Available via license: CC BY 4.0
Content may be subject to copyright.
47
Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science, 4 (2018) 47-63
ISSN 2526-2270
www.historiographyofscience.org
© The Authors 2018 – This is an open access article
Dossier Georges Canguilhem
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria1
Charles T. Wolfe2
Abstract:
In this paper we examine aspects of Canguilhem’s philosophy of biology, concerning the
knowledge of life and its consequences on science and vitalism. His concept of life stems
from the idea of a living individual, endowed with creative subjectivity and norms, a Kantian
view which “disconcerts logic”. In contrast, two different approaches ground naturalistic
perspectives to explore the logic of life (Jacob) and the logic of the living individual
(Maturana and Varela) in the 1970s. Although Canguilhem is closer to the second, there are
divergences; for example, unlike them, he does not dismiss vitalism, often referring to it in
his work and even at times describing himself as a vitalist. The reason may lie in their different
views of science.
Keywords:
Canguilhem; Vitalism; Biology; Logic of life; Autopoietic/Heteropoietic; Analysis/Synthesis;
Living individual
Received: 10 November 2017. Reviewed 30 January 2018. Accepted: 28 February 2018.
DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24117/2526-2270.2018.i4.06
____________________________________________________________________________
La vie déconcerte la logique
(Canguilhem 1977, 1)
To do biology, even with the aid of intelligence,
we sometimes need to feel like beasts ourselves
(Canguilhem 2008a, xx)
Introduction
In Canguilhem’s philosophy, life disconcerts logic by its intrinsically self-produced or
“autopoietic” nature in contrast with mechanical devices. This is logic in the sense of the
method of scientific discovery, even that which Claude Bernard theorized for experimenting
1Arantza Etxeberria is an Associate Professor at the University of the Basque Country UPV/EHU – IAS
Research Centre for Life, Mind and Society – Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science. Address:
Avenida de Tolosa 70, 20018 Donostia – San Sebastián – Spain. E-mail: arantza.etxeberria@ehu.eus
2 Charles T. Wolfe is a Research Fellow (Flemish Research Council) in the Department of Philosophy
and Moral Sciences and Sarton Centre for History of Science, Ghent University / Institute for Advanced
Study at the Central European University, Budapest. Address: Blandijnberg 2, 9000 Gent – Belgium. E-
mail: ctwolfe1@gmail.com
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
48
with organisms in vivo (Bernard 1865, Coleman 1985), but also logic understood as a model
or scheme of the internal organization or functional integration that underlies the living
state. Therefore, the knowledge of life, the method, is challenging for biology. Experimental
biology tends to consider living beings as machines, and the knowledge operation required
for that leaves part of life aside; it cannot grasp life in full. In fact, although Canguilhem as a
historian and philosopher of science has a high regard for biology,3 he nevertheless thinks
that there is something missing in scientific knowledge trying to understand life via analysis,
although this is the only way knowledge can probably proceed. The analysis/synthesis
dichotomy is important for Canguilhem’s view on life and especially for his understanding of
medicine, and the pathological more generally. Life is not analyzable, he contends, i.e., life
defies scientific methods because of its inherent plasticity and variability, and also in its
interactive or relational capacity, especially because of his conceptualization of the milieu as
an intermediary between two entities. Canguilhem’s philosophy develops from a given
understanding of life. It has to do with its capabilities to establish its multiple own norms
according to its environment or milieu, and change them to establish a new physiological
order when required.4
This is the main distinctive feature of Canguilhem’s vitalism. Not that he posits the
matter of life as an ontological or metaphysical entity different from that of physicochemical
systems. Canguilhem denies that vitalism is a metaphysics, and then adds immediately
afterwards that it is “the recognition of the originality of the fact of life [le fait vital]”
(Canguilhem 1965, 156). But what is this originality, then? It is not an ontological specificity
(like a Drieschian entelechy), yet is a feature which resists any ‘logic of life’. Although he
warns that there are intellectual dangers inherent in positing that living beings are like an
empire within an empire – imperium in imperio – (Canguilhem 1965, 95), he asserts that Life
itself determines livings beings to act in interpretive, purposive, normative, vital ways. Life
“disconcerts logic” (Canguilhem 1977, 1). He does not reject biology’s kind of knowledge as
science either. It is mainly the idea that life is something that is beyond the knowledge
capabilities of a logic or method as these are devised for inert systems, those that can be
manipulated from the outside. The something beyond is related to the fact that one has to
be alive to be able to grasp it. And being alive is the same as being synthetic, as opposed to
analytic, and synthetic, like autopoietic, means that it is a system in continuous creativity.
Here we examine Canguilhem’s ideas concerning the knowledge of life and its
consequences on science and vitalism. First, his concept of life, which stems from the idea of
the living individual, as endowed with creative subjectivity and norms; we will consider it as
a Kantian view which shares Kant’s challenge to a science for living beings (as we discuss in
the next section). Second, why life disconcerts logic. In order to explicate this, we examine
two different perspectives, the evolutionary genetically based logic of life of works such as
Jacob’s, and the organizational dynamic logic of the individual of the autopoietic school.
Although Canguilhem is closer to the second, both in its conclusions and in the kind of
materials used to depict the image, there are divergences. For example, unlike them, he does
3 The relation of Canguilhem with science and its knowledge has been questioned (for example Gabel
2015 mentions Jacob’s comment in the Web Stories video, that Canguilhem told him that he would not
have written much of what he did, had he read Jacob earlier. Although Jacob seems to have
understood Canguilhem’s remark at face value, we could always think he was just being polite and
appreciative of the work of the scientist). In any case we will argue that Canguilhem’s thesis is not
empirical and therefore not vulnerable in principle to such criticisms.
4 “Man is only truly healthy when he is capable of multiple norms, when he is more than normal. The
measure of health is a certain capacity to overcome organic crises in order to establish a new
physiological order, different from the initial order. In all seriousness, health is the ability [le luxe] to
fall ill and then get over it. On the contrary, illness is the reduction of the power to overcome other
illnesses” (Canguilhem 1965, 167). See also (Canguilhem 1972, 77, 155). (All translations are ours unless
otherwise indicated).
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
49
not dismiss vitalism. Third, we explore his claim for vitalism connected with views about the
role of analysis in the scientific knowledge of life and his characterization of life as synthesis
(in the second and third sections, respectively).
Canguilhem and the Life of an Individual
Since the second half of the 19th century there have been two distinctive styles in the study
of biology. Physiology is centered in the living individual, in the organism, and its main topic
is the organization of parts or organs to produce the organized whole. The other style is that
of evolutionary biology, concerned by the changes in lineages of individual forms through –
mainly – genealogical processes.
The philosophical topic of physiology is biological individuality, its delimitation and its
cohesion. Physiology’s problem is how a living individual maintains its integrity and
organization through the causal interactions of its parts and the regulation of those
interactions (Bernard 1878-1879; Pradeu 2016). This was the approach pursued
experimentally by Claude Bernard’s physiology, as it aimed to reach scientific status; some
considered him as the Newton of medicine (see note 5 below). Physiology thus understood
parted ways with the more observational approach of natural history. Canguilhem’s
philosophy of life is embedded in this kind of thinking and operates within this framework.
