ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

Property is pervasive, and yet we organization scholars rarely discuss it. When we do, we think of it as a black-boxed concept to explain other phenomena, rather than studying it in its own right. This may be because organization scholars tend to limit their understanding of property to its legal definition, and emphasize control and exclusion as its defining criteria. This essay wishes to crack open the black box of property and explore the many ways in which possessive relations are established. They are achieved through work, take place as we make sense of signs, are invoked into existence in our speech acts, and travel along sociomaterial networks. Through a fictionalized account of a photographic exhibition, we show that property overflows its usual legal-economic definition. Building on the case of the photographic exhibit, we show that recognizing the diversity of property changes our rapport with organization studies as a field, by unifying its approaches to the individual-vs.-collective dilemma. We conclude by noting that if theories can make a difference, then whoever controls the assignment of property – including academics who ascribe properties to their objects of study – decides not only who has or who owns what, but also who or what that person or thing can be.
Running head: PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 1
Property and Organization Studies
Nicolas Bencherki
TÉLUQ Montréal
nicolas.bencherki@teluq.ca
Alaric Bourgoin
HEC Montréal
alaric.bourgoin@hec.ca
A more recent version has been published in Organization Studies
https://doi.org/10.1177/0170840617745922
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 2
Abstract
Property is pervasive, and yet we organization scholars rarely discuss it. When we do, we think of it as a
black-boxed concept to explain other phenomena, rather than studying it in its own right. This may be
because organization scholars tend to limit their understanding of property to its legal definition, and
emphasize control and exclusion as its defining criteria. This essay wishes to crack open the black box of
property and explore the many ways in which possessive relations are established. They are achieved
through work, take place as we make sense of signs, are invoked into existence in our speech acts, and
travel along sociomaterial networks. Through a fictionalized account of a photographic exhibition, we
show that property overflows its usual legal-economic definition. Building on the case of the
photographic exhibit, we show that recognizing the diversity of property changes our rapport with
organization studies as a field, by unifying its approaches to the individual-vs.-collective dilemma. We
conclude by noting that if theories can make a difference, then whoever controls the assignment of
property including academics who ascribe properties to their objects of study decides not only who
has or who owns what, but also who or what that person or thing can be.
Keywords: human relations and practices, performativity, property and possession, relationality
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 3
Property and Organization Studies
Property matters. On that, both common sense and social sciences agree. Property resonates with our
deepest intuitions, our most personal experiences. We cherish our own ideas, holding them close to our
chests, and proudly show off our creations and accomplishments. We yearn for a space we can call our
own, physical or otherwise, and we protect it with locks and passwords. We resent usurpation and
sympathize with the dispossessed.
The intimacy of property may explain why the concept has permeated Western thought so
profoundly. It is the very foundation of capitalism, and even Marxist critique does not reject property so
much as alter the set of proprietors (c.f. Cohen, 1995, p. 173 et sq.). Property is at the root of our
conceptions of personal freedom (Knowles, 1983; Radin, 1982), value (Suttie, Ginsberg, Isaacs, &
Marshall, 1935), justice (Harris, 1996) and the state (Underkuffler, 1990), and social institutions such as
marriage are based on how we view property (Anderson & Bidner, 2015). As early as Adam Smith’s
recognition that property is in reality instituted for the defence of the rich against the poor, or of those
who have some property against those who have none at all(Smith, 1776/1801, p. 167), the notion has
resonated with power and resistance (see Banerjee, 2008). Perspectives on property form the
infrastructure of labour relations theory (Pagano, 1991), the theory of the firm (e.g. Demsetz, 1983;
Dobson, 1994) and stakeholder theory (Freeman, 1984; see also Kuhn, 2008), and underpin our
understanding of organizations of all kinds. As work is increasingly post-bureaucratic (Hodgson, 2004;
Kellogg, Orlikowski, & Yates, 2006), and as information technology draws us ever deeper into a service
and knowledge economy built on intangibles, property has all but disappeared. It has infiltrated the
interstices of our relationships, and now fuels debates over the ownership of intellectual production (e.g.
Epstein, 2010) and the fragmentation and modularization of organizations and persons alike (Golden &
Geisler, 2007; Kallinikos, 2003).
Property is pervasive, and yet we organization scholars rarely discuss it. Perhaps we have
accepted Talcott Parsons’ ‘division of labour between economics and sociology, and assign property
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 4
exclusively to the former (Velthuis, 1999). When we do use the notion, we take it as a black box to
explain other phenomena, rather than studying it in its own right. Organization studies have adopted a
restrictive view of property and its related notions, focusing on the ownership of resources through
contractual arrangements. In this respect, scholars have paid great attention to investigating legal formats
of firm ownership (e.g. Pinnington & Morris, 2002) and the effects of transaction costs on firm structure
and performance (Langlois, 2006). Others have considered owners and shareholders’ role in firm
governance (Connelly, Hoskisson, Tihanyi, & Certo, 2010), or what power stakeholders may wield within
the organization (de Bakker & den Hond, 2008). Such questions, however, begin with the assumption that
people are shareholders or stakeholders, thus sidestepping the issue of how they may hold shares or
stakes in the first place, and missing the opportunity to pinpoint the specifics of each form of engagement
(Sloan & Oliver, 2013; Turcotte & Pasquero, 2001). Such views of property risk substantializing the
notion by requiring the existence of a set of owners who possess, through a privileged mode, a set of
things that are external to them and over which they have a right of control. In contrast, legal authors (e.g.
Honoré, 1993) have recognized that there is no single form or effect of ownership, but they have done so
from within a legal and/or economic stance. Indeed, as legal theorist Carol Rose (2015, p. 60) notes, “The
truth is that legal definitions of possession largely refer back to legality itself. Legality […] is the chief
focal point around which social norms of property congeal.”
Property, we will see, is in fact achieved in many different ways a multiplicity that unleashes
the notion’s heuristic power to account for the mutual constitution of people and organizations. When we
throw off our conceptual blinkers, we can look at what people who care for their organization do in their
daily work and life: they have their projects, their duties, their disciplines and their departments but also
their bodies, their emotions and their friends (Ashcraft, 2008). Belonging to a team, sharing an
experience, appropriating a skill’… the vast lexicon of property is an invitation to closely examine the
practices we describe with such phrases. When we do so, we learn that what people and collectives are
cannot be distinguished from what they have: beings gain existence as they acquire properties through
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 5
additional modes; as they fill themselves with the world, prehend it, integrate it within (Debaise, 2006,
p. 89). It is high time, therefore, that organizational scholars cracked open the black box of property and
reclaimed one of their discipline’s core concepts.
Through a fictionalized account of a photographic exhibition that the first author helped organize
in an underprivileged district of Montréal, Canada, we will show that property overflows its usual legal-
economic definition. The people and organizations involved in the project a community worker, a
photographer, district residents, a tenants association, a gallery, politicians, etc. variously established
what we call possessive relations with the exhibit through work, semiotics, speech acts, materiality and
legal contracts. Those relationships shaped the exhibit itself as well as its many proprietors. Building on
this story, we show that recognizing the diversity of property changes our rapport with organization
studies as a field, by unifying its approaches to the individual-vs.-collective dilemma. We conclude by
noting that if theories can make a difference (McKenzie, 2006, p.18), then whoever controls the
assignment of property including academics who ascribe properties to their objects of study decides
not only who has/owns what, but also who or what that person or thing can be. Organization studies
therefore carries an important responsibility: as we define the boundaries of our field, we alter the balance
of power in organizations.
‘We’ve got to take a shot of this’: property through action
The apartment block was in a state of crumbling disrepair, making one wonder how it even supported
itself, let alone the families who called it home. The two visitors, their nostrils assailed by the foul stench
of mould, were becoming increasingly aware of their own laboured breathing. Wait, wait, said Harry to
his friend Michael, ‘we’ve got to take a shot of this hallway; I can’t believe the Aman family lives in
here. Harry was a professional photographer, while Michael was a community worker with the Montréal
tenants association. Two weeks before, they had decided to bring a long-cherished project to fruition:
they would organize a photographic exhibition to highlight the appalling housing conditions of the city’s
most underprivileged residents. Since then, they had walked the streets for hours to meet immigrant
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 6
families, elderly people living alone, younger flatmates sharing run-down apartments and many others
whose income condemned them to live on the rough side of town. When not knocking at apartment doors
to negotiate photo shoots with local residents, they could be found selecting the best images of the day at
Harry’s studio.
Ali Aman opened the door and warmly greeted the two young men with a hot cup of tea. As they
settled themselves in the humble living room, Ali affirmed that his family would be delighted to ‘play a
part in the project. First, Harry photographed Ali’s elderly father Hassan who, with his earnest smile,
seemed oblivious to his decrepit surroundings. The best shot, though, was of Tariq, Ali’s young son,
staring right at the camera as if pleading to be released from his cell. Back at Harry’s studio, admiring
Tariq’s portrait on screen, the two men realized that their project was shaping up nicely. ‘We’ve been
toiling away like slaves,’ said Harry, but our exhibition is going to be a blast!
