ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

Responding to purported taxonomic anarchy, in an article published in the widely read journal Nature, Garnett & Christidis (2017) [hereafter GC] opined on the need for “standardized global species lists”, at the behest of conservationists, and proposed the construction of a judicial committee to “restrict … freedom of taxonomic action” and promote taxonomic stability. Here we reflect on this perspective and contest that the view of GC conflicts with some basic and indisputable principles underpinning the philosophy of science, most notably: it must be free. They appear to believe that taxonomic revisions should be based on political, economic and conservation concerns, and they treat species as fixed real entities, instead of refutable scientific hypotheses. In addition to such theoretical misconceptions, GC did not consider important practical aspects of what they term taxonomic anarchy, most significantly the participation of conservationists as authors of taxonomic works, and the importance of alternative management units, a well-established discussion in conservation biology.
Accepted by A. Minelli: 19 Jul. 2017; published: 1 Sept. 2017
ZOOTAXA
ISSN 1175-5326 (print edition)
ISSN
1175-5334
(online edition)
Copyright © 2017 Magnolia Press
Zootaxa 4317 (1): 179
184
http://www.mapress.com/j/zt/
Article
179
https://doi.org/10.11646/zootaxa.4317.1.10
http://zoobank.org/urn:lsid:zoobank.org:pub:88FA0944-D3CF-4A7D-B8FB-BAA6A3A76744
What really hampers taxonomy and conservation? A riposte to Garnett and
Christidis (2017)
MARCOS A. RAPOSO
1,2
, RENATA STOPIGLIA
3,4
, GUILHERME RENZO R. BRITO
1,5
, FLÁVIO A.
BOCKMANN
3,6
, GUY M. KIRWAN
1,7
, JEAN GAYON
2
& ALAIN DUBOIS
4
1
Setor de Ornitologia, Departamento de Vertebrados, Museu Nacional, Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro, Quinta da Boa Vista,
s/n, 20940–040 Rio de Janeiro, RJ, Brazil. raposo@mn.ufrj.br (MAR), grenzobrito@gmail.com (GRRB), gmkirwan@aol.com (GMK)
2
UMR 8590, IHPST–Institut d'Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques, UMR 8590, Université Paris 1 Panthéon-
Sorbonne & CNRS, 13 rue du Four, 75006 Paris, France. jean.gayon@univ-paris1.fr (JG)
3
Laboratório de Ictiologia de Ribeirão Preto, Departamento de Biologia, FFCLRP, Universidade de São Paulo, Av. dos Bandeirantes
3900, 14040–901 Ribeirão Preto, SP, Brazil. renata.stopiglia@usp.br (RS), fabockmann@ffclrp.usp.br (FAB)
4
Institut de Systématique, Évolution, Biodiversité, ISYEB – UMR 7205 – CNRS, MNHN, UPMC, EPHE, Muséum national d’Histoire
naturelle, Sorbonne Universités, 25 rue Cuvier, CP 30, 75005, Paris, France. adubois@mnhn.fr (AD).
5
Departamento de Zoologia, Instituto de Biologia, Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro, Av. Carlos Chagas Filho, 373, 21941-
902, Rio de Janeiro, RJ, Brazil.
6
Programa de Pós-Graduação em Biologia Comparada, FFCLRP, Universidade de São Paulo, Av. dos Bandeirantes 3900, 14040–
901, Ribeirão Preto, SP, Brazil.
7
Research Associate, Field Museum of Natural History, 1400 South Lakeshore Drive, Chicago, IL 60605, USA.
Abstract
Responding to purported taxonomic anarchy, in an article published in the widely read journal Nature, Garnett & Chris-
tidis (2017) [hereafter GC] opined on the need for “standardized global species lists”, at the behest of conservationists,
and proposed the construction of a judicial committee to “restrict … freedom of taxonomic action” and promote taxonomic
stability. Here we reflect on this perspective and contest that the view of GC conflicts with some basic and indisputable
principles underpinning the philosophy of science, most notably: it must be free. They appear to believe that taxonomic
revisions should be based on political, economic and conservation concerns, and they treat species as fixed real entities,
instead of refutable scientific hypotheses. In addition to such theoretical misconceptions, GC did not consider important
practical aspects of what they term taxonomic anarchy, most significantly the participation of conservationists as authors
of taxonomic works, and the importance of alternative management units, a well-established discussion in conservation
biology.
