ArticlePDF Available

Teaching Philosophy through Paintings: A Museum Workshop

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

There is wide research about the Philosophy for/with Children program. However, there is not any known attempt to investigate how a philosophical discussion can be implemented through a museum workshop. The present research aims to discuss aesthetic and epistemological issues with primary school children through a temporary art exhibition in a museum in Cyprus. Certainly, paintings have been used successfully to connect philosophical topics with the experiences of the children. We suggest, though, that this is not as innovative as the conduction of a dialogue in a museum. Results were mostly positive. Pupils participated in the discussion and they gave intensive definitions of beautiful paintings and counterexamples for given definitions. The structure of inductive arguments and the difference between belief and knowledge were discussed. Progress in the analysis of inductive arguments was slightly noticeable, but it is likely that this was due to limited time spent on analysing those arguments. Furthermore, more sessions are needed to make generalisations for the effectiveness of the Philosophy for Children program in a museum instead of a traditional classroom. Even though there is discussion about the different stimuli of the discussion, it might be worth considering the effectiveness of different contexts where the discussion can take place.
No caption available
… 
No caption available
… 
No caption available
… 
Content may be subject to copyright.
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
62
Teaching Philosophy through Paintings: A Museum Workshop
Savvas Ioannou, Kypros Georgiou & Ourania Maria Ventista
ABSTRACT: There is wide research about the Philosophy for/with Children program. However,
there is not any known attempt to investigate how a philosophical discussion can be implemented
through a museum workshop. The present research aims to discuss aesthetic and epistemological issues
with primary school children through a temporary art exhibition in a museum in Cyprus. Certainly,
paintings have been used successfully to connect philosophical topics with the experiences of the
children. We suggest, though, that this is not as innovative as the conduction of a dialogue in a museum.
Results were mostly positive. Pupils participated in the discussion and they gave intensive definitions of
beautiful paintings and counterexamples for given definitions. The structure of inductive arguments and
the difference between belief and knowledge were discussed. Progress in the analysis of inductive
arguments was slightly noticeable, but it is likely that this was due to limited time spent on analysing
those arguments. Furthermore, more sessions are needed to make generalisations for the effectiveness
of the Philosophy for Children program in a museum instead of a traditional classroom. Even though
there is discussion about the different stimuli of the discussion, it might be worth considering the
effectiveness of different contexts where the discussion can take place.
Keywords Philosophy for Children Museum Workshop Paintings Aesthetics - Epistemology
Introduction
hilosophy for Children was developed in the USA in the late 1960’s by Matthew Lipman
and it is currently being taught in approximately 60 countries (SAPERE, 2015). Primary
school philosophy is about providing children with the opportunity to explore fundamental
aspects of their experiences which are already meaningful to them, in order to become more
sensitive to their philosophical dimensions (ethical, logical, metaphysical, epistemological)”
(Ventista & Paparoussi, 2016, p. 613). This paper aims to present a Philosophy for Children
intervention in a different context than usual. It presents how P4C can be implemented in a
museum as a workshop. This paper presents a museum workshop focusing on aesthetics and
epistemology. This paper will suggest a new way of teaching P4C combined with museum
education. Even though this paper does not make any causal claims about the effectiveness of
teaching P4C in a museum, it does set a new context for further investigation.
The aim of this research was to investigate whether fifth-grade primary school children can
engage in a philosophical dialogue concerning aesthetic and epistemological issues and be critical
of their and other’s opinions. This research also aimed to experiment with a new way of
P
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
63
implementing a philosophical dialogue; that is, philosophizing through a workshop in an art
museum. Another aim was to develop the verbal reasoning of children about philosophical issues.
At the beginning, topics of aesthetics and epistemology related to the workshop will be
presented and approaches for teaching philosophy in primary school will be described. Then, this
paper will briefly explain the exhibition and the paintings used as stimuli for the philosophical
discussion. The material created will be presented and the ways that Year 5 students acted on them
will be reported.
Theoretical Background
Aesthetics and Epistemology
Aesthetics and epistemology are two sub-fields of philosophy. The description of them in this
paper and the workshop about them were based on the tradition of analytic philosophy. A
philosophical inquiry into art refers to the philosophical discourse about conceptual questions
raised by experiences with aesthetic objects (metal-level) (Russell, 1991, p.95). For Hagaman
(1988, p.19), aesthetics is a branch of philosophy that analyses;
[T]he basic concepts and language people use in thinking and talking about art:
beauty, expression, representation, symbolism, and the like. Additionally, they
investigate questions in which these concepts are embedded: What is the function or
purpose of art? Do criteria exist for distinguishing a good work of art from a poor one?
[…] What is the relationship between an artist's intent and a viewer's response? […] And
of course there is the big one: What is (or isn't) art, anyway?
Aesthetic questions are close to children’s experience. For example, they discuss whether
certain art works are beautiful or not. They argue that something is beautiful based on certain
criteria. Their teachers explicitly and implicitly judge some artworks of theirs and others as
beautiful.
Concerning epistemology, for Steup (2016, para.1)
[D]efined narrowly, epistemology is the study of knowledge and justified belief. As the
study of knowledge, epistemology is concerned with the following questions: What are
the necessary and sufficient conditions of knowledge? What are its sources? What is its
structure, and what are its limits? As the study of justified belief, epistemology aims to
answer questions such as: How we are to understand the concept of justification?
What makes justified beliefs justified?
According to Audi (2011), epistemology investigates particular sources of knowledge and
justification: perception, introspection, memory, a priori intuition (reason in one sense of the
term), testimony, and inference. We know and are justified to believe several things because of
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
64
those sources. A belief is justified, if it is grounded in those sources which give justification for
beliefs.