Harry and Michael describe the exhibition as their project, and they are quite right: they sweated
over it for weeks, agonizing over every tiny decision. Locke’s ‘labour theory of property (1689/1821,
sec. V), probably the most canonical in the literature, rings true here. If someone works on a project, they
should share in its spoils. Even Marx’s idea that private property is theft assumes the Lockean possessive
individualism (Macpherson, 2011): for the fruits of labour to be stolen by capitalists, they must have
belonged to the workers in the first place (Cohen, 1995). Michael and Harry, though, were not working in
the hope of appropriating some outcome or surplus of their work, as the theory suggests (Keyes, 1981, p.
38). The event, they hoped, would belong to the whole community. A clear separation between an activity
and its outcome implies a linear and additive view, where work is but a part, along with capital, towards a
product, which is the real object of value. Harry and Michael did not need an ulterior goal: they started to
feel that Montréal’s housing issues, the tenants’ problems and, indeed, the project in itself were all theirs.
Insofar as they related to them through a diversity of concrete working practices, those aspects belonged
to them (Cooper, 2005; Hennion, 2015). Property is not the outcome of work, it is coextensive to it. It is
accomplished by the possessive relationships one constitutes with an object through action.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 7
‘[If] I own a can of tomato juice and spill it in the sea... do I thereby come to own the sea…?’ the
libertarian critic Nozick (1974, p. 74) famously asked. Of course, mixing anyone’s labour with anything
doesn’t magically produce legal-economic property. And yet, even spilling tomato juice say, as part of
some biology research project can create a possessive relationship between you and that portion of the
sea. It’s ‘your spot, where you spend hours measuring reductions in oxygen levels as the juice decays;
it’s ‘your dissertation fieldwork. In fact, even as he criticizes Locke, Marx and other proponents of the
labour theory of property, Nozick shares with them a narrow legal-economic focus on the product of
work. As soon as we understand property as a variety of possessive relations accomplished in action, the
nature of these relations is no longer limited, and the black box of property can be opened.
We really belong here: semiotic relations of property
When Harry and Michael returned to the Amans’ apartment a week later, they came proudly bearing a
thick portfolio of images they were considering for the exhibition, and on which they wanted the family’s
opinion. The group went through the photographs, discussing them and sorting them into piles. Tariq’s
portrait struck all those present with its forceful beauty. Harry and I were thinking of using this one on
our promotional material,’ explained Michael. ‘We could use it on the exhibit’s poster, as well as on our
website.’ Gazing at his son’s image, Ali was silent for a moment before saying tearfully, This has a lot of
meaning for us, you know.’ Then he reached into his wallet, retrieved a refugee identification card, and
showed it to the two visitors. ‘Since we came to Montréal, we’ve always been strangers and on the
receiving end of charity. Now you’re telling us that we’ll have a chance to be the ones doing the helping,
thanks to this project, and that we really belong here.’
One of the most powerful ways to establish possessive relations is through the creation of
meaning and the signs that make it possible. Images and photographs are semiotic devices that attach us
to places, organizations and identities (Hancock, 2005; Itakura, 1994). A reputable brand strongly
affiliates and controls employees through identification (Müller, 2016), and when it prints its logo on a
shirt, that shirt becomes its shirt, even if the garment was stitched in a sweatshop on the other side of the
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 8
world (Blombäck & Axelsson, 2007). As Peirce (1958) noted, signs both depend on relations and
establish them: the picture of Tariq not only reminds the Amans that they belong to Canadian society, but
also effectuates that belonging, since it gives flesh to their participation in the project. The image of their
son is also the image of the photographic exhibition, as it would be used on all its promotional material,
and would soon be circulating around their city.
Semiotic relations of property are open to ambiguity, contradiction and polyphony. To the
refugee card’s representation of the Amans’ paradoxical bond with their host country indicating that
they belonged in Canada, but at the same time that it was not their country the family could now oppose
another set of semiotic relations: a picture of their son that tied them to a meaningful project. The family
may not legally have had a country as they still had the property of being refugees, but as far as
signification and significance were concerned, they were part of a neighbourhood and becoming valued
contributors to their society. The multiplication of semiotic relations intensified their belonging; it
allowed the Amans to have a community and, reciprocally, to belong to it (see, e.g., Derrida, 1991, p. 11
et sq.).
My administration did it: property as a speech act
A few weeks later, the opening night of the exhibition finally arrived. Everyone was there: all the
community partners, the Amans along with the other families, the press and of course a flock of
politicians. Even the local borough mayor had graced the gathering with his presence. Speeches were
made; glasses of effervescent enthusiasm were raised. Half the reporters were busy harassing a score of
politicians about the now-obvious housing issues, while the Amans were showing off their son Tariq to
the other half. At some point during the party, Michael’s attention was caught by a remark the mayor
made during an interview. The borough is happy to offer exhibitions such as this one to raise awareness
of important social issues,’ he said. ‘It is crucial that our cultural institutions reflect the borough council’s
focus on housing.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 9
Michael couldn’t believe his ears. The mayor had held no meetings with any of them, offered
nothing in the way of support and in fact had never previously shown any concern for housing issues
whatsoever. Yet here he was, taking their project from under their noses in plain sight. ‘It’s only words,
soothed Mary, the gallery manager, when Michael told her of his outrage. He was worried that the
mayor’s claim would allow him to hijack the project – if not literally, then enough to taint it with his bad
reputation. Michael and Harry’s own stake in the project could be compromised, but most importantly the
exhibit would lose its fundamental community-centred aspect its very raison d’être.
Michael’s fears were not unfounded. If property had been an intrinsic attribute and words nothing
more than (mis-)representations of reality, the mayor’s claim would have been harmless. But the fact is
that possessive relations are also established through words. This is true even in the strictest legal sense:
courts may recognize an unchallenged claim as an effective appropriation of the claimed good (Epstein,
1978; Rose, 1985). The way we speak does not merely reflect possessive relations, but also effectuates
them, and constitutes certain people or things as proprietors or as property (Kockelman, 2007). At a
linguistic level, possessive pronouns categorize what can be possessed and by whom (Seiler, 1983).
Speech acts (see Austin, 1962) too, have the power to distribute actions and things between various
beings. This is literally what the mayor is doing by attributing paternity of the exhibition to the borough.
In doing so, he constitutes the borough’s ‘cultural institutions and opportunistically provides them with a
purpose, an agenda, even a sense of morality or virtue. At the same time, he dispossesses Michael and
Harry, and therefore their community-based organization, of their work, authority and responsibilities for
the project. Our properties, both in the sense of what we own and who we are, are made and unmade
through words which are never, in fact, just words.
Who gets to keep the photographs?: the materiality of property
Once the opening party had wound down, festivities continued at The Household, a nearby pub. Harry
and Michael joined the group, as did Mary and Charles (the director of the Montréal tenants association
and Michael’s boss). All those present celebrated the evening’s success and their exhibition’s promising
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 10
future, reminiscing about their communal efforts over the past few weeks and sharing anecdotes about the
party. At one point during the evening, though, Mary raised a question that put a damper on the happy
mood: So, who gets to keep the prints once the exhibition is over? For Mary, it was obvious that the
photos should remain at her gallery. ‘They’re already there, so they might as well stay and become part of
our permanent collection, she suggested. That way our public will always have access to our pictures.
Harry scoffed at her attempt to keep the photographs for herself, and pointed out that the long-
term conservation of printed photographs was a delicate business. ‘It’s not the same as with paintings,’ he
explained. ‘You’ve got to have the right skills and equipment. The photographs should be stored at his
studio, or they risked being lost. Michael, who was trying to accommodate everyone, ingeniously
remarked, ‘Couldn’t we share the digital files among everyone, and whoever wants a print can just get
one done? But Charles rejected this solution, as he did not want the files to end up on the Internet where
they could be copied at will by anyone.
As Mary implied, being in physical control of something is a form of possessive relation. The
chair I sit on in a meeting room is my chair, at least for as long as I sit on it. That’s what Proudhon
(1873, p. 38) called possession in fact. Again, the law may acknowledge such possessive relations: some
jurisdictions recognize adverse possession’, and grant legal title to someone tending the land of an absent
owner for a given period of time (Ballantine, 1918). Possession may be the very foundation of legal
property (Honoré, 1993; Rose, 1985), which is why it needs enforcement, and could regress back to brute
physical force (Umbeck, 1981). War has historically served to dispossess colonized nations of their
resources and lawfully appropriate them in the courts of the conqueror (Banerjee, 2008). From planting
a flag on a newly discovered island to destroying indigenous constructions, colonizers understood the
materiality of property very well (Latour, 2010a).