Key words: Taxonomy, freedom, science, philosophy, conservation
Introduction
The journal Nature has historically published important contributions on biodiversity, evolution and taxonomy, the
science behind the classification of living organisms. One such was Bremer et al. (1990) who wrote persuasively:
Taxonomists should pursue their scientific venture and stop worrying about instability in classification. Taxonomy
is not a service function for labeling organisms, but a science of its own, dealing with variation, relationships and
phylogeny” (see also Dubois 1998; Carvalho et al. 2007). These views are aligned with modern concepts of science
and freedom of expression. However, the opinion of Garnett & Christidis (2017) [GC hereafter] expressed in an
article published in the same journal appears to blatantly contradict these principles, by arguing for “standardized
global species lists”, supposedly at the behest of conservationists, and proposing a structure to “restrict the freedom
of taxonomic action” and promote taxonomic stability. Interestingly, Bremer et al. (1990) had also stated: “to
establish some international peer-review system to approve or reject proposed modifications overlooks the benefits
of change in taxonomy”.
RAPOSO ET AL.
180
·
Zootaxa 4317 (1) © 2017 Magnolia Press
Here we reflect on these perspectives following two necessary lines of thought: a theoretical one, where we
concentrate on different philosophical aspects of their propositions and statements; and a practical approach, where
we analyse, based on GC’s examples, the consistency of their statements as true representation of the current
taxonomic universe.
Theoretical perspective
The dispute between those who need, for practical ends, stable lists of existing species and those who classify and
catalogue life is old
(e.g. Crisp & Fogg 1988) and motivated Bremer et al. (1990) to write in defence of taxonomic
work. Twenty-seven years later GC (but see also Thiele & Yeates 2002; Godfray 2007) brought back to the widely
read journal Nature a pragmatic view of the function of taxonomy, demonstrating that the debate is far from over
and revealing the necessity of more profound reflections and clarification.
GC commence by stating that “The assumption that species are fixed entities underpins every international
agreement on biodiversity conservation, all national environmental legislation …[etc.]”. The statement that
species are “fixed entities” goes back to Linnaeus (vide Zachos 2016: 30) and is unacceptable from a modern
evolutionary viewpoint. Furthermore, this belief goes against the very widespread conception of science whose aim
is not a search for definitive or ‘fixed truth’, but to produce rational and testable hypotheses, and the replacement
via refutation of once-adopted hypotheses by better ones until they are in their turn subject to modification or
rejection. Thus is science and, particularly in taxonomy, stability is ignorance, as well expressed by Gaffney
(1979), Dominguez & Wheeler (1997) and Dubois (2005).
Species are scientific hypotheses and their definition and limits should change whenever scientists judge this
necessary. We will refrain from discussing whether species hypotheses refer to real entities or not (see Dubois
2007; Raposo & Kirwan 2017), because under either perspective (existing or non-existent), they represent
hypotheses and consequently are not static.
Some of the consequences of such a misguided notion of species and the role played by scientific hypotheses
are better understood by examining GC’s statement that “Paradoxically, finer splitting could also make certain
species more vulnerable”. To claim that finer splitting renders species more vulnerable is inconsistent with facts
and logic. From the perspective that a species is a human intellectual construct, it can only be endangered once it
has gained existence through formal taxonomic procedures, such as description or validation. If species should be
regarded as pre-existing real entities, the splitting action becomes even more important as it equips the
conservation community with the appropriate knowledge to take specific measures to protect these entities. On the
other hand, ignorance or omission leads to real risk of extinction simply because it is impossible to preserve what is
unknown.
Another common misunderstanding is their apparent belief that taxonomists should be driven by conservation
and economic goals, and not otherwise. Although we are sensitive to some of these consequences, at least in theory,
a better understanding of the natural world will always positively impact conservation policy. The few examples
mentioned by GC attest to this and not to the contrary as they purport. For example, according to GC, a taxonomic
revision of the “central Asian argali wild sheep (Ovis ammon), turned one species into nine, and overnight
Kazakhstan had five mountain sheep species in need of protection, not just one”. Apparently, following this
taxonomic revision we discovered that the group’s conservation was much more problematic than previously
thought. This line of reasoning provides response to virtually all of the examples presented by GC. There is no
option but to find the hypothesis that best approaches our conception of reality under present knowledge.