The art exhibition provided a suitable environment to discuss specific issues about those
sources. One of them is visual perception (e.g., seeing a bird) which is a type of perception.
Usually, seeing an object entails that this object really exists. People may assume that beliefs about
the external world are justified because we perceive it to be so. However, the world is not always as
it looks like. It may seem to us that we see something, but we are mistaken about it. There are cases
that it seems to us that an object is perceived, but it’s not really there (hallucinations). Another
case is seeing a hologram of a cup of coffee that is indistinguishable from a real one and mistake it
for a real cup of coffee.
According to Audi (2011, p.185-193), inductive inference is one type of inference. When we
reason inductively, the premises of a strong inductive argument provide good grounds for believing
its conclusion, i.e., there is a high probability that the conclusion is true, if the premises of the
argument are true. The premises are based on beliefs we have. Still, even the likeliest conclusion
may be false. Inductive reasoning is probabilistic reasoning and a form of probabilistic knowledge.
An inductive argument can be inductively strong or inductively weak. It’s inductively strong, if its
conclusion is highly probable. It’s inductively weak, if its conclusion is not very probable.
Justification and knowledge is transmitted in inductive inference only if the underlying argument
is inductively strong.
Teaching epistemological issues in primary school students is not usually the focus of
educational research. A literature review didn’t find any research about teaching epistemological
issues in an art museum. We believe this is possible and the following workshop was a way to test
it. Children already argue about several issues in their daily life. They argue for and against views,
and consider the views of classmates and adults. Engagement with epistemological issues could
help them to recognise the relevance of issues concerning justification and knowledge, when they
formulate beliefs. Recognizing the difference between belief and knowledge could help them
analyse better their and others’ opinions. The discussion with their classmates could help them to
contemplate whether their beliefs are justified or not. The particular art exhibition provided a
great opportunity to initiate a discussion with children about the aforementioned epistemological
issues.
Approaches for Teaching Philosophy in Primary School
There are different approaches for teaching philosophy with young children. Different
researchers debate about the material which could stimulate the discussion and the activities that
could be included. In this article, the context of the discussion is also questioned. The dialogue
should not necessarily take place in a classroom. For example, Vansieleghem (2011) implemented
a Philosophy for Children session in Cambodia through a walk. Later, this research will suggest
the implementation of the sessions in a museum.
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
65
Concerning the different stimuli, Glasser (1992) argues that any material could be used to
initiate a philosophical inquiry or extend a theme of the IAPC (Institute for the Advancement of
Philosophy for Children) materials. Those could be poetry, songs, and stories. Additional
resources could also be used to explore themes that are not mentioned in the IAPC materials (e.g.,
environmental issues). Glasser (1992) recommended that plays, films, games, chance events in the
classrooms, and the subject matter of any discipline could also be used to create a philosophical
inquiry. What is more, paintings and children’s drawings had been also used by teachers to discuss
a philosophical issue (Jespersen, 1993). Furthermore, the curriculum for ethical education in
primary schools in Germany also recommended the use of paintings to philosophize with children
(Brüning, 2008).
Various methods for discussing philosophical issues were suggested. Venable (2001) suggested
role play as a strategy for teaching and learning aesthetics. Role play can be inspired by current
events, scandalous or unusual artwork, activities of artists, galleries, and museums. Moreover,
Russell (1991) mentioned that “puzzle cases” can be utilized to confront aesthetic questions. For
Brüning (2008), another method of philosophizing with children is thought experiments with
ideas. This method aims to develop the philosophical imagination of children. It asks us to
imagine what we would do or what the world would be like under certain imaginary situations.
According to Hagaman (1988), discussing a painting can be used as an initiation for talking
about global and abstract ideas of aesthetics. The underlying meanings of a specific work of art can
be discussed and then, discussion about the meanings of all works of art can be started.
Liptai (2005) maintained that while purpose-written philosophical texts are used just for
initiating the philosophical inquiry and don’t have intrinsic, aesthetic qualities, works of art have a
different kind of physical reality and unavoidable aesthetic qualities. A work of art appeals to the
eyes in a different way than a text. It helps pupils who are visual or kinaesthetic learners to focus
on the stimulus. Children with short attention span and fidgety limbs can also be helped because
questioning starts sooner. Children are magnetized by a work of art, and hence, they are forced to
revisit it a lot of times and gain new and deeper layers of meaning. Works of art can be
remembered by the children, influence their aesthetic choices, and function as reference points, as
resources, and as thinking repertoire. A good stimulus for initiating a philosophical enquiry can be
a work of art that is problematical and controversial, and thus, it motivates children to
reconceptualize the categories of aesthetics and taste (e.g., beauty and ugliness) and leads them to
construct (new) criteria. An aesthetic inquiry uses the aesthetic object for more than just a trigger
for discussion.
We suggest that topics in aesthetics and epistemology can be discussed with primary school
students through an art museum workshop. Paintings can be used to initiate philosophical
discussions that are suitable for their age and relevant with their experience.
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
66
The context is crucial for the philosophical discussion. Brüning (1987) emphasized the
importance of presenting the philosophical problem in a context that enables children to discuss
it. Instead of beginning with posing a complex and abstract question, it’s better to analyse a
concrete situation as a starting point. A visit to a museum could be more beneficial than discussing
paintings in or outside of the classroom. In the classroom, the pupils wouldn’t have the space to
do the activities that are possible in the museum. In and outside of the classroom, the pupils aren’t
close to the real paintings. The proximity to the paintings could help the children to notice details
of the painting that they wouldn’t notice otherwise. A philosophical discussion can arise by
discussing those details.