Harry’s argument illuminates another fact of the materiality of property: one may only own what
one can own. For property to take place, one needs to tangibly care for the possessed object, but also for
the network of material artefacts through which property passes (Latour, 2010b). We ascertain our
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 11
properties with documents that have physical features, from golden seals to microchips, that connect them
to a complex institutional apparatus of authentication (About & Denis, 2010). Record-keeping techniques
affect an administration’s level of (de-)centralization, therefore shaping the contours of (property) law and
determining where power resides today (Vismann, 2008, p. 164). Digital technology, by making
property apparently incorporeal, has only exacerbated its controversies by subverting the spatial metaphor
on which it used to rest. Property now applies to objects that are not localizable in space, and the hall of
records has itself been substituted with myriads of digital traces of possessive relations pictures on
social media, files in the cloud, user names and passwords that overflow the legal-economic perimeter
of centralized government supervision (Varian, 2005).
I am the legitimate owner: the role of the contract
The question of who would get to keep the photographs began to sour the conversation between the four
friends. Finally, Charles forcefully intervened to close down the debate. This is a key project for the
tenants’ association,’ he pointed out. ‘We’ve all signed the contract that says the photographs will belong
to us. I can show it to you if you’ve forgotten. However, this only fanned the flames even further. Well,
I thought the agreement only covered the way we distribute tasks among us,’ protested Harry, his voice
rising. ‘I am not sure it’s all that clear on who owns the photographs.’ He reminded the group that he had
agreed to work on the project at a fraction of his usual rate precisely because he could include the pictures
in his portfolio and showcase his community engagement.
Charles sighed, but had to admit their agreement was ambiguous. Listen, I need to write in my
report to the funding agency that we got something concrete out of this project, and that the association
owns the photographs,’ he reasoned finally. If you want, we can agree to license them to you, to include
in your portfolio. In exchange, perhaps you could teach the gallery’s staff how to handle and look after
the photographs, and they could continue to exhibit them? This proposal momentarily ended the dispute,
as each one realized that even though Charles would retain legal ownership, they could all maintain the
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 12
possessive relations that made the project worthwhile for them. Happy with this conclusion, the quartet
toasted their new friendship and spent the rest of the evening envisioning future collaborations.
Contracts are the emblems of legal-economic property, and yet the enforcement of property
through courts and legal contracts is exceptional and secondary to other, less formal practices (e.g.
Fauchart & von Hippel, 2008). Jurists themselves know all too well that contracts cannot account for the
diversity of actual practice, and they have developed ideas much subtler than the monolithic concept of
property that organization scholars borrow from them (e.g. Epstein, 1978; Honoré, 1993; Underkuffler,
1990). For instance, Rose (2015, p. 60) recognizes that owners must also rely on physical assistance to
exercise their rights, for instance to ‘exclude others with the help of neighbours and legal officers.
Indeed, the strength of property contracts is not transcendental; rather, it stems from their combined
material and semiotic nature. As a piece of paper, a contract can be literally shown and opposed to other
claims, but also bears the signs of prior agreements that lend themselves to renewed interpretation. In
other words, the law and the contracts that presumably enforce it are embedded in the sociomaterial
relations through which property is achieved. While invoking the contract was a way for Charles to
establish himself as having the jus ad rem, as being the legal owner, the very fact that he had to invoke it
shows that it neither predicts nor guarantees behaviour (c.f., Suchman, 1987). Contracts must be made to
talk as people speak in the name of the law(Cooren, 2015). Charles and Harry could only settle their
disagreement when they laid bare the other types of possessive relations that mattered to them with
respect to the photographs.
Possessive relations and the mutual constitution of people and collectives
What unites the various forms of property in Michael and Harry’s case? They all contribute to
shaping their’ project and its participants through the circulation of action (and its meaning) between
them. This is the core of possessive relations: they establish constitutive links between beings, a link
through which they reciprocally set each other in motion by sharing their actions. The initial work of the
two young men gave the exhibit its first existence, while providing them, in return, with an occupation,
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 13
and their respective legitimacy as a community worker and a photographer. The Amans offer their son’s
image to the exhibit, only to acquire, in the same movement, a sense of belonging to the community.
When Harry, the Mayor or Mary perform speech acts in the name of the project, they also shape its
contours and purpose. Reciprocally, these speakers are provided with their own contours and purpose:
moral virtue for community workers, political justification for elected officials, and an artistic program
for the gallery manager. The protagonists of the story negotiate the physical control of the photographs,
for the materiality of the photographs provides a lasting bond to the many actions that define each one of
them. The dispute over the contract showed, for its part, that while it helped decide over one legitimate
owner of the photographs, it could not exhaust all the ways in which the project belonged to each
protagonist.
This is why we suggest complementing the legal-economic literature’s usual definition of
property. The latter rests on the right or ability to control the possessed thing, which maintains a
distinction between controller and controlled, and is mostly concerned with whether the relationship
between both conforms with legal definitions. An alternative criterion for discriminating property is the
passage of action (and its meaning) from the possessed to the possessor. Property is mutual: the
possessed acts reciprocally on the possessor, in the same way as football fans win when their team wins
and the team wins on behalf of its fans. Michael, Harry and the others own the exhibition not only
because they have a right, in potentia or in actu, to use, discard, or capitalize on it; but also because the
exhibition, in turn, provides them with a role, a purpose, a sense of belonging. It provides them, among
others, with a portfolio to show for their talent and a justification for public funding. Each owner can act
more and differently because the exhibit moves them, and they can partly claim its actions as their own.
We care about what we own because a possessive relation constitutes us as much as we constitute what
we possess, by circulating action from one to the other. This reciprocal relationship is captured, in the
negative, by Nietzsche’s (1896, p. 63) maxim: ‘Verily, he who possesseth little is possessed still less.’
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 14
Property, in this original sense, establishes a constitutive link between people, collectives, and
things: it allows each of them to act more and differently. The possessive relations to which people
participate define them. This is true for legal property, which delimits the sphere of the proper, the
personal, in opposition to outside infringement (Underkuffler, 1990), but also of other forms of
possession. I have a job, a task, a department, an idea, but also friends, a gender and so forth, and the
things I have participate to what I am. They also make me do things I could not do without them the
joys and hardships of my friends are also mine, the talent of my colleagues makes me proud, the prestige
of my job shines on me. To have great luck is to be lucky; to have subordinates is to be their superior; to
have students is to be a teacher. As Greimas explains, to have and to be express the same logical
function(1987, p. 88), and there is something artificial in opposing property’s both senses what defines
me vs what I own which share the same etymological root.
Property, however, is also, in the same movement, the creative principle of collectives, as it
necessarily implies alterity, in at least two ways. First, property both supposes and causes the possessed
thing to be different from me. From the moment I speak of ‘my’ arm, I am stressing that it is not ‘me.
Similarly, Latour (2005, p. 204) speaks of the ‘plug-ins’ that supplement human beings: the methods,
instruments, apps and other gizmos we own and that help us calculate, be smarter and more perceptive,
but that can be taken away, break down or betray us. Property therefore always involves improperty, a
reality Derrida (1994, p. 112) called exappropriation: a thing that would entirely be mine would not be
my property, since it would not be distinct from me. I can change, become someone different, because I
may gain properties or let them go. In this first sense, property reveals that the individual is already
collective, made up of many parts thanks to an effort (as small as it may seem to an able-bodied, sound-
minded person). Second, property takes on new meanings as it is shared with others. I can be similar to
my peers, belong to a community, identify with my company, because we share properties: values,
traditions, aspirations, goals. I am part of a family because my spouse and I have a history, a house, and
kids in common. While sharing may appear as a form of dispossession, it also makes property
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 15
meaningful. ‘Sentimental value, for instance, stems from the object having belonged to someone else a
parent, a friend, a lover (Belk, 1988); a consulting assignment’s value proceeds from the consultant’s
ability to have the client appropriate his work and deliverables (Bourgoin, 2015). It is because the
exhibition came to belong to the Amans and other families, and because Harry and Michael shared it
together, that it was so precious to each one of them, but also that they became a team. Common property
creates a common identity, as well as a need to coordinate the way the sharing takes place: the everyday
life of organizations is driven by controversies over responsibility for tasks and duties; attribution of
credit; ownership of roles, projects, ideas and so forth. Even when I must dispossess someone of
something in order to own it, it is precisely the shared nature of property or at least of the bid for
property that determines the value of the good: it is the number would-be proprietors for a same good
that makes it rare, and therefore valuable from an economic standpoint. The reason for controversies over
property is that we know very well that what we have determines what we can do and who we can be,
individually and collectively.