More seriously, GC confound science and politics stating that the “community’s failure to govern taxonomy
threatens the effectiveness of global efforts to halt biodiversity loss, damages the credibility of science and is
expensive to society.” Following this line of reasoning, the authors complain that “a single taxonomic paper can
affect whole conservation programmes, tourist enterprises and employment opportunities.” But should taxonomists
try to predict future economic or political disputes when reviewing taxonomy? Such considerations would discredit
taxonomy as a scientific enterprise. The idea that a taxonomist should not validate species that might be
endangered or should not refute as inadequate hypotheses insufficiently robust species or, much less to create a
“judicial committee” to analyse the political impacts of taxonomic works before accepting them is scientifically
unacceptable and ethically reprehensible. Such a body would transform taxonomy into a merely political tool for
Zootaxa 4317 (1) © 2017 Magnolia Press
·
181
A RIPOSTE TO GARNETT AND CHRISTIDIS
guiding economic decisions that are not necessarily aligned with species preservation policies. The authors refer to
the International Union of Microbiological Societies (IUMS) as an example of success, but criticise it because of
the statement “Nothing in this Code may be construed to restrict the freedom of taxonomic action.” GC are
apparently impervious to what lies behind such an important ruling, the only really indisputable truth in science: it
must be free.
The authors also attest that the International Union of Biological Sciences (IUBS) should restrict the freedom
of taxonomists. This is anti-scientific and would result in science “losing its soul” with significant negative results,
as demonstrated by Trofim Lysenko’s rejection of Mendelian genetic inheritance theory, which gained the support
of Joseph Stalin, described in Leone’s (1952: 379) words thus “Science cannot long remain unfettered in a social
system which seeks to exercise strict control over the whole spiritual and intellectual life of a nation. The
correctness of a scientific theory can never be adjudged by its readiness to give the answers desired by political
leadership” (see also Hołynski 2017). In this sense, taxonomists should struggle to maintain their “freedom of
taxonomic thought or action”, as noted in the preamble to the International Code of Zoological Nomenclature
(Anonymous 1999, hereafter ‘the Code’; see also Minelli 2000).
Practical perspective: who is really demanding stability?
The main argument motivating GC is the putative demand for stability by conservationists. To illustrate this, they
provide a diagram demonstrating supposedly anarchic avian taxonomy. At this point, a detailed look at the very
specific case reported by the authors becomes important.
Among the taxon Aves, the most recently published world checklist (del Hoyo & Collar 2014, 2016)
recognises 4,372 species of non-passerines and 6,592 species of passerines, versus totals of 4,016 and 6,005
species, respectively, in the well-respected Howard & Moore checklist (Dickinson & Remsen 2013; Dickinson &
Christidis 2014). Thus, del Hoyo & Collar chose to recognise overall 943 more species, sometimes as a result of
different responses to taxonomic works published in peer-reviewed literature. However, a substantial measure of
the discrepancy in totals is the result of del Hoyo & Collar attempting to apply an operational method governing
use of morphological and vocal characters towards species delimitation (Tobias et al. 2010) to as many taxa as
possible that were thought might require revision. Nevertheless, in common with other prior published works, del
Hoyo & Collar chose to treat as species quite a number of taxa, e.g. among Procellariforms, that would not have
“passed” the Tobias criteria for recognition. At least in some of these cases, they considered that the conservation
benefits outweighed the negatives of recognising additional species, many of them breeding on oceanic islands at
high risk from introduced predators. This fact directly contradicts GC’s baseline hypothesis.
