOC Medical Commission, the body long charged with the creation and enforcement of “sex
testing” of women Olympians.
Ljungqvist began by giving a brief, editorialized history of “gender verification” in sport.
Before we turn to his narrative, it is helpful to know some history. Women’s entry into elite sport
nearly a century ago was accompanied by regulations variously called gender verification, “sex
testing,” and other terms, all of which had the same goal: to verify that those in the female
category are really women. An early iteration of these eligibility regulations involved physical
exams, which garnered intense criticism. Starting in 1967, based on the assumption that
chromosomes are adequate proxies for sex, the IOC and the IAAF embraced chromosomal
testing as a less intrusive and scientifically objective method (de la Chapelle 1986). Struggles
over whether and which chromosomal or genetic tests could distinguish men from women,
however, caused decades of infighting among athletes, medical commission members, and even
26
professional medical societies. The main problem with all “sex testing” is not with the tests per
se, but with the assumption that any singular marker of sex is adequate to classify people into a
two-sex system. Sex is complex, comprising at least five core elements (karyotype, genitals,
gonads, hormones, and secondary sex characteristics). None of these is dimorphic; all of them
can vary independently of the others. Nor is there an objective way to choose which criterion or
criteria “determines” sex: the decisions are made differently in different contexts (e.g., medicine,
law, and the social sciences).
The case of Olympian Maria José Martínez-Patiño is crucial to this history; at ICSEMIS,
Ljungqvist rehashed the official claim that her story ushered in the end of “sex testing.” In the
mid-1980s, the IOC disqualified the Spanish hurdler from competitions and withdrew her medals
and records because she was “chromosomally male” (Martınez-Patiño 2005). Martínez-Patiño
has complete androgen insensitivity syndrome, which is characterized by a 46, XY karyotype
and high levels of circulating T, but her tissues are unable to respond to T and other androgens.
After “failing” the sex chromatin test owing to XY chromosomes, Martínez-Patiño challenged
her exclusion and won (Martínez-Patiño 2005).
Martínez-Patiño’s victory needs to be re-read not for how it killed “sex testing,” but for
how it ushered in a focus on T. She and her advocates, including Ljungqvist, successfully
argued that her insensitivity to T should be the deciding factor in the case. In 1992 and 2000,
both the IAAF and the IOC, respectively, cited her challenge as a key rationale in their choice to
“abandon” sex testing.
27
The IAAF and IOC have repeatedly insisted that “sex testing” is over, to the extent that
we initially repeated their claim as fact (Karkazis et al. 2012). Ljungqvist’s talk at ICESMIS,
though, put the lie to their abandonment narrative. Sport governing bodies, he said, always
retained the authority to take “proper measures for the determination of the gender of the
competitor” through ad hoc investigations of targeted athletes. “Sex testing” never stopped, it
just was not mandatory for all women. And then he went one important step further: the T
regulation “is a still existing regulation to which has now been added some further elements.”
Female athletes have long been subject to T testing. The central element of the “new” regulation
is to make the focus on T transparent. A second element has to do with providing legal cover.
Earlier regulations aimed at actually determining athletes’ sex, potentially going against athletes’
legal documents, and left the sports organizations open to legal challenge for exceeding their
authority.
Ljungqvist revealed that underneath the T talk, sport regulators are still interested in sex
determination. He bemoaned “cases that were doubtful in terms of whether particular athletes
were actually men or women.” The concern, he said, was “intersex people—of course most of
them are women—but what to do with those cases.” Toggling between confirmation that
governing bodies still engage in “sex testing,” and insistence that they do not, he explained that if
an athlete’s gender is questioned, “the relevant sporting body shall have the authority to take
proper measures for the determination of the gender of the competitor” (emphasis added). Again,
though, he insisted that this new elaboration of the ad hoc rule is “not a sex test or a gender test.”
The IOC policy likewise notes that “Nothing in these Regulations is intended to make any
28
determination of sex” (IOC 2012), revealing the disavowal of “sex testing” to be a legal
disclaimer intended to protect sport authorities from challenge rather than a meaningful
description of the regulation.
T talk seems to make this disavowal appear more plausible, perhaps because the T
criterion appears to be scientific, objective, and narrow. As a singular chemical, T is simpler than
sex, and common wisdom holds that T is both sex dimorphic and the driver of athleticism. T talk
thus offers scientized cover for a regulation that looks new, but continues many of the same
problems as the earlier policies. For example, focusing on T deflects attention from the fact that
the current regulation also entails intrusive physical exams such as those that Ljungqvist had just
denounced.
T talk is fork tongued: not only does high T supposedly provide “unfair advantage” to
women athletes, it also makes them sick. After framing naturally high T in women as a health
problem, Ljungqvist asserted that sport authorities have “a duty within the context of medical
ethics” to identify women with high T and direct them into treatment “to protect the health of the
athlete.” The health justification is embedded in the regulation texts: IAAF claims the regulation
is for “the early prevention of problems associated with hyperandrogenism” and an IOC press
release for the regulation reads “In order to protect the health of the athlete, sport authorities
should have the responsibility to make sure that any case of female hyperandrogenism that arises
under their jurisdiction receives adequate medical follow-up” (IAAF 2011, IOC 2011, cf.
Karkazis et al. 2012, Karkazis and Jordan-Young 2013, Jordan-Young et al. 2014).
29
This appeal to medical ethics vacates the power, which is to say the politics, of the
situation. Ticktin’s critique of humanitarian “regimes of care” as “politics based on care and
produced as a moral imperative” is instructive (16). Sport authorities appeal to the notion of a
sick or “suffering” body, as do humanitarians seeking to provide some refuge within restrictive
immigration laws, and in both cases, medical science is the arbiter of suffering. With the
regulation, experts operating in the name of medical science can designate bodies as “suffering”
and in need of intervention even when this designation runs contrary to subjective experience
and desires, and even as they acknowledge that this intervention is medically unnecessary (e.g.,
Fenichel et al. 2013).
The idea that high T is dangerous to women is one of the oldest staples of sex hormone
ideology (Oudshoorn 1994), a kind of T talk that appears self-evident. But high T in and of itself
is not a health problem (Jordan-Young et al. 2014). Moreover, when Ljungqvist and other
proponents of the regulation argue that concerns about the risks of high T are behind their efforts
to identify women athletes “affected” by hyperandrogenism, they are inverting the story. Health
worries about high T are a post-hoc justification for continuing concerns about how to “deal”
with “ambiguous gender cases.” In 2010, just months after targeting Semenya, the IOC
organized a medical conference in Miami “to look at the state-of-the-art science and see what we
should recommend to sport” for “ambiguous gender cases” (Foxsports 2009). At the time,
Ljungqvist said “The general recommendation is obvious: they should be treated as medical
cases in compliance with up-to-date procedures. But we have to be more specific in telling the
sports people what that actually means and what they should do.” While health was supposedly
30
the core focus, the IOC also sought advice on which sex variations among women ostensibly
confer athletic advantage. But panelists observed that extensive research on intersex variations
would be necessary to map any ostensible “advantages” they might confer, “a complex and
perhaps impossible task” (Wells 2010).
T talk offered a bridge between the considerable complexity acknowledged at the Miami
meeting and the confident and streamlined assertions that emerged in the regulation itself. In
Miami, “None of the presenters attempted to link athleticism with particular disorders or
conditions studied, nor did they relate their research directly or indirectly to the issues of athletic
advantage of intersex athletes, gender verification policy,” or particular athletes (Wells 2010).
Later, when the regulation was announced with a narrow focus on T levels, it was taken as
obvious that high T provides athletic advantage to women. Bermon even closed his ICSEMIS
presentation by showing a table purporting to parse the clinical conditions associated with high T
that do and do not provide athletic “advantage.”
In the rebranding of sex testing, high T was doubly framed as both an advantage and a
health problem, giving a new health-based rationale for intervention and transforming an issue
that had previously caused public relations problems for sport authorities into an unequivocal
good. Think back to Prelude 2, in which we describe the four young athletes who were
intervened upon in the “specialist reference center” in France. None of those interventions were
medically necessary. But as the athletes were told, “gonadectomy would most likely decrease
their performance level but allow them to continue elite sport in the female category” (Fenichel
et al., E1057). In Glasgow, Ljungqvist even suggested that the new regulation benefits women
31
who are specifically disadvantaged: “These cases … are pretty rare. The competence is not found
all over the world.” With this sentence, Ljungqvist revealed the geographical focus of his
concerns: the Global South. Humanitarian “regimes of care” have routinely figured women and
children of the Global South as the prototypical “suffering body,” which entails a coupling of
bodily pathology with cultural pathology (Ticktin). In the domain we analyze, the cultural
pathology implicitly entails incompetent or uncivilized “neglect” of bodies figured as damaged
or ill. “The competence is not there,” Ljungqvist stated, thereby invoking a progress narrative
that links the West with science, modernity, a privileged insight into biological “truth,” and the
obligation to “perfect” bodies that do not fit aesthetic and cultural norms.10 This narrative
mandates intervention from a supposedly beneficent position, erasing power differentials and
echoing colonial rationales for bringing less “developed” people under control.