When it is not reduced to its legal-economic understanding, and when it is looked at from outside
of the discipline of the law, property appears as layered and potentially polyphonic phenomena. Indeed, a
thing, idea or person may have as many senses as there are forces capable of taking possession of it
(Deleuze, 1983, p. 4). My’ office means something different to me than it means to the State auditor who
compiles the government’s real estate assets. Of course, possessive relations of different kinds, including
the legal one, can align with each other, creating a densification of property, which then appears simple
and non-problematic. Sometimes, though, they don’t, especially in organizations, which are crossroad of
people, technologies and ideas with competing interests, and indeed possessive relations. In those cases,
property ceases to be a stable explanans of the social, and rather reveals itself as an explanandum that
requires explication in itself. Shifting from the first posture to the second makes us realize the role
property plays in organizations, and how reclaiming the concept may shift our understanding of
organizational action and constitution.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 16
Property and organization studies
In organization studies, considerable effort has gone into attempting to reconnect individual and
organizational action (see Weik, 2011) through various theoretical lenses. They all stress different facets
of the organization, which are exactly the ones that guide our vignettes: action, semiotics, speech acts,
materiality and legality. An emphasis on property helps us understand that, despite the apparent diversity
of approaches in our field, we researchers do, in fact, have a core agreement. We all struggle, in our own
way, with the sharing, appropriating, attributing, etc., that is implicated as organizations are constituted,
and with a different type of possessive relations through which that goal is accomplished. In other words,
organization scholars have been in agreement across our diverse theoretical approaches, but perhaps we
must return to a first principle property to understand why. When we do so, new questions can be
asked, and answered, across perspectives. In the remainder of this essay, we take a first look at what these
new questions and answers may look like.
First and foremost, a property lens specifies perspectives based on action, such as practice-based
research (e.g. Orlikowski, 2010), performativity (Gond, Cabantous, Harding, & Learmonth, 2016) and
processuality (Chia & Tsoukas, 2003; Langley, 1999). Here, a key question posed by the concept of
property is: Whose actions are we talking about? This brings us back to the very origin of organizations:
the first companies were created to carry out activities that only made sense when accomplished jointly
(such as religious groups; North, 1979), or to share resources and risks when embarking on maritime
explorations (see Wills, 1993). Enabling more action as when the tenants’ association, the
photographer, the families, and the gallery join forces is the key role property plays in the constitution
of organizations: an organization’s various ‘owners own a share of its greater capacity to act. This was
understood by pioneering organization scholars, including Mary Parker Follett (Follett, 1940; see Snider,
1998) and Chester Barnard (1938/1968), for whom contribution as the giving or sharing of action with
the collective was a key theoretical and empirical concern. How action moves from the individual to the
organization, and the other way around, is considered in the works of a handful of scholars, including
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 17
Cooren’s (2010) ventriloquism theory, Czarniawska’s (2004) action nets, and Taylor and Van Every’s
reliance on French narratologist A. J. Greimas’ ‘actantial model (Taylor & Van Every, 2011).
Researchers from ethnomethodology or workplace ethnography (e.g. Hutchins, 1995; Llewellyn &
Hindmarsh, 2010) also focus on how action is shared among interactants. Looking at these works through
the lens of property reveals that organizations exist as the (partial) possessors of people, things and action:
the organization acts inasmuch as it has employees, has machines, has buildings, has intellectual property
and so forth, so that their actions are also its own. However, this relation is mutual: I can act more
attract students and funding, go to conferences, work on exciting projects precisely because I am
(partially) possessed by my university. Understanding the link between individual and organizational
action, therefore, amounts to tracing the movements through which an organization may appropriate a
variety of actions, and vice versa.
From a meaning-based perspective, this sharing of action may be considered as what
psychologists have called attribution (see Harvey, Madison, Martinko, Crook, & Crook, 2014). The
term makes it clear that this process establishes a possessive relation; however, attribution theory locates
those relations in the meaning-making processes of people. In this sense, it aligns with interpretive
perspectives on organizing (Putnam & Pacanowsky, 1983), which look at how people interpret
environmental clues to choose a course of action (see e.g. Mills, 2002; Weick, 1993). This view of
attribution, however, has two limitations when interrogated from a property viewpoint. First, it fails to
account for the fact that Tariq’s picture or the refugee card were quite tangible, and rested on real efforts
to be produced or obtained, on computer networks to circulate or authenticate them, and so forth. The
Amans did not just think they belonged; they could prove it. In that sense, attribution is not only
cognitive, but also as social and material as the signs and symbols that perform it. Second, when
considered as happening in people’s minds, it is not clear whose attributions count towards the
constitution of the organization, and whose are dismissed. Concretely, this means that interpretive
researchers should not assume, for instance, that interviews with only formal members provides a
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 18
complete picture of the organization, since membership itself is the outcome of polyphonic and
ambiguous attributions (Bencherki & Snack, 2016). Again, this entails decentering the study of signs,
symbols and meaning from an exclusive focus on individual people, to allow a more comprehensive
observation of the ways in which they contribute to establishing possessive relations.
In that sense, signs and symbols do not merely refer to realities and entities that already exist;
they also create new ones (Austin, 1962). As in the case of our borough mayor above, Robichaud (2003)
explains how, at a town hall meeting, a mayor tells stories that link various narratives describing activities
and, thus, appropriates those threads to weave the city’s action. Language, through speech acts, brings
about organizational reality (Cooren, 2000), whether in face-to-face interaction (e.g. Bencherki, Matte, &
Pelletier, 2016; Bencherki & Cooren, 2011), in writing (Brummans, 2007; Cooren, 2004) or through
technology (Taylor & Virgili, 2008). Speech acts construct (social) reality: couples are married when the
priest says ‘I now pronounce you…’, and institutional facts such as money, baseball or human rights exist
in and through language use (Searle, 1995). This ability, we contend, rests in part on language’s
participation in the establishing of possessive relations. For instance, speech acts attribute the interaction
between two individuals to a broader recognizable institution (this conversation is a meeting, that one
was a pep talk, etc.) by establishing that X counts as Y in context C (Searle, 1995, p. 28; see also
Taylor & Van Every, 2011). Accounting practices, in the same vein, not only reflect an organization, but
also write down the possessive relation through which the organization has people, buildings, equipment
and actions (Quattrone, 2004). A property lens clarifies that what speech acts do is attribute the actions
that constitute organizations and make them act. Rules, protocols and standards, in that sense, are so many
speech acts that operate attributions; when those attributions repeat themselves steadily, we iteratively
produce collectives, organizations, nations and other apparently abstract entities.
Possessive relations endure and can repeat thanks to the durability of materiality, among other
reasons. The town hall meeting minutes will continue describing actions as the city’s long after the mayor
retires. The accounting books of the Jesuits continue to tell us about their organizational structure. The
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 19
pictures will outlast the exhibit, showing that the Amans belong to their community. Software, slide decks
and other documents turn a consultant’s individual field experience into their firm’s collective knowledge,
even after they move on (Bourgoin, Bencherki, & Cooren, 2017; Schoeneborn, 2013). Materiality, it
follows, detaches attribution from an author’s initial intention, making it autonomous (Derrida, 1988).
Artifacts and technology in organizations become what Deleuze and Guattari (1987, p. 424) call
apparatuses of capture: people, work and actions are routinely appropriated by the organization thanks
to the inscription of rules and protocols into machines and objects. Time and attendance software
appropriates the work done during clock-in hours (Paulsen, 2013). Personal files I store on a shared drive
may be reaped by my employer (Franklin, 2012). The autonomy of attribution poses important ethical
dilemmas, especially by making action impersonal. The materiality of property draws attention to the
mechanisms that naturalize dispossession and disempowerment, but also invites us to think critically
about how we deflect responsibility. For instance, a graduated stick used by Doctors Without Borders to
identify children tall enough to receive medical care transfers the heartbreaking choice from each
individual to the organization, so that it becomes its decision (Cooren & Matte, 2010). Materiality
depersonalizes action, but in doing so, also incorporates it into the organizational body.