What might be surprising to readers of GC is that one of the co-authors of that operational approach (Tobias et
al. 2010 [Collar]) and the just-mentioned checklist (del Hoyo & Collar 2014, 2016), has worked in international
bird conservation for 40 years, with a special focus on the compilation of Red Data books. Furthermore, all of the
other authors of the Tobias criteria are primarily avian ecologists or conservation biologists. The motivation for
undertaking a revision of the taxonomy of the world’s birds is clearly explained in del Hoyo & Collar (2014: 19–
20): “Given that conservation very largely takes the species as its unit of concern, and that the future of many taxa
might in part depend on their recognition or not as species …, it has become increasingly frustrating to have to
wait—frequently in vain—for authoritative decisions from other sources over whether form A or form B is a species
or subspecies”. The del Hoyo & Collar checklist was developed in collaboration with BirdLife International, the
body responsible for assigning IUCN threat categories to birds, and its taxonomy has been adopted in full by the
same organisation. Furthermore, various legislative bodies have also quickly elected to work with this checklist,
including the EU and the UN Convention on the Conservation of Migratory Species of Wild Animals. In other
words, one influential bird conservationist had to some extent “lost patience” in waiting for the input of
professional taxonomists and elected to “do it himself”. The resulting taxonomic inflation (almost 10%) seems to
have been of no concern at least to some conservationists.
We will not discuss here the quality of the taxonomy employed by del Hoyo & Collar (2014, 2016), which is
unimportant in the present context, but, contradicting GC, it demonstrates that real conservationists, at least in
ornithology, do not, of necessity, require stability. They demand more and better taxonomy and are, in fact, behind
what GC consider taxonomic anarchy, as illustrated by their own diagram. It also illustrates that there is no
RAPOSO ET AL.
182
·
Zootaxa 4317 (1) © 2017 Magnolia Press
necessary polarization between conservationists and taxonomists. But it raises one important question: who, after
all, is demanding stability?
Furthermore, still considering their example, authorities must understand the difference between online lists
and genuine taxonomic revisions. Species lists are useful for some practical purposes (e.g. to stimulate the general
interest of the public in citizen science programmes), but they are obviously unscientific and should never serve as
the base (data matrix) for any kind of serious research (see Nemésio et al. 2014 for a specific case). GC base their
conclusion on a comparison between some of these online lists and the Howard & Moore checklist. Appropriate
sources of information are always taxonomic revisions produced group by group. It is more difficult, but authors
really interested to produce robust science should do so themselves, or invite a taxonomist to assist.
Even if the GC example of Aves taxonomy was true, the use of anecdotal observations to draw general
assumptions is quite dangerous. In the present case, other examples from vertebrate taxonomy could easily be used
to contradict that claim. For example, fishes, which possess a strong conservation appeal, including for economic
reasons, currently number 34,401 valid species as of 31 May 2017, of which 3,924 have been described in the last
ten years (Eschmeyer & Fong 2017). Despite the increasing rate of species descriptions, fish taxonomy can in no
way be termed “anarchic”, because cases of conflict are relatively rare, probably due to the standards of excellence
established by the ichthyological community. Therefore, before accepting the conclusions of GC, it is necessary to
perform thorough research that attests to the solidity of their statements.
Concluding remarks
Ending their paper with the phrase “Vagueness is not compatible with conservation, GC threaten the credibility of
conservation biology as a science. The evolution of all sciences implies the constant revision of concepts in an
effort to make scientific discourse best reflect our understanding of the natural world, and this is also valid for
conservation biology, which has debated which entities represent the best targets for protection for more than 30
years. The case is sufficiently complex that the Moritz (1994) paper on the importance of alternative management
units (Evolutionary Significant Units and Management Units) to species has been heavily cited since its
publication. This debate is crucial to resolve the problems highlighted by GC’s paper, but these authors appear to
avoid or ignore the maturity achieved by conservation biology, as exemplified by Avise (1989) who predicted that
An up-dated taxonomy that includes input from molecular genetics should provide a firmer foundation for the
proper recognition and hence management of biotic diversity… Management personnel will have to keep an open
mind regarding the prospect of taxonomic revision, particularly in groups that have been problematic or poorly
studied. Most systematists are well aware of the provisional nature of existing taxonomic assignments, particularly
at the subspecies and species levels… Inevitably, conflicts will occasionally arise when multiple data bases are
used to assess taxonomic and evolutionary relationships.”
In fact, part of this problem stems from the embarrassing fact that, contrary to its introductory statement, the
zoological Code indeed partly infringes on the freedom of taxonomic thought and action in forbidding to name taxa
at ranks below subspecies (e.g., variety or form). This precludes the possibility to include such taxa in Red Lists
and official juridical text, unlike the case in botany. Such lower ranks could very well be used for such alternative
management units. Both taxonomists and conservationists have so far proved unable to explore these possibilities,
despite recommendations that they do so (Dubois 2006, 2011: 43–44) (see also Daugherty et al. 1990 and May
1990 for the emblematic case of the extinctions of tuatara Sphenodon populations, or Valbuena-Ureña et al. 2013
for the newt genus Calotriton).