Murris (2000) argued that both children and adults should analyse our concepts by focusing
on how the words that denote our concepts are used in everyday circumstances. Analysing
concepts out of the context of their use generates problems and doesn’t help at all. A concept
doesn’t have an absolute, universal meaning outside the particular context in which it is used.
Russell (1991) suggested some procedures that are steps for learning principles of concept
analysis. First, case delineation elucidates a concept by examining different cases of its use. Second,
concept comparison elucidates a concept by contrasting it to similar concepts. Third, definition
elucidates a concept by formulating and/or assessing a definition of the concept. While
formulating and assessing a definition, it should be confirmed whether the definition is not
circular and covers all and only the cases of the concept. Counterexamples can be used to show
that a definition is not satisfactory. Case delineation can lead to a definition.
Benefits of Museum Education
Research revealed that it’s beneficial for children to visit museums and participate in
programmes there. To begin with, pupils that participated in museum multi-visits generated more
instances of critical-thinking skills and used various critical thinking categories compared to pupils
who didn’t participate in this programme (Adams et al., 2007; Burchenal & Grohe, 2007).
Second, a multi-visit program in an art museum created positive attitudes in children toward art
museums and art in general, and compared to a control group, participators of this program were
able to express better their appreciation and love for works of art and articulated better their
responses toward art (Falk, 1999). Furthermore, in museums, shy and unconfident children
became more open and assertive, able to hold their own in conversations, and able to explain
what they had done and why (Hooper-Greenhill, 2004, p.437). Moreover, children with learning
difficulties were more confident and focused in museums compared to classrooms (Hooper-
Greenhill, 2004).
Jeffery-Clay (1998) noticed that a museum is an ideal environment that allows pupils to move
and explore freely and work at their own pace. This environment encourages group interaction
and sharing. The personal experience with real objects can make them curious and encourage
them to investigate and compare the objects with their own lives and experiences. This can lead
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
67
children to question their knowledge structures, and hence, adding to or rebuilding those
structures.
Methodology
Aim of the Workshop
The workshop aimed to help the children to formulate and assess intensive definitions that
mention necessary and sufficient conditions for the use of a concept. For Russel (1988), a “perfect”
intensive definition “(1) "is not circular," (2) "describes all of the things it is supposed to define,"
and (3) "describes only the things it is supposed to define." The latter two principles refer to
necessary and sufficient conditions, respectively (p.284). An intensive definition is a summary
statement of what is common and unique to the instances of a concept. Philosophical inquiry is
concerned with formulating intensive definitions. In contrast, an extensive definition is a mere list
of examples or attributes that explain the concept.
In the workshop, we aimed to improve the philosophical skills of the students in the
following philosophical issues:
Assessing and formulating definitions of beautiful paintings.
The distinction between “believing something” and “knowing something”. How beliefs are
formulated through perception? The workshop focused on general conditions that must be
fulfilled in order to have perception that gives us beliefs that constitute knowledge. Focus
was on two types of perception: vision and hearing.
The structure of inductive arguments. What premises must be true to give us justification
for our conclusions? How can the conclusion of an inductively strong argument be proven
wrong? What are some examples?
The exhibition
The Loukia & Michael Zampelas Art Museum hosted the solo exhibition of Cypriot woman
artist Kyriaki Phili, entitled speculum mundi, from the end of April to the end of May of 2017. The
exhibition displayed works which are visual references to historic paintings as well as works with
stills taken from film. Her two main visual references are the paintings of Johannes Vermeer and
Luchino Visconti’s film, Death in Venice. She used pencil, oil, sand as materials to make her
paintings. Further, the exhibition included a video. Kyriaki Phili attempted to generate a new
reading for selected artworks by Vermeer by modifying particular symbols of the historic paintings.
Consequently, a new narrative and inevitably a new meaning emerges. Photos of the main
paintings that were examined by the children can be found in the appendix.
A fifth-grade primary school class attended the workshop. The class consisted of 12 students.
The primary school of the students is close to the centre of Nicosia, the capital city in Cyprus. The
sample selection is not random and the school was selected because of the proximity to the
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
68
museum. It was assumed that the workshop was suitable for children from 9-12 years old.
Therefore, the fifth-grade was considered an appropriate selection.
Implementation of the Workshop
The workshop lasted for two hours. Two of the authors of this paper, who are qualified
teachers, implemented the workshop. The workshop included several kinds of activities:
discussion, performing plays, and drawings. A variety of activities is needed as different students
can contribute to the philosophical inquiry in different ways. According to Hagaman (1990), while
discussing with children, some pupils can be models for the rest because they have better verbal
skills and are confident to share their thoughts. Other pupils can be models in other activities,
such as performing plays on a theme or an idea which is related to the dialogue. A variety of
activities can be used to develop a community of inquiry into philosophical issues. This inquiry
could be impossible for a pupil studying individually.
Following Gregory’s (2007) suggestion, the role of facilitators was to (a) model and request
good dialogue moves and (b) to help the children recognize in which stage of the dialogue they are
and how the dialogue progresses. During the dialogue, the facilitators were intervening to detect
assumptions that were not recognized by the children, suggest important different views that were
not mentioned by the children, and help children to move from one stage of the dialogue to the
next.
It was the first time that pupils engaged with issues of aesthetics and epistemology. For this
reason, we thought it suitable to focus on encouraging pupils to give counter-examples for given
definitions, and then, propose improved definitions that don’t have the above mentioned counter-
examples. Weekly philosophical sessions could examine the aforementioned and related issues in
more depth.
A visit to the museum can be considered an example which facilitates experiential learning.
The students can act differently when they are in the museum. Even though they interact with
their classmates, they do not adhere strictly to the rules of the classroom and they do not strictly
belong to a classroom community. They can focus on their own feelings when they see the
authentic paintings and they can be inspired. In the museum, the students had the opportunity to
see the authentic paintings and they were also asked to paint their own drawings.
An evaluation sheet (see appendix) was developed and administered as a pre-test and post-test
to all the children, who participated to the workshop. The tests were used to identify the children’s
understanding and verbal reasoning about the aforementioned issues. More precisely, they were
used to discover whether the workshop helped the children to understand the aforementioned
aesthetic and epistemological issues, give intensive definitions about them, and evaluate definitions
by noticing unnecessary and insufficient conditions and giving counter-examples. The pre-test was
used to recognize the views and philosophical skills of the children prior to the implementation of
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
69
the workshop. The pupils faced difficulties on giving definitions and completing the exercises
related to inductive arguments. Therefore, the workshop proceeded by emphasizing improvement
on those areas. Almost all the pupils gave counter-examples for the given definitions. The post-test
was used to uncover whether there was any change on the views and skills of the pupils and help
them with any difficulty they still face. The facilitators were checking the answers of the pupils and
helping them to fill the sheet by reminding them what they did so far or trying new ways to help
them. During both tests, the pupils needed the most guidance in the exercises related to inductive
arguments.
The evaluation sheet was testing whether pupils could implement specific philosophical skills.
In 1 (a) and 1 (b), the pupils should have given a counter-example for each definition. In 1 (c), the
pupils should have stated an intensive definition. In 2 (a), the pupils should have recognized that
we don’t know and explained why. In 2 (b), the pupils should have described one or more
circumstances. In 2 (c), the pupils should have given a counter-example for the definition. In 2 (d),
the pupils should have stated an intensive definition. In 3 (a), the pupils should have recognized
which inductive argument is better and explained why. In 3 (b), the pupil should have written one
premise that makes the conclusion of the inductive argument more likely to be true. In 3 (c), the
pupils should have described one situation that if it really happens, the conclusion of the inductive
argument is false. In 3 (d), the pupils should have mentioned what is similar in the
aforementioned inductive arguments (if the premises are true, the conclusion is likely to be true,
but it is not certainly true).
After giving time to students to complete the pre-test, the evaluation sheets were collected and
the activities sheet (see appendix) was given to them. Each activity had a different aim. In activity 1,
the aim was for the children to formulate and assess definitions of “beautiful paintings”.
Pondering what it is to be beautiful could help pupils to analyse paintings thoroughly and hence,
appreciate their complexity. While the mimic game was happening, the kids that did the mimic
were asked to tell us why they thought this specific painting was beautiful. The mimic game was
used to help the children to recognise characteristics of the paintings. The children were going
close to the paintings and were describing what exactly they found beautiful and why. Other pupils
were encouraged to go close to the painting and mention reasons that they agree and disagree with
the other children. Being close to the real paintings help the student to spot details of the
paintings that could be missed in the classroom. After the mimic game was over, the teachers
summarized what characteristics the children found beautiful in the paintings. The teachers asked
whether all the paintings that are beautiful have any of these characteristics and whether only the
paintings that are beautiful have any of these characteristics. After a brief discussion, pupils were
asked to find other paintings that have the characteristics that they like and decide whether those
paintings are beautiful or not. They were expected to argue for or against their initial views. Their
classmates were asked if they agree or not and why. After discussion, those characteristics were
found inadequate for defining the beautiful paintings, and the children were asked to propose
other characteristics. During the discussion, the children were encouraged to criticize the views of
their classmates. E.g., Does this definition cover all the beautiful paintings?”. “Does this
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
70
Image 1 “Girl during a
music lesson”
definition cover only the beautiful paintings?” Children were comfortable in their own opinions,
as evidenced by the fact that no consensus was formed.
In activity 2, the aim was for the children to recognize the
distinction between “believe” and “know” and discuss which
conditions must be fulfilled so my belief can constitute
knowledge. Contemplating the distinction between belief and
knowledge could lead pupils to be more critical about their
views and consider how certain they should be about them.
One of the teachers drew three times the woman who wears a
hat in the painting. Each time, he drew her hat and clothes
with different colours. The three triplet nieces were named
differently, and the children were asked to guess based on the
portraits which sister stole the diamond ring. Then, they were
asked to tell us why they chose the specific sister. The goal of
the activity was for the pupils to formulate hypotheses about
which woman is the murderer and recognise that their views
were only assumptions and that they cannot be certain about
them. They were also asked to tell us whether they only believe
the specific sister was the thief or whether they also know that it
was her. The pupils were led to contemplate how certain they
were about their views and what could make them doubt their
beliefs. Whenever a child said that he/she knew, the teachers
mentioned good reasons given from other students for
believing that another woman was the thief. They were asked to
describe what exactly doesn’t make them sure about their belief
in this scenario. It was recognised that in this scenario, the mist
prevents us from being sure about our beliefs. Then, the kids
were encouraged to mention other cases in which we believe
something, but we cannot be sure and know that it’s true.
“Under what conditions are we not sure about the truth of our
beliefs?”. The distinction between belief and knowledge was
discussed. Sometimes we believe that something is true, but we
don’t know it is true because the conditions of the environment
or our physical condition hinder us from doing so. Ideal
conditions for our beliefs to constitute knowledge were
mentioned by the children. The teachers summarized those
ideal conditions, and asked whether our beliefs constitute
knowledge whenever those conditions are fulfilled. The
discussion was continued with more counter-examples and
discussion between the children. During the discussion and at
the end of it, the teachers were stating all the conditions that
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
71
Image 2 “Adzio”
the children mentioned in the form of the following definition: “we believe something and know
it is true, if ….”.
In activity 3, the students were required to analyse the structure
of inductive arguments and produce examples of them. Children
use inductive arguments in their daily lives without recognising it.
If they do recognise it, they will probably be more critical about
their views and think about how sure they should be about them.
After the children completed the exercises, it was noticed by the
teachers that all the children have drawn a woman as the owner of
the items. The children were asked to explain why they chose to
draw a woman. The children mentioned that the earring belongs to
a woman. The structure of the children’s arguments was made
clearer by the facilitators. They were asked what alternative
situations can be true. Given answers were that a man bought the
earring for a present to his wife and that it’s not even an earring
but an olive instead. This led the children to recognise that the
available evidence could be used to support another conclusion.
Two more paintings were discussed with the students. Those
paintings depicted the half part of a male and female human body
respectively (Image 1 and Image 2). The children were asked to
guess what is the other half missing. Most of the answers were that
the man wears pants and the woman wears a skirt. The children
were asked to justify their answer and tell different alternatives that
can be true. Some children justified their answers by mentioning
what they observed so far (men wearing pants, women wearing
skirts). Memory was described as a source of justification. Then, the
teachers told the children that what they have done so far in this
activity is similar to what we do in our life every day. We come to
some conclusions about the world around us by using some beliefs
we have about it. “But, how certain are we for the truth of the
conclusions?” Through the discussion, the children realized that
the conclusions are highly probable, but we cannot be certain of
their truth. What we observed and observe give us some reasons for
believing the truth of the conclusions, but we still cannot exclude
alternative situations to be true. Then, the children were asked to
give examples of other similar arguments, but few of them
participated.
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
72
Results and Discussion
We spotted some positive differences, when we compare the pre-test and post-test of each
pupil. In 1 (a) and 1 (b), 2 and 4 pupils respectively gave more or different counter-examples for
the given definitions of beautiful paintings. In 2 (a), in the pre-test, 3 pupils said that they don’t
know that he is their friend because of the mist, and in the post-test, they gave a more detailed
explanation of why they don’t know. In 3 (b), 4 pupils gave a different premise that makes the
conclusion more likely to be true. In 3 (c), 2 pupils gave different explanations of what Sotiris
thought wrongly. While there were some positive effects, it seems that more sessions are needed to
notice big improvement in the philosophical skills of pupils. The 2-hour session had some impact
on the answers of the children, but more time is needed to develop more skills.
Another difference was that some pupils became more sceptical after the workshop. In the
pre-test, 2 pupils gave definitions of beautiful paintings and 3 pupils gave definitions of knowing
something exists that we believe we saw. However, they didn’t give any definition in the post-test.
This may have happened because the workshop helped the students to be critical about their views
and reduce their certainty for what is the definition of some concepts. The pupils were
experimenting with different definitions during the workshop, but they may have not wanted to
commit to one specific definition during the post-test. It is possible that later, they will ponder
about those philosophical issues longer because of this uncertainty. On the other hand, this
change may have happened because we confused the children during the workshop. However,
their willingness to participate with insightful comments during the activities make this hypothesis
unlikely to be true. It seems that time is needed to encourage students to write down their views,
even if they are not certain about them.
It seems that topics in aesthetics and epistemology can be discussed with primary school
students. Children found the activities interesting and comprehensible. They participated in all of
them, even though, altogether, they lasted for two hours. The pupils were enthusiastic to share
their views, argued for them, and changed them when they heard a counter-example. Still, this was
the first time that the children participated in a philosophical dialogue, and hence, the teachers
needed to intervene often to progress the dialogue. Activity 3 needed the most intervention from
the teachers. This shows that more time is needed to make clear the structure of inductive
arguments and help pupils to give examples of this type of argument.
The visit in the museum was a suitable stimulus for initiating a philosophical discussion. The
paintings were easily used to relate the philosophical issues with the experiences of the children.
Moreover, the paintings were excellent stimuli to maintain focus on the topics. There were not as
many distractions as in the classroom. The environment had mostly stimuli related to the topic of
the workshop. Therefore, the discussion didn’t have any digression. This is in agreement with
Hooper-Greenhill (2004) who supported that pupils participate more often and are more
confident and focused in a museum. Furthermore, children engaged the philosophical topics
through playful activities that would be impossible to be implemented in a classroom. They found
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
73
those activities interesting, and as a result, they participated lively in the discussion. This
engagement of the students in the discussions and the story-based activities are likely to promote
the retention of the museum experience by the students later in time and establish learning. More
specifically, according to Anderson et al. (2002), children usually recall and describe museum
experiences that were embedded in the medium of story. This is not surprising as engagement with
stories is a common and enjoyable part of a child's everyday culture. This finding reveals the
importance of tapping into the familiar socio-cultural aspects of children’s everyday experience to
mediate learning(Anderson et al., 2002, p.223).
This workshop was a first step for improving the verbal reasoning of pupils. For Russel (1988),
verbal reasoning refers to the use of words to articulate thinking that is logically sound and based
on examples that support or do not support a position on the conceptual issue in question (p.
282). Reasoning is an important part of philosophical inquiry. Cam (2016) mentioned the basic
operations of reasoning: logical justification and inference. He suggested that pupils can carry out
these operations, even if the terms “justification” and “inference” are not used. ‘Giving a reason’
can be used to introduce logical justification, and ‘draw a conclusion’ can be used to introduce
inference. Logical justification is the giving of reasons in support of a suggestion(p.8). The term
‘because’ can be used when the pupils carry out a logical justification. According to Brüning
(1987), giving and examining reasons for opinions and beliefs is a feature of philosophical
thinking. It should be examined whether the reasons for believing something are good or not.
People have a good reason for believing something when a warrant can serve as a reason for having
this reason. For Cam (2016), inference happens when we reason in order to draw conclusions or
to infer one thing from another(p.9). The term ‘therefore’ can be used when the pupils carry out
an inference.
Of course, one session is not enough to notice significant improvement in the verbal
reasoning of pupils. Time is needed to make pupils accustomed to give reasons for their views and
evaluate critically their reasons and that of others (Fair et al. (2015). However, the lively
participation of pupils gives us a reason to examine more thoroughly the effects of teaching
philosophy this way.
Limitations and Future Directions
There were some limitations on this research. First, the workshop was implemented with only
12 students, and hence, the results cannot be generalized. Second, there was only one session, and
thus, we couldn’t go into depth in the aforementioned philosophical topics and test whether
significant improvement can be identified.
Future sessions could examine the aforementioned issues in more detail and talk about
relevant topics. We assumed that some paintings are beautiful and some are not, but is this true?
Are there objective criteria that can distinguish beautiful paintings from poor ones? What is the
difference between being justified in believing something and knowing something? What is the
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
74
difference between being justified and truly believing something and knowing something? What
are some problems of the inductive arguments?
Creating a randomised controlled trial to examine the effectiveness of conducting philosophy
in museums compared to the normal classrooms is recommended. The environment as an
intervention could play a significant role, particularly in an intervention like philosophy where the
thinking should be stimulated appropriately and it does not necessarily require a typical
environment with students sitting at their desks.
Conclusions
The implementation of the workshop had positive results. Primary school children can discuss
topics of aesthetics and epistemology and found them interesting. Analysing paintings seems to be
a good way to raise questions and discussion about belief, knowledge, and perception. More
research is needed to analyse the peculiarities of this area of philosophy. For example, are some
educational materials more effective than others to initiate an epistemological discussion? Are
some epistemological topics too complex to be comprehended by children?
There was a lot of participation in the philosophical topics discussed. A variety of definitions
of beautiful paintings and counter-examples were given. Students were trying to distinguish
between belief and knowledge and analyse the structure of inductive arguments. Doing the
philosophical discussion in the art museum was helpful. The children could focus in the
discussion by paying attention to the paintings. It’s quite probable that the children were focusing
more time on the paintings than they would if they were seeing a photo of them. They were
observing the paintings from different distances because they wanted to see every detail of the
paintings, and hence, they had more stimulus for participating in the discussion. The paintings
also helped them to connect the philosophical topics with their experiences. Moreover, the playful
activities attracted the attention of the children. They participated in the discussion because they
wanted to solve the mysteries. Walking around the museum and going closer and further away
from the paintings helped the children to get into the mood of exploration. It would be impossible
to implement those activities in a classroom because of the lack of paintings and space. From this
experience, we conclude the benefits and drawbacks of discussing philosophical issues in a
museum should be the topic of further research.
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank Michael Zampelas, who is the Chairman and Managing Director
of Loukia and Michael Zampelas Art Museum, for the opportunity to implement the workshop
there. We would also like to thank Kyriaki Phili for her permission to use photos of her paintings.
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
75
References
Adams, M., Foutz, S., Luke, J., & Stein, J. (2007). Thinking through art: Isabella Stewart
Gardner museum school partnership program year 3 research results. Annapolis: Institute
for Learning Innnovation.
https://www.gardnermuseum.org/sites/default/files/uploads/files/Year_3_Report.pdf . Accessed
November, 3, 2017.
Anderson, D., Piscitelli, B., Weier, K., Everett, M., & Tayler, C. (2002). Children's museum
experiences: Identifying powerful mediators of learning. Curator: The Museum Journal, 45(3),
213-231.
Audi, R. (2011). Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge (3rd ed.).
New York, NY: Routledge.
Brüning, B. (1987). What is a Philosophical Discussion with Young Children? Analytic
Teaching, 8(1), 87-92.
Brüning, B. (2008). Philosophizing with Children at Universities and Schools in Germany.
Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children, 18(4), 2-5.
Burchenal, M., & Grohe, M. (2007). Thinking through art: Transforming museum
curriculum. Journal of Museum Education, 32(2), 111-122.
Cam, P. (2016). Basic operations in reasoning and conceptual exploration. Journal of Philosophy
in Schools, 3(2), 7-18.
Fair, F., Haas, L. E., Gardosik, C., Johnson, D. D., Price, D. P., & Leipnik, O. (2015). Socrates in
the schools from Scotland to Texas: Replicating a study on the effects of a Philosophy
for Children program. Journal of Philosophy in Schools, 2(1), 18-37.
Falk, J. H. (1999). Museums as institutions for personal learning. Daedalus, 128(3), 259-275.
Glasser, J. (1992). What’s So Special About This Story Anyway? Analytic Teaching, 12(2), 45-52.
Gregory, M. R. (2007). A framework for facilitating classroom dialogue. Teaching Philosophy,
30(1), 59-84.
Hagaman, S. (1988). Philosophical aesthetics in the art class: A look toward implementation.
Art Education, 41(3), 18-22.
Hagaman, S. (1990). The Community of Inquiry: An Approach to Collaborative Learning.
Studies in Art Education, 31(3), 149-157.
HooperGreenhill, E. (2004). Learning from Culture: The Importance of the Museums and
Galleries Education Program (Phase I) in England. Curator: The Museum Journal, 47(4), 428-
449.
Jeffery-Clay, K. R. (1998). Constructivism in museums: How museums create meaningful
Learning environments. Journal of Museum Education, 23(1), 3-7.
Jespersen, P. (1993). Problems with Philosophy for Children. Analytic Teaching, 14(1), 69-71.
Liptai, S. (2005). What is the meaning of this cup and that dead shark? Philosophical inquiry
with objects and works of art and craft. Childhood & philosophy, 1(2), 537-554.
Murris, K. (2000). Can children do philosophy?. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 34(2), 261-279.
Russell, R. L. (1991). Teaching students to inquire about art philosophically: procedures
derived from ordinary-language philosophy to teach principles of concept analysis.
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
76
Studies in Art Education, 32(2), 94-104.
SAPERE(2015). What is P4C? Available at: http://www.sapere.org.uk/default.aspx?tabid=162
(access: 15 April 2017)
Steup, M. (Fall 2016 Edition). Epistemology. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy.Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/epistemology/ .
Vansieleghem, N. (2011). Philosophy with children as an exercise in parrhesia: An account of a
philosophical experiment with children in Cambodia. Journal of Philosophy of
Education, 45(2), 321-337.
Venable, B. B. (2001). Using role play to teach and learn aesthetics. Art Education, 54(1), 47-55.
Ventista, O.M. & Paparoussi, M., (2016). How to introduce a philosophical discussion in your
classroom: A community of enquiry in a Greek primary school. Childhood & Philosophy,
12(25),611-629. http://www.e-publicacoes.uerj.br/index.php/childhood/article/view/24994
Appendix
Evaluation Sheet (pre-test and post-test)
Did you know that philosophers wonder about different issues that concern us? Let’s see some of
them?
1. (a)
Do you agree with this definition? What do you think? A painting is beautiful only if it
represents exactly the nature or can it be beautiful even without representing the nature?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
(b)
Why are some
paintings beautiful
and some are not?
“A painting is beautiful,
if it represents exactly
the nature”
“A painting is beautiful,
if it has a lot of colors”.
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
77
Do you agree with this definition? A painting is beautiful only if it has a lot of colors or can it be
beautiful even without having a lot of colors?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
(c) Can you think of a better definition that reveals which paintings are beautiful?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
2. (a)
It is foggy. Someone is approaching, but we can’t recognize his characteristics clearly. He looks
like a friend of ours and we believe he is our friend. Can we say that we know that he is our
friend? Yes? No? Why?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_________________________________________
(b) We have a lot of beliefs about what exists around us and in the rest of the world. Can you
think of some circumstances that would stop us from creating precise views about the world
around us?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
78
(c) We believe that we see something. But do we know that it actually exists? A definition of
whether we know that something exists that we believe we saw is the following:
Do you agree with this definition? Why?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
(d) Can you think of a better definition?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
3. (a) During our lives, we come to a lot of conclusions about many situations by giving
arguments. George and Andreas heard someone shouting and came to different conclusions
through the following arguments:
George:
I hear someone shouting, but I don’t see him.
The voice is similar to Kostas’ voice.
Conclusion: probably, then, Kostas is shouting.
Andreas:
I hear someone shouting, but I don’t see him.
I don’t see John.
Conclusion: probably, then, John is shouting.
Which conclusion is better and more persuasive? Why?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
(b) Look at the following argument:
The pencil of Maria has been broken.
______________________________________________________________________________
Conclusion: probably, then, Anna broke Maria’s pencil.
What should we fill to make the conclusion more likely to be true?
We believe we saw something and we know that
it exists, if there was good visibility”.
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
79
(c) Sotiris came to a conclusion.
But the conclusion is false! Why is the conclusion of this argument wrong? What did Sotiris
think wrongly?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________________________
(d) How are the above arguments similar to each other?
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
_____________________________________________________________________________________________
Activities Sheet
Welcome to the Loukia & Michael
Zampelas Art Museum.
You are in the temporary exhibition Speculum Mundi.
1. Look carefully at the works of Kyriaki Phili. Write in the following box the title of
the art work that you think it is the more beautiful and tell us why.
I listen to the sound of a musical instrument.
This sound is similar with the sound of a guitar.
Conclusion: probably, then, someone is playing
guitar somewhere close.
Name: ………………………………………………………………………………………
The more beautiful art work in this exhibition is the one with the title
……………………………………………………………………………………………..
It’s the more beautiful because
………………………………………………………………………………………….…………
……………………………………………….……………………………………………………
……….…………………………………………………………….……………………………
…………………….
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
80
A mimic game will start soon. Can you mimic the content of your favorite work to
help the other kids to recognize it?
2. Go and sit in front of the following art work. “In Lido of Venice”
Solve the mystery!
In a misty summer day, there was a robbery! Someone stole a diamond ring from the house
of Mrs. Richy. The above photo was taken by the camera of Mrs. Richy’s house. It looks
like the thief was wearing a hat. The only people who were wearing a hat that day were the
triplet nieces of Mrs. Richy. Let’s meet them? Which of the three sisters can be this
mysterious woman?
We have just met the triplet nieces. Write in the following box which of the 3 sisters
you believe that she appears behind the mist in the painting.
How sure are you about your answer? Draw yourself to the step that represents
your view.
………………………………………………………………………
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
81
Paint the figure by using the
colors that represent the sister
that stole the ring. Where
would you draw her look?
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
82
3. Look at the following art work. Find it and sit in front of it.
“Locus I”
Draw in the following box the things that belong to someone.
Can you imagine their owner or owners? Draw him/her/them in the above art work and
give him/her/them name/names.
I painted …………………………………………………………………………………..
ANALYTIC TEACHING AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAXIS
VOL. 38, ISSUE 1 (2017)
83
Address Correspondences to:
Savvas Ioannou, Doctoral Researcher
School of Philosophical, Anthropological and Film Studies
University of St Andrews
savvasioa@hotmail.com
Kypros Georgiou, Museum Educator
Loukia & Michael Zampelas Art Museum
kypros1991@hotmail.com
Ourania Maria Ventista, Doctoral Researcher and Teaching Assistant
School of Education
Durham University
o.m.ventista@durham.ac.uk
... Two other American studies mapped the influence of Museum visit intervention on visual literacy and the Spanish language study in middle school students [36], [40]. Two Cyprus studies mapped the influence of museum visits on possibility thinking features and philosophical discussion in primary school context [38], [39]. Similarly, one study from the Philippines focuses on the impact of natural history museums on students' interest in environmental issues One study from China focuses on children's creativity in informal settings like museums [37]. ...
... The other two studies employed qualitative research design, including semi-structured interviews and observations. Positive differences exist with pre and post-test of 12 primary-school students' museum visits intervention [39]. Another study analyzed a significant difference in students' knowledge in the experimental group in the disaster management program organized by the museum compared to the control group. ...
Article
Full-text available
This scoping review aims to provide an overview of empirical studies on worldwide museum visit intervention in K-12 education. The study employed Mendeley citation software to identify the articles in the database. A meta-analysis PRISMA statement is used for reporting the items. Out of 135 possibly rich articles, the present study reviewed 18 studies that met the inclusion criteria and were subjected to descriptive and content analyses published between 2017 and 2021. Most of the studies are experimental and from primary school contexts. It is revealed that science is the subject matter context majority of the studies, but philosophy, disaster management, language, and environmental science are also represented. The content analysis resulted in the following learning and social outcomes. It states that social outcome is explored chiefly, followed by learning outcome. The findings indicate that museum visit intervention positively impacts students learning and social outcome. The review also identifies the need for further research on museum visit intervention in the Asia Pacific region.
... P4C can be implemented in a less traditional setting. Last year, whilst I was participating in a research team, we investigated implementing P4C in a museum context (Ioannou, Georgiou & Ventista, 2017). Vansieleghem (2011) engaged students in Cambodia in a P4C session where the main activity was walking. ...
Article
Full-text available
Conceptualisation and reasoning involve intellectual operations that can and should be taught. This paper identifies pairs of basic operations in reasoning and conceptualisation that are comparable to the basic operations of arithmetic and just as important. Examples are provided to illustrate how these operations may be introduced in the classroom.
Article
Full-text available
Philosophy for Children (P4C) is implemented in different countries, but there are not many studies which examine P4C in Greek primary schools. This research examines a P4C intervention in a primary school in northern Greece. This study can be used as a guide for educators who are interested in starting implementing P4C, because it describes the structure of the initial P4C session in an untrained classroom and it provides an analysis of easily implemented formative assessment practices. The research questions are similar to the questions that educators could set when they initially implement P4C: Do the students raise philosophical questions? Are the students engaged in the dialogue? Do students provide concrete reasons to support their opinions? Are students willing to listen to the different opinions of their classmates? Do they enjoy participating in the sessions? Does P4C intervention have an impact on the students’ opinion concerning the discussed topic after the intervention? The conducted research used Shel Silverstein’s, The Missing Piece Meets the Big O (1976/ 2006) as an introductory stimulus. The participants were twenty Year 6 students. The research design is experimental with pre-testing and post-testing of the students’ opinion about fulfilment before and after the sessions. The findings cannot be generalized, but they clearly demonstrate that the participating students wonder about philosophical issues and they developed a dialogue on fulfilment. All the students in our sample were engaged in this dialogue and the post-tests showed a modification in the expressed opinion after P4C sessions. (Open access publication)
Article
Full-text available
Article
Full-text available
In this article we report the findings of a randomised control clinical trial that assessed the impact of a Philosophy for Children program and replicated a previous study conducted in Scotland by Topping and Trickey. A Cognitive Abilities Test (CAT in the UK or CogAT in the USA) was administered as a pretest and a posttest to randomly selected experimental groups (N = 363, 186 seventh graders + 177 eighth graders) and control groups (N = 177, 79 seventh graders + 98 eighth graders). The students in the experimental group engaged in philosophy lessons in a setting of structured, collaborative inquiry in their language arts classes for one hour per week for a number of weeks. The control group received the standard language arts curriculum in that one hour. The study found that the seventh grade students who had experienced the P4C program showed significant gains relative to those in the seventh grade control group at a high level of statistical significance, but the eighth grade students in the experimental group did not show such gains over the eighth grade control group. It was discovered that the seventh grade teachers started the program early in the school year and continued it for a period of 22 to 26 weeks, while the eighth grade teachers started much later and used the program for only 4
Article
Full-text available
Classroom dialogue can be democratic and evidence critical and creative thinking, yet lose momentum and direction without a plan for systematic inquiry. This article presents a six-stage framework for facilitating philosophical dialogue in pre-college and college classrooms, drawn from John Dewey and Matthew Lipman. Each stage involves particular kinds of thinking and aims at a specific product or task. The role of the facilitator-illustrated with suggestive scripts-is to help the participants move their dialogue through the stages of the framework and to model and prompt good social and cognitive dialogue moves within each stage, until the participants learn to become self-managed.
Article
Sociocognitive theorists have stressed the importance of both teacher and peer collaboration in learning and academic achievement. Such collaboration may be lacking in an art education modelled on the tradition of the solitary artist producing original works of art in the studio. This paper describes the Philosophy for Children program in critical thinking, its pedagogical approach involving the community of inquiry, and the sociocognitive learning theories upon which it is based. This program may serve as a pedagogical model for development of collaborative learning approaches in art education, especially within the discipline of aesthetics.