Given the polymorphous nature of property, conflicts between attempts to establish possessive
relations are inevitable. To handle such cases, a stable legal system that predictably resolves disputes is
essential to business (Lau & Johnson, 2012; Perry, 2000). The law, then, may appear to be an overarching
framework in which organizations operate. Many subfields in organization studies, including studies on
transparency, corporate social responsibility or alternative organizations, have had difficulty moving past
the legal origins of these notions (for exceptions, see Flyverbom & Albu, 2017; Jensen & Sandstrom,
2011; Paranque & Willmott, 2014). An important example of how the definition of property may expand
beyond its legal scope is the shift in focus from shareholders to stakeholders (West, 2016). By
recognizing that the organization does not only pertain to its owners in a narrow sense, this shift has
unshackled governance and made participation a hot topic (see Putterman, 1988), especially when it
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 20
comes to CSR (Morsing & Schultz, 2006). A broader understanding of property also subsumes the duality
between organization and market that situates production either inside the firm (by owning productive
equipment) or outside it (by buying goods from providers) (Ouchi, 1980; Williamson, 1985). Coworking
and creative spaces, fablabs incubators, telework, volunteering and other new forms of work and
production where space, equipment or even labour are shared can only be understood from an
organization lens when property is cracked open (Gandini, 2015; Leca, Gond, & Barin Cruz, 2014;
McNamee & Peterson, 2014). It follows that the law and its courts must deal with several forms of
possessive relations at once. As an example, when users sued Apple after discovering that iPhones
collected location data, the court adjudicated between two modes of property: the phone, as a literal
apparatus of capture’, appropriated users’ movements, while the text of the end-user agreement stated
that those movements belonged to users alone (Bishop, 2013). The number of modes of property that a
decision whether from a judge or a manager considers is finally what may differentiate between it
being merely legal or conclusively ethical. For instance, appropriating an employee’s private emails on
their work computer may be lawful, but still not quite the right thing to do, for such an appropriation
fails to account for other modes of property that link the emails to the employee (Brandeisky, 2015).
Organizations are legal entities but it is time that we, organizational scholars, recognized that the law
accounts for a richer reality than we have granted it.
Conclusion
More than yet another object of study for our existing theories, property calls for a different way of
theorizing. Property is an empirical matter; whether an organization has these or those members,
buildings, brands, partners, missions, markets, and so forth, is an observable achievement, rather than an
assured starting point for inquiry (see e.g. Bencherki & Snack, 2016). Property concerns both what
someone or something has and what he / she / it is, and we must resist defining people, organizations, or
other things before we study the possessive relations that constitute them. Our studies, as researchers, are
so many bundles of speech acts through which we attribute properties to organizations and other beings.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 21
As our research gain traction outside academia, then we normalize the fact that organizations ‘have’ their
environment, their stakeholders, their human capital, their intangible assets, their intellectual property,
and so forth. We turn various things into possessions available for the organization to manage, capitalize
on, or otherwise deal with.
In doing so, researchers are also appropriating objects to constitute the field of organization
studies. If we show that stakeholders belong to ‘their’ organization, then they also become our problem.
As we attributed all sorts of possessions to organizations, we have also expanded our own capacity to act;
from a narrow focus on work processes in manufactures, we now discuss urban planning, the arts, climate
change, and a score of issues to the extent that, we claim, pertain to organization studies. This extension
of organization studies is possible because organizations are ‘bits and pieces from the social, the
technical, the conceptual, and the textual […] fitted together’ (Law, 1992, p. 381) through possessive
relations. Property establishes connections between beings of different ontologies, channels actions from
one of the other, and constitutes the organization not only as property as a contractual perspective would
consider but also as the meeting point of its properties.
In a sense, our suggestion may be read as agreeing with capitalism and its critiques: property is at
the heart of organizations and our work relations. Capitalism, however, operates by suggesting that one
particular mode of property is superior to others, one that channels surplus value upward and lets some of
it ‘trickle down.’ A renewed critique may consist not in fighting against property, but in multiplying the
forms it takes, to allow everyone managers, workers, stakeholders, customers to have a share in their
collective endeavor and to retain a portion of their machines, ideas, responsibilities, space, colleagues,
even without a piece of paper that bears witness to their contribution. In fact, post-industrial production
has shifted property from things to information, making such a broader definition of property inevitable
(Casey, 1996; Hill, 1974). Relatedly, authors have described property’s role in power relations (Cohen,
1995; Galbraith, 1983). That role can be more precisely pinpointed when property is understood as the
circulation of action: indeed, the appropriation of means of production, the purchase of labor, and the
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 22
privatization of space and natural resources (Baer, 2014; Low, 2006), are so many ways to augment one’s
repertoire of actions, but also to limit the activities and identities available to others.
By capturing more practices and people in the net of property, a more generous and ecumenical
definition of property has the potential to open the door to other proprietors, and shift the balance of
power. Property, as a constitutive element of both people and collectives, is the seed for a theory of the
world we own in common and that we must care for together. It draws attention to our responsibility for
our possessions, for ourselves and for each other, as society is, after all, in the words of Gabriel Tarde
(1893, p. 42), the reciprocal possession, under extremely varied forms, of all by each.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 23
References
About, I., & Denis, V. (2010). Histoire de l’identification des personnes. Paris: La Découverte.
Anderson, S., & Bidner, C. (2015). Property Rights over Marital Transfers. The Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 130, 14211484.
Ashcraft, K. L. (2008). Bringing the body back to work, whatever and wherever that is: Occupational
evolution, segregation, and identity. In Annual Meeting of the National Communication
Association.
Austin, J. L. (1962). How to Do Things with Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press.
Baer, M. (2014). Private Water, Public Good: Water Privatization and State Capacity in Chile. Studies in
Comparative International Development, 49, 141167.
Ballantine, H. W. (1918). Title by Adverse Possession. Harvard Law Review, 32, 135159.
Banerjee, S. B. (2008). Necrocapitalism. Organization Studies, 29, 15411563.
Barnard, C. (1968). The functions of the executive. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Original work
published 1938)
Belk, R. W. (1988). Possessions and the Extended Self. Journal of Consumer Research, 15, 139168.
Bencherki, N., & Cooren, F. (2011). Having to be: the possessive constitution of organization. Human
Relations, 64, 15791607.
Bencherki, N., Matte, F., & Pelletier, É. (2016). Rebuilding Babel: A Constitutive Approach to Tongues-
in-use. Journal of Communication, 66, 766788.
Bencherki, N., & Snack, J. P. (2016). Contributorship and Partial Inclusion: A Communicative
Perspective. Management Communication Quarterly, 30, 279304.
Bishop, B. (2013, November 27). iPhone location-tracking lawsuit against Apple is dismissed. The Verge.
Blombäck, A., & Axelsson, B. (2007). The role of corporate brand image in the selection of new
subcontractors. Journal of Business & Industrial Marketing, 22, 418430.
Bourgoin, A. (2015). Les équilibristes, une ethnographie du conseil en management. Paris: Presses des
Mines.
Bourgoin, A., Bencherki, N., & Cooren, F. (2017). Questioning the paradox of knowledge
commodification. Presented at the European Group for Organizational Studies, Copenhagen,
Denmark.
Brandeisky, K. (2015, March 5). 5 Things You Didn’t Know About Using Personal Email at Work.
Retrieved September 1, 2017, from http://time.com/money/3729939/work-personal-email-hillary-
clinton-byod/
Brummans, B. H. J. M. (2007). Death by document: Tracing the agency of a text. Qualitative Inquiry, 13,
711727.
Casey, C. (1996). Corporate Transformations: Designer Culture, Designer Employees and `Post-
Occupational’ Solidarity. Organization, 3, 317339.
Chia, R., & Tsoukas, H. (2003). Everything Flows and Nothing Abides: Towards A “Rhizomic” Model of
Organizational Change, Transformation and Action. Process Studies, 32, 196224.
Cohen, G. (1995). Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality. Cambridge, UK: Cambride University Press.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 24
Connelly, B. L., Hoskisson, R. E., Tihanyi, L., & Certo, S. T. (2010). Ownership as a Form of Corporate
Governance. Journal of Management Studies, 47, 15611589.
Cooper, R. (2005). Peripheral Vision Relationality. Organization Studies, 26, 16891710.
Cooren, F. (2000). The organizing property of communication. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: J. Benjamins.
Cooren, F. (2004). Textual agency: How texts do things in organizational settings. Organization, 11, 373
393.
Cooren, F. (2010). Action and Agency in Dialogue: Passion, Ventriloquism and Incarnation.
Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Cooren, F. (2015). In the name of law: Ventriloquism and juridical matters. In K. McGee (Ed.), Latour
and the passage of law (pp. 235272). Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press.
Cooren, F., & Matte, F. (2010). For a constitutive pragmatics: Obama, Médecins Sans Frontières and the
measuring stick. Pragmatics and Society, 1, 931.
Czarniawska, B. (2004). On Time, Space, and Action Nets. Organization, 11, 773791.
de Bakker, F. G. A., & den Hond, F. (2008). Introducing the Politics of Stakeholder Influence: A Review
Essay. Business & Society, 47, 820.
Debaise, D. (2006). Un empirisme spéculatif : lecture de Procès et réalité de Whitehead. Paris: Vrin.
Deleuze, G. (1983). Nietzsche and Philosophy. London: Athlon Press.
Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1987). A thousand plateaus : capitalism and schizophrenia. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Demsetz, H. (1983). The structure of ownership and the theory of the firm. Journal of Law and
Economics, 26, 375389.
Derrida, J. (1988). Signature, Event, Context. In Limited Inc. (pp. 123). Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Press.
Derrida, J. (1991). L’autre cap ; suivi de La démocratie ajournée. Paris: Editions de Minuit.