Finally, it is important that taxonomists reflect on the permanence of this discourse in scientific journals. It is
clear that it has no philosophical or factual consistency. Yet, it would be a mistake for us to believe the discussion is
futile. Taxonomy is a complex and strongly empirical science. Particularly in groups of great visual appeal, as in
the case of vertebrates, the taxonomist responds, on the one hand, to the simpler demand of the ordinary citizen to
know what merits a name and on the other hand, to Popper, Peirce and the many other philosophers of science, who
demand the difficult goal of deductibility. It endeavours to identify unique clades that represent hypotheses of
discontinuity in a fluid and continuous world. It is backed by reasonability and historical process, rather than by the
formal logic that is supposed to characterize other sciences (Raposo & Kirwan 2017).
Under this scenario, there are no alternatives other than to constantly seek to improve the theoretical quality of
Zootaxa 4317 (1) © 2017 Magnolia Press
·
183
A RIPOSTE TO GARNETT AND CHRISTIDIS
our science and our discourse. This is part of the refinement of concepts important to the structure of our
knowledge, as is the case of the concept of species, which taxonomists should acclaim as proof of maturity and not
the opposite (GC’s total misunderstanding of this was well tackled by Hołyński 2017).
As Kierkegaard (1841) remarked in the introduction to his “On the Concept of Irony with Continual Reference
to Socrates”: “The observer ought to be an amorist; he must not be indifferent to any feature, any factor. But on the
other hand he ought to have a sense of his own predominance—but should use it only to help the phenomenon
obtain its full disclosure. Therefore, even if the observer does bring the concept along with him, it is still of great
importance that the phenomenon remain inviolate and that the concept be seen as coming into existence
[tilblivende] through the phenomenon.” For this, taxonomy requires time, work, academic recognition, positions,
funding and historical balance, nothing more, or less.
Acknowledgements
The authors received research funding from the following agencies, for which they are deeply grateful: Fundação
de Amparo à Pesquisa do Estado de São Paulo (Proc. # 2016/18963-8 to RS); Conselho Nacional de
Desenvolvimento Científico e Tecnológico (Proc. # 312067/2013-5 to FAB) and Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento
de Pessoal de Nível Superior (PNPD fellowship to GRRB).
Literature cited
Anonymous [International Commission on Zoological Nomenclature] (1999) International code of zoological nomenclature.
4
th
Edition. International Trust for Zoological Nomenclature, London, xxix + 306 pp.
Avise, J.C. (1989) A role for molecular genetics in the recognition and conservation of endangered species. Trends in Ecology
& Evolution, 4, 279–281.
https://doi.org/10.1016/0169-5347(89)90203-6
Bremer, K., Bremer, B., Karis, P. & Källersjö, M. (1990) Time for change in taxonomy. Nature, 343, 202.
https://doi.org/10.1038/343202a0
Carvalho, M.R. de, Bockmann, F.A., Amorim, D.S., Brandão, C.R.F., Vivo, M. de, Figueiredo, J.L. de, Britski H.A., de Pinna,
M.C.C., Menezes, N.A., Marques, F.P.L., Papavero, N., Cancello, E.M. & Crisci, J.V. (2007) Taxonomic impediment or
impediment to taxonomy? A commentary on systematics and the cybertaxonomic-automation paradigm. Evolutionary
Biology, 34, 140–143.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11692-007-9011-6
Crisp, D.J. & Fogg, G.E. (1988) Taxonomic instability continues to irritate. Nature, 335, 120–121.
https://doi.org/10.1038/335120b0
Daugherty, C.H., Cree, A., Hay, J.M. & Thompson, M.B. (1990) Neglected taxonomy and continuing extinctions of tuatara
Sphenodon. Nature, 347, 177–179.
https://doi.org/10.1038/347177a0
del Hoyo, J. & Collar, N. (2014) HBW and Birdlife International Illustrated Checklist of the Birds of the World. Vol. 1. Non-
passerines. Lynx Edicions, Barcelona, 904 pp.
del Hoyo, J. & Collar, N. (2016) HBW and Birdlife International Illustrated Checklist of the Birds of the World. Vol. 2.