The antagonism between mechanist and vitalist views about the special status of living
beings and in what sense they constitute a challenge for the scientific knowledge of life are
ingrained here.
This subject matter is reminiscent of Kant’s view of organized beings and scientific
knowledge. Kant promoted the view of living beings as purposeful and self-organized, in his
1790 Critique of Judgment (§ 65, AA 5, 374). There he established the grounds for
understanding organized beings whose components are mutually dependent on each other
and on the whole they generate. Being teleological and self-organized they are very different
from a watch, organised according to a designer’s plan. But this understanding set a limit for
science. Difficulties appear in the project of reconciling it with the conceptual framework
Kant developed for natural sciences in his Critique of Pure Reason (1781), founded in natural
laws without purposiveness, in external causes, and in mechanical principles (Nuño de la
Rosa and Etxeberria 2010). Kant did not think there can be a naturalist scientific explanation
for living beings, such as there is one for physical systems. His declaration that there will not
be a “Newton of the blade of grass”5 is well known: “Indeed, so certain is it, that we may
confidently assert that it is absurd for human beings even to entertain any thought of so
doing or to hope that maybe another Newton may some day arise, to make intelligible to us
even the genesis of but a blade of grass from natural laws that no design has ordered.” (Kant,
Critique of Judgment, § 75, AA 5, 400).6
Kant’s view of the organism as a self-organized system constitutes a challenge for
science. There have been attempts to reconcile teleology and mechanism, such as Lenoir
5 Since then, there was a long controversy about who could be the scientific figure that would
contradict Kant. According to Cassirer, for biologists like Haeckel, Darwin was the “Newton of the
blade of grass,” yet Roux rejected this (Cassirer 1950, 163). Others have mentioned Claude Bernard
(Prochiantz 1990), and still others thoroughly agree with Kant (Nuño de la Rosa and Etxeberria 2010).
We return to this topic in the final section.
6 This statement of Kant’s is often quoted approvingly, a rare exception being Zammito (2006), who
notes that Kant is neatly placing himself in the rearguard of scientific thought of his time concerning
living entities. Our point here is simply to note the existence of this influential position according to
which ‘Life’ is not reducible to a certain set of empirical (measurable, quantifiable) features. In that
sense Canguilhem can be said to be a Kantian. See Brilman (2017) for an interesting development of
this connection.
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
50
(1982)’s who understood the Kantian tradition as a way to integrate self-organization and
teleology within scientific biology. But naturalizing efforts or scientific explanations of
material self-organizing appear to be reductionistic7 (Moss and Newman 2016). In sum, the
Kantian challenge is basically the problem of whether our knowledge of life or of living
systems can be naturalized. Canguilhem’s approach to this, asks how we can know about
living beings with the kind of knowledge developed to investigate inanimate realms such the
production of technical devices.
Canguilhem’s view of living systems as actively self-produced or autopoietic
establishes the difference with technological objects. He referred to living beings as
“autopoétique” or “autopo(i)etic”8 in “L’expérimentation en biologie animale”, an essay on
the experimental tradition started by Claude Bernard, originally delivered as a talk in 1951 and
included in La connaissance de la vie. There he distinguishes the “heteropoietic” character of
human technical activity in the interaction with the environment: “Man first experiences and
experiments with biological activity in his relations of technical adaptation to the milieu. Such
technique is heteropoetic, adjusted to the outside, and it takes from the outside its means,
or the means to its means” (Canguilhem 2008a, 9). However, he contends that when in
interaction with other living beings, experimenters become aware of the “autopoetic
character of organic activity”. The realization of this has been an achievement: “Only after a
long series of obstacles surmounted and errors acknowledged did man come to suspect and
recognize the autopoetic character of organic activity and to rectify progressively, in contact
with biological phenomena, the guiding concepts of experimentation.” Human action
producing technology “presupposes a minima logic – for the representation of the exterior
real, which human technique modifies, determines the discursive, reasoned facet of the
artisan’s activity, and all the more so the engineer’s.” This does not work in the case of living
entities because humans cannot produce them externally, therefore: “we must abandon this
logic of human action if we are to understand living functions” (Canguilhem 2008a, 9).
Canguilhem’s attention is focused on the kind of knowledge of or attitude towards
living entities, in epistemological terms. The “autopoetic” character of living beings, in
contrast with artefacts, refers to the kind of object of knowledge. Later Maturana and Varela
(1973, 1980) will use a similar term (autopoiesis) to characterise the constitutive organization
of living beings. The work of Rheinberger (2015) further pursues this reflection on the nature
of the different knowledge objects produced by science to explain life. This topic appears
also in the analysis/synthesis opposition: Canguilhem insists that knowledge of living systems
proceeds by analysis, to know living individuals science or biology has to analyze them, while
they are ontologically synthetic, as they dynamically make themselves in an active and
creative way. As he remarks in “Le tout et la partie dans la pensée biologique”:
The physiology of regulation (or homeostasis, as it has been called since Walter
Bradford Cannon), together with cytologic morphology, enabled Bernard to treat the
organism as a whole and to develop an analytic science of organic functions without
7 To be precise, there is a ‘material difficulty’ of the sort just outlined, and a ‘conceptual difficulty’ in
the sense that such programs strongly invoke the Kantian pedigree, while somehow overlooking the
fact that a core element of the Kantian concept of the living (of organism) is that it cannot be the
object of a causal-naturalist science.
8 Canguilhem wrote “autopoétique” and “heteropoétique” without the “i”, translated into English as
“autopoetic” and “heteropoetic” in Canguilhem (2008a). As the term has stabilized in usage as
“autopoiesis” (reflecting the Greek ποίησις), we use the term in this way throughout the paper. When
we quote Canguilhem we write in the same way he wrote it, i.e., without the “i”; “autopoetic”
(“autopoétique”) and “heteropoetic” (“heteropoétique”).
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
51
brushing aside the fact that a living thing is, in the true sense of the word, a synthesis.
(Canguilhem 1994, 298).
To argue that living bodies are special, Canguilhem takes over Kurt Goldstein’s chief
holistic or organismic idea presented in his influential work The Organism (1934/1939) – it is
the organism as a totality, not a cluster of functions or organs, which acts and reacts as a
unified approach to its environment and its challenges (Canguilhem 1972, 49) – and strips it
of some of its more overtly metaphysical trappings. Yet the holistic dimension, the emphasis
on the ‘whole person’, reappears now and then with surprisingly existentialist and humanist
overtones, when Canguilhem opposes Life to technology and the various forms of the
“mechanization of life.”
In sum, in Canguilhem’s unique way of engaging with ‘organisms’ and the question of
their uniqueness we find one of the curious features of Goldstein’s account: the way in which
he wavers or moves back and forth between a cautious, epistemological position
(reminiscent of the Kantian regulative ideal in the third Critique) in which organisms are real
and special because of the way we cognitively constitute them, and a bold, ontological position
in which organisms are real because of basic, intrinsic features which are just there. However,
this convenient distinction between the epistemological (projective, constitutive) vision of
biological entities and the ontological vision (strong vitalist, ‘rational metaphysics’ as Kant
might have said) is somewhat muddied when Canguilhem introduces a further vitalist twist,
in “Aspects du vitalisme”: that it might be an objective (‘ontological’) feature of living beings
that they are interpretive beings, and especially that they need to consider other entities as
themselves organismic, purposive, vital. We interpret Canguilhem as alluding to this need of
being interactively immersed with other organisms to know what they are, when he writes
in La connaissance de la vie that “We suspect that, to do mathematics, it would suffice that
we be angels. But to do biology, even with the aid of intelligence, we sometimes need to feel
like beasts ourselves” (Canguilhem 2008a, xx). There may also be an existentialist parfum in
Canguilhem’s reflections, as when he describes this interpretive stance as essentially a kind
of fundamental existential attitude. In any case what is distinctive of his position, especially
when we consider the core arguments of The Normal and the Pathological, is the
presupposition that normativity is a power or capacity proper to living beings:
We, on the other hand, think that the fact that a living man reacts to a lesion, infection,
functional anarchy by means of a disease, expresses the fundamental fact that life is
not indifferent to the conditions in which it is possible, that life is polarity and thereby
even an unconscious position of value; in short, life is in fact a normative activity.
Normative, in philosophy, means every judgment which evaluates or qualifies a fact in
relation to a norm, but this mode of judgment is essentially subordinate to that which
establishes norms. Normative, in the fullest sense of the word, is that which establishes
norms. And it is in this sense that we plan to talk about biological normativity.
(Canguilhem 1972, 126-127)
We find here an insistence that there is something unique about living entities that
makes them creators of a certain world which they inhabit. Upon closer examination, this
idea seems to contain some Nietzschean overtones (Foucault also pointed to this aspect in
his mentor’s work: Foucault 1991, 21), namely, the idea that values, norms and other higher-
level constructs are in fact products of our vital instincts, so that life integrates rationality to
itself through its normative activity. In a lecture in the problem of regulations in the organism
and society, Canguilhem also insists that
An organism is an entirely exceptional mode of being, because there is no real
difference, properly speaking, between its existence and the rule or norm of its
existence. From the time an organism exists, is alive, that organism is ‘possible’, i.e., it
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
52
fulfils the ideal of an organism; the norm or rule of its being [existence] is given by its
existence itself. (Canguilhem 2002, 106-107)
Yet he does not appeal to a disembodied, foundational subjectivity, like more anti-
naturalistic trends in phenomenology; there is no pure ego contemplating the reality of the
flesh like a sailor in a ship, for him. As regards the relevance of experience, it would seem that
– despite their shared affinity for Goldstein – it is more than unlikely that Canguilhem would
go as far as Merleau-Ponty, as we see when he reflects on the limitations of a
conceptualization of the living body as “inaccessible to others, accessible only to its titular
holder” (Canguilhem 2008b, 476).
Canguilhem’s position on organic uniqueness and what he somewhat cryptically calls
‘experience’ is subtly yet significantly different:
the classical vitalist grants that living beings belong to a physical environment, yet
asserts that they are an exception to physical laws. This is the inexcusable
philosophical mistake, in my view. There can be no kingdom within a kingdom [empire
dans un empire], or else there is no kingdom at all. There can only be one philosophy
of empire, that which rejects division and imperialism. [...] One cannot defend the
originality of biological phenomena and by extension, of biology, by delimiting a zone
of indeterminacy, dissidence or heresy within an overall physicochemical
environment of motion and inertia. If we are to affirm the originality of the biological,
it must be as a reign over the totality of experience, not over little islands of experience.
Ultimately, classical vitalism is (paradoxically) too modest, in its reluctance to
universalize its conception of experience. (Canguilhem 1965, 95; emphasis added)
‘Classical’ vitalism as described here is what one of us has termed substantival vitalism
elsewhere (Wolfe 2011, 2015a). And Canguilhem’s diagnosis of an “inexcusable philosophical
mistake” is clear enough. But what should we make then of his defense of the “originality of
the biology,” i.e. the autonomy of biology, as a “reign over the totality of experience”? What
looks at first glance like metaphysical holism might instead be an ‘attitudinal’ conception,
that is, a point of view on experience.
Canguilhem was aware and acceptant of the biology of his times,9 and paid attention
both to the physiological perspective and to the evolutionary/molecular biology perspective.
Yet he does not appear to be keen to develop what we could call a logic of life or the living,
why? Taking into account Canguilhem’s views, we examine some aspects of the nature of life
and organisms as discussed in the biology of the 1970s, such as F. Jacob’s and Maturana and
Varela’s, each proposing a particular proposal for a logic in biology. Canguilhem’s ideas
contrast with those of biologists of the time: we will specifically take into account François
Jacob’s evolutionary perspective in La logique du vivant and Humberto Maturana and
Francisco Varela’s organizational one in Autopoiesis and cognition. Both books were originally
written in the early 1970s (in languages different from English) and elaborate very different
research programs to explore living organization.
9 Yet some authors appear dismissive of the understanding of genetics and evolutionary biology of
authors of the French philosophical tradition. For example, Gabel writes: “In France, institutional
biology largely rejected both Darwinian natural selection and Mendelian genetics. Biologists do not
believe that evolution could be explained by natural selection” (Gabel 2016, 71). This is an often
repeated cliché but unlikely. In the case of Canguilhem’s work, we should consider it more a case of
philosophical disagreement than of bad scientific perception. Similarly, if Bernard ignored
evolutionary biology it was because it was hardly relevant for the experimental approach he pursued
(see note 10).
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
53
The Logic of Life at Large
In the philosophy of biology of the 19th and 20th centuries two different intuitions about life,
related either to the evolution of life at large, or to the organization of particular living
individuals, have run parallel courses.10 The former was mainly concerned with the fact that
all life is connected, and requires that connection, so that the study of isolated individuals, as
it is usual in physiology, is very limited and insufficient. The latter aimed to explain the
physiological organization of living entities as organisms or agents, both constitutively and
interactively.
In the early 1970s, related to the above-mentioned distinction of two styles of biology,
different and opposed views were held on the primacy of organization and reproduction /
evolution for biology. The former would imply a principle grounding the mechanisms of living
individuality; the latter, a connection among somewhat ephemeral living forms. These
differences implied separate research programs for biology. François Jacob’s logic of life
represents the mainstream view that the most important feature of life is reproduction and
evolution (although very aware of the historical concerns for organization, Jacob considered
them to be overcome with the new findings in molecular biology).
Jacob’s La logique du vivant was a very important book in the 1970s in which the author,
already a Nobel Prize winner and a widely recognized molecular biologist, made a remarkable
attempt at reconstructing the history and philosophy of biology around the notion of
biological organization and the “logic of life”. Jacob attempted to reconcile classical views in
European continental thought on biology with views stemming from contemporary ideas on
genetics and evolution. It is full of enthusiasm towards the notion of biological information
and the logic of genetics of the 1960s and 1970s, which he understands to be the corollary of
biological struggles to understand biological organization. (This he shares with Canguilhem
to a certain point, as is visible in the latter’s 1966 additions to Le normal et le pathologique,
displaying a real openness to genetics as a “nouvelle connaissance de la vie”.) This book was
very important and had a deep influence on biologists of the time and defends a model of
life sympathetic to informational formalisms for genetic regulation.
For Jacob, the special features of life appear in the evolutionary genetic image, linked
not to the properties of living beings studied by classical philosophy (e.g. Thomism) but by
the new image made possible by the evolutionary science of the time. Some of its features
are that it enhances the view of life as a genealogically connected succession, rather than
mechanistically explainable in the living being:
An organism is merely a transition, a stage between what was and what will be (Jacob
1973, 2).
Everything in a living being is centred on reproduction (4).
Let us imagine an uninhabited world. We can conceive the establishment of systems
possessing certain properties of life, such as the ability to react to certain stimuli, to
assimilate, to breathe, or even to grow - but not to reproduce. Can they be called living
systems? Each represents the fruit of long and laborious elaboration. Each birth is a
unique event, without a morrow. Each occasion is an eternal recommencement.
Always at the mercy of some local cataclysm, such organizations can have only an
ephemeral existence. Moreover, their structure is rigidly fixed at the outset, incapable
10 As several authors have noted, Claude Bernard’s physiological tradition had little interest in
evolutionary or developmental biology, which it did not view as proper sciences. See (Normandin
2007).
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
54
of change. If, on the contrary, there emerges a system capable of reproduction, even
if only badly, slowly, and at great cost, that is a living system without any doubt. (4-5)
Jacob distinguishes explicitly the two views of biology. According to his preferred
perspective, evolutionary accounts consider the genealogical connection among living
beings so that from this perspective it is very evident that living beings are not systems that
arise and disappear due to their physicochemical properties, or at least not only because of
them, as many of their capacities have been inherited from their ancestors. These systems,
or part of them, have been informed by others:
Much of the controversy and misunderstanding, particularly with regard to the finality
of living beings, is caused by a confusion between these two attitudes. Each tries to
establish a system of order in the living world. For one, it is the order which links beings
to one another, sets up relationships and defines speciations. For the other, it is the
order between the structures by which functions are determined, activities
coordinated and the organism integrated. One considers living beings as the elements
of a vast system embracing the whole earth. The other considers the system formed
by each living being. One seeks to establish order between organisms; the other within
each organism. The two kinds of order meet at the level of heredity, which constitutes
the order of biological order, so to speak. (Jacob 1973, 7-8)
Darwinian evolution implies two main ideas: one is that of the genealogical connection
among all forms of life, which is often represented as the tree of life, the second is that of
natural selection as a main cause of evolution, implying that any trait or important feature of
living beings has evolved by natural selection. The received view of the Modern Synthesis
answered the two questions, proposing genes as the main ontology. However, critics of this
view affirm, as expected, that evolution does not contribute to our knowledge of living
organization. Very soon, and especially after the 2000s, new approaches in systemic and
synthetic biology made clear the need to take into account more organismic approaches
both for molecular and evolutionary biology. Jacob made a great effort to integrate the new
biology based on genetics and molecular biology with the organizational tradition. But he
appears to consider that the new understanding overcomes philosophical efforts to
understand living organization. In fact, Jacob identifies the genetic program, and the
determinism it embodies, as the fundamental element of its theory of the living. However he
also admits the importance of different levels of integration in the domain of life, called
integrons, each of them being characterized by some independence with respect to lower
ones.
Current systemic approaches consider the need of the two perspectives. On the one
hand, the study of evolution needs to include the mechanical causal processes taking place
in development – in addition to population dynamics at various levels and contingent events-
and processes responsible for organizations and entities that emerge in interactions such as
symbionts, ecosystems, etc. The extended evolutionary synthesis (Pigliucci and Müller, eds.,
2010) has vindicated a perspective that would be encompassing and inclusive. On the other
hand, the search of living organization cannot rely on the analysis of logical and mathematical
aspects only; organizations need to be studied in the material domain, which includes
evolutionary processes. Jacob underlines biology as an exploration of a logic of life that is
beyond any logic of the living individual. This knowledge is not concerned with individuality,
finality or causal mechanisms because it is a science of living forms that appear and are
transmitted in a contingent way.
In his review of François Jacob’s evolutionary perspective, Canguilhem (1971)
addresses the view of life taking place at the level of cells and the logic of reproduction, as
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
55
disclosed by the genetics of the time. He now maintains that “in order to understand what
we are as living beings, we must look to the chromosome, the gene, the DNA molecule. The
biochemical study of the bacteria is the beginning of self-knowledge of oneself as a living
being” (Canguilhem 1971, 23). This obliges one to reject finalism, and the centrality of
individuality. In addition, he seems to accept the new playground of biological science,
namely the informational perspective. Gabel quotes Jacob saying that only in the fifties
Canguilhem began reading contemporary biological research, and contends that after that
he gave up his vitalism. “Though he did not renounce his old positions – in fact he seems to
have felt his philosophy to be consistent with the discoveries of genetics and molecular
biology – he in fact moved away from both humanism and vitalism” (Gabel 2015, 82). We
disagree, as in that paper Canguilhem remains sceptical about informational logic of life. Also
philosophical positions may be modulated, but are not dictated by scientific facts, and this is
evident in Canguilhem’s case, who writes: “The execution of a program that is identified with
its realization is a blunt fact, without cause or responsibility. The logic of life does not refer
to any logician” (Canguilhem 1971, 23). In that sense, blind evolution is change without
history, as “evolution through natural selection is only history in its incidents, errors and rare
events” (24). And at the end of the review, Canguilhem reflects on Jacob’s much-quoted
pronouncement that biological research no longer “inquires into Life” (“On n’interroge plus
la vie aujourd’hui dans les laboratoires”), i.e., that the concept of Life (and by extension any
ontologically foundational clauses attached to work in the life sciences) no longer serves any
purpose in such work (Jacob 1970, 320).11 With a curious kind of pathos that is however not
‘Romantically anti-scientific’, he observes that living beings “think they live” a life “outside
of laboratories”, not realizing (Canguilhem literally writes “not knowing”) that in
laboratories, “Life has lost its life with its secret” (Canguilhem 1971, 25).12
The Logic of the Living
Very soon after the 1970s, and especially at the turn of the century, both in the philosophy of
biology and in most biological disciplines there was a big movement in search of systemic
and organizational principles, as is made evident by advances in systems biology, synthetic
biology and the extended evolutionary synthesis. Historically there are (at least) two
organizational traditions: the physiological one starting in Claude Bernard, to which
autopoiesis (and most of the work on biological autonomy) belongs, and the developmental
one which has led to structuralism and Evo-Devo (Etxeberria and Bich 2017; Etxeberria 2004).
Both are connected to Kant’s Critique of Judgment, although they have kept quite apart
during the twentieth century.
To Jacob’s plea for a logic of life, Varela and Maturana respond with a new vindication
of the centrality of the living individual as a foundation of biology, this time looking for a
“logic” of the living. Maturana and Varela’s notion of autopoiesis can be considered as an
answer to Jacob’s picture reject the informational perspective in biology, a view shared by
the Developmental Systems Theory in philosophy of biology, especially after Susan Oyama
(1985). Their narrative on the logic of the living, clearly influenced by Jacob’s book,
deliberately disputes many of his positions about the logic of life and the centrality of
11 At the conceptual level, this corresponds to Edouard Machery’s deliberately deflationary suggestion
(Machery 2012) that we should give up seeking to provide definitions of life, as these are either folk
concepts, or unresolvable with other competing definitions: namely, evolutionists, theoretical
biologists, self-organization theorists, molecular biochemists and artificial life researchers cannot
agree on a definition.
12He adds that “it is outside laboratories that love, birth and death continue to present living beings –
the children of order and chance – the immemorial figures of these questions that life science no
longer asks of life”.
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
56
reproduction and evolution. In contrast, for the positive part, it often draws Canguilhem’s
views to contrast Jacob’s informational stance. But their main claim goes far beyond
Canguilhem’s position and points to developments in biology that Canguilhem did not
foresee, probably because he was not aware of work in cybernetics and complex artificial
systems that was aiming to explore living phenomena through synthetic and systemic
models and simulations.
The autopoietic approach to the living belongs to the above-mentioned physiological
systemic tradition focused on the problem of the relational unity of the living, associated to
Kant’s understanding of organisms in the Critique of Judgment, Claude Bernard’s concept of
milieu intérieur, and the organicist tradition that considers life as organization – a tradition
including Hans Jonas and Jean Piaget among others.13 Other clear associations are with the
cybernetic movement, especially with second-order cybernetics (Etxeberria and Bich 2017).
The notion of autopoiesis was proposed by Maturana and Varela14 (Varela 1979;
Maturana and Varela 1973, 1980) to refer to the biological self-organization of individual living
beings, in contrast with other properties of life that the biology of their time considered as
primary (genes as DNA or informational properties). The basic idea of autopoiesis is self-
production, as a relational dynamic of components that generates or brings forth a
membrane or boundary. This constitutes the individual living being’s identity as separated
from the surroundings (Varela 1981).
The autopoietic approach to life is different from that of evolutionary and molecular
biology in that the theory focuses on autonomy and identity to naturalize them as marks of
life, and not in reproduction or evolution. They claim that living organization has primacy with
respect to those other phenomena associated to life (Etxeberria 2004). In contrast with
Jacob’s view, it is not life at large, but individual organisms and their autopoietic organization,
what is central for biology. All system components have the same status to explain the self-
referent dynamics by which they produce a unity; that is to say, living phenomenology is not
explained in terms of some components being information carriers, but in terms of relations.
Autopoietic systems, also initially called autopoietic machines, explore the general relational
scheme common to all living systems as the configuration of transformative processes
whose result is the configuration itself, so that identity and activity, producer and product
coincide (Bich and Etxeberria 2013). The individual identity constituted by the system itself
and not by anything external (heteropoietic) is a central idea of this approach. As said, some
of the distinctions they stress, for example the one between autopoiesis and heteropoiesis,
already appear in Canguilhem’s La connaissance de la vie, as we have noted before. The
relations of the autopoietic unity and its surroundings cannot be understood in terms of
input/output fixed interactions. Instead, non-specific perturbations are coupled with plastic
behaviors of the system within the range of internal coherence.
In their initial writings the authors embrace mechanism and criticize vitalism. This is
important because, according to them, vitalism focuses on entities bearing properties, in
contrast with the relational approach they vindicate in which properties appear in the
relations among components (see Bich and Arnellos 2012, 79). Maturana writes that
in a vitalistic explanation, the observer explicitly or implicitly assumes that the
properties of the system, or the characteristics of the phenomenon to be explained,
are to be found among the properties or among the characteristics of at least one of
13 Canguilhem sits somewhat unsteadily here, given that he is less of a ‘naïve (ontological) organicist’
than the rest.
14 Both Francisco Varela and Humberto Maturana have separately claimed to have coined the term,
referring to different sources for the invention. In this paper we maintain that they probably conceived
the notion from those passages of Canguilhem’s La connaissance de la vie in which he says that living
systems are autopoetic.
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
57
the components or processes that constitute the system or phenomenon. In a
mechanistic explanation the relations between components are necessary; in a
vitalistic explanation they are superfluous. (Maturana 1978, 30)
For interactionist or ecological perspectives living beings cannot be fully accounted for
in terms of intrinsic properties, but need to take into account relational properties arising
from interactions between living constituents.
There is a tension in naturalism, regarding whether the organization of living beings is
spontaneous or pre-existent. In fact, to the question: can life be understood in terms of
pure/actual/synchronic organization?, both creationists and evolutionists answer no! For
creationists the organization of life is pre-existent as life was created by a designer (God), for
evolutionists it is obtained from ancestors that transmit it in various ways. The notions of tree
of life and common ancestor suggest that the living state must come from another living
being, that living organization cannot be produced spontaneously. This would entail that a
naturalistic evolutionary theory with commitments to understand the organization of life –
and living beings – needs to give up the intention to explain the evolutionary process in an
algorithmic way (Dennett, genetic algorithms, ultra-Darwinist arguments…) and attend to
other factors that can give clues about how the elements of living organization come to be.
One difference between Canguilhem’s usage of the term ‘autopoetic’ and Maturana
and Varela’s account of autopoiesis may be that the latter intend to explore ways in which
the autopoiesis of living systems can be explored in artificial models. This is not exactly like
Canguilhem, who thinks that the autopoetic character of living beings is equivalent to their
not being susceptible to be grasped by knowledge. Canguilhem starts his book La
connaissance de la vie with the sentence: “Connaître c’est analyser” (“To know is to analyse”)
only to remind us quickly of the difficulties of grasping a true knowledge of what it means to
be alive through knowledge, through analysis. Today not everyone would accept that biology
as a science proceeds merely by analysis. On the contrary, many fields including Synthetic
Biology and, earlier, Artificial Life, have attempted to build synthetic models, systems or
simulations by integrating knowledge from many biological fields and exploring their
emergent and creative properties.
To try and understand Canguilhem in relation to recent theoretical biology (including
the ‘organizational’ theories, see Moreno and Mossio 2015, Bechtel 2007) results in a curious
situation. The concept of scientific knowledge associated with many of current fields is far
from the idea that the aim of models is to represent reality. In fact many systems can be in
some ways creative or autopoietic as well. Then to ask ‘are organisms unique in the physical
world? If so, why?’ as an orienting question does not only affect issues of an ontological kind
(what is life?), or an epistemological kind (how can we know life?), but also brings about
issues that start having a new relational or interactive character. If Canguilhem’s problem
was how the knower relates to a known that is autopoietic, similar situations appear with
respect to some scientific and technological products.
Canguilhem’s Claim for Vitalism
A main feature of vitalism in scientific research is to consider that living beings are in some
sense different from inorganic or inert beings;15 this does not always have further ontological
15 “The difference between what is life and what is not has changed with the advance of science. For
a long time, especially in antiquity, when life had total primacy, the opposite of the living was ‘dead’.
Later, it changed to simply ‘inorganic’, reflecting the fact that during the twentieth century the
question of what is life mostly concerned physicists, who sought to understand the peculiarities of
living matter, as opposed to the inorganic. Today, the opposite of life is generally ‘inert’, which is a
category that includes organic materials. The difference between the inorganic and the inert reflects
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
58
and methodological implications. Canguilhem´s work appears to be among those believing
the first. Canguilhem appears more cautious than Jacob or other prominent figures who try
to dissolve the problem of what life is into an evolutionary logic. This deflationary view
underlies usual attempts to substitute the definition of life by a list of living properties, such
as those appearing in many biology textbooks. In contrast Canguilhem is suspicious of the
rejection of vitalism in this way because many of the features that are associated with life, in
contrast with those of inanimate systems do surreptitiously appear in normative concepts
such as evolutionary advantage (1971, 24).
Canguilhem often refers to vitalism in his work, going as far as describing himself –
playfully – as a vitalist.16 He acknowledges that vitalism is a position that is difficult to
maintain. As Dominique Lecourt comments, “Canguilhem, a hero of the Resistance, clearly
expresses the difficulty of presenting himself as a ‘vitalist’ in 1946-1947” (Lecourt 2011, 8),
and he thus quotes this passage from “Aspects of Vitalism”:
Today, above all, the usage of vitalist biology by Nazi ideology, the mystification that
consisted in using theories of Ganzheit to advocate against individualist, atomist, and
mechanist liberalism and in favor of totalitarian forces and social forms, and the rather
easy conversion of vitalist biologists to Nazism have served to confirm the accusation
formulated by positivist philosophers like Philipp Frank, as well as by Marxists (Marcel
Prenant) that it is a “reactionary biology”. (Canguilhem 1965, 97; Canguilhem 2008a,
72)
In the same essay, Canguilhem asserts from the outset that when the philosopher
inquires into biological life, she has little to expect or gain from “a biology fascinated by the
prestige of the physicochemical sciences, reduced to the role of a satellite of these sciences”
(Canguilhem 1965, 83; Canguilhem 2008a, 59). What this entails for vitalism is that it has a
specifically philosophical place, whether it is scientifically ‘validated’ or ‘refuted’, and apart
from its status as a scientific ‘construction’. In this sense, as Canguilhem suggests in “Aspects
du vitalisme”, vitalism is not like geocentrism or phlogiston: it is not refutable in quite the same
way.17
To summarize these two dimensions of Canguilhem’s thought, one could say that on
the one hand his vitalism is heuristic, a claim that living phenomena need to be approached
in a certain way in order to be understood; but on the other hand, it possesses a more
ontological, Aristotelian dimension. Consider the example Canguilhem had given in “Aspects
du vitalisme”: vitalism is not like (the theory of) phlogiston or geocentrism. Now, faced with
this ‘fact’ that vitalism is not like phlogiston, there are two possible responses: it’s not like
phlogiston because it’s true and thus one’s ontology needs to include it or it’s not like
phlogiston because it has this heuristic value, or explanatory power.
For Canguilhem vitalism is a way to understand Life in a certain way in order not to miss
its essential spontaneity; historically, thinkers known as vitalists have had what he calls “this
an increasing awareness that life is so complex that the scientific study of transients cannot attempt
to start from raw inorganic materials, but rather needs to begin with organic compounds and
processes to study how these, or similar alternatives, are produced in living systems and the
laboratory” (Etxeberria and Ruiz-Mirazo 2009, S33-4).
16 For example, in the Foreword to his book on the development of the notion of reflex: “Il nous
importe peu d’être ou tenu pour vitaliste…” (It does not matter to us to be or to be considered a
vitalist ...) and he presents the book itself as a “defense of vitalist biology” (Canguilhem 1955, 1). But
some years earlier, he had devoted one article exclusively to the topic, “Aspects du vitalisme”
(originally a series of lectures given at the Collège Philosophique in Paris in 1946-1947), in Canguilhem
1965.
17 (Canguilhem 1965, 84; Canguilhem 2008a, 60). The Medawars note that it is hard to devise an
experiment to ‘refute’ vitalism. (Medawar and Medawar 1983)
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
59
vitalist confidence in the spontaneity of life” (Canguilhem 1965, 89). In other words, the
philosopher in this position is almost inexorably led to a vitalist positionnement. The type of
questions she will have for biological science entails that the latter not be conceived of in
reductionist terms, although Canguilhem doesn’t explicitly say if a purely physicochemical
perspective on biological entities is flawed ontologically, or just methodologically.
Nevertheless, this is a loaded, rather a prioristic conception of biological science, actually
quite reminiscent of the holism of Goldstein, who Canguilhem openly credits as a major
influence.18
But what sort of claim is the insistence on the originality of vital facts? Just because it
is not naïve ontological vitalism does not mean it is vitalism without any ontology. As this is
not an analysis of vitalism in general but of certain issues in the thought of Canguilhem, it
may be worth rapidly clarifying this terminology. It seems that, in addition to a kind of ‘de
facto’ vitalism of some life scientists who insist on the specificity of the systems they study,
including in relation to the objects of other sciences such as chemistry and physics, there is a
non-ontological vitalism, articulated in thinkers like Claude Bernard and at times in Xavier
Bichat, distinct from an ontological vitalism in that the latter will consider the difference
between living and non-living beings, organisms and mechanisms, ‘whole-person’ analyses in
medicine and molecular analyses, etc., as having ontological significance and/or as being
ontologically grounded.
This sense of privacy, of inaccessible interiority, is a crucial feature of many defences
of what organisms are and how they are different from machines. This raises the issue of the
relation between Canguilhem and phenomenology.19 That is, while mainstream biologists
thought the problem with vitalism was its appeal to immaterial vital forces, or ‘entelechies’
that could not themselves be located anywhere in the spatiotemporal world, there may be a
different, more philosophical problem with vitalism, in that it can become an appeal to a kind
of foundationalist subjectivity, a Self, a Centre. Interestingly – and idiosyncratically –
Canguilhem’s way of renewing vitalism is neither that of the “classical” vitalist, in his terms
(which matches the standard critical portrayal of the vitalist), nor that of the subjectivist.
Kurt Goldstein and Canguilhem were, we suggest, onto something when they insisted
that rather than say what is unique about the biological, we look to the observer: to be an
organism is to have a point of view on organisms; one which produces intelligibility, which
reveals organisms as meaning-producing beings. Goldstein stressed a kind of ‘standpoint’
dimension in ‘the organism’ (in fact, typically the human patient), namely, the idea that we
necessarily have ‘points of view’ on our environment and that such points of view enter into
the basic definition of what it is to be such an organism. Canguilhem gave further inflection
to this idea by speaking of how vitalism is not a mere scientific theory (true or false, refutable,
experimental, etc.) but, crucially, something existential, what he calls an exigence:
Vitalism expresses a permanent requirement or demand [exigence] of life in living
beings, the self-identity of life which is immanent in living beings. This explains why
mechanistic biologists and rationalist philosophers criticize vitalism for being nebulous
18 On Canguilhem and Goldstein, Gayon (1998, 309-310) and Métraux (2005) make some useful
observations (Métraux also reproduces a letter from Canguilhem to Goldstein); see also Wolfe (2015b).