Derrida, J. (1994). Specters of Marx: the state of the debt, the work of mourning, and the New
international. New York: Routledge.
Dobson, J. (1994). Theory of the Firm. Economics and Philosophy, 10, 73.
Epstein, R. A. (1978). Possession as the Root of Title. Georgia Law Review, 13, 1221.
Epstein, R. A. (2010). The disintegration of intellectual property? A classical liberal response to a
premature obituary. Stanford Law Review, 455521.
Fauchart, E., & von Hippel, E. (2008). Norms-Based Intellectual Property Systems: The Case of French
Chefs. Organization Science, 19, 187201.
Flyverbom, M., & Albu, O. B. (2017). Transparency. In The International Encyclopedia of
Organizational Communication. John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
doi:10.1002/9781118955567.wbieoc210
Follett, M. P. (1940). The Psychology of Consent and Participation. In The Dynamic Administration: The
Collected Papers of Mary Parker Follett (pp. 196217). London: Routledge.
Franklin, S. (2012). Cloud Control, or The Network as Medium. Cultural Politics an International
Journal, 8, 443464.
Freeman, R. E. (1984). Strategic management: a stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 25
Galbraith, J. K. (1983). The Anatomy of Power. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Gandini, A. (2015). The rise of coworking spaces: A literature review. Ephemera, 15, 193.
Golden, A. G., & Geisler, C. (2007). Work-life boundary management and the personal digital assistant.
Human Relations, 60, 519551.
Gond, J.-P., Cabantous, L., Harding, N., & Learmonth, M. (2016). What Do We Mean by Performativity
in Organizational and Management Theory? The Uses and Abuses of Performativity.
International Journal of Management Reviews, 18, 440463.
Greimas, A. J. (1987). On meaning: selected writings in semiotic theory. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Hancock, P. (2005). Uncovering the Semiotic in Organizational Aesthetics. Organization, 12, 2950.
Harris, J. W. (1996). Property and justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Harvey, P., Madison, K., Martinko, M., Crook, T. R., & Crook, T. A. (2014). Attribution Theory in the
Organizational Sciences: The Road Traveled and the Path Ahead. Academy of Management
Perspectives, 28, 128146.
Hennion, A. (2015). Enquêter sur nos attachements. Comment hériter de William James ? SociologieS.
Retrieved from http://sociologies.revues.org.proxy.bibliotheques.uqam.ca:2048/4953
Hill, R. (1974). The Coming Of Post Industrial Society. Critical Sociology, 4, 37.
Hodgson, D. E. (2004). Project Work: The Legacy of Bureaucratic Control in the Post-Bureaucratic
Organization. Organization, 11, 81100.
Honoré, A. M. (1993). Ownership. In P. Smith (Ed.), The Nature and Process of Law: An Introduction to
Legal Philosophy (pp. 370375). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Hutchins, E. (1995). How a Cockpit Remembers Its Speeds. Cognitive Science, 19, 265288.
Itakura, S. (1994). Symbolic representation of possession in a chimpanzee. In S. T. Parker, R. W.
Mitchell, & M. L. Boccia (Eds.), Self-awareness in animals and humans: Developmental
perspectives (pp. 241247). New York, NY, US: Cambridge University Press.
Jensen, T., & Sandstrom, J. (2011). Stakeholder Theory and Globalization: The Challenges of Power and
Responsibility. Organization Studies, 32, 473488.
Kallinikos, J. (2003). Work, Human Agency and Organizational Forms: An Anatomy of Fragmentation.
Organization Studies, 24, 595618.
Kellogg, K. C., Orlikowski, W. J., & Yates, J. (2006). Life in the trading zone: Structuring coordination
across boundaries in postbureaucratic organizations. Organization Science, 17, 2244.
Keyes, T. W. (1981). Karl Marx on Property (Ph.D.). Marquette University, Milwaukee, WI. Retrieved
from http://search.proquest.com/docview/303183896/abstract
Knowles, D. (1983). Hegel on Property and Personality. The Philosophical Quarterly, 33, 45.
Kockelman, P. (2007). Inalienable possession and personhood in a Q’eqchi’-Mayan community.
Language in Society, 36, 343369.
Kuhn, T. (2008). A Communicative Theory of the Firm: Developing an Alternative Perspective on Intra-
organizational Power and Stakeholder Relationships. Organization Studies, 29, 12271254.
Langley, A. (1999). Strategies for theorizing from process data. Academy of Management Review, 24,
691710.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 26
Langlois, R. N. (2006). The Secret Life of Mundane Transaction Costs. Organization Studies, 27, 1389
1410.
Latour, B. (2005). Reassembling the social: an introduction to actor-network-theory. Oxford ; New York:
Oxford University Press.
Latour, B. (2010a). On the modern cult of the factish gods. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Latour, B. (2010b). The making of law: An ethnography of the Conseil d’Etat. (M. Brilman & A. Pottage,
Trans.). Cambridge, UK: Polity.
Lau, T., & Johnson, L. (2012). Importance of Rule of Law to Business. In Business and the Legal and
Ethical Environment. Boston, MA: FlatWorld.
Law, J. (1992). Notes on the theory of the actor-network: Ordering, strategy, and heterogeneity. Systems
Practice, 5, 379393.
Leca, B., Gond, J.-P., & Barin Cruz, L. (2014). Building ‘Critical Performativity Engines’ for deprived
communities: The construction of popular cooperative incubators in Brazil. Organization, 21,
683712.
Llewellyn, N., & Hindmarsh, J. (2010). Organisation, interaction and practice : studies in
ethnomethodology and conversation analysis. Cambridge, UK ; New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Locke, J. (1821). Two treatises of government. London: Whitmore and Fenn, and C. Brown. (Original
work published 1689)
Low, S. M. (2006). The Erosion of Public Space and the Public Realm: paranoia, surveillance and
privatization in New York City. City & Society, 18, 4349.
Macpherson, C. B. (2011). The political theory of possessive individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Don Mills,
ON: Oxford University Press.
McNamee, L. G., & Peterson, B. L. (2014). Reconciling “Third Space/Place” Toward a Complementary
Dialectical Understanding of Volunteer Management. Management Communication Quarterly,
28, 214243.
Mills, C. (2002). The Hidden Dimension of Blue-collar Sensemaking about Workplace Communication.
Journal of Business Communication, 39, 288313.
Morsing, M., & Schultz, M. (2006). Corporate social responsibility communication: stakeholder
information, response and involvement strategies. Business Ethics: A European Review, 15, 323
338.
Müller, M. (2016). ‘Brand-Centred Control’: A Study of Internal Branding and Normative Control.
Organization Studies, 0170840616663238.
Nietzsche, F. W. (1896). Thus Spake Zarathustra: A Book for All and None. (A. Tille, Trans.). New York:
Macmillan.
North, J. A. (1979). Religious toleration in Republican Rome. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological
Society, 25, 85103.
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books. Retrieved from
http://www.loc.gov/catdir/enhancements/fy0832/73091081-b.html
Orlikowski, W. J. (2010). Engaging Practice in Research: Phenomenon, Perspective, and Philosophy. In
D. Golsorkhi, L. Rouleau, D. Seidl, & E. Vaara (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook on Strategy as
Practice (pp. 2333). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 27
Ouchi, W. G. (1980). Markets, Bureaucracies and Clans. Administrative Science Quarterly, 25, 129141.
Pagano, U. (1991). Property rights, asset specificity, and the division of labour under alternative capitalist
relations. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 15, 315342.
Paranque, B., & Willmott, H. (2014). Cooperativessaviours or gravediggers of capitalism? Critical
performativity and the John Lewis Partnership. Organization, 21, 604625.
Paulsen, R. (2013). Non-work at work: resistance or what? Organization.
doi:10.1177/1350508413515541
Peirce, C. S. (1958). The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. (A. W. Burks, Ed.) (Vol. VII
VIII). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Perry, A. (2000). An Ideal Legal System for Attracting Foreign Direct Investment? Some Theory and
Reality. American University International Law Review, 15, 16271657.
Pinnington, A., & Morris, T. (2002). Transforming the architect: Ownership form and archetype change.
Organization Studies, 23, 189210.
Proudhon, P.-J. (1873). Qu’est-ce que la propriété? (2nd ed.). Paris: A. Lacroix et Cie.
Putnam, L. L., & Pacanowsky, M. E. (1983). Communication and organizations, an interpretive
approach. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications. Retrieved from
http://www.loc.gov/catdir/enhancements/fy0660/83013702-d.html
Putterman, L. (1988). The Firm as Association Versus the Firm as Commodity. Economics and
Philosophy, 4, 243.
Quattrone, P. (2004). Accounting for God: accounting and accountability practices in the Society of Jesus
(Italy, XVIXVII centuries). Accounting, Organizations and Society, 29, 647683.
Radin, M. J. (1982). Property and Personhood. Stanford Law Review, 34, 957.
Robichaud, D. (2003). Narrative institutions we organize by: The case of a municipal administration. In
B. Czarniawska & P. Gagliardi (Eds.), Narratives we organize by: Advances in organization
studies (pp. 3754). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Rose, C. M. (1985). Possession as the Origin of Property. The University of Chicago Law Review, 52, 73
73.
Rose, C. M. (2015). The law is nine-tenths of possession: an adage turned on its head. In Y.-C. Chang
(Ed.), Law and Economics of Possession (pp. 4064). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schoeneborn, D. (2013). The pervasive power of PowerPoint: How a genre of professional
communication permeates organizational communication. Organization Studies, 34, 17771801.
Searle, J. R. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York ; Toronto: Free Press.
Seiler, H. (1983). Possession as an operational dimension of language. Tübingen: G. Narr.
Sloan, P., & Oliver, D. (2013). Building trust in multi-stakeholder partnerships: Critical emotional
incidents and practices of engagement. Organization Studies, 0170840613495018.
Smith, A. (1801). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations (6th ed., Vol. 2). Dublin:
N. Kelly. (Original work published 1776)
Snider, K. (1998). Living Pragmatism: The Case of Mary Parker Follett. Administrative Theory & Praxis,
20, 274286.
Suchman, L. (1987). Plans and situated action: the problem of human-machine interaction. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
PROPERTY AND ORGANIZATION STUDIES 28
Suttie, I. D., Ginsberg, M., Isaacs, S., & Marshall, T. H. (1935). A symposium on property and
possessiveness. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 15, 5183.
Tarde, G. (1893). Monadologie et sociologie. (J.-M. Tremblay, Ed.). Chicoutimi, QC: J.-M. Tremblay.
Taylor, J. R., & Van Every, E. J. (2011). The situated organization: Studies in the pragmatics of
communication research. New York, NY: Routledge.
Taylor, J. R., & Virgili, S. (2008). Why ERPs Disappoint: the Importance of Getting the Organisational
Text Right. In B. Grabot, A. Mayère, & I. Bazet (Eds.), ERP Systems and Organisational Change
(pp. 5984). Springer, London.
Turcotte, M.-F., & Pasquero, J. (2001). The Paradox of Multistakeholder Collaborative Roundtables. The
Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, 37, 447464.
Umbeck, J. (1981). Might makes rights: A theory of the formation and initial distribution of property
rights. Economic Inquiry, 19, 3859.
Underkuffler, L. S. (1990). On Property: An Essay. The Yale Law Journal, 100, 127.
Varian, H. R. (2005). Copying and copyright. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19, 121138.
Velthuis, O. (1999). The Changing Relationship between Economic Sociology and Institutional
Economics: From Talcott Parsons to Mark Granovetter. American Journal of Economics and
Sociology, 58, 629649.
Vismann, C. (2008). Files: law and media technology. (G. Winthrop-Young, Trans.). Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Weick, K. E. (1993). The collapse of sensemaking in organizations: The Mann Gulch disaster.
Administrative Science Quarterly, 628652.
Weik, E. (2011). In Deep Waters: process theory between Scylla and Charybdis. Organization, 18, 655
672.
West, A. (2016). Applying Metaethical and Normative Claims of Moral Relativism to (Shareholder and
Stakeholder) Models of Corporate Governance. Journal of Business Ethics, 135, 199215.
Williamson, O. E. (1985). The economic institutions of capitalism: firms, markets, relational contracting.
New York, NY: Free Press.
Wills, J. E. (1993). Maritime Asia, 1500-1800: The Interactive Emergence of European Domination. The
American Historical Review, 98, 83.
... This paper considers the connections between ownership, organisational structure and managerial regime within a larger theory linking those factors with the organisational environment, work processes and policy-relevant outputs (Sheaff et al., 2004). It elaborates Donabedian's (1980) reasoning about organisational structures to include organisations' ownership, defined as the de facto control of that organisation's activity, plant and products: that is, in terms of property, which "is in fact achieved in many different ways" (Bencherki and Bourgoin 2017), not only through legal or contractual rights. This implies that an organisation's structure embodies, enacts and reproduces that ownership. ...
Article
Full-text available
Purpose Neo-liberal “reform” has in many countries shifted services across the boundary between the public and private sector. This policy re-opens the question of what structural and managerial differences, if any, differences of ownership make to healthcare providers. The purpose of this paper is to examine the connections between ownership, organisational structure and managerial regime within an elaboration of Donabedian’s reasoning about organisational structures. Using new data from England, it considers: how do the internal managerial regimes of differently owned healthcare providers differ, or not? In what respects did any such differences arise from differences in ownership or for other reasons? Design/methodology/approach An observational systematic qualitative comparison of differently owned providers was the strongest feasible research design. The authors systematically compared a maximum variety (by ownership) sample of community health services; out-of-hours primary care; and hospital planned orthopaedics and ophthalmology providers ( n =12 cases). The framework of comparison was the ownership theory mentioned above. Findings The connection between ownership (on the one hand) and organisation structures and managerial regimes (on the other) differed at different organisational levels. Top-level governance structures diverged by organisational ownership and objectives among the case-study organisations. All the case-study organisations irrespective of ownership had hierarchical, bureaucratic structures and managerial regimes for coordinating everyday service production, but to differing extents. In doctor-owned organisations, the doctors’, but not other occupations’, work was controlled and coordinated in a more-or-less democratic, self-governing ways. Research limitations/implications This study was empirically limited to just one sector in one country, although within that sector the case-study organisations were typical of their kinds. It focussed on formal structures, omitting to varying extents other technologies of power and the differences in care processes and patient experiences within differently owned organisations. Practical implications Type of ownership does appear, overall, to make a difference to at least some important aspects of an organisation’s governance structures and managerial regime. For the broader field of health organisational research, these findings highlight the importance of the owners’ agency in explaining organisational change. The findings also call into question the practice of copying managerial techniques (and “fads”) across the public–private boundary. Originality/value Ownership does make important differences to healthcare providers’ top-level governance structures and accountabilities and to work coordination activity, but with different patterns at different organisational levels. These findings have implications for understanding the legitimacy, governance and accountability of healthcare organisations, the distribution and use power within them, and system-wide policy interventions, for instance to improve care coordination and for the correspondingly required foci of healthcare organisational research.
... This paper considers the relationships between ownership, organisational structure and managerial regime within a larger theory linking those factors with organisational environment and performance. (Sheaff et al. 2004) It elaborates Donabedian's (1980) reasoning about organisational structures to include organisations' ownership, defined as the de facto control of that organisation's activity, plant and products: that is, in terms of property, which 'is in fact achieved in many different ways' (Bencherki and Bourgoin 2017), not only through legal or contractual rights. That implies that an organisation's structure embodies, enacts and reproduces that ownership. ...
Article
Full-text available
Health sector ‘reform’ has re-opened the question of what structural and managerial differences, if any, differences of ownership make to healthcare providers. Using new data from England this paper considers: 1. How do the internal managerial regimes of differently owned healthcare providers differ, or not? 2. In what respects did any such differences arise from differences in ownership or for other reasons? Observational systematic qualitative comparison of a maximum-variety (by ownership) sample of community health services (CHS); out-of-hours primary care (OOH); hospital planned orthopaedics and ophthalmology providers (N=12 cases). The framework of comparison was a set of ownership categories related to current NHS policy. Top-level governance structures diverged by organisational ownership and objectives. At operational level all the case-study organisations irrespective of ownership had hierarchical, bureaucratic structures and managerial regimes for coordinating everyday service production, but to differing extents. In doctor-owned organisations the doctors’, but not other occupations’, work was controlled and coordinated in a more-or-less democratic, self-governing ways. This study was empirically limited to just one sector in one country, although within that sector our case-study organisations were typical of their kinds. It focused on formal structures, omitting to varying extents other technologies of power and the differences in care processes and patient experiences within differently-owned organisations. Type of ownership does appear, overall, to make a difference to at least some important aspects of an organisation’s governance structures and managerial regime. For the broader field of health organisational research these findings highlight the importance of the owners’ agency in explaining organisational change. Our findings also call into question the practice of copying managerial techniques (and ‘fads’) across the public-private boundary. This paper is one of the few to examine empirically what difference ownership makes, to the management of health organisations.
... This paper considers the connections between ownership, organisational structure and managerial regime within a larger theory linking those factors with the organisational environment, work processes and policy-relevant outputs (Sheaff et al., 2004). It elaborates Donabedian's (1980) reasoning about organisational structures to include organisations' ownership, defined as the de facto control of that organisation's activity, plant and products: that is, in terms of property, which "is in fact achieved in many different ways" (Bencherki and Bourgoin 2017), not only through legal or contractual rights. This implies that an organisation's structure embodies, enacts and reproduces that ownership. ...