Passerines. Lynx Edicions, Barcelona, 1013 pp.
Dickinson, E.C. & Christidis, L. (Eds.) (2014) The Howard and Moore Complete Checklist of the Birds of the World. Vol. 2.
Passerines. 4
th
Edition. Aves Press, Eastbourne, 752 pp.
Dickinson, E.C. & Remsen Jr., J.V. (Eds.) (2013) The Howard and Moore Complete Checklist of the Birds of the World. Vol. 1.
Non-Passerines. 4
th
Edition. Aves Press, Eastbourne, 461 pp.
Dominguez, E. & Wheeler, Q.D. (1997) Taxonomic stability is ignorance. Cladistics, 13, 367–372.
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1096-0031.1997.tb00325.x
Dubois, A. (1998) Lists of European species of amphibians and reptiles: will we soon be reaching “stability”? Amphibia-
Reptilia, 19, 1–28.
https://doi.org/10.1163/156853898X00304
Dubois, A. (2005) Proposed rules for the incorporation of nomina of higher-ranked zoological taxa in the International Code of
Zoological Nomenclature. 1. Some general questions, concepts and terms of biological nomenclature. Zoosystema, 27,
365–426.
Dubois, A. (2006) New proposals for naming lower-ranked taxa within the frame of the International Code of Zoological
Nomenclature. Comptes rendus Biologies, 329, 823–840.
RAPOSO ET AL.
184
·
Zootaxa 4317 (1) © 2017 Magnolia Press
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.crvi.2006.07.003
Dubois, A. (2007) Phylogeny, taxonomy and nomenclature: the problem of taxonomic categories and of nomenclatural ranks.
Zootaxa, 1519, 27–68.
Dubois, A. (2011) The International Code of Zoological Nomenclature must be drastically improved before it is too late.
Bionomina, 2, 1–104.
https://doi.org/10.11646/bionomina.2.1.1
Eschmeyer, W.N. & Fong, J.D. (2017) Species by family/subfamily. Califonia Academy of Sciences, San Francisco. Available
from: http://researcharchive.calacademy.org/research/ichthyology/catalog/SpeciesByFamily.asp (accessed 20 June 2017).
Gaffney, E.S. (1979) An introduction to the logic of phylogeny reconstruction. In: Cracraft, J. & Eldredge, N. (Eds.),
Phylogenetic Analysis and Paleontology. Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 79–111.
Garnett, S.T. & Christidis, L. (2017) Taxonomy anarchy hampers conservation. Nature, 546, 25–27.
https://doi.org/10.1038/546025a
Godfray, H.C.J. (2007) Linnaeus in the information age. Nature, 446, 259–260.
https://doi.org/10.1038/446259a
Hołyński, R.B. (2017) Taxonomy: should it remain a serious branch of science or be transformed into a formal game?
Procrustomachia, 2, 11–13.
Kierkegaard, S. (1841) The concept of irony with continual reference to Socrates; notes of Schelling’s Berlin lectures. Princeton
University Press, Princeton, 222 pp.
Leone, C.A. (1952) Genetics: Lysenko versus Mendel. Transactions of the Kansas Academy of Science, 55, 369–380.
https://doi.org/10.2307/3625986
May R. (1990) Taxonomy as destiny. Nature, 347, 129–130.
https://doi.org/10.1038/347129a0
Minelli, A. (2000) The ranks and the names of species and higher taxa, or a dangerous inertia of the language of natural history.
Memoirs of the California Academy of Sciences, 25, 339–351.
Moritz, C. (1994) Defining “Evolutionarily Significant Units” for conservation. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 9, 373–375.
https://doi.org/10.1016/0169-5347(94)90057-4
Nemésio, A., Rasmussen, C., Aguiar, A.P., Pombal Jr., J.P. & Dubois, A. (2013) Nomenclatural issues in ornithology: the
incredible controversy on the identity of a long overlooked Brazilian bird. Zootaxa, 3734 (2), 241–258.
https://doi.org/10.11646/zootaxa.3734.2.8
Raposo, M.A. & Kirwan, G.M. (2017) What lies beneath the controversy as to the necessity of physical types for describing
new species? Bionomina, 12, 52–56.
https://doi.org/10.11646/bionomina.12.1.6
Thiele, K. & Yeates, D. (2002) Tension arises from duality at the heart of taxonomy. Nature, 419, 337.
https://doi.org/10.1038/419337a
Tobias, J.A., Seddon, N., Spottiswoode, C.N., Pilgrim, J.D., Fishpool, L.D.C. & Collar, N.J. (2010) Quantitative criteria for
species delimitation. Ibis, 152, 724–746.
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1474-919X.2010.01051.x
Valbuena-Ureña, E., Amat, F. & Carranza, S. (2013) Integrative phylogeography of Calotriton newts (Amphibia,
Salamandridae), with special remarks on the conservation of the endangered Montseny brook newt (Calotriton arnoldi).
PLoS ONE, 8 (6), e62542. [1–12]
https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0062542
Zachos, F.E. (2016) Species concepts in biology: historical development, theoretical foundations and practical relevance.
Springer International Publishing, Cham, 220 pp.
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-44966-1
... The partial solution proposed by Garnett and Christidis, that a governance body should be established to define the process for how species are accepted and how differing opinions are managed, sparked concern among many taxonomists (9)(10)(11)(12)(13)(14). Some argued such a body would introduce unnecessary bureaucracy to a fundamentally scientific process. ...
... Others argued that a governance system for taxonomic lists is a threat to fundamental scientific freedom (11,13). Debate and dissent are fundamental to scientific process, producing new insights and knowledge by challenging current understandings of the world. ...
... Indeed, the process developed by the GSLWG is consistent with the ideals of the scientific process. Garnett and Christidis' (5) suggestion that a governance system for taxonomic lists was needed was, as noted in the introduction to this paper, met with skepticism and was widely debated in the scientific literature (9)(10)(11)13). In response, instead of abandoning the idea, the original arguments were refined and improved taking early criticism into account and with the help of a much larger group of scientists from taxonomy and other fields, including many of those who published critical critiques of Garnett and Christidis' (5) commentary (7-8, 12, 15-19, 27). The results of the survey show that support for list governance in the taxonomic community, and the wider community of scientists and users of taxonomic information, is now widespread. ...
Article
Full-text available
Taxonomic data are a scientific common. Unlike nomenclature, which has strong governance institutions, there are currently no generally accepted governance institutions for the compilation of taxonomic data into an accepted global list. This gap results in challenges for conservation, ecological research, policymaking, international trade, and other areas of scientific and societal importance. Consensus on a global list and its management requires effective governance and standards, including agreed mechanisms for choosing among competing taxonomies and partial lists. However, governance frameworks are currently lacking, and a call for governance in 2017 generated critical responses. Any governance system to which compliance is voluntary requires a high level of legitimacy and credibility among those by and for whom it is created. Legitimacy and credibility, in turn, require adequate and credible consultation. Here, we report on the results of a global survey of taxonomists, scientists from other disciplines, and users of taxonomy designed to assess views and test ideas for a new system of taxonomic list governance. We found a surprisingly high degree of agreement on the need for a global list of accepted species and their names, and consistent views on what such a list should provide to users and how it should be governed. The survey suggests that consensus on a mechanism to create, manage, and govern a single widely accepted list of all the world’s species is achievable. This finding was unexpected given past controversies about the merits of list governance.
... Species delimitations are scientific hypotheses that can be revisited, refuted, or revalidated (Bremer et al., 1990;Gaston & Mound, 1993;Raposo et al., 2017;Sluys, 2013) as knowledge of phylogenetic relationships and new tools become available (Sangster et al., 1999;Streicher et al., 2023). Likewise, the use of different species concepts and taxonomic practices can vary both temporally and geographically, which may also affect biological classifications (De Queiroz, 2007;Freeman & Pennell, 2021;Gaston & Mound, 1993;Padial & De la Riva, 2021). ...