Breaking the Code of Hyperandrogenism
To understand who the regulation affects, it is crucial to take apart the coded work that is
accomplished by the idiosyncratic and strategic way that sport authorities use the word
“hyperandrogenism.” Hyperandrogenism, defined generally as “excess androgen in women,” is a
medical concept with no analogue in men. In practice, it nearly always refers to polycystic ovary
syndrome (PCOS). PCOS affects up to twenty percent of women worldwide, and “ethnic and
racial variation is remarkably low” (Azziz et al. 2016), so regulation of hyperandrogenism-qua-
PCOS should be largely race and region neutral.
32
Sport authorities have introduced an entirely new usage for the term hyperandrogenism,
giving a new twist to T talk. The 2012 Olympic regulation reads: “intersex female athletes with
elevated androgen production give rise to a particular concern in the context of competitive
sports, which is referred to as ‘female hyperandrogenism.’” Thus, the IOC is concerned
specifically with high T in the context of intersex. But even given the IOC’s chillingly broad
mandate to surveil gender non-conformity, directing National Olympic Committees to “actively
investigate any perceived deviation in sex characteristics” (IOC 2012), this does not mean that all
the women surveilled or investigated are intersex. Rather, authorities are concerned about
women who they see as “masculinized” by T, as we show in detail below.
Bermon opportunistically departed from conventional usage of the terms
hyperandrogenism and DSD in two ways. First, Bermon paired the image of the woman
bodybuilder with a neologism for doping, “exogenous hyperandrogenism,” aligning
hyperandrogenism with cheating. He immediately followed with a reference to “endogenous
hyperandrogenism, what we call DSD.DSD, a medicalized term for intersex, and
hyperandrogenism are medically distinct.11 None of the medical descriptions of
hyperandrogenism that we have found mentions DSD/intersex, nor did the hyperandrogenism
clinical guideline Bermon mentioned (Goodman et al. 2001). Hyperandrogenism typically means
PCOS, but the regulation has been crafted to specifically exclude women with PCOS. Bermon
explained that they set the eligibility threshold for naturally occurring T much higher than those
observed in women with PCOS. If any more confirmation were needed indicating that for sport
regulators hyperandrogenism is code for intersex, there is the report of the four athletes “treated”
33
at the IAAF reference center describing the focus of the T regulation as “detecting those athletes
who are competing unknowingly with a disorder of sex differentiation (DSD)” (Fenichel et al.,
E1056).
Three linked claims apparent in the Glasgow presentations collectively explain the racial
and geographic effects of the regulation, that is, why it overwhelmingly if not exclusively targets
black and brown women from the Global South. First, Bermon claimed there is “huge ethnic and
area variation” in prevalence of intersex, with the suggestion that there is higher prevalence in
the Global South. Second, he showed a slide claiming to sort intersex variations according to
whether they provide “athletic advantage,” which he implicitly linked to ethnic and area
variation by repeatedly discussing the two points in direct succession, without transition. This
created the impression that the people with the most advantage are clustered in the Global South.
Third, he repeated Ljungqvist’s point that “local expertise” to diagnose and treat intersex
variations is not common outside of Western industrialized states:
[A]s I told you before, a lot of these cases arise in poor countries or developing countries
where diagnosis is not done at birth like is the case in Western countries at least.
Diagnosis is not done and you realize that you have a 16 or 18 years old very well-
performing athlete with an intersex condition who’s going to enter into a major
championship, and here probably [would be] stopped.
34
With the “here” in that last sentence, Bermon anchored himself and his listeners in the
“rich” and “developed” countries of the Global North, referring in the same breath to both the
literal space in which the talk was delivered, and the typical referential space of his audience
who, though scant in number, were overwhelmingly from Western industrialized nations. In the
context of repeated assertions that cases have typically surfaced in poor, developing nations, the
vague statement about “ethnic and area variation” is automatically interpreted as meaning that
intersex itself is more common in poor regions (Magubane 2014). There is no evidence that this
is so. The major point of geographic variation is not in the prevalence of intersex, but in medical
responses to intersex. Specifically, the standard protocol in the Global North has, for more than
five decades, been characterized by an urgency to identify and “normalize” people with intersex
traits at the earliest possible stage of life, which includes modifying atypical genitals and
controlling hormone levels by surgery or pharmacological intervention (Karkazis 2008, Davis
2015). For a variety of reasons that might include cultural differences, general infrastructure,
medical resources, and others, early medical intervention has never been routinized outside the
Global North.
The point is not to argue whether women targeted by the regulation are “really” intersex
or whether there are “really” more intersex women in the Global South, and it is certainly not an
argument about whether anyone “should” identify as intersex. The point is instead to attend to
the politics of race and nation that shape the search for and perception of sexual difference.
Magubane has demonstrated that the relevant histories go well beyond the racist display of
Saartjie Baartman and the pathologization of black women’s bodies more generally, and has
35
suggested that we must ask “what role race and imperial history have played in rendering
intersex visible or invisible” (768).
This helps us to decode Bermon’s claim that there is “huge ethnic and area variation” in
incidence of intersex. Bermon padded this idea with references to “poor countries or developing
countries” and to Africa, Asia, and South America. In the context of Western racial ideology,
these ideas in close proximity fill in the mental blank of “ethnic” with brown/black and with
race. It is accurate to say that there is ethnic variation in specific kinds of intersex, but the ethnic
variations in prevalence do not track onto racial categories (e.g., Boudon et al. 1995, Maimoun et
al. 2011). Nonetheless, a regulation that is about atypically high T in women, through a variety
of conceptual associations with race and the explicit material focus on regions where intersex
women are not routinely subject to early intervention, manifests in targeted concern about black
and brown women from the Global South.
Emergence and Emergencies: “A lot of people coming from Africa, Asia”
For all the talk of a duty to treat affected athletes, and concerns about where there is
“competence” to do so, the overall framing of the regulation indicates that health talk is highly
strategic. T talk does a lot of things, but one of the most important is to keep certain kernels of
received wisdom readily available to make the regulation seem rational. These self-evident
claims, sometimes implicit but often explicit, include the idea that T is male, and renders women
with high T masculine; that women with high T have an “advantage” in sport; and that T is a
foreign substance to women, its presence akin to doping and therefore unfair. It’s important to
36
read all the different threads concurrently to see how the issue becomes racial and regional. Who
has high T? Untreated intersex women. And where are they found? In the Global South. The
regulation was released within this assemblage of claims, revealing seemingly abstract, neutral
concerns about women with “masculine traits” and “uncommon athletic capacity” to be far from
abstract or neutral. This provides an important backdrop for understanding the regulation itself,
and who it targets:
Despite the rarity of such cases, their emergence from time to time at the highest level of
women’s competition in Athletics has proved to be controversial since the individuals
concerned often display masculine traits and have an uncommon athletic capacity in
relation to their fellow female competitors (1).
This brings us to one of the most direct articulations of how concerns about race and
region drive this regulation, again from Bermon’s talk:
First, HA, especially DSD, is not so rare in female sports, at least athletics. I say ‘at least
athletics’ because as you probably know athletics is a whole world sports, it’s not purely
the Caucasian sports. We have a lot of people coming from Africa, Asia and we have a
lot of these cases coming from these countries. So, of course, there is a kind of
recruitment bias, a double one. One because they have an unfair advantage, some of
them, so of course they compete better and they reach more easily the higher level. And
37
the other one is I would say an ethnic or local area recruitment bias, because they are
undiagnosed at birth, so they are raised with this condition, and they arrive at the highest
level with this condition, which is quite seldom in rich countries where they are treated
just after birth.12
According to Bermon, women from Africa and Asia are “arriving” at the highest level
because of unfair advantage owing to not having been “treated.” The repetition of the word
“bias” and the explicit reference to cheating indicates that their very presence in competition is
unfair. The idea that these women “reach more easily the higher level” signals that they have not
worked hard, that they have just magically jumped the line. Likewise, Bermon’s explanation of
“biases” that enable the success of such women is a breathtaking inversion of the biases that
work against any athlete from the Global South, including challenges of inadequate nutrition,
lack of access to specialized equipment and excellent training facilities, and the enormous risk of
pouring time and energy into sport instead of more secure income generation. This claim of
“unfair advantage” forcefully reverberates with the “racialist logic that presents the black body
especially as vitality, as raw force, as athleticism itself” (Doyle, 420).
World-record-holding marathoner Paula Radcliffe, a white runner from the UK,
demonstrated the interlocking assumptions driving the targeting of women from the Global
South in a recent interview (5 Live Sport 2016). In a quote that resonates with our opening image
of the disappointed white runners at the Rio Olympics, Radcliffe said that when “we fully expect
no other result than Caster Semenya” winning at the Olympics, “then it’s no longer sport.” Blind
38
to her own privilege and dominance and the politics that shape them, she said she feared that
people would go to “certain villages in South Africa” where she claimed hyperandrogenism is
more prevalent and “seek out girls who look like they’re going to be able to go out and perform
and to run fast.”
In a 2013 defense of the regulation, Bermon and colleagues explained the regulation as
grounded in “Concerns for fairness for women athletes,” and referred to “Concerns among
women athletes that they should not be compelled to compete against other athletes who may
have a massive androgenic advantage” (Bermon et al. 2013, 63). This supposedly universalizing
statement about “women athletes” explicitly excludes women with high T from this category and
favors a construction of fairness that benefits both women with “typical” T levels and women
from the Global North (Jordan-Young and Karkazis 2012, Bavington 2016). T talk obfuscates
this bias, but reading the narratives of health, of the lack of medical competence in the Global
South, regional and ethnic variations, and advantage together makes this bias impossible to miss,
as another of Bermon’s statements illustrates:
And we have a lack of local suitable testing facilities...and you can easily understand that
when such cases arise in Africa, South America, Asia, it’s very complicated to get local
expertise there. And as they have a very clear advantage, they were pushed to compete at
the highest level.
He elaborated: “this is a way of cheating.”
39
How, then, would this unfair emergence of women with “advantage” from high T be
prevented? In short, by pushing the investigations down to lower levels. Within existing Olympic
policy, the National Olympic Committees are mandated to look for “any perceived deviation in
sex characteristics” (IOC 2012). Likewise, the IOC’s regulation was modified in 2014 to offload
the obligation to investigate women to the specific international federations for individual sports
(IOC 2014). The IAAF regulation in turn stipulates that the national athletics federations should
enforce the regulations. This multi-pronged attempt to stop women from competing in
international competitions, especially the Olympics, involves a decentralization of tasks and
diffusion of responsibility: scrutiny will not look the same in all contexts. For example, while
race is a powerful presence in the designation of normative femininity, race might not be
especially salient at every local or national level. But the discourses of “advantage” and “sex
deviation” that circulate around this regulation make available an enormous array of signs and
signals that can be attached to particular bodies in particular circumstances and used
strategically.
How exactly is this mandate operationalized? To investigate any perceived deviation, you
first have to understand the perceived norm.
Looking at the Clitoris, Seeing “Advantage”
Like his earlier presentation of La Maja, Bermon’s description of the protocol for investigating
suspected hyperandrogenism resonated with broad cultural ideas about the aesthetics of T.
Midway through his presentation, he showed a spreadsheet with what he described as the most
40
frequent types of intersex that IAAF sees in investigations, indicating which ones they believe
convey advantage in sport, and notably, one they believe does not. Recalling Ljungqvist’s
discussion of Martínez-Patiño, Bermon said that complete androgen insensitivity syndrome
(CAIS), in which women have high T but their bodies do not respond to it:
is not a problem at all, because as Arne has told you before, there are females with a high
level of testosterone but with perfect female, at least external perfect female phenotype.
And they have no advantage at all, since they don’t have any functional testosterone
receptors. By the way, most of the time these are very beautiful females, and you can find
them as models.
If the “perfect female phenotype” signals “no advantage at all” (think of Goya’s prone
and inert La Maja), how does a female body display an “advantage” stemming from T? It is
difficult to measure androgen receptor function directly, so sport investigations draw on
protocols developed by doctors specializing in intersex, who infer the function of androgen
receptors from the body’s surface. The IAAF regulation (2011, 20) lists the following indicators
of high functional T:
• Deep voice
• Breast atrophy
• Never menstruation (or loss of menses since several month)
• Increased muscle mass
41
• Body hair of male type (vertex alopecia, >17 years)
• Tanner score low (I / II) [see figure 3]
• F&G score (>6 / ! minimized by the beauty) [sic] [see figure 4]
• No uterus
• Clitoromegaly [larger than typical clitoris]
Many of these features are deeply subjective, drawing on aesthetic judgments about femininity
and its opposite; several are also a common result of extreme athletic training in women. It is
crucial here to understand that this list is not used alongside some objective medical test for a
woman’s physical sensitivity to T: it is the test.
At ICSEMIS, Bermon stressed one trait above all others as the most important for
determining whether an athlete under investigation for high T has unfair advantage: the size of
her clitoris. The IAAF investigations follow “three levels of medical assessment”: an initial
clinical examination, preliminary endocrine assessment, and a full examination and diagnosis.
Bermon clarified that a gynecological exam should be included in the first level, emphasizing its
importance by using bold font, all caps, and three plus signs. Bermon claimed that clitoral size
“gives you very good information about the level of virilization”—that is, whether someone has
been masculinized by T. Androgen receptor function is difficult to measure directly, so the
clitoris is the sine qua non for divining so-called advantage.12
Bermon made a series of inferences: a large clitoris indicates both high T and functional
receptors; high T and functional receptors indicate athletic advantage. But these indicators have
42
no predictive capabilities regarding athleticism. In his testimony during the CAS hearing,
Ljungqvist acknowledged that “it [i]s not possible to quantify the magnitude of athletic
advantage enjoyed by a particular athlete based on assessment of physical virilisation”
(summarized at 64).
Beyond being used in investigations, the list plays a role in marking some women as
suspicious, which has the potential to bring all women athletes under scrutiny. The IAAF
guideline is “scientific” insofar as these are the elements endocrinologists look for when
assessing high T in women, but the logics and aesthetics of this list boil down to common ideas
of what T does to women’s bodies, and the idea that evidence of high T can be gleaned from the
body’s surface characteristics. But while this list is used clinically as if it is objective, judgments
about what makes a woman masculine vary by historical period, place, racial ideologies, and
individual situation. How deep is too deep for a woman’s voice, and in which contexts is it
considered normal for a woman to speak “roughly” versus cultivating a soft and quiet voice? Is
body hair feminine, or is it suspiciously masculine? Measures of the patterns and density of hair
growth were developed in the context of racial science, and anthropologists used these as “a
principal method of defining race” (Yildiz et al. 2010, 53). The scale that IAAF recommends for
assessing a so-called male pattern of body and facial hair (hirsutism) is profoundly subjective,
and the literature on hirsutism reveals an ongoing obsession with racial and ethnic variations
(see, e.g., Yildiz, Goodman et al. 2001). Several listed traits are also common results of intensive
athletic training in women. How small must breasts be to show “atrophy”? The small breasts
common in women across different sports might be interpreted as the result of high T, rather than
43
a result of the demands and effects of their specific training. How much muscle mass indicates
increased muscle mass in a woman? Muscle mass is a particularly fraught characteristic for elite
women athletes, because even in some sports where larger muscles could benefit performance,
some elite women athletes (and notably their coaches) strive to avoid “bulking up” (Dworkin
2001, Krane et al. 2004, Rothenberg 2015). T talk erases the subjectivity from these judgments,
certifying the list as scientifically valid, universal effects of high T on women, and thus signs of
advantage.
Bermon ended his talk with a slide carrying five take home messages, one of which was
in all caps: “Importance of GYNAECOLOGICAL EXAMINATION: PPHE.” In other words,
not only is a genital exam the first step in investigating women under the T regulation, but he
called for all women athletes to have one as part of a pre-participation health exam (PPHE). He
called the PPHE “very, very, very important,” but noted with regret that it “is not very much
popular in poor countries, as you can imagine.” With that reference to poor countries, he made
the slip from supposedly looking for athletic advantage to claims that the process is in the service
of women’s health: “It’s very easy to detect a labial fusion, clitoral enlargement, or very small
vagina, or very short,” he said. “Once you detect this, you can help the athlete for diagnosis and
treatment.” Not twenty minutes before Bermon described these assessments, Arne Ljungqvist
had bemoaned the “humiliation” involved in the physical exams of “sex testing,” and had
assured the audience that “sex testing” was over.
Multiple analyses of the genital inspections associated with “sex testing” in sport have
pointed out the resonance of these exams with the historical pathologization of black women’s
44
genitals (Nyong’o 2010, Munro 2010, Merck 2010, Jordan-Young and Karkazis 2012, Doyle
2013, Dworkin, Swarr, and Cooky 2013, Adjepong and Carrington 2014). Writing about how
shifting racial and national contexts affect perceptions of sexual (a)typicality, Magubane has
observed that “One thing that South African, US, and European medical texts from the
seventeenth century through the twentieth seem to agree on was the fact that malformed or
ambiguous genitalia, especially an enlarged clitoris or overdeveloped labia, were particularly
common among women of African descent” (769). As Adjepong and Carrington (2015) note,
“colonial myths around black women’s bodies are reproduced even after the formal dismantling
of western colonial regimes” (173). Colonial myths concern “pathological cultures” as well as
pathological bodies, re-casting violent colonial interventions as “saving” women from their own
(violent and misogynist) communities. We see here a double parallel to what Ticktin documents
in her critique of humanitarianism, where “Both NGOs and the French state give attention to
women who are subject to exceptionally violent or exoticized practices, such as excision or
modern slavery, but this renders them visible as victims of cultural pathologies and hence in need
of help, rescue—not equal rights.” (4-5). In the instance we examine, the exoticized practice is
not excision, but failure to excise. The women targeted for the “help” of IAAF and IOC medical
teams are not thereby included as equals among other women athletes, as the official aim of
intervention is to reduce athleticism among the former for the benefit of the latter.
T as the Great Distraction
45
Returning to that striking image taken minutes after the 800m women’s final ended, we can
understand it within a more complex web of context. The image is more than a representation of
multiple discourses circulating around the women on the podium and those at its periphery. It is
also a snapshot of particular people with material lives and specific histories and locations in the
intersecting orders of privilege and “rights” to winning, to privacy, to respect. In a context in
which T alone is deemed to determine advantage and disadvantage, what makes sense and is
valued as legitimate in this scene is the sense of injustice expressed acutely by the women who
did not win the race. But women investigated for possible high T face harms that are nowhere in
the picture: having their identity publicly questioned, their genitals scrutinized, the most private
details of their lives subject to “assessment” for masculinity, their careers and livelihoods
threatened, and being subject to pressure for medically unnecessary interventions with life-long
consequences. The narrative of harm is inverted: how does the putative advantage conferred by T
matter more than concrete and demonstrable harms to people?
The stories emerging from development and implementation of this regulation are
“predictable failures,” which Holloway describes as “instances where medical issues and
information that would usually be seen as intimate, private matters are forced into the public
sphere.” The intrusions are predictable precisely because hierarchies of race, gender, and nation
place these women athletes far from power, and the policy-making process instrumentalizes
these very hierarchies by constructing “fairness” as an objective phenomenon that could
therefore be defined absent consideration of its meaning to women who would be excluded by
the regulation. A regulation aimed at ensuring fairness “for all female athletes” fails to take into
46
account the perspective of women directly affected: “None of the female athletes disqualified by
prior policies were invited to attend the meetings that were held to formulate the new policies”
(Viloria and Martínez-Patiño 2012, 17). Far from being objective or universal, this regulation
mobilizes a version of “fairness” that is a privilege reserved for those with favored racial, gender,
sexual, class, or national status. This exclusion from the purview of “fairness” is occluded by
magnanimous claims of protecting health. Sport officials opportunistically move between two
platforms of justification for the regulation: protecting health and protecting fairness. The
women being “protected” in these two different justifications are mutually exclusive. Women
with high T are not “visible” in the fairness portion of this regulation except as a threat; the
“help” offered requires that they submit to the designation of “ill” despite having no health
complaints (Jordan-Young, et al. 2014). T talk thus obscures how the regulation benefits those
with more power and privilege, making it look like defense against unfairness rather than the
exercise of power.
T talk deflects attention from social structures and institutions, attributing the result of
competitions completely to individual bodies, as though these bodies have developed, trained,
and ultimately competed in some socially-neutral vacuum. At one level, the regulation harms all
women athletes. It is built upon the premise that sport is a masculine domain and it is a distortion
of nature for women to enter it in a serious, competitive way (Kahn 1998, Krane et al. 2004).
“Sex testing” is the traditional way of policing this line, and reframing this as a rule about T
obscures the fact that this regulation is still “sex testing.” The regulation has even provided a
47
fresh occasion for an IOC policymaker to argue with a straight face that barriers to equality in
sport are gone (2015).
At another level, some women are harmed in a much more direct, material, and
significant way. The premise that women are a vulnerable class that needs protection is readily
endorsed in this domain even by some who are otherwise champions of gender equity (e.g.,
Dreger, quoted in Epstein 2014), but history is full of examples of how the “female
vulnerability” argument has consistently valued more privileged women (whether by class, race,
gender presentation, or region) over less privileged women, who are ironically but systematically
seen as less vulnerable. T talk deflects attention from the racial and regional politics of intra-sex
competition in women’s sport.
The IOC and IAAF frame interventions as an unmitigated good, especially because they
target women from the Global South, coming from situations that Bermon and Ljungqvist have
described as “lacking competence” for dealing with the conditions that are “revealed” through
investigations. We must, however, attend to resonances, co-occurring narratives, and indirect
logic. The designated “Centers of Excellence” are in Sweden, France, Australia, Japan, Brazil,
and the United States; the athletes are repeatedly described as coming from “Africa, South
America, Asia” and from “poor countries or developing countries” as opposed to the “western
countries” where medical diagnosis and intervention for intersex happens at or near birth. A
high-ranking IOC official told us in an interview that “these women have dangerous diseases,”
underscoring the way that sport authorities frame untreated intersex as a seriously harmful
problem. Together with the refrain that outside the West there is not the “competence” to deal
48
with such conditions, the picture that assembles is almost that of a missionary relationship, and
certainly resonates with a long legacy of colonialist ideologies. Emphasizing the delivery of
scientific and medical prowess to women in need obscures the extremely asymmetrical power
relations involved.
The interventions on athletes are not directed by their goals and needs, but by the goals of
sport organizations. Neither the regulations nor any sport officials’ publications or presentations
that we have encountered acknowledge the now decades old controversies that have raged over
genital surgeries and other medical interventions for intersex. Intersex adults have argued for
more than two decades that the kinds of interventions performed on women in order to comply
with the regulation are driven by gender ideologies that pathologize sex atypical bodies and
gender atypical behavior, and cause irreparable harm to sensation and function (Karkazis 2008,
Davis 2015). Many have questioned the right of clinicians to intervene on intersex bodies at all.
These complaints, delivered forcefully from individuals in countries around the world, have
caught the attention of national legislative bodies and human rights organizations (Carpenter
2016, OII Australia n.d.). Moreover, high T may signal a medical problem but it does not
constitute a medical problem (Karkazis et al. 2012, Jordan-Young et al. 2014). Physicians do not
lower T in the absence of patient complaints or functional impairments. Lowering T can cause
significant health problems, which can include depression, fatigue, osteoporosis, muscle
weakness, low libido, and metabolic problems; these may be life-long problems, and may require
hormone replacement treatments, which are both costly and often difficult to calibrate (Jordan-
Young et al. 2014).
49
Beyond performing unnecessary medical interventions and violating IAAF rules, the
report on the four women raises serious ethical concerns about coercion and violations of
confidentiality and privacy (Jordan-Young et al. 2014, Sönksen et al. 2015). Implicitly
addressing concerns about coercion, the IAAF regulation states that no woman is required to
undergo medical intervention, but this claim is deeply misleading. The regulation applies to
women in the category of elite athletes. If a woman with hyperandrogenism wishes to continue
her career as an athlete, she is required to lower her T levels. If she does not, then she can no
longer be in the category. Since sport authorities have no grounds to make rules about people
who are not in that category, it is meaningless for them to say that women athletes do not need to
have medical interventions.
Because the IOC and IAAF have delegated the obligation to investigate women to the
lower level sport authorities, when predictable failures occur, the IOC/IAAF frame these as
“implementation problems” that happen under the aegis of the national federations or National
Olympic Committees. For example, in Dutee Chand’s successful challenge to the IAAF
regulation, any problems Chand had encountered—medical harm, violations of privacy,
discrimination, psychological distress, and wrongful suspension of her career—were not inherent
to the regulation itself, but to how it was implemented. Any problems could be attributed to the
ineptitude and bungling of the national officials, Athletics Federation of India (AFI), and the
doctors that AFI chose to examine her. This is yet another resonance with colonial ideas of the
backwardness of those in the Global South.
50
A month before the photo that opens this essay was taken, a debate erupted on Twitter
about the T regulation. Shannon Rowbury, a middle-distance runner who was goaded into
speaking about the issue immediately after a race commented that “It challenges and threatens
the integrity of women’s sports to have intersex athletes competing against . . . genetic women . .
.” (Rowbury 2016). Justifiably angry that Rowbury had excised intersex women from the
category of women, several intersex advocates asked her to apologize for her statement. The
debate torqued and turned picking up more interlocutors until it included a sports scientist known
for his spirited defenses of the regulation. One participant argued the regulation cannot be
isolated from questions of race, “Even if it makes dialogue YOU want to have about it more
difficult. I dont [sic] think it’s good science to isolate physiology from history + politics and race
plays direct role if it contributes to who does/doesn’t get tested” (Eisenberg-Guyot 2016). The
sport scientist rejected the idea and replied dismissively that race “is irrelevant to the science and
so to me, the introduction of race is an intellectually lazy approach” (Tucker 2016).
No one had to introduce race; it was there all along. M’charek et al. argue that in
contemporary European discourses race is an “absent presence” both normatively and
methodologically (M’charek, Schramm, and Skinner 2014). Normatively, race is “a tabooed
object often removed and excluded from discourse and viewed as something that belongs to the
problematic past.” Methodologically, the obfuscation of race engenders a “slippery-ness”; race
“come(s) in many different guises.” The analyst’s task, then, is “to attend to things that are
othered (silenced and excluded): such things do not fully go away, but might give rise to things
that are (made) present” (462). Similarly, sociologist Avery F. Gordon writes of being haunted
51
by a photograph while immersed in a project as she kept “looking for the language that could
render what wasn’t easily or normally seen, what was in the blind field, what was in the
shadows, what only crazy people or powerless people saw.” She struggled “to conjure, to
present, to bring back to a different life what was living and breathing in the place blinded from
view” (9). We have aimed here to bring forth what others do not see, cannot see, refuse to see.
Foregrounding the intertwined workings of colonialism, race, and modernity reveal race as
central to, not apart from, this regulation. Exposing and centering these relationships, the
regulation and its effects can only be understood as intentional and as a predictable outcome of
legacies that not only continue to haunt, but to harm.
Key
CAIS Complete androgen insensitivity syndrome
CAS Court of Arbitration for Sport
IAAF International Association of Athletics Federations
ICSEMIS International Convention on Science, Education and Medicine in Sport
IOC International Olympic Committee
PCOS Polycystic Ovarian Syndrome
Acknowledgements
This paper was supported by a grant from the National Science Foundation (SES 1331123 and
1331123), a Presidential Research Award from Barnard College, and fellowships from the
52
American Council of Learned Societies and the Guggenheim Foundation. Karkazis: This paper
was written while cloaked in sadness from the death of Cedric J. Robinson. Revealing “the
nastiness” here, as he called it, has been a way to grieve through writing, to write through grief,
and to awaken the possibility for justice.
Notes
1. This prelude draws on the previously published article (Karkazis 2016).
2. The IAAF and the IOC were the original architects of the T regulation and their officials
have been its most vigorous defenders. Here we focus on the IAAF and the IOC
regulations, though the general analysis will apply to similar regulations. Likewise,
because the IOC and IAAF developed their respective regulations together, are materially
similar, and involve many of the same institutional actors, we use the singular noun
“regulation” in this piece.
3. The T regulation concerns only higher natural levels of testosterone and not higher levels
due to doping. With doping, which is regulated by the World Anti-Doping Agency, the
hormones are external to the athlete’s body. The women targeted by this regulation have
not introduced testosterone into their bodies.
4. Intersex is a term long used to refer to individuals born with atypical sex traits. In 2006
participants at a medical conference updated treatment guidelines agreed to change the
nomenclature from intersex to Disorder of Sex Development (DSD) (Lee et al. 2006).
Others, including IAAF and IOC officials, have sometimes used the alternative phrase
53
“disorders of sex differentiation” for the same DSD concept. DSD has been controversial
among many intersex individuals, advocates, activists, and community
organizations owing to the its use of “disorders,” which pathologizes atypically sexed
bodies prompting imperatives for medical intervention. Many thus reject the term DSD,
preferring instead intersex. In this paper, we use intersex except when quoting or
referencing the regulations themselves or addressing policymakers’ use of the term DSD.
5. This has been confirmed through several sources including a talk given in 2012 by
Stéphane Bermon, a key IAAF policymaker, at the International Convention on Science,
Education and Medicine in Sport (ICSEMIS) and interviews with other policymakers.
6. Sport policymakers have variably and interchangeably used the terms “sex testing” or “sex
tests,” and “gender tests” or “gender verification” to refer to the vetting of women athletes
for eligibility in the female category. In this paper, unless we are directly quoting a source,
we use “sex testing.” One of the key points of this paper is to show how gender ideologies
are embedded in assessments of sex, including those that are thought to be “purely”
biological (Kessler and McKenna 1978). Drawing on Kessler and McKenna, Westbrook
and Schilt use “‘determining gender’ as an umbrella term for these diverse practices of
placing a person in a gender category” (Westbrook and Schilt 2014). We are sympathetic
to that usage, which points to the social nature of these processes. We opt for different
usage here to clearly spotlight the fact that official regulations have aimed to link eligibility
to biological criteria, in this case testosterone, and at the same time to show in detail how
the assessment of testosterone and testosterone function are social phenomena.
54
7. We have written extensively, both separately and together, about how scientific notions of
“normal” and “atypical” sex are always deeply entangled with commitments to
heteronormative relationships among sex, gender, and sexuality (e.g., Karkazis 2008,
Jordan-Young 2010, Karkazis et al. 2012). In this piece, we do not deal in any detail with
the operations of homophobia, primarily because the techniques for assessing sexuality
among women who are identified as having high T via this regulation are the most opaque
of the assessments. The IAAF regulation includes six mentions of “anamnestic” data as an
important element of assessing the degree of virilization. Anamnesis literally means an
interview on a “patient’s” subjective medical and psychiatric history, but the term has a
particularly strong history of use in sexology, where it specifically indicates an interview
on the subjective experiences of gender and sexuality. The only direct indication of the
content of anamnestic interviews or how they should be used to assess virilization is found
in Fenichel et al., where the authors report that none of the four young women athletes
“reported male sex behavior” (E1056)—a confused and confusing locution that we
presume means that the women did not have women sex partners. The lack of specific
direction in terms of how to interpret anamnestic data is a signal that regulators believe
“virilized” sexuality can simply be recognized by anyone who looks, an assumption that
closely conforms to our prior observations of heteronormativity in medical science
(Karkazis 2008, Jordan-Young 2010).
8. The IAAF and IOC regulation and much discussion about it use the terminology “female
athletes” or “female hyperandrogenism.” The term “female” has strong biological
55
connotations, and this may indeed be the reason that the term is preferred by sport
regulators. We understand that many women athletes also refer to themselves and their
competitive category as comprising “females” rather than women. Nonetheless, in this
paper, we have opted to use the words “woman” or “women” rather than “female(s)” in
order to highlight the fact that we are interested in social operations of gender.
9. Goya also painted a nearly identical work titled La Maja Vestida –the clothed maja—
which portrays the same woman draped over a green divan and propped up by pillows,
but this time clad in a clinging, transparent white dress. Bermon not only chose one of
Goya’s La Maja paintings for his presentation, he chose the naked one.
10. Showing that similar progress narratives operate across political lines and domains of
discourse, Magubane has offered a sustained analysis of feminist scholarship on Caster
Semenya, showing that feminist and queer scholars have often perpetuated the association
of modernity, knowledge, and the West.
11. Here’s a sleight of hand that we do not have room to address fully in this paper: the
regulation and official statements related to it not only merge high T with intersex, but
flatten intersex into a singular thing. This flattening obscures a great deal of empirical and
logical slippage in their rationale for the regulation.
12. Bavington notes that the IAAF regulation specifically stipulates that the “burden of proof”
for partial androgen insensitivity is “put on the athlete precisely because it is so difficult to
prove” (124).
56
References
5 Live Sport. 2016. “Radcliffe: Caster Semenya Rio Gold ‘Won’t Be Sport’.”
http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p0425m52.
Adjepong, L. Anima, and Ben Carrington. 2014. “Black Female Athletes as Space Invaders.” In
Routledge Handbook of Sport, Gender and Sexuality, edited by Jennifer Hargreaves and
Eric Anderson. London and New York: Routledge.
Amandla Awethu. 2016. “Stop the Bullying of Caster Semenya.”
https://awethu.amandla.mobi/petitions/stop-the-bullying-of-caster-semenya.
Associated Press. 2010. “Caster Semenya’s Comeback Statement in Full.” The Guardian, March
30. http://www.theguardian.com/sport/2010/mar/30/caster-semenya-comeback-statement.
Azziz, Ricardo, Enrico Carmina, ZiJiang Chen, Andrea Dunaif, Joop S. E. Laven, Richard S.
Legro, Daria Lizneva, Barbara Natterson-Horowtiz, Helena J. Teede, and Bulent O.
Yildiz. 2016. “Polycystic Ovary Syndrome.” Nature Reviews. Disease Primers 2: 16057.
Bavington, L. Dawn. 2016. “Regulating Hyperandrogenism in Female Athletes: The History and
Current Politics of Sex-Control in Women’s Sport.” Unpublished doctoral dissertation,
Dunedin, New Zealand: University of Otago.
Bermon, Stéphane, Martin Ritzen, Angelica Hirschberg, and Thomas Murray. 2013. “Are the
New Policies on Hyperandrogenism in Elite Female Athletes Really Out of Bounds?
Response to ‘Out of Bounds? A Critique of the New Policies on Hyperandrogenism in
Elite Female Athletes.’” American Journal of Bioethics 13 (5): 63–65.
57
Boudon, Corinne., Serge Lumbroso, Jean-Marc Lobaccaro, Maria Szarras-Czapnik, Thomas E.
Romer, Patrick Garandeau, Pedro Montoya, and Charles Sultan. 1995. “Molecular Study
of the 5 Alpha-Reductase Type 2 Gene in Three European Families with 5 Alpha-
Reductase Deficiency.” The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology and Metabolism 80 (7):
2149–53.
Brook, Benedict. 2016. “South African Athlete Caster Semenya Reportedly under Armed Guard
at Rio Olympics Following Safety Fears.NewsComAu. August 17.
http://www.news.com.au/sport/olympics/south-african-athlete-caster-semenya-
reportedly-under-armed-guard-at-rio-olympics-following-safety-fears/news-
story/d0fd6608d4d2aff4ba98cf9a2c6d0664.
Browning, Ella. 2016. “Rupturing the World of Elite Athletics: A Feminist Critical Discourse
Analysis of the Suspension of the 2011 IAAF Regulations on Hyperandrogenism.”
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Tampa, FL: University of South Florida.
Carpenter, Morgan. 2016. “The Human Rights of Intersex People: Addressing Harmful Practices
and Rhetoric of Change.” Reproductive Health Matters 24 (47): 74–84.
Cahn, Susan. 1998. Coming on Strong: Gender and Sexuality in Twentieth-Century Women's
Sports. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
CAS. 2015. “CAS2014/A/3759 Dutee Chand v. Athletics Federation of India (AFI) & The
International Association of Athletics Federations (IAAF)” Lausanne, Switzerland: Court
of Arbitration for Sport.
58
Collins, Patricia Hill. 1990. Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the
Politics of Empowerment. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman.
Cooky, Cheryl, and Shari L. Dworkin. 2013. “Policing the Boundaries of Sex: A Critical
Examination of Gender Verification and the Caster Semenya Controversy.” Journal of
Sex Research 50 (2): 103–11.
Cooky, Cheryl, Ranissa Dycus, and Shari L. Dworkin. 2013. “What Makes a Woman a
Woman?” Versus “Our First Lady of Sport” A Comparative Analysis of the United States
and the South African Media Coverage of Caster Semenya.” Journal of Sport and Social
Issues 37(1): 37-56.
Davis, Georgiann. 2011. “‘DSD is a Perfectly Fine Term’: Reasserting Medical Authority
through a Shift in Intersex Terminology,” for Volume 12 in the Advances in Medical
Sociology series, “Sociology of Diagnosis” Editors P. J. McGann and David J. Hutson
———. 2015. Contesting Intersex: The Dubious Diagnosis. New York, NY: New York
University Press.
de la Chapelle, Albert. 1986. “The Use and Misuse of Sex Chromatin Screening for `Gender
Identification’ of Female Athletes.” Journal of the American Medical Association 256
(14): 1920–23.
Doyle, Jennifer. 2013. “Dirt off Her Shoulders.” GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies 19
(4): 419–33.
Dworkin, Shari L. 2001. “‘Holding back’: Negotiating a glass ceiling on women’s muscular
strength.” Sociological Perspectives, 44(3), 333-350.
59
Dworkin, Shari L., Amanda Lock Swarr, and Cheryl Cooky. 2013. “(In) Justice in Sport: The
Treatment of South African Track Star Caster Semenya.” Feminist Studies 39 (1): 40–69.
Epstein, David. 2013. The Sports Gene: Inside the Science of Extraordinary Athletic
Performance. London, UK: Yellow Jersey Press.
Eisenberg-Guyot, Jerzy. 2016. Twitter posts. July 13, 2016, 9:30 a.m.
https://twitter.com/JerzyEisenGuyot/
Fenichel, Patrick, Françoise Paris, Pascal Philibert, Sylvie Hieronimus, Laura Gaspari, Jean-
Yves Kurzenne, Patrick Chevallier, Stéphane Bermon, Nicolas Chevalier, and Charles
Sultan. 2013. “Molecular Diagnosis of 5 Alpha-Reductase Deficiency in 4 Elite Young
Female Athletes Through Hormonal Screening for Hyperandrogenism.” Journal of
Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism 98 (6): E1055–59.
Foxsports. 2009. “AP NewsBreak: IOC to Hold Meeting on Gender.” October 27.
http://www.foxsports.com/olympics/story/ap-newsbreak-ioc-to-hold-meeting-on-gender-
cases2-102709.
Gordon, Avery F. 2007. “‘Who’s there?’: some answers to questions about ghostly matters.”
Talk presented at UnitedNationsPlaza (Berlin), October 22–26.
http://www.averygordon.net/writing-haunting/whos-there/
Goodman, Neil, Maya Bledsoe, Rhoda Cobin, Walter Futterweit, Joseph Goldzieher, Steven
Petak, Keith Smith, Emil Steinberger, and American Association of Clinical
Endocrinologists Hyperandrogenic Disorders Task Force. 2001. “American Association
60
of Clinical Endocrinologists Medical Guidelines for Clinical Practice for the Diagnosis
and Treatment of Hyperandrogenic Disorders.” Endocrine Practice 7 (2): 120–34.
Guardian Sport. 2016. “Sebastian Coe Indicates IAAF Will Challenge Female Testosterone
Ruling.” The Guardian, August 11.
https://www.theguardian.com/sport/2016/aug/11/caster-semenya-sebastian-coe-iaaf-cas-
testosterone-olympics.
Healy, Marie-Louise, James Gibney, Claire Pentecost, Mike J. Wheeler and Peter H. Sönksen.
2014. Endocrine profiles in 693 elite athletes in the post-competition setting. Clinical
Endocrinology 81 (2), 294-305.
Henne, Kathryn. 2015. Testing for Athlete Citizenship: Regulating Doping and Sex in Sport.
New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Hoad, Neville. 2010. “‘Run, Caster Semenya, Run!’ Nativism and the Translations of Gender
Variance.” Safundi 11 (4): 397–405.
Holloway, Karla FC. 2011. Private Bodies, Public Texts: Race, Gender, and a Cultural
Bioethics. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
IAAF. 2011. “IAAF Regulations Governing Eligibility of Females with Hyperandrogenism to
Compete in Women’s Competitions.”
http://www.iaaf.org/mm/Document/AboutIAAF/Publications/05/98/78/20110430054216
_httppostedfile_HARegulations(Final)-Appendices-AMG-30.04.2011_24299.pdf.
ICSEMIS. 2016. Introduction to ICSEMIS. http://www.icsemis2016.org/.
61
IOC. 2011. “IOC Addresses Eligibility of Female Athletes with Hyperandrogenism,” April.
http://www.olympic.org/content/press-release/ioc-addresses-eligibility-of-female-
athletes-with-hyperandrogenism/.
———. 2012. “IOC Regulations on Female Hyperandrogenism.”
———. 2014. “IOC Regulations on Female Hyperandrogenism.”
Jordan-Young, Rebecca M. 2010. Brain Storm: The Flaws in the Science of Sex Differences.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jordan-Young, Rebecca M., and Katrina Karkazis. 2012. “Some of Their Parts.” Anthropology
News, May.
Jordan-Young, Rebecca M. and Katrina Karkazis. 2017. “The Powers of Testosterone: Race,
nation, and the regulation of women athletes,” Annual Meeting of the Society for Social
Studies of Science, August 30.
Jordan-Young, Rebecca M., Peter Sönksen, and Katrina Karkazis. 2014. “Sex, Health, and
Athletes.” British Medical Journal 348 (April): g29264.
Karkazis, Katrina. 2008. Fixing Sex: Intersex, Medical Authority, and Lived Experience.
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
———. 2016. “The Ignorance Aimed at Caster Semenya Flies in the Face of the Olympic
Spirit.” The Guardian, August 23.
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/aug/23/caster-semenya-olympic-
spirit-iaaf-athletes-women.
62
Karkazis, Katrina, and Rebecca M. Jordan-Young. 2015. “Debating A Testosterone ‘Sex Gap.’”
Science 348 (6237): 858–60.
Karkazis, Katrina, Rebecca M. Jordan-Young, Georgiann Davis, and Silvia Camporesi. 2012.
“Out of Bounds? A Critique of the New Policies on Hyperandrogenism in Elite Female
Athletes.” The American Journal of Bioethics 12 (7): 3–16.
Kessler, Suzanne, and Wendy McKenna. 1978. Gender: An Ethnomethodological Approach.
New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Komorniczak, Michał. 2009. “Tanner scale-female.” Wikipedia.
https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Tanner_scale-female.svg
Krane, Vikki, Precilla Yee L. Choi, Shannon M. Baird, Christine M. Aimar, and Kerrie J. Kauer.
2004. Living the paradox: Female athletes negotiate femininity and muscularity. Sex
Roles, 50, 315-329.
Lee, Peter A., Christopher P. Houk, Syed F. Ahmed, and Ieuan A. Hughes. 2006. “Consensus
Statement on Management of Intersex Disorders.” Pediatrics 118 (2): e488–500.
Ljungqvist, Arne, and Stéphane Bermon. 2012. “New Eligibility Rules for Female
Competitions.” Presented at the ICSEMIS, Glasgow, Scotland, July 21.
M’charek, Amade, Katharina Schramm, and David Skinner. 2014. “Technologies of Belonging:
The Absent Presence of Race in Europe.” Science, Technology, & Human Values 39(4)
459-467.
Macharia. 2009. “On Caster Semenya.” Gukira. September 20.
https://gukira.wordpress.com/2009/09/20/on-caster-semenya/.
63
Magubane, Zine. 2014. “Spectacles and Scholarship: Caster Semenya, Intersex Studies, and the
Problem of Race in Feminist Theory.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society
39 (3): 761–85.
Maimoun, Laurent, Pascal Philibert, Benoit Cammas, Françoise Audran, Philippe Bouchard,
Patrick Fenichel, Maryse Cartigny, et al. 2011. “Phenotypical, Biological, and Molecular
Heterogeneity of 5α-Reductase Deficiency: An Extensive International Experience of 55
Patients.” The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology and Metabolism 96 (2): 296–307.
Marshall, W.A. and James M. Tanner (1969). “Variations in pattern of pubertal changes in girls”
Archives of Disease in Childhood 44 (235): 291–303.
Martínez-Patiño, Maria. 2005. “Personal Account: A Woman Tried and Tested.” Lancet 366
Suppl 1 (December): S38.
McRae, Donald. 2016. “The Return of Caster Semenya: Olympic Favourite and Ticking
Timebomb.” The Guardian. July 29.
Merck, Mandy. 2010. “The Question of Caster Semenya.” Radical Philosophy, no. 160.
https://www.radicalphilosophy.com/commentary/the-question-of-caster-semenya.
Munro, Brenna. 2010. “Caster Semenya: Gods and Monsters.” Safundi: The Journal of South
African and American Studies 11 (4): 383–96.
Nehm, Ross and Rebecca M. Jordan-Young. 2008. “Sex hormones” in secondary school biology
textbooks. Science & Education 17 (10): 1175-1190.
Nyong’o, Tavia. 2010. “The Unforgivable Transgression of Being Caster Semenya.” Women &
Performance: A Journal of Feminist Theory 20 (1): 95–100.
64
OII Australia. n.d. “Frequently Asked Questions (FAQs): Human Rights Reports.” OII Australia
- Intersex Australia. https://oii.org.au/faq/.
O’Sullivan, Sonia. 2016. “Sonia O’Sullivan: Intersex Athletes and the Problem of Testosterone.”
The Irish Times. June 9. http://www.irishtimes.com/sport/sonia-o-sullivan-intersex-
athletes-and-the-problem-of-testosterone-1.2677419.
Oudshoorn, Nelly. 1994. Beyond the Natural Body: An Archeology of Sex Hormones. London
and New York: Routledge.
Pieper, Lindsay Parks. 2014. “Sex Testing and the Maintenance of Western Femininity in
International Sport.” The International Journal of the History of Sport 31 (13): 1557–76.
———. 2016. Sex Testing: Gender Policing in Women’s Sports. Champaign, IL: University of
Illinois Press.
Rothenberg, Ben. 2015. “Tennis’s Top Women Balance Body Image With Ambition.” The New
York Times, July 10. https://www.nytimes.com/2015/07/11/sports/tennis/tenniss-top-
women-balance-body-image-with-quest-for-success.html.
Rowbottom, Mike. 2016. “Coe Admits IAAF and IOC ‘Surprised’ by CAS Ruling That Allows
Semenya to Compete at Rio 2016.” Inside the Games. August 11,
http://www.insidethegames.biz/articles/1040505/coe-admits-iaaf-and-ioc-surprised-by-
cas-ruling-that-allows-semenya-to-compete-at-rio-2016.
Rowbury, Shannon. 2016. “Shannon Rowbury Speaks Out…,” YouTube video, 2:44 minutes,
Posted by letsrundotcom, July 7, 2016,
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=qMQJeL302Qs.
65
SAHO (South African History Online). 2017. “Sara ‘Saartjie’ Baartman.”
http://www.sahistory.org.za/people/sara-saartjie-baartman.
Schuhmann, Antje. 2010. “Taming transgressions: South African nation building and ‘body
politics.’” Agenda 24 (83): 95–106.
Schultz, Jaime. 2011. “Caster Semenya and the ‘Question of Too’: Sex Testing in Elite Women’s
Sport and the Issue of Advantage.” Quest 63 (2): 228–43.
Sönksen, Peter, Malcolm A. Ferguson-Smith, L. Dawn Bavington, Richard I. G. Holt, David A.
Cowan, Don H. Catlin, Bruce Kidd, et al. 2015. “Medical and Ethical Concerns
Regarding Women with Hyperandrogenism and Elite Sport.” The Journal of Clinical
Endocrinology and Metabolism 100 (3): 825–27.
Ticktin, Miriam I. 2011. Casualties of Care: Immigration and the Politics of Humanitarianism in
France. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Tucker, Ross. 2016. Twitter post. July 13, 2016, 10:07 a.m.. https://twitter.com/Scienceofsport/.
Viloria, Hilda, and Maria Martínez-Patiño. 2012. “Reexamining Rationales of ‘Fairness’: An
Athlete and Insider’s Perspective on the New Policies on Hyperandrogenism in Elite
Female Athletes.” The American Journal of Bioethics 12 (7): 17–19.
Visser, Ellen de. 2013. “Topatletes Laten Teelballen Verwijderen Op Last van IAAF.” De
Volkskrant, May 25, http://www.volkskrant.nl/wetenschap/topatletes-laten-teelballen-
verwijderen-op-last-van-iaaf~a3446744/.
66
Wells, Cassandra. 2010. “Diagnosing Sex–Gender Verification and the IOC,” Proceedings:
International Symposium for Olympic Research London, Ontario, Canada: 301–311.
http://library.la84.org/SportsLibrary/ISOR/isor2010zg.pdf
Westbrook, Laurel, and Kristen Schilt. 2014. “Doing Gender, Determining Gender: Transgender
People, Gender Panics, and the Maintenance of the Sex/Gender/Sexuality System.”
Gender & Society 28 (1): 32–57.
Yildiz, Bulent O., Sheila Bolour, Keslie Woods, April Moore, and Ricardo Azziz. 2010.
“Visually Scoring Hirsutism.” Human Reproduction Update 16 (1): 51–64.
... 64 See, e.g., Richardson (in progress). 65 Karkazis and Jordan-Young (2018). indicator. ...
Article
Full-text available
Alex Byrne’s article, “Are Women Adult Human Females?”, asks a question that Byrne treats as nearly rhetorical. Byrne’s answer is, ‘clearly, yes’. Moreover, Byrne claims, woman is a biological category that does not admit of any interpretation as (also) a social category. It is important to respond to Byrne’s argument, but mostly because Byrne’s argument is a paradigmatic instance of a wider phenomenon. The slogan “women are adult human females” is a political slogan championed by anti-trans activists, appearing on billboards, pamphlets, and anti-trans online forums. In this paper, I respond to Byrne’s argument, revealing significant problems with its background assumptions, content, and methodology.
Article
Full-text available
If all goes as expected, new sex testing rules for female athletes will be in place for the 2012 Olympic Games in London this summer. The change came in response to the case of Caster Semenya, a young South African runner whose muscular body and spectacular win at the Berlin World Championships in 2009 in the 800m sparked an international debate over whether she was " really " female and thus eligible for women's competitions. The process for determining her eligibility, which included a detailed and protracted examination of her body to determine her " true " sex, left her shamed and humiliated. Amid ensuing debates about how to determine sex and whether universal sex testing is necessary in elite sports, the International Association of Athletics Federations (IAAF) released new policies for determining eligibility to compete as a female; the IOC is expected to pass a similar policy in the time for the summer Olympic Games. These policies engage a labyrinth of contemporary political and scientific struggles concerning the boundaries between male and female. Earlier modes of sex testing aimed to distinguish males from females, which might seem the easiest of tasks. Yet with at least six biological markers of sex, and none present in all people labeled " female, " each attempt to identify " biological women " failed, inappropriately excluding people that experts and lay people alike would consider women, and failing to exclude others whom most would consider men. For the new policies officials sought to identify " masculine advantage " rather than sex itself based on the notion that observed differences between male and female athleticism are due to differences in testosterone levels. Female athletes whose endogenous (ie, non-doping) levels are above the typical female range, which includes many women with intersex traits, are presumed to have an advantage over women with lower levels of testosterone. Females athletes known or suspected to have hyperandrogenism will be allowed to compete only if they agree to medical intervention, or if they are found to be " insensitive " to androgens. Earlier modes of sex testing aimed to distinguish males from females, which might seem the easiest of tasks. Yet … each attempt to identify " biological women " failed, inappropriately excluding people that experts and lay people alike would consider women, and failing to exclude others whom most would consider men. Like with earlier sex testing policies, there is an unquestioned assumption that " science " and " experts " can resolve what seems confusing about sex, and these policies once again draw a line between male and female. What is the perceived urgency to have such a line? And what are the proposed methods for producing it? What cultural work is performed by a return to an official, medico-scientific process of " gender verification " ? How is the task accomplished especially given that the scientific basis for the new policies is so weak? Three core elements bolster the story of " scientific gender verification " : the " sex hormone " concept; tensions between discursive and material " modes " of sex; and erasure of the contexts in which an athlete's sex is " doubted. " OUR HORMONES, OUR SELVES For a century, so-called sex hormones have been called on to do a lot of heavy lifting for explaining what makes us men and women. As Nelly Oudshoorn notes, however, the cultural idea of " sex hormones " as " essences of masculinity and femininity " doesn't map well onto what these steroids actually do in bodies, which extends far beyond producing sex traits. These hormones influence cell, tissue, organ, and functions in the brain, breast, bone, and the cardiovascular system. The labeling of testosterone and estrogen as " sex hormones " then persistently discounts data that doesn't fit this paradigm, distorting research, theory, and even medical practice owing to a persistent faith that so called sex hormones are responsible only and primarily for most physical and behavioral differences between men and women. What useful facts are supposedly revealed by testosterone levels in female bodies? Women's bodies make testosterone, and our bodies vary greatly in terms of the amounts we produce and the way we use it (the distribution and sensitivity of hormone receptors also varies within individuals, as well as between people). Testosterone levels then not only can't tell the fully story of someone's sex (or gender, for that matter), but they also can't predict an individual's athletic performance relative to other people, even those with dramatically different testosterone levels. Although it's common wisdom that " off the charts " testosterone levels will propel women into male-level performance, it's doesn't bear out. None of the women who have been suspended because of questions about their sex (and who likely have hyperandrogenism) have been world record holders; they aren't " outliers " among their elite athletic peers. A great athletic performance doesn't allow you to infer that someone has high testosterone, but then, a great athletic performance isn't what brings women athletes under scrutiny (at least
Book
Full-text available
What happens when a baby is born with “ambiguous” genitalia or a combination of “male” and “female” body parts? Clinicians and parents in these situations are confronted with complicated questions such as whether a girl can have XY chromosomes, or whether some penises are “too small” for a male sex assignment. Since the 1950s, standard treatment has involved determining a sex for these infants and performing surgery to normalize the infant’s genitalia. Over the past decade intersex advocates have mounted unprecedented challenges to treatment, offering alternative perspectives about the meaning and appropriate medical response to intersexuality and driving the field of those who treat intersex conditions into a deep crisis. Katrina Karkazis offers a nuanced, compassionate picture of these charged issues in Fixing Sex, the first book to examine contemporary controversies over the medical management of intersexuality in the United States from the multiple perspectives of those most intimately involved. Drawing extensively on interviews with adults with intersex conditions, parents, and physicians, Karkazis moves beyond the heated rhetoric to reveal the complex reality of how intersexuality is understood, treated, and experienced today. As she unravels the historical, technological, social, and political forces that have culminated in debates surrounding intersexuality, Karkazis exposes the contentious disagreements among theorists, physicians, intersex adults, activists, and parents—and all that those debates imply about gender and the changing landscape of intersex management. She argues that by viewing intersexuality exclusively through a narrow medical lens we avoid much more difficult questions. Do gender atypical bodies require treatment? Should physicians intervene to control the “sex” of the body? As this illuminating book reveals, debates over treatment for intersexuality force reassessment of the seemingly natural connections between gender, biology, and the body.
Article
Polycystic ovary syndrome (PCOS) affects 5–20% of women of reproductive age worldwide. The condition is characterized by hyperandrogenism, ovulatory dysfunction and polycystic ovarian morphology (PCOM) — with excessive androgen production by the ovaries being a key feature of PCOS. Metabolic dysfunction characterized by insulin resistance and compensatory hyperinsulinaemia is evident in the vast majority of affected individuals. PCOS increases the risk for type 2 diabetes mellitus, gestational diabetes and other pregnancy-related complications, venous thromboembolism, cerebrovascular and cardiovascular events and endometrial cancer. PCOS is a diagnosis of exclusion, based primarily on the presence of hyperandrogenism, ovulatory dysfunction and PCOM. Treatment should be tailored to the complaints and needs of the patient and involves targeting metabolic abnormalities through lifestyle changes, medication and potentially surgery for the prevention and management of excess weight, androgen suppression and/or blockade, endometrial protection, reproductive therapy and the detection and treatment of psychological features. This Primer summarizes the current state of knowledge regarding the epidemiology, mechanisms and pathophysiology, diagnosis, screening and prevention, management and future investigational directions of the disorder.
Article
Intersex people and bodies have been considered incapable of integration into society. Medical interventions on often healthy bodies remain the norm, addressing perceived familial and cultural demands, despite concerns about necessity, outcomes, conduct and consent. A global and decentralised intersex movement pursues simple core goals: the rights to bodily autonomy and self-determination, and an end to stigmatisation. The international human rights system is responding with an array of new policy statements from human rights institutions and a handful of national governments recognising the rights of intersex people. However, major challenges remain to implement those statements. Human rights violations of intersex individuals persist, deeply embedded in a deliberate history of silencing. Rhetoric of change to clinical practice remains unsubstantiated. Policy disjunctions arise in a framing of intersex issues as matters of sexual orientation and gender identity, rather than innate sex characteristics; this has led to a rhetoric of inclusion that is not matched by the reality. This paper provides an overview of harmful practices on intersex bodies, human rights developments, and rhetorics of change and inclusion.
Book
Incidents of doping in sports are common in news headlines, despite regulatory efforts. How did doping become a crisis? What does a doping violation actually entail? Who gets punished for breaking the rules of fair play? In Testing for Athlete Citizenship, Kathryn E. Henne, a former competitive athlete and an expert in the law and science of anti-doping regulation, examines the development of rules aimed at controlling performance enhancement in international sports. As international and celebrated figures, athletes are powerful symbols, yet few spectators realize that a global regulatory network is in place in an attempt to ensure ideals of fair play. The athletes caught and punished for doping are not always the ones using performance-enhancing drugs to cheat. In the case of female athletes, violations of fair play can stem from their inherent biological traits. Testing for Athlete Citizenship combines historical and ethnographic approaches to offer a compelling account of the origins and expansion of anti-doping regulation and gender-verification rules. Drawing on research conducted in Australasia, Europe, and North America, Henne details how race, gender, class, and postcolonial formations of power shape these ideas and regulatory practices. Testing for Athlete Citizenship makes a convincing case to rethink the power of regulation in sports and how it separates athletes as a distinct class of citizens subject to a unique set of rules because of their physical attributes and abilities.