Gayon notes several further references to Goldstein in (Canguilhem 1965, 11–13, 24, 146); (Canguilhem
2002, 347); (Canguilhem 1977, 138). Canguilhem (along with Merleau-Ponty) played a key role in the
introduction of Goldstein into France, through the translation of the Organism book, which
Canguilhem initiated (the co-translator, Jean Kuntz was his student) and also by translating Goldstein’s
article on the “problème épistémologique de la biologie” together with his wife Simone.
19 For a nice discussion which makes Canguilhem a phenomenologist, see (Gérard 2010); for an equally
convincing reading which seeks to draw Canguilhem away from phenomenology, see (Sholl 2012).
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
60
and vague. It is normal, if vitalism is primarily a ‘demand’, that it is difficult to formulate
it in a series of determinations. (Canguilhem 1965, 86).
Other prominent recent figures like Varela also underline the uniqueness of the
biological by rejecting that life can be characterized by providing some empirical criteria and
vindicate the need for a concept of life that takes into account the self-producing activities
of living systems. Yet he explicitly rejects vitalism and embraces naturalism. In this respect
Weber and Varela differ from Kant, who believed that living organization cannot be explained
scientifically: “Our immodest conclusion is that Kant, although foreseeing the impossibility
of a purely mechanical, Newtonian account of life, nonetheless was wrong in denying the
possibility of a coherent explanation of the organism. But this ‘Newton of the Grassblade’
was surely not Darwin.” Instead, they maintain that it is the “convergence of philosophical
and biological thinking” which offered “an objective account of biological individuality that
joins in circle with the constitution of a subject” (Weber and Varela 2002, 120-121). Thus, they
think that the times are ripe for a naturalistic understanding of the living individual. However
both authors would probably agree with Canguilhem that there is a difference between
knowing life and interacting with it.
Summary/Conclusions
Does life have a logic that can be scientifically studied? Kant answered no; later biologists
have tried to find affirmative answers based either in evolution by natural selection or in self-
organization.
In this paper we have tried to show the main problems Canguilhem faced in challenging
the existence of a logic of life, namely embodiment, relations of the living with other living
organisms, and sympathy to some phenomenological ideas about the nature of life and living
bodies, notably their ‘existential’ and ‘attitudinal’ dimensions (even though this definitely
does not make him a phenomenologist), although he does not go all the way into literal
appeals to the “truth of my body” (Canguilhem 2008b, 475); his residual existentialism (with
occasional overtones of anthropocentrism) may hold some lessons for present-day thinking
about life.
Perhaps the difference between vitalism and organicism, given the Kantian difficulties
for a science of the living, lies in the difference between a complete scepticism (towards
some vitalist positions, although most of them are caricatures) and the hope that science can
advance, however partially or perspectivally, in understanding at least some aspects of
biological organization. Although it is clear that most vitalists were in agreement with this
position, criticisms (like for example those of logical empiricists like Frank, although closer
reading reveals important nuances20) have built a straw-man of vitalism as a position that
wholly rejects scientific understanding of life and embraces mysticism instead. Canguilhem is
not a vitalist according to this excessively partial picture, yet he also does not believe that life
has a logic that can be grasped in fixed norms or regulations. And this not only because the
norms are internal or internally produced and managed (like in autopoiesis), but also and
more importantly because they are variable and their very organization may be contingent in
some respects. The recognition that some scientific models may have properties of the kind
Canguilhem attributes to living beings – that is to say, they are also emergent, creative, and
synthetic, and oblige scientists to interact with their products instead of just analyse or
represent them – may be a landmark separating different views of science. Organicism tends
to value these models as scientific whereas vitalism as understood by and in Canguilhem,
takes a step back from scientific models.
20 On such nuances see (Chen, ms. a and b)
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
61
Acknowledgments
The authors wish to thank Sebastjan Vörös for his helpful reading of an earlier draft of this
paper. AE acknowledges funding from projects IT 590-13 (Basque Government) and FFI2014-
52173-P (Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness, Spain), CW was funded by the FWO
(Flemish Research Council) and then by the IAS (Institute for Advanced Study) at CEU,
Budapest.
References
Bechtel, William. 2007. Biological mechanisms: Organized to maintain autonomy. In Systems
Biology: Philosophical Foundations, edited by F. Boogerd, F.J. Bruggeman, J-H.S.
Hofmeyr, and H.V. Westerhoff, 269-302. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Bernard, Claude. 1865. Introduction à l’étude de la médecine expérimentale. Paris: J.-B. Baillière
and Fils.
Bernard, Claude. 1878-1879. Leçons sur les phénomènes de la vie communs aux animaux et aux
végétaux, 2 vols., Paris, J.-B. Baillière.
Bich, Leonardo and Arnellos, Argyris. 2012. Autopoiesis, autonomy, and organizational
biology: critical remarks on ‘Life after Ashby’. Cybernetics and human knowing 19(4): 75-
103.
Bich, Leonardo and Etxeberria, Arantza. 2013. Systems, Autopoietic, in Encyclopedia of
Systems Biology, edited by Dubitzky, W., Wolkenhauer, O., Cho, K-H. and Yokota, H.,
2110-2113. New York: Springer.
Brilman, Marina. 2017. Canguilhem’s Critique of Kant: Bringing Rationality Back to Life.
Theory, Culture and Society (n.p.).
Canguilhem, Georges. 1972 [1943]. Le Normal et le pathologique. Paris: PUF.
Canguilhem, Georges. 1965 [1952]. La connaissance de la vie. Paris: Vrin.
Canguilhem, Georges. 1977 [1955]. La formation du concept de réflexe aux XVIIe et XVIIIe siècles.
Paris: Vrin.
Canguilhem, Georges. 2002 [1968]. Études d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences concernant
les vivants et la vie. Paris: Vrin.
Canguilhem, Georges. 1971. Logique du vivant et histoire de la biologie. Sciences 71: 20-25
Canguilhem, Georges. 1977. Idéologie et rationalité dans l’histoire des sciences de la vie. Paris:
Vrin.
Canguilhem, Georges. 1989. The normal and the pathological, ed. Robert S. Cohen, trans.
Carolyn R. Fawcett. New York: Zone Books.
Canguilhem, Georges. 1994. A vital rationalist: selected writings from Georges Canguilhem, ed.
François Delaporte, trans. Arthur Goldhammer. New York: Zone Books.
Canguilhem, Georges. 2002. Puissance et limites de la rationalité en médecine (1978). In
Canguilhem, Études d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences concernant les vivants et la
vie, 392-411. Paris: Vrin
Canguilhem, Georges. 2008a. Knowledge of Life. Edited by Paola Marrati and Todd Meyers
and translated by Stefanos Geroulanos and Daniela Ginsburg. New York: Fordham
University Press.
Canguilhem, Georges. 2008b. Health: crude concept and philosophical question (translation
of “La santé, concept vulgaire et question philosophique” (1988), by T. Meyers and S.
Geroulanos). Public Culture 20 (3): 467-477
Cassirer, Ernst. 1950. The problem of knowledge: Philosophy, science, and history since Hegel,
trans. W. Woglom and C. Hendel. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Chen, Bohang. ms. (a). Revisiting the logical empiricist criticisms of vitalism.
Chen, Bohang. ms. (b). An alternative logic of evaluating vitalism in the early twentieth
century.
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
62
Coleman, William. 1985. The cognitive basis of the discipline: Claude Bernard on physiology.
Isis 76: 49-70.
Etxeberria, Arantza. 2004. Autopoiesis and natural drift: Genetic information, reproduction,
and evolution revisited. Artificial Life 10 (3): 347-360.
Etxeberria, Arantza and Umerez, Jon. 2006. Organización y organismo en la Biología Teórica
¿Vuelta al organicismo? Ludus Vitalis 26: 3-38.
Etxeberria, Arantza and Ruiz-Mirazo, Kepa. 2009. The challenging biology of transients. A
view from the perspective of autonomy. EMBO Reports 10: S33-S36.
Etxeberria, Arantza and Bich, Leonardo. 2017. Auto-organización y autopoiesis. In Diccionario
Interdisciplinar Austral, edited by C. E. Vanney, I. Silva and J. F. Franck.
http://dia.austral.edu.ar/Autoorganizaci%C3%B3n_y_autopoiesis
Foucault, Michel. 1991. Introduction, in G. Canguilhem, The normal and the pathological, ed.
Robert S. Cohen, trans. Carolyn R. Fawcett, 7-24. New York: Zone Books.
Gabel, Isabel. 2015. Biology and the philosophy of history in mid-twentieth-century France.
Doctoral dissertation, Columbia University.
Gabel, Isabel. 2016. Undisciplined biology in twentieth-century France. Perspectives on Europe
(Spring): 69-73.
Gayon, Jean. 1998. The concept of individuality in Canguilhem’s philosophy of biology.
Journal of the history of biology 31 (3): 305-325.
Gérard, Marie. 2010. Canguilhem, Erwin Straus et la phénoménologie: La question de
l’organisme vivant. Bulletin d’analyse phénoménologique 6 (2): 118-145.
http://popups.ulg.ac.be/bap.htm
Goldstein, Kurt. 1939. The organism: A holistic approach to biology derived from pathological
data in man. New York: American Book Company (reprint, New York: Zone Books, 1995)
(translation of Der Aufbau des Organismus (1934))
Jacob, François. 1970. La logique du vivant. Paris: Gallimard.
Jacob, François. 1973. The logic of life. A History of heredity, trans. B. Spillmann. New York:
Pantheon Books.
Kant, Immanuel. 1790/1987. Critique of Judgment, trans. W. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Lecourt, Dominique. 2011. La philosophie de la vie de Georges Canguilhem, in Pascal Nouvel
(ed.) Repenser le vitalisme: histoire et philosophie du vitalisme, 5-13. Paris: PUF.
Lenoir, Timothy. 1982. The strategy of life: Teleology and mechanics in nineteenth-century
German biology. Dordrecht-Boston: D. Reidel.
Machery, Edouard. 2012. Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life… And why you
should as well. Synthese 185: 145-164.
Maturana, Humberto R. 1978. Biology of language. In Psychology and biology of language and
thought: Essays in honor of Eric Lenneberg, edited by G.A. Miller and E. Lenneberg, 27-
63. New York: Academic Press.
Maturana, Humberto R., and Francisco J. Varela. 1973. De máquinas y seres vivos. Autopoiesis,
la organización de lo vivo, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria; new edition in Lumen,
Santiago, 1994.
Maturana, Humberto R., and Francisco J. Varela. 1980. Autopoiesis and cognition: The
realization of the living. Dordrecht: Springer.
Medawar, P.B. and J.S. Medawar. 1983. Reductionism and Vitalism. In From Aristotle to zoos:
A Philosophical dictionary of biology, 227-232, 275-277. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press
Métraux, Alexandre. 2005. Canguilhem als Architekt einer Philosophie des Lebenden. In Maß
und Eigensinn. Studien im Anschluß an Georges Canguilhem, edited by C. Borck, Hess, V.,
and Schmidgen, H., 317-346. München: Wilhelm Fink.
Moreno, Alvaro and Mossio, Matteo 2015. Biological autonomy: a philosophical and theoretical
enquiry. Dordrecht: Springer.
Canguilhem and the Logic of Life
Arantza Etxeberria – Charles T. Wolfe
63
Moss, Lenny, and Newman Stuart A. 2016. The grassblade beyond Newton: the pragmatizing
of Kant for evolutionary-developmental biology. Lebenswelt 7: 94-111.
Normandin, Sebastian. 2007. Claude Bernard and An introduction to the study of experimental
medicine: ‘Physical vitalism’, dialectic, and epistemology. Journal of the history of
medicine and allied sciences 62(4): 495-528.
Nuño de la Rosa, Laura and Etxeberria, Arantza. 2010. ¿Fue Darwin el ‘Newton de la brizna de
hierba’? La herencia de Kant en la teoría darwinista de la evolución. Endoxa 24: 185-216.
Oyama, Susan. 1985. The ontogeny of information, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pigliucci, Massimo and Müller, Gerd, Eds. 2010. Evolution-the extended synthesis. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Prochiantz, Alain. 1990 Claude Bernard. La révolution physiologique. Paris: PUF.
Sholl, Jonathan. 2012. The knowledge of life in Canguilhem’s critical naturalism. Pli 23: 107-127.
Pradeu, Thomas. 2016. Organisms or biological individuals? Combining physiological and
evolutionary individuality. Biology and Philosophy 31 (6): 797–817
Ruíz-Mirazo, Kepa, Etxeberria, Arantza, Moreno, Alvaro and Ibáñez, Jesús. 2000. Organisms
and their place in Biology. Theories in Bioscience 119 (3-4): 209-233.
Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg. 2015. Preparations, models, and simulations. History and philosophy
of the life sciences 36 (3): 321-334.
Weber, Andreas and Varela, Francisco J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the
autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the cognitive
sciences 1: 97–125.
Varela, Francisco J. 1979. Principles of biological autonomy. New York: Elsevier/North-Holland.
Varela, Francisco J. 1981. Autonomy and autopoiesis. In Self-organizing systems: An
interdisciplinary approach, edited by G. Roth and H. Schwegler, 14-24. Frankfurt and
New York: Campus Verlag.
Wolfe, Charles T. 2011. From substantival to functional vitalism and beyond, or from Stahlian
animas to Canguilhemian attitudes. Eidos 14: 212-235
Wolfe, Charles T. 2015a. Il fascino discreto del vitalismo settecentesco e le sue riproposizioni.
In Il libro della natura, vol. 1: Scienze e filosofia da Copernico a Darwin, edited by Paolo
Pecere, 273-299. Rome: Carocci.
Wolfe, Charles T. 2015b. Was Canguilhem a biochauvinist? Goldstein, Canguilhem and the
project of ‘biophilosophy’, in Medicine and Society, New Continental Perspectives, edited
by Darian Meacham, 197-212. Dordrecht: Springer.
Zammito, John. 2006. Teleology then and now: The question of Kant’s relevance for
contemporary controversies over function in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy
of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37: 748-770.