Article
Full-text available
Despite the urgency imposed by the current biodiversity crisis, many species remain undescribed, facing extinction before their formal recognition by science. Accelerating species descriptions is thus imperative. However, descriptions should be robust and based on good taxonomic practice, which may enhance long-term nomenclatural stability that is crucial for scientific research and conservation planning. Yet, few studies have assessed the robustness of species description. Here, we evaluated temporal trends in species descriptions of nearly 4,000 squamate reptiles spanning more than three decades (from 1990 to 2023). We observed an average increase of about 115% in the number of lines of evidence used in descriptions, such as pholidosis, morphometrics, and genes sequenced for molecular analysis. Type-series size decreased by nearly half for lizards but remained roughly constant for snakes, while page length dedicated to descriptions showed an upward trajectory for both taxa, increasing 42.7% on average over time. Furthermore, our study highlights the positive correlation between robust species descriptions (i.e. measured by the number of lines of evidence provided, type-series size, and number of pages) and taxonomic reviews, as well as the impact of collaborative efforts, with more authors on descriptions associated with greater lines of evidence and pages. Overall, descriptions of reptiles have become more thorough and robust over recent decades. The proportion of species descriptions that included molecular analysis has grown over time, with more than half of all species described annually in recent years having molecular data. Despite hundreds of new reptile species being described annually, the potential invalidation of many species in the future may jeopardise current conservation efforts. Therefore, thorough, accurate descriptions are important in addressing the biodiversity crisis and providing reliable data for biodiversity analyses and conservation planning.
... Lists of species are essential for the scientific community and general users, forming a base on the richness and diversity of studies and projects in conservation, local livelihoods, zoonoses surveillance, and scientific research (Garnett et al. 2020). With that in mind, there has been a recent push to create a single, authoritative list of the Earth's biota, which has been met with a series of publications both for and against the proposal (Raposo et al. 2017, Thomson et al. 2018. Irrespective of the merits associated with the global list proposal, a specific set of 10 principles has been recommended to form the foundation of its governance (Garnett et al. 2020). ...
Article
Full-text available
We present an updated checklist of Brazilian bats, commenting on the endemic and threatened status of the species listed and providing information on recent taxonomic and nomenclatural changes. The bats of Brazil comprise 186 species, 68 genera, and nine families, with 13 species exclusive to the country. From the previous checklists, we add eight species to Brazil: Artibeus amplus, Choeroniscus godmani, Glossophaga bakeri, Lichonycteris obscura, Platyrrhinus guianensis, Trachops ehrhardti, Molossus melini and Myotis pampa. The latter is reported for the country for the first time in this study. The Brazilian list of threatened species includes three species as vulnerable (Furipterus horrens, Lonchophylla bokermanni, and Natalus macrourus) and Lonchophylla dekeyseri as endangered. The International Union for the Conservation of Nature (IUCN) lists Natalus macrourus as “near threatened”, and Lonchophylla bokermanni and L. dekeyseri as “endangered”. Twenty-two additional species are probable for the country. Compared to previous lists, five species are now considered doubtful records and 19 are considered erroneous records. We reinforce the importance of a continuous update of the bat checklists in all Brazilian states as well as taxonomic revisions and bat inventories in unsampled areas. KEY WORDS: Neotropics; nomenclature; species list; taxonomy
... Recently, a controversy developed over a desire to make taxonomy and nomenclature even more stable for conservation applications (Garnett & Christidis 2017;Raposo et al. 2017;Thomson et al. 2018). This debate arose between the creation and maintenance of biodiversity knowledge (the purview of taxonomy), with its inherent unruliness, and the desire for more taxonomic certainty in order for conservation to have authoritative, widely accepted global species lists. ...
Article
Standardized taxonomies and lists of birds were created to improve communication. They are linguistic infrastructure―biodiversity indices and dictionaries―that have been painstakingly built and maintained and that have enhanced regional and global participation in the study and enjoyment of birds. Inclusion of people has been a core objective in creating and maintaining these standardized lists, and dissatisfaction and desires to overwrite objectionable names have been associated with them for nearly two centuries. Suggestions that bird names should be changed are continuous. Today, these suggestions include the view that some bird names must be changed to make them more accurate, inoffensive, and culturally appropriate to further increase diversity and inclusion among ornithologists and bird watchers. The latter, meritorious goal has been largely successful thus far despite many ongoing objections. Historic examples indicate that large-scale name changes, however, are not needed to accomplish major societal goals of inclusion. Some barriers to inclusion likely remain, and some changes are likely needed for English names. Often overlooked or underappreciated in name change discussions are that: 1) standardized names lists have had numerically staggering success in fostering inclusion of diverse participants globally; 2) stability is vital in such systems, and destabilization has exclