Content uploaded by Jesse Crosson
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Jesse Crosson on Apr 27, 2021
Content may be subject to copyright.
MULTIPLE VOTE ELECTORAL SYSTEMS
A Remedy for Political Polarization
------
Jesse M. Crosson George Tsebelis
Trinity University University of Michigan
ABSTRACT
We examine the mechanical effect of a multiple vote, proportional representation electoral
system on party vote share in n dimensions. In one dimension, Cox (1990) has proven that such a
system is centripetal: it drives parties to the center of the political spectrum. However, as
populism has swept across Western Europe and the United States, the importance of multiple
policy dimensions has grown considerably. We use simulations to examine how a multiple vote
system could alter electoral outcomes in all possible parliamentary systems. We find that
multiple vote systems act centripetally in multiple dimensions too, though weakly in extreme
cases where parties are sorted into ideological clusters at opposite corners of the ideological
space. Even in these cases, though, we find that a slight disturbance of the conditions (by
introducing an additional party- even if it is very small) strengthens the centripetal properties of
the multiple vote system.
KEYWORDS: Electoral systems, polarization, populism, approval voting, rank-choice voting,
parties
1
INTRODUCTION
Modern electoral competition has become more complicated with the emergence of new issue
dimensions (most notably, immigration and economic inequality, but also environment,
globalization, institutional efficiency, etc.). It has also become more unpredictable: the successes
of Donald Trump in the U.S. and Emmanuel Macron in France were considered hopeless
longshots only a year (and sometimes less) before their victories in two major Western
democracies. Probably the most telling case in terms of multidimensionality and unpredictability
is the United Kingdom, where the “Brexit” dimension was not at all captured by the existing
party system. This led to the emergence of new parties, the splitting of old ones, as well as a
series of negative votes in Parliament that led to its “prorogation” (suspension) months before the
electoral triumph of Johnson. These episodes illustrate that our present understanding of key
facets of electoral politics, such as voters’ preference formation, relation between electoral
systems and voting, and analyses of voting on the basis of one-dimensional models (Downs
1957) should be reevaluated. Particularly given the modern trend of ideological polarization in
many Western democracies, understanding the ramifications of multidimensionality for proposed
institutional changes and reforms is imperative.
The goal of this paper is to examine the dynamics of multidimensionality within one particular
electoral system: a multiple vote system according to which each voter is endowed with multiple
votes and can use as many of them as (s)he wants, to support different parties.
1
In previous
work, Cox (1990) has proven that such an electoral system produces centripetal results in a
single policy dimension. In this paper, we will demonstrate that the same policy implication is
true even in multiple dimensions. We believe this result is of both substantive and
methodological importance. Substantively, this result suggests that the multiple vote system
2
described above and analyzed below provides a means for addressing extremism within our
increasingly multidimensional political reality. Methodologically, the result helps to overcome
the fact that median voter equilibria exist in one dimension but disappear in multiple dimensions,
leading us to use computer simulations.
To arrive at these results, we execute a series of simulations that build upon actual electoral
results in four different countries: Belgium, Netherlands, Germany, and Romania. Using
existing partisan seat distributions from these countries, we calculate the percentage of votes
each party would receive under our proposed multiple vote system, and then compare that
distribution of seats to seat shares under the prevailing electoral system. Along the way, the
procedure incorporates key features of electoral politics such as random non-proximity voting
and existing national electoral rules, in order to generate hypothetical vote and legislative seat
distributions.
From the point of view of the voter, the only difference between our system and the existing ones
is that voters may cast more than one vote. However, as we show in the analysis of our results,
the resulting differences are significant. First, multiple votes enable voters to express their
preferences more completely than in the usual single-vote case. For example, a country with ten
political parties, a switch from one to three votes affords voters with 176 unique choice sets—
compared to just 11 under a single-vote system (any one particular party or abstention). Second,
our system incorporates all these choices into the final outcome. Third, though outside the scope
of our paper empirically, we believe this system should lead to a breakdown of “party
identification,” since it encourages voters to use multiple criteria when selecting among parties.
Consequently, voters would no longer “identify” with any single party in particular. Finally, we
show how the forces inherent to this system lead to a party system wherein centrist parties
3
prevail, and wherein the political debate becomes less polarized. We also identify the few
conditions under which this kind of result may not prevail, and demonstrate how a small
perturbation of these conditions will lead again to a centripetal party system.
We believe the political effects of adopting of such a system would be significant. First, the
increase in parliamentary representation of centrist parties would lead to more centrist
governments than the ones that prevailed in certain countries in the recent past (e.g., Netherlands
in 2010, Denmark in 2015, Italy in 2018, and Austria in 2017). However, beyond this result, we
believe the system would also encourage the creation of more flexible and long-lasting
governing coalitions, since the ideological distance of the partners will be smaller and coalitions
will be able to respond to unpredicted political events instead of collapsing.
2
Taken together,
these advantages represent important improvements over existing arrangements, especially
during a volatile time in political history.
MULTIPLE VOTE SYSTEMS IN THEORY AND PRACTICE
Multiple Vote Systems in Theory
Electoral systems have been shown to affect not only the number of parties (Duverger 1951) but
also their positions along the political spectrum (Cox 1990). With respect to the latter, Cox
(using a one-dimensional policy space) has demonstrated that granting voters with multiple votes
creates centripetal forces inside a political system. More specifically, when the number of
candidates is small enough relative to the number of votes per voter, and when cumulation (i.e.,
allowing a voter to cast all of her votes for one candidate) is not allowed, centripetal forces will
predominate and candidates and parties will be drawn to the center of the political spectrum.
4
Cox’s results depend on a series of assumptions about voters, candidates, and the policy space,
and provide a clear theoretical framework for understanding why a polity might choose to
implement a multiple vote system as a means for combatting political polarization. However,
Cox’s results are not the only, nor the first, to suggest that multiple vote systems moderate
candidates. Indeed, the term “multiple vote” we use in this paper is designed to encompass both
approval voting systems and rank-ordering systems, by incorporating their underlying common
feature: such systems allow voters to select more than one candidate or party. Under approval
voting, voters have an unconditional choice: they use as many of the available votes as they
wish. Under rank-order voting, voters must rank their choices, and a subordinate choice is not
used unless the higher-ordered option is not operational. Both systems have been proposed for
single member districts, while in our paper we combine multiple votes with any district size, as
well as adding existing national rules from each corresponding country.