Article
Full-text available
For older people with multiple chronic co-morbidities, strategies to coordinate care depend heavily on information exchange. We analyse the information-sharing difficulties arising from differences between patients’ oral narratives and medical sense-making; and whether a modified form of ‘narrative medicine’ might mitigate them. We systematically compared 66 general practice patients’ own narratives of their health problems and care with the contents of their clinical records. Data were collected in England during 2012–13. Patients’ narratives differed from the accounts in their medical record, especially the summary, regarding mobility, falls, mental health, physical frailty and its consequences for accessing care. Parts of patients’ viewpoints were never formally encoded, parts were lost when clinicians de-coded it, parts supplemented, and sometimes the whole narrative was re-framed. These discrepancies appeared to restrict the patient record's utility even for GPs for the purposes of risk stratification, case management, knowing what other care-givers were doing, and coordinating care. The findings suggest combining the encoding/decoding theory of communication with inter-subjectivity and intentionality theories as sequential, complementary elements of an explanation of how patients communicate with clinicians. A revised form of narrative medicine might mitigate the discursive gap and its consequences for care coordination.
Article
Drawing on Judith Butler’s understanding of performativity, this study aims to explore how power embeds in CSR videos of multinational companies. It adopts a critical semiotics multimodal analysis to show how a particular kind of responsible corporation is constituted by the language, both verbal and visual, that those CSR videos speak. Our findings show in-depth the multimodal construction of three subjects of a responsible corporation: hero, missionary, and architect. We advance the constitutive turn in CSR communication by conceptualizing CSR communication as a political project which 1) subjectifies the corporation through the articulation of a relationship that subordinates CSR beneficiaries and the audience and 2) iterates the business ideology. We discuss how multimodality contributes to masking power, and conclude with guidelines for alternative multimodal CSR communication.
Article
Full-text available
Au cours des dernières années, plusieurs chercheurs et chercheuses en communication organisationnelle ont mis de l’avant un ensemble d’approches proposant une vision constitutive de la communication (Brummans et al., Putnam et Nicotera, Taylor et Robichaud). Ces approches ont été fédérées sous l’appellation « communication constitutive des organisations » (ou CCO), étiquette qui a été consacrée au tournant du siècle (McPhee et Zaug). Même si l’on peut retracer l’émergence de l’approche constitutive au texte de 1988 de James R. Taylor, Une organisation n’est qu’un tissu de communications, l’année 2000 fut une année charnière avec les premières apparitions explicites dans la littérature scientifique de l’appellation CCO et de la notion de constitution, ainsi que la publication de plusieurs textes fondateurs pour le domaine de recherche (ex McPhee et Zaug, Taylor et Van Every).
Article
Organization scholars have developed an extensive literature around the criteria defining what an organization is or what organized phenomena are. However, these theoretical developments do not explain how an organized form emerges, develops and eventually dies out. We propose to address to this gap by exploring what we call the basic organizing unit, i.e. the minimal form that a sequence of actions must take to claim a degree of organizationality. In order to empirically test this proposal, we propose to analyze non-organizational interactional episodes, i.e., street hypnosis sessions. Une littérature foisonnante s’est développée autour des critères permettant de définir ce qu’est une organisation ou encore ce que sont des phénomènes organisés. Toutefois, ces développements théoriques ne nous expliquent pas comment une forme organisée émerge, se développe et éventuellement s’éteint. Nous proposons de répondre à cette lacune en explorant ce que nous appelons l’unité organisante de base, soit la forme minimale que doit prendre une séquence d’action pour prétendre à un degré d’organisationnalité. Afin de mettre empiriquement à l’épreuve cette proposition, nous proposons d’analyser des épisodes interactionnels a priori non-organisationnels, soit des séances d’hypnose de rue.
Article
One question not addressed in communicative constitution of organizations (CCO) literature is where an organization is located. As more workers work on the road, at coffee shops, from home, and in coworking spaces, it is important to consider the relationship of these spaces to the organization. In this paper, I argue that when someone appropriates features of a space to do work, that space becomes organizational. This process allows spaces like coffee shops and homes to become at least partially and temporarily organizational, rendering these workspaces as organizational contributors (to a certain extent). Using photo-elicitation interviews with workers in a variety of fields and organizations, I demonstrate gradients of spatial organizationality and show how, through appropriation, some spaces are more clearly organizational than others.
Article
Full-text available
In this review essay, we explore how Luhmann's radical communication approach, which conceptualizes communication without recourse to human beings' intentions, can reorient existing research on organizational communication. We show how Luhmann's perspective puts decisions back into organizational communication studies, how it changes our perspective on organizational continuity and on organizational boundaries, and how it redirects our understanding of human agency in organizations. We also discuss three areas in which Luhmann's theory could draw inspiration from other research on organizational communication.
Article
Full-text available
Although the lion’s share of scholarship in management and organization studies conceives of organizations as entities within which communication occurs, “Communication Constitutes Organization” (CCO) scholarship has attracted interest because it makes a productive reversal, that is, by asking how organization happens in communication. Over the past decade, Organization Studies has become the key scholarly outlet for CCO thinking in the management and organization studies field. Accordingly, in this paper we discuss seven articles that have appeared in this journal as evidence of the perspective’s centrality. We first situate CCO theorizing within the linguistic turn, and position CCO with respect to other lines of scholarship underwritten by a rich conception of language and discourse. We examine the varied ways CCO thinking has found organization in communication, locating in the seven articles productive tensions between the process of communication, on the one hand, and organization, organizing, and organizationality, on the other. We contribute to CCO scholarship with reflections on these three theoretical orientations and provide a set of possibilities for its further development.
Chapter
Full-text available
Transparency is an increasingly prominent research topic in many scholarly disciplines and offers valuable insights for organizational communication. This entry provides an overview of the historical background and identifies some themes that presently inform the transparency literature. The entry then outlines the most important dimensions of the concept of transparency by highlighting two paradigmatic positions underpinning contemporary research in this area: namely, informational approaches that focus on the sharing of information and the perceived quality of that information and social process orientations that explore the dynamics of transparency in organizational settings. The entry highlights emergent methodological and conceptual insights concerning transparency as a dynamic and paradoxical social process with performative characteristics – an approach that remains underexplored.
Article
Full-text available
In this paper, we suggest that the Montreal School (TMS) tradition of organizational communication offers a fruitful analytical framework that allows us to better take into account the way people practically deal with plurilingual situations as they go on with their daily activities and contribute to shaping their organizations. We identify six core features of TMS and show their analytical power in studying plurilingual interactions. TMS, we argue, is conceptually well equipped to reveal the ways in which multiple tongues are dealt with in everyday organizational settings and to uncover the constitutive nature of tongue-in-use.
Article
In this article I present brand-centred control as a new form of normative control and examine the ways in which it affects employees. To do so, I draw on the results of a qualitative case study of a consumer products company with a strong corporate culture and brand, and examine internal branding as an extension of culture management. The key insights of the case study show that brand-centred control – unlike traditional normative control that typically works inside the company – also engages an external audience (customers, fans, and the wider public) as an additional source of normative control. As employees internalise the brand image of this external audience, they turn into brand representatives even in absence of face-to-face interactions with others and in their private lives. Brand-centred control thus blurs the boundaries between work and employees’ private lives in unprecedented ways. I discuss the ways in which employees respond to and resist brand-centred control and point to further research on brand-centred control as a significant new form of normative control.
Chapter
Cooren here applies his model of ‘ventriloquism’ to law and to the performances of legal speech, which allows him to detect the slight shifts in agency so characteristic of legal argumentation, and which helps reveal the complexity and polyphony of the apparently homophonic judicial utterance. From the Latourian notion of distributed action and the structure of faire faire – a theorem that consistently earns a central place in Latour’s oeuvre , Cooren launches his study by problematising anew canonical givens such as the binaries of passivity/activity and autonomy/heteronomy. We must not forget that ventriloquism involves not only the ventriloquist’s manipulation of the puppet but also the puppet’s manipulation of the ventriloquist, insofar as the latter says things that she, quite frankly, would never say were the puppet not attached to her hand. It is this strange loop of action and passion, autonomy and heteronomy, animation and inanimation, that characterises not only the puppeteer’s performance but also the lawyer’s and the judge’s performances, and, indeed, the structure of communication in general. What, then, does it mean to speak in the name of the law? Without succumbing to the snares of spontaneous hypostatisation, Cooren argues, in contrast to numerous theorists, that the law indeed possesses a sort of agency of its own. A host of legal and non-legal beings (prior judgments, witness testimony, documents of all kinds, emotions like frustration and anger, balances of power, statutes, healthcare reform policies, duplicity, etc.) are figured and mobilised to say certain things in the saying of the law: they are voiced by lawyers and judges, of course, but they also lend their own voices to the latter, shaping the means through which the law may pass.