The approval voting literature has suggested that multiple vote systems could, in fact, help
moderate candidates--and in the American context, weaken or even destroy the two-party system
(Brams and Fishburn 1978). Under approval voting, voters receive m votes that they may or may
not choose to use on different candidates in an election. Under this system, cumulation is
prohibited, similar to the centripetal case underscored in Cox’s analysis. Its proponents (e.g.,
Brams and Fishburn 2007 [1980], Kellett and Mott 1977) argue its practical effects, “would
probably be to give comparatively more support to moderates” (Brams and Fishburn 1978: 840).
Consequently, such proponents have in the past argued that the major parties in America should
adopt approval voting as their primary-election voting system, because “most delegates find
[moderates] acceptable,” while “extremists […] are only acceptable to ideological factions in
their party” (Brams and Fishburn 1978: 840).
5
A similar logic has evolved in support of ranked choice voting, particularly in state-level
elections in the United States. According to one prominent version of ranked-choice voting,
voters rank candidates on their ballots according to preference, ranging from most to least
favorable. Should a single candidate not receive a majority of first-place votes following the
election, the ballots of the last-place candidate flow to the respective remaining candidates—a
process that is repeated until the final winner is selected. Proponents of this system argue the
procedure generates a winner that is more centrist and/or more widely acceptable to a larger
portion of the electorate than does majority rule or (especially) plurality elections (Santucci
2018, Fromuth 2019). These potential advantages have not gone unnoticed outside of political
science. For example, a recent study of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences, Reinventing
American Democracy for the 21st Century, proposes the adoption of “ranked-choice voting in
presidential, congressional, and state elections” as one of the most prominent institutional
modifications precisely in order to promote moderation (American Academy of Arts & Sciences
2020,I2)
Multiple Vote Systems in Practice: Past and Present
While these systems differ in several important regards, which we discuss below, they
nevertheless share a crucial common feature: they grant voters with a larger choice set with
which they can express their preferences. The centripetal forces resulting from these systems
help to explain why variants of these systems have been adopted in a wide variety of settings
over thousands of years. Most of the time, such systems have been adopted in single member
districts (with one winner). In ancient Greece, the Spartans’ “acclamation vote” served as an
early form of approval voting, as voters were allowed to shout in favor of more than one
candidate for the Gerousia (Girard 2010, Tsebelis 2018). Though undoubtedly quieter than the
6
Spartan vote, papal elections from the late thirteenth to the early seventeenth century also took a
form that resembled approval voting. According to this voting system, cardinals had the option
of voting for more than one papal candidate. The pairing of this system of voting with a 2/3rds
qualified majority threshold created long vacancies in the papacy, ultimately leading to the
voting system’s demise. However, as Colomer and McClean (1998) argue, the system did
encourage the election of largely unobjectionable popes, which helped to address longstanding
tension (and even violence) within the Church.
Political entities today have also adopted variations of the multiple vote system. In the most
prominent victory for ranked-choice advocates to date, Maine adopted a system of ranked-choice
voting for its legislative and gubernatorial elections. As noted above, proponents of the system
tout its majority-friendly and centripetal features, though the recency of the reforms have
precluded direct empirical tests of these assertions. Nevertheless, reformers ultimately succeeded
in Maine due in part to the election and reelection of a widely unpopular Republican governor
who never succeeded in securing absolute majority support from voters in the state (Santucci
2018). Similarly, in 2019, New York City residents elected to revise the city’s charter to
establish ranked-choice voting for all primary and special elections. New York City is now
among more than fifteen cities that use ranked-choice voting (Drutman 2019).
3
In multimember districts, STV systems in Ireland and Malta (and the Australian Senate) provide
some empirical examples. Researchers have found that voters sometimes transcend party or
group barriers under such systems and vote for individual candidates of their liking. For
example, Mitchell (2014) compares the electoral results before and after the 1998 Belfast
Agreement in Ireland and observes that “prior to the 1998 Agreement inter-ethnic vote-pooling
in Northern Ireland was very close to zero.” However, he continues: “[a]fterwards (1998-2007),
7
terminal transfers from the moderate unionist UUP to the moderate nationalist SDLP averaged
32 per cent (and 13 per cent in the opposite direction). Although most transfers clearly remain
within ethnic blocs, these inter-ethnic terminal transfers are a change with the past and suggest
that SW may be an appropriate electoral system choice for some divided societies.”
Other modern entities have also either proposed or adopted versions of multiple vote systems.
According to a review on approval voting success and failure by Brams and Fishburn (2010),
several professional societies have adopted some version of approval voting. These include the
Mathematical Association of America, the American Mathematical Society, the Institute for
Operations Research and Management Sciences, the American Statistical Association, the
Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers, the Society for Judgment and Decision Making,
the Social Choice and Welfare Society, the International Joint Conference on Artificial
Intelligence, and the European Association for Logic, Language and Information, the
Econometric Society, and the National Academy of Sciences. While elections in these societies
may not be exactly ideological or high stakes, Brams and Fishburn (1978) find that the multiple
vote systems appear to advantage candidates who enjoy support from a large cross-section of the
societies’ memberships. Similarly, in highly multidimensional contests like gymnastics and
diving, Olympians are judged using either multiple rankings or ratings. In doing so, officials
hope that the athlete agreed upon as best by the largest group of judges will be selected for a
medal. The same voting system is used for the Academy Awards. To our knowledge the only
case of approval voting application at a national level election was the Greek electoral system
from 1864-1920 (Tsebelis 2014: 172).
4
Theoretical and Practical Challenges for Understanding Multiple Vote Systems
8
While previous implementations of multiple vote systems have encountered some success in
terms of electing broadly supported, moderate candidates, they nevertheless face limitations in
both theory and practice. First, as we noted at the outset of the paper, although studies like Cox’s
prove in one dimension that multiple vote systems can draw candidates to the center of the
political spectrum, he (nor anyone else to date) does not offer a proof in more than a single
dimension. This stands as a challenge to the multiple vote system, as a second or third dimension
can change the definition of “moderate” in a political system and create possibilities for
candidates to be close to one another in one dimension while remaining dispersed in another.
Perhaps the most relevant example in contemporary politics lies in the current populist
movements across the United States and Western Europe. While populists lie to the far right of
the political spectrum on cultural issues, they nevertheless often support interventionist policies
in the economy. In short, the rise in popularity of populist ideas has muddied the neat left-right
distinction implied by unidimensional models.
Since the STV system asks voters to rank candidates, the multiple votes it provides are
conditional choices only. That is, the voters’ second or third choices influence the election only
after the first vote is invalidated. This feature makes each additional choice less important than
the prior, and complicates the system (although the logic of each successive choice is the same as
in the system we analyze below).
Given these challenges to the current theory and practice of multiple vote systems, we focus in
this paper on the mechanical consequences of adding m issue dimensions and a proportional
voting mechanism to a multiple vote system. In doing so, we find that multidimensionality and
proportional representation create centripetal party systems—just as current literature predicts.
9
We also find that under certain extreme centrifugal conditions that the electoral system cannot
overcome in the first election, but is likely to modify in the medium and long run. We conclude
by discussing some scope conditions of this effect.
A MULTIDIMENSIONAL, MULTIPLE VOTE MODEL
Voting System Design
Tsebelis (2014) has proposed a multiple vote electoral system, which permits a certain number of
votes, and is combined with the national distribution requirements of different countries. For
example, countries like the Netherlands and Israel have absolutely proportional electoral
systems; others, like Germany have national quotas (5%), while still others like Greece may give
seat bonuses to the first party (a fixed amount or, a number proportional to its size). In this study,
we simulate such a system by calculating the number of votes that each party receives under the
multiple vote system and distribute the seats on the basis of the national features of the electoral
system.
The fact that we use multiple member constituencies and distribute the seats on the basis of
national (more or less proportional) rules is the major difference between the system we analyse
in this paper and approval voting, which has been applied in single member constituencies (see
previous section). Under the system we examine, voters may cast up to n votes in total, with a
maximum of one vote per party. In other words, even if a voter strongly prefers one party to the
next best option, she may not cast a second or third vote for that preferred party (no cumulation
of votes). However, if she strongly dislikes all other options besides her most preferred party, she
can opt against casting more than one ballot at all. Thus, voters may cast any number of votes
10
they desire, with a maximum of m and a minimum of 1 (all abstainers are assumed to have
already been removed). In our implementation of this system, the ballot entities are conceived of
as parties (although one could imagine implementing a similar system with actual candidates,
instead of parties).
In order to demonstrate the significant growth in voters’ choice sets under this arrangement,
consider a country with 10 parties (like the Netherlands in our simulations below). The current
single-vote proportional representation system provides the voters with 11 choices (abstention,
plus selection of any one of 10 parties) in such a party system. In a two-vote system, however,
the choices increase to 56 (abstention, 10 single party choices plus 45 two-party vote
combinations); in a three-vote system the number of choice profiles increases to 176 (abstention,
plus the 10 single party votes, 45 two party votes, and 120 three party votes). Even more
impressively, a four-vote system affords the voter 386 unique choices.
5
The maximum number of
available choices lies at 5 total ballots, wherein Dutch voters would enjoy 638 total choice
profiles. One may object that the number of choices is overwhelming for the voter; but in
reality, it is a simple, repetitive task, since the voter only has to determine whether she likes
enough each one of the parties to vote for them (as long as (s)he has available votes).
6
According to this model, parties receive the same proportion of representation in the legislature
as a proportion all votes cast. In our multiple vote case, this proportion is not as straightforward
as the single-vote case. In our system, representation is allotted by
where is the legislative proportion earned by party i. is the total number of votes cast for
party i, m is the number of votes allotted to each voter in the system, and N is the total number of
11
voters. A is an important term in this fraction, as it signifies the total number of abstentions
present in an election. As noted above, voters can choose against casting all their multiple votes
if they deem some unacceptable. Thus, the inclusion of this term is necessary for calculating the
actual proportion of total votes cast.
Our proportion differs from ranked choice voting in that it all votes count equally in the final
tabulation of Vi . This is a significant difference from the STV system, where the multiple votes
count only conditionally (i.e., only after incapacitation of the previous vote). This difference has
the double effect of: 1) Simplifying the system for both voters and authorities alike (two of the
main criticisms of STV) and 2) Providing more motivation for voters to use many of their votes,
since such a behavior increases their contribution to the electoral result. We believe that casting
multiple votes is less cognitively demanding for voters as it only requires them to inquire
whether a given candidate is sufficiently acceptable to warrant one of their votes. Given that
some literature has demonstrated that voter exhaustion leads ranked-choice voting to rely on only
a fraction of total ballots in the final vote distribution used to select a winner (Burnett and Kogan
2015), we believe the equally weighted and singularly tabulated votes in our system improve
upon this particular weakness of ranked-choice voting.
Modeling Assumptions and Mode of Analysis
To examine how multidimensionality and proportional representation impact the centripetal
nature of multi-vote systems, we create a voting simulation in R, using the electoral system
defined above. A simulation is necessary in this context, because of our interest in
multidimensional issue spaces (analytic proofs in n dimensions are impossible). Instead, we run
simulations and examine the results that obtain for various parameter specifications.
12
To proceed with the simulation, we created a customizable function that implements the
aforementioned multiple-vote PR system. The function proceeds as follows. First, the user
specifies several system-wide parameters of interest. These include both the number of votes m
allotted per voter and the total number of voters N in the political system. The user must also
define the platform locations points of each party i in each issue dimension d. The function
generalizes to any number of parties and dimensions, on the condition that the user provides a
platform location estimate for every party in each dimension. In addition, parties may decide not
to take position in some dimension.
Beyond these parameters, there are several other user-defined parameters of note, including one
related to abstentions (which are incorporated directly to the voting decision rules programmed
into the model). In the model, voters have single peaked preferences. Therefore, they vote on the
basis of ideological proximity: voter n ϵ N casts each vote on the basis of the following decision
rule:
where ||*||d represents the Euclidean distance in d dimensions between voter n’s ideal point and
party i’s platform location. As noted earlier, voters may vote for each party only once (like in
approval or transferable voting).
Because voters are prohibited from casting multiple voters for their top choice, they are not
obligated to make use of all their vote choices m. Instead, voters will only cast a vote for a party
if and only if the following condition obtains:
13
where i– refers to the nearest available party and a refers to a user-defined range of acceptability.
In other words, once the distance between voter n’s ideal point and the remaining parties’
platform locations exceeds the user-defined range of acceptability a, voter n will stop casting
votes. If the user is not interested in restricting voter behavior in this way, a can be easily set to a
very large number.
7
Finally, to render our model more “realistic,” we incorporate an error term in the voter’s
calculations. Voters make their choices on the basis of distance between their preferences and the
parties’ programs; however, with a probability 1-r they may not select the party closer to them.
In this case, the voter casts her vote randomly to one of the available parties. This behavior can
also be generated if a voter attributes higher significance to a particular issue (quality of
leadership) or is willing to vote for a party that is closer to her in a particular dimension, despite
the fact that the overall distance (taking into account all dimensions) is large--which is
sometimes called “valence” in the literature (Green and Hobolt 2008, Bittner 2011, Green and
Jennings 2017). This parameter adds noise to our results and is a useful way to relax the strictly
single peaked preference account of voting inherent to the model’s implementation. Like a, m, N,
d, and i, r is a user-specified parameter that represents the probability that voter n selects the
party closest to her.
Simulation Procedure
The simulation proceeds by first transforming a matrix of party shares into a society of voters.
Because multidimensional ideological estimates do not exist for entire citizenries, we begin first
with a user-specified list of proportions of the legislature held by each party. From these
proportions, the simulation creates a vector of length N with voter identities and ideal points
14
equal the proportions and ideological locations of the legislative parties. In other words, if Parties
X, Y, and Z occupied 20, 30, and 50 percent of the legislature, respectively, then a 10-person
society would include 2 citizens who identify with X, 3 who identify with Y, and 5 who identify
with Z. The first vote vector is always equal to the actual electoral outcomes from the year in
question-20 percent X, 30 percent Y, and 50 percent Z in the example above.
After generating this initial vector of voters, the algorithm calculates the Euclidean distance
between all voters and parties and determines which party lies second-closest to each party’s
voters. If this distance is greater than the acceptability parameter a, the voter refrains from
casting any more ballots. If the distance is less than a, the voter (with probability r) casts a vote
for the most proximate party. With probability 1-r, however, she casts her vote randomly. Once
this process occurs for all voters, votes are tabulated for each party and representation is allotted
accordingly.
For multiple vote systems that feature more than two ballots, the algorithm then proceeds as
follows. For the third ballot (and beyond), rather than assuming that all voters in a given party
share exactly the same preferences, the algorithm instead assumes that each voter n is likely
between her first-choice and second-choice parties. Consequently, when the voters cast their
third ballots, their choices are based on this assumed position—a position that evolves as the
algorithm continues from one ballot to the next. As a result, by the end of the simulation, the
estimated distribution of voters is considerably different than the distribution of parties. This is
far more realistic, of course, than voters sharing the ideal points of their chosen party. An
example of the resulting estimated voter locations (in the Netherlands) is depicted in Figure 1.
[INSERT FIGURE 1 HERE]
15
In this paper, we base our simulations on actual countries, using the classification of party
systems generated by Laver and Benoit (2015). They present a mutually exclusive and
collectively exhaustive classification of party systems into 5 basic categories. According to this
system of classification, Category “A” countries exhibit a single “winning” party that controls all
legislative decisions; Category “B” countries are led by a single, dominant party that governs in
coalition with a smaller party; in Category “C”, the legislature is led primarily by three
parties—any two of which are large enough to form a coalition government; Category “D”
countries, on the other hand, are dominated by two “top” parties; Category “E” countries exhibit
a party system that is truly “open,” in that no winning two-party coalition is possible (based on
the sizes of the parties in the system).
For our purposes, the most interesting countries are of Types C and E, because there is no clear
majority (like in dominant or competitive party systems), so, voters can use their preferences to
influence the electoral results in a more significant way. If new parties emerge in the other
systems, the policy space dimensions will increase and the party system will move to one of the
two categories we examine.
8
In this application, we select Germany and Romania to serve as
examples of Type C, and the Netherlands and Belgium as examples of Type E.
To generate ideological positions for each party (as well as initial party sizes), we rely upon data
from the Manifesto Project (Krause et al. 2018). More specifically, we use the 15-dimension
refinement of the Manifesto Project scores generated by Lowe et al. (2011). Lowe et al. (2011)
generate these 15 dimensions from a much larger number of topical categories found within the
Manifesto Project data. The authors reduce the Project’s dimensionality in a principled way, by
pairing opposing positions within the Project’s data into individual dimensions--rather than
incorporating some positions that lack a clear “opposite” position within the data.
16
Once the parties of the selected countries were matched to the Lowe et al. Manifesto scores, our
algorithm measured n dimensional Euclidean distances between our generated voter populations
and the locations of each of the parties. Given the high dimensionality of the data, providing
visual representation of the parties’ locations is impossible. However, as we present our results,
we ultimately present ideological centrism as each party’s distance from the “center of gravity”
of the ideological distribution of voters. We define these measures more precisely in the results
section.
Taken together, our expectations are as follows:
Proposition 1 (centripetal effect): Multiple votes will increase the shares held by centrist
parties (and reduce extremist ones).
The logic underlying this proposition is simply that centrist parties will receive votes from all
directions, while extremist ones only from their own area (if there are neighbor parties).
Proposition 2 (redistributive effect): Multiple votes will have a negative effect on the
initial size of parties.
Indeed, smaller parties will get a higher number of “transfer” votes than larger ones and vice
versa. However, beyond these two propositions, we do not anticipate that the other variables will
have a systematic effect on party shares, but will depend on the distribution of parties in space.
RESULTS
In order to show the centripetal effects of the multiple voting system we present our results as a
comparison between the m-vote cases and the classic, one-vote system of proportional
17
representation, asking which parties gain (and lose) as a result of the m-vote system? In general,
we present our results using the multidimensional center of gravity as our measure of
moderation.
As noted above, our simulation features parameters that may affect our findings. These include
the probability 1-r that voters will fail to vote on the basis of ideological proximity, the range of
“acceptability” (ideological distances within which an individual is willing to actually cast a
vote), and the total number of ballots. Thus, in presenting our results, we regress the gains from
the m-vote system (relative to the one-vote) on each of these parameters: the probability of
voting based on proximity (1-r), acceptability (a), and the number of ballots (b). Inclusion of
each of these covariates ensures that we hold factors besides ideological centrism constant when
examining the centripetal forces present in the m-vote system.
[TABLE 1 HERE]
Table 1 demonstrates that the centripetal and redistributive properties of the system exist in all
countries when pooled together. While the coefficients of the parameters used in the model are
overall as expected (higher acceptability, higher number of votes, and lower error term in the
single peaked preferences lead to more vote gains for the average party), they also show
variability across different countries. This finding indicates that the significance of these
parameters depends on the party distribution in each country. Similarly, in Germany, while the
signs of the coefficients of centripetal and redistributive effects are the “correct” ones and
statistical significance is high, the relative size of the coefficients indicates that the redistributive
effect is much more significant than the centripetal one.
18
Given these significant across country differences, we examine the results more closely by
country. For visualization purposes, we plot the parties’ locations in Figure 3 according to Lowe
et al.’s scaling of Laver and Benoit’s (2007; p.98, Table 2) two-dimensional party scores. These
scores place parties along “social conservatism” and “state involvement in the economy”
dimensions.
[FIGURE 2 HERE]
Among the countries that do experience centripetal results, this visualization provides some
context as to which parties tend to drive the result. In Germany, a different set of dynamics is at
play. Here, we observe a party system that is ideologically scattered, with parties located in loose
clusters that lie far apart from one another. Under these conditions, the multiple vote system
lacks a party to attract votes from the extremes. Instead, parties exchange votes within
ideological clusters, limiting the effectiveness of a multiple vote system at alleviating preference
polarization in the legislature. In fact, such preference configurations reward a different sort of
centrality: cluster-specific centrality.
To be clear, as Table 1 indicates, our multiple vote system generates a significantly more
centripetal result in Germany than does the single-vote alternative. However, compared to the
other countries in our simulations, this result is smaller in magnitude. Figure 3 depicts why this is
the case. In particular, non-centrist parties such as The Left and FDP make gains due to the fact
that they receive votes in multiple directions: FDP receives votes from CDU/CSU and SPD,
while The Left draws votes from the Greens and SPD. In a perfectly centripetal case, another
centrist party would serve as a vote-trading partner with SPD, allowing SPD to make gains
instead of The Left and/or FDP (depending on the exact location of the hypothetical party).
19
In order to corroborate this argument in all 15 dimensions, we perform an additional test below,
wherein we perturb the Germany’s party distribution. That is, we show that when a small party is
added in the hypothesized neighborhood, centripetal forces become significantly more
pronounced.
Reinforcing Moderation in Polarized Systems
To test our claim that a small spatial deviation can strengthen centripetal results, we introduce a
small centrist party (though bordering on “populist” given its social conservatism) into
Germany’s party system. This party occupies four percent of the total vote, representing the
smallest vote share out of any party in our simulation.
9
When we introduce this small-but-centrist party, we find that even a weak centripetal
configuration, such as Germany’s, may exhibit stronger centripetal properties. As is depicted in
Appendix B and in the final column of Table 1, this “Centrist Party” makes sizable gains as a
result of the m-vote system. Indeed, because the party draws votes from both parties in the
rightward bloc (CSU/CDP and FDP) and parties in the center-left bloc (SPD and, in the three-
vote case, the Greens) this new party experiences significant gains that improve the centripetal
nature of the system.
This trend does not necessarily apply only to perfectly centrist parties. Indeed, the “centrist”
party itself appears as fairly conservative in the overall distribution. However, so long as any
“new” party lies within the acceptability range of the innermost parties from each cluster, we
observe a significant coefficient on Distance to Center variable in the above models. In this case,
the coefficient on Distance to Center is nearly twice as large in the perturbed case than in the
original simulation in Table 1. This result is supported by the fact that, because more “centrist”
20
parties performed no worse (and, in fact, marginally better) under this configuration than in the
original, the introduction of a centrist party benefited other more centrally located party blocs.
For example, while SPD still loses votes relative to the single-vote case, it nevertheless performs
better than in the original simulation, having received votes from Centrist Party (in addition to
retaining votes from The Greens and FDP).
CONCLUSIONS
This paper examines the mechanical effect of a multiple vote system, using actual countries’
party distributions as a means for examining how and when our system should encourage the
election of centrist parties or candidates. In doing so, we demonstrate that moderation effects in
one dimension, demonstrated by Cox (1991), obtain in multiple dimensions. As we caution
throughout, our analysis does not examine the strategic effects of such a system. Nevertheless,
we believe that examining the mechanical effect of multiple vote systems is important for a
number of reasons. First, it demonstrates that such systems do not behave identically in all
countries, but nevertheless that countries have broad similarities as Table 1 indicates. Second, it
is upon these broad similarities that strategic calculations of voters and parties will be based. One
may argue that voters have personal, social, or cultural misgivings about voting for an extreme
party (like, say, a fascist or communist party). In addition, parties are constrained in their ability
to adjust their ideological positions in a rapid fashion. Activists within the party would likely
resist such changes, and voters may respond poorly to drastic changes in the ideological “brand”
associated with the party. Thus, while future research may account for important strategic
considerations faced by voters and parties, these considerations have to be based on the
21
mechanical effects of the multiple vote system in the same way as Duverger’s (1951)
“psychological effect” was grafted upon the “mechanical effect” of the plurality system.
In this paper, we have used simulations in order to calculate the mechanical effects of multiple
voting systems (whether they are applied to single or multiple member constituencies). Our
findings confirm the ones of Cox in a single dimension. He was able to prove his results, because
the combination of single peaked preferences with a single dimension leads to an equilibrium
(the median voter). However, in multiple dimensions the equilibrium disappears (and so do the
formal proofs), generating the need for simulations. The lack of equilibrium in multiple
dimensions leads us to a different logic for our investigation. While Cox’s model leaves the
parties free to move in the one dimensional space and determines whether (in equilibrium) they
cluster in the middle or disperse all over the (one-dimensional) space in order to maximize the
number of votes, we keep the parties in their initial location and have the voters select the parties
that are closer to them (as the different parameters of the model permit). The outcome of our
model is that centrist parties get better results with multiple votes. So, our model demonstrates
that the single dimension is not a necessary condition for convergence, but that the single peaked
preferences of the voters is.
However, beyond this mechanical effect, we believe that the adoption of this multiple vote
system may imply several additional long-term changes. With respect to voters, this system
presents an exponential increase in the number of voting alternatives. Indeed, if we permit voters
to have number of votes equal to half the number of parties, the number of choices is:
22
where N equals the total number of parties in a country. This increase of choices is likely to
reduce the number of abstentions (since it reduces abstention from indifference (e.g., Plane and
Gershtenson 2004, Adams, Dow and Merrill 2006, Llavador 2006). Indeed, a voter who does not
know if she should vote for party A or B in a multiparty system may now vote for both.
Moreover, she may do so without confronting the cognitively taxing task of ranking candidates:
all votes in this setting are “worth” the same.
In addition to its potential for decreasing abstention, we believe that a multiple vote system may
help to increase voter information. In order to evaluate different candidates under such a system,
voters will have to pay attention to the positions of a larger number of parties or candidates—
understanding that they will ultimately be voting for more than a single party.
Moreover, understanding that actually casting multiple votes increases their impact on the
outcome, voters face incentives both to cast more votes and improve their information in the
process. We are hopeful that particular feature of the multiple voting system will have a
significant impact on the voting habits of the public. With respect to parties, our results—
particularly in the perturbation exercise—suggest that the total number of parties will multiply,
since there is no reason for any political entrepreneur not to create their own party and try their
chances. This is particularly true given that they can reasonably expect many second or third
votes from major parties around them (if the party is situated appropriately). In order to reduce
this tendency, countries may consider strict rules of which parties are allowed to compete should
be enforced (for example, parties have to exist 6 months before the election, and a large number
of signatures is required for the creation of a new party). These restrictions will enable voters to
know the positions of the parties in competition, and choose them according to their preferences.
23
Third, with respect to the party positions, we showed that centrist parties are privileged in a
multiple vote system. However, these advantages are attenuated in cases where party clusters
emerge in large distance from each other (like the case of Germany in our examples). Still, when
the system is applied several times, the emergence of a centrist party—or the convergence of
existing parties close to the multidimensional median—is likely, because political entrepreneurs
will understand the potential for success of such a party. This is a similar argument with the one
in the report of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, in defense of the ranked-choice
electoral system that it proposes for the US case: “Because second and third choices matter in the
ranked-choice model, candidates have an incentive to speak to a broader group of voters. The
result: more moderate candidates and campaigns, a more welcoming environment for third-party
candidates, and greater confidence among voters that their votes are not being wasted or
distorting the outcome” (American Academy of Arts & Sciences 2020).
Finally, perhaps the most important consequence of such a voting system (although not directly
demonstrated in this paper) is the potential promotion of a critical attitude of voters vis a vis
parties, as opposed to an identification attitude. That is, instead of voters trying to find a party to
identify with, they can be more critical and express their preferences more fully (if they so wish).
This result carries with it both pros and cons. On one hand, party identification may fulfill a
variety of positive societal functions, such as increasing voter turnout, serving as a policy
evaluation heuristic, and encouraging other types of political participation (see Dalton 2016 for a
review). On the other, as Lavine, Johnston, and Steenbergen (2012) and others have underscored,
intense partisan identification can lead to narrow-mindedness on the part of partisans. Indeed,
such identifications may lead partisans to disregard important information that does not confirm
24
their partisan biases. Doing so could empower demagogic leaders or create partisan
informational asymmetries and fracture a society according to partisan identifications.
Finally, the centripetal effects of the electoral system are likely to have important ramifications
for the governing coalitions of each country. In fact, ideological proximity is a key feature of
coalition formation (Warwick 1996, 1998; Tsebelis and Ha 2014), and the multiple vote electoral
system will lead to governments with more uniformly centrist composition. The policy
implications of such a transformation will be significant, given parliamentary governments’
control of the legislative agenda. As a result, such coalitions’ proposals and legislation will lie in
closer correspondence with the aspirations and desires of a broader portion of the public.
WORD COUNT: 7,560 + 2 pages tables/figures = 8,510 words
Jesse M. Crosson is Assistant Professor of Political Science and Faculty Affiliate for the
Program on Urban Studies, Trinity University.
George Tsebelis is Anatol Rapoport Collegiate Professor of Political Science at the University of
Michigan, Ann Arbor
1
The technical term for this system is that it is non-cumulative. In cumulative systems voters can use their votes to
support candidates of the same party. For example, in Bremen and Hamburg voters are endowed with five votes
each and they can use them to support the same party. We thank an anonymous reviewer for providing this
information to us.
2
See Tsebelis and Ha (2014) for the theoretical argument and Tsebelis and Crosson (2020) for the application in the
case of the Netherlands.
3
Another important reform at the U.S. state level is the “top two” candidate primaries. Here, voters participate in a
common “primary” and then select between the prevailing top two candidates in the general elections. Crucially,
these general-election candidates may belong to the same party. When they do, the more moderate of the two
candidates tends to prevail. Since the adoption of this system in the states of Washington and California, several
studies have found evidence of moderation (see Grose 2014, Crosson 2020, and Grose 2020).
4
The election of Doges of Venice was also done through approval voting but in multiple rounds, though a
deliberately complicated system so that the influence of organized clan interests would be minimized.
5
The total number of available choice sets decreases after 5 votes, since the voters now face the decision of who to
exclude in their ballot, rather than who to include.
6
The very fact that this system is the “acclamation vote” of ancient Sparta indicates that the logic is simple and
straightforward! Nevertheless, we do not mean to suggest that, in practice, voters would not take some time to
25
acclimate to the system. Certainly, voters would learn how to use their new choice set to express their preferences.
However, we aim primarily to underscore the potential effects of the system after these transitional factors have run
their course.
7
Practically speaking, this means that the voter stops casting votes entirely (rationally or randomly) once the a
threshold is reached. For precision, one may define vj as the set of parties that lie within voter j’s range of
acceptability a. By definition, for voter j must be in the set vj in order for the voter to actually cast their vote.
8
Interested readers may use our appendix to apply our model to analyze any system or particular country they want.
9
We selected this size so that with a single vote this party would not have been represented in the Budestag, and it
would not have altered the results of a single vote system.
Works Cited
American Academy of Arts & Sciences. (2020). Our Common Purpose: Reinventing American
Democracy for the 21st Century Retrieved December 1, 2020, from
https://www.amacad.org/ourcommonpurpose/report
Adams, J., Dow, J. and Merrill, S.. (2006). The political consequences of alienation-based and
indifference-based voter abstention: Applications to presidential elections. Political
Behavior, 28(1), pp.65-86.
Aodha, Gráinne Ní. (2020). “How Did They Do It? Sinn Féin's Historic 24% Win Was Built on
Learnt Lessons and a Fed-up Electorate.” The Journal, February. https://www.thejournal.ie/sinn-
fein-comeback-5001379-Feb2020/.
Bittner, Amanda, (2011). Platform or Personality?: The Role of Party Leaders in Elections.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bowler, S. & Grofman, B. (2000). Elections in Australia, Ireland and Malta under the Single
Transferable Vote: Reflections on an Embedded Institution. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Press.
Brams, and Fishburn P.C., (2010). Going from Theory to Practice: The Mixed Success of
Approval Voting, in Laslier, J.F. and Sanver, M.R. eds., 2010. Handbook on approval voting.
Springer Science & Business Media.
Brams, S. and Fishburn, P.C., (2007). Approval voting. Springer Science & Business Media.
Brams, S.J. and Fishburn, P.C., (1978). Approval voting. American Political Science Review,
72(3), pp.831-847.
1
Colomer, J.M. and McLean, I., (1998). Electing popes: approval balloting and qualified-majority
rule. The Journal of interdisciplinary history, 29(1), pp.1-22.
Cox, G.W., (1990). Centripetal and centrifugal incentives in electoral systems. American Journal
of Political Science, pp.903-935.
Crosson, J., (2020). Extreme districts, moderate winners: Same-party challenges, and deterrence
in top-two primaries. Political Science Research and Methods, pp.1-17.
Dalton, R. (2016). “Party Identification and Its Implications.” Oxford Research Encyclopedia of
Politics. Retrieved from http://politics.oxfordre.com/view/10.1093/acrefore/
9780190228637.001.0001/acrefore-9780190228637-e-72.
Drutman, L. (2019). A New Voting System Could Fix American Democracy: Ranked-Choice
Ballots. NBC News. https://www.nbcnews.com/think/opinion/new-voting-system-could-fix-
american-democracy-ranked-choice-ballots-ncna1078491.
Duverger, Maurice. (1951). Les Partis Politiques. Paris: A. Colin
Fromuth, Peter. (2019). Ranked choice voting is easier than it sounds. Maybe it would cure our
awful politics. USA Today. Available at:
https://www.usatoday.com/story/opinion/2018/09/06/ranked-choice-voting-elevate-moderates-
reduce-polarization-column/1196693002/ [Accessed 5 Sep. 2019].
Girard, C., (2010). Acclamation voting in Sparta: an early use of approval voting. In Laslier, J.F.
and Sanver, M.R. eds., 2010. Handbook on Approval Voting, pp.15-17.
Green, Jane, and Sara B. Hobolt, (2008). “Owning the Issue Agenda: Party Strategies and Vote
Choices in British Elections.” Electoral Studies 27(3): 460: 476.
2
Green, Jane, and Will Jennings, (2017). The Politics of Competence: Parties, Public Opinion and
Voters. Cambridge University Press.
Kellett, J. and Mott, K., (1977). Presidential primaries: Measuring popular choice. Polity, 9(4),
pp.528-537.
Benoit, K. and Laver, M., (2007). Estimating party policy positions: Comparing expert surveys
and hand-coded content analysis. Electoral Studies, 26(1), pp.90-107.
Grose, Christian R. (2014). The adoption of electoral reforms and ideological change in the
California State Legislature. Schwarzenegger Institute Report, University of Southern California,
Price School of Public Policy.
Grose, Christian R., (2020). Reducing Legislative Polarization: Top-Two and Open Primaries
Are Associated with More Moderate Legislators. Journal of Political Institutions and Political
Economy, 1(2), pp.267-287.
Laver, M. and Benoit, K., (2015). The basic arithmetic of legislative decisions. American
Journal of Political Science, 59(2), pp.275-291.
Lavine, H.G., Johnston, C.D. and Steenbergen, M.R., (2012). The ambivalent partisan: How
critical loyalty promotes democracy. Oxford University Press.
Llavador, H. (2006). Electoral platforms, implemented policies, and abstention. Social Choice
and Welfare, 27(1), pp.55-81.
Lowe, W., Benoit, K., Mikhaylov, S. and Laver, M., (2011). Scaling policy preferences from
coded political texts. Legislative studies quarterly, 36(1), pp.123-155.
3
Mitchell, P., (2014) The single transferable vote and ethnic conflict: The evidence from Northern
Ireland. Electoral Studies 33: 246-257
Maskin, E., & Sen, A. (2016). How Majority Rule Might Have Stopped Donald Trump. New
York Times. April 28. Retrieved from
https://www.nytimes.com/2016/05/01/opinion/sunday/how-majority-rule-might-have-stopped-
donald-trump.html
O'Leary, N. (2020). “Why Sinn Féin Is Surging in the Irish Election.” POLITICO, St. Petersburg
Times. https://www.politico.eu/article/why-sinn-fein-is-surging-in-the-irish-election/.
Plane, D.L. and Gershtenson, J., (2004). Candidates' ideological locations, abstention, and
turnout in US midterm Senate elections. Political Behavior, 26(1), pp.69-93.
Puri, Madan L.; Sen, Pranab K. (1971). Nonparametric Methods in Multivariate Analysis, John
Wiley & Sons, New York, NY.
Santucci, J., (2018). Maine ranked-choice voting as a case of electoral-system change.
Representation, 54(3), pp.297-311.
Shea, I.E., (1984). The grange was my life. Ye Galleon Press.
Tsebelis, G. (2014). The Greek Constitution from a Political Science Point of View”, Greek
Political Science Review (July; 42): 145-72
Tsebelis G. (2018) “How Can We Keep Direct Democracy and Avoid "Kolotoumba"” Homo
Oeconomicus 35(1): 81-90
4
Tsebelis G. and E.Y. Ha (2014) “Coalition Theory: A Veto Players approach” European
Political Science Review (2014), 6:3, 331-357 European Political Science Review 6:3, 331-357
Tsebelis, G. and J. M. Crosson. (2020). “Can the Dutch Electoral System Be Improved Upon?”
Munich Social Science Review.
Warwick, P. (1996), ‘Coalition government membership in Western European parliamentary
democracies’, British Journal of Political Science 26: 471–499.
Warwick, P. (1998), ‘Policy distance and parliamentary government’, Legislative Studies
Quarterly 23: 319–345.
5
Figure 1. Estimated Voter Locations in the Netherlands
Simulations for the Netherlands, with four total ballots (m=4), acceptability (a =
12), and error term (r= 0.35). Locations depicted in Lowe et al.’s (2011) two-
dimensional reduction of the Manifesto Project data. Party platform locations are
depicted by the location of the textual abbreviation for each respective party.
Table 1. Country-Specific m vote Regression Results
(Center of Gravity)
6
Figure 2. Two-Dimensional Depictions of Parties, Gains and Losses
Two-dimensional projections of parties’ Manifesto scores, depicted with gains and losses in an m vote (n = 3; a = 12) setting.
Here, the larger the plus sign, the larger the gains for a party, whereas the larger the minus sign the larger the losses. As the
figures depict, centrally located parties generally benefit in the m vote setting, relative to peripheral parties.
APPENDIX
A: R Function Used to Calculate New Vote Share
require("plyr")
require("Gmedian")
require(SDMTools)
require("ggrepel")
require(ggthemes)
require("jtools")
COG_ndim <- function(ideology, parties){
M <- sum(parties[,2])
output_mean <- NA
output_sd <- NA
for(i in 1:ncol(ideology)){
assign(paste("COG", i, sep=""), wt.mean(ideology[,i], parties[,2]))
assign(paste("COG.sd", i, sep=""), wt.sd(ideology[,i], parties[,2]))
output_mean[i] <- get(paste("COG",i,sep=""))
output_sd[i] <- get(paste("COG.sd", i, sep=""))
}
data.frame(cbind(output_mean, output_sd))
}
result <- function(population, parties, ideology, acceptability, ballots,
rational){
voters <- c()
lengths <- round_preserve_sum(parties$percentages, 3)
for(i in parties$names){ # creates the party-voter vector
subvector <- c()
length = population*lengths[i]
length[is.na(length)] <- 0
subvector <- c(rep(i, times=length))
voters <- append(voters, subvector)
}
vote.mat <- matrix(ncol = ncol(ideology)) #dimensionality
for(i in voters){
vote.mat <- rbind(vote.mat, ideology[i,])
}
### VOTES ###
# First Vote
votes <- c()
vote1 <- c()
for(i in 2:nrow(vote.mat)){
distances <- c()
for(j in 1:nrow(ideology)){
distances <- append(distances, dist(rbind(vote.mat[i,], ideology[j,])))
}
vote1 <- append(vote1, which.min(distances))
}
votes <- vote1
# Second vote
vote2 <- c()
for(i in 2:nrow(vote.mat)){
if(runif(1) <= rational){
distances <- c()
for(j in 1:nrow(ideology)){
distances <- append(distances, dist(rbind(vote.mat[i,],
ideology[j,])))
}
ifelse(sort(unique(distances))[2] < acceptability, vote2 <-
append(vote2,which(distances == sort(unique(distances))[2])), vote2 <-
append(vote2, NA))
} else{vote2 <- append(vote2,sample(parties$names,1))}
}
votes <- append(vote1, vote2)
recorded <- cbind(vote1, vote2)
# 3rd vote and beyond
if(ballots>2){
for(b in 3:ballots){
voters <- NA
vote.vec.init <- votes
vote.total <- data.frame(table(vote.vec.init, useNA = "always"))
vote.vec.perc <-
round_preserve_sum(vote.total$Freq/sum(vote.total$Freq),3)
vote.total <- cbind(vote.total, vote.vec.perc)
lengths <- round_preserve_sum(vote.total$vote.vec.perc, 3)
for(i in 1:length(as.character(vote.total$vote.vec.init))){ # creates
the party-voter vector
subvector <- c()
length = round_preserve_sum(sum(vote.total$Freq)/(b-1)*lengths[i], 3)
sum(vote.total$Freq)
length[is.na(length)] <- 0
subvector <- c(rep(as.character(vote.total$vote.vec.init[i]),
times=length))
voters <- append(voters, subvector)
}
voters <- as.numeric(voters[2:length(voters)])
vote.mat.init <- matrix(ncol = ncol(ideology))
for(i in voters){
vote.mat.init <- rbind(vote.mat.init, ideology[i,])
}
vote.mat.init <- vote.mat.init[2:nrow(vote.mat.init),]
assign(paste("vote", b, sep=""), c())
for(i in 1:nrow(vote.mat.init)){
distances <- c()
loopnums <- 1:nrow(ideology)
loopideo <- subset(loopnums, loopnums%in%recorded[i,]==F)
if(runif(1) <= rational){
for(j in loopideo){
distances <- append(distances, dist(rbind(vote.mat.init[i,],
ideology[j,])))
}
ifelse(is.na(sort(unique(distances))[1])==F &
sort(unique(distances))[1] < acceptability, assign(paste("vote", b, sep=""),
append(get(paste("vote", b, sep="")),loopideo[which.min(distances)])),
assign(paste("vote", b, sep=""),append(get(paste("vote", b,
sep="")), NA)))
} else{assign(paste("vote", b, sep=""), append(get(paste("vote", b,
sep="")),sample(c(1:length(loopideo)),1)))}
}
votes <- append(votes, get(paste("vote", b, sep="")))
recorded <- cbind(recorded,get(paste("vote", b, sep="")))
}
}else{NA}
counts <- data.frame(table(votes))
percentage <- (counts$Freq)/sum(counts$Freq)
vote1count <- data.frame(table(vote1))
vote1count <- (vote1count$Freq)/sum(vote1count$Freq)
distance_from_center <- c()
for(i in 1:nrow(ideology)){
distance_from_center <- append(distance_from_center,
dist(rbind(ideology[i,],COG_ndim(ideology, parties)$output_mean)))
}
results <- data.frame(cbind(counts$votes, percentage, vote1count,
distance_from_center))
names(results) <- c("Party", "Votes", "Initial Vote", "Distance from
Center")
results
}
B: Simulation Results for Germany Perturbation
Figure A1. Two-Dimensional Depictions of Parties, Gains and Losses
Two-dimensional projections of parties’ Manifesto scores, depicted with gains and losses in an
m vote (n = 3; a = 12) setting. Here, the “Centrist Party” has been added, and its somewhat
central location enhances the centripetal nature of the hypothetical results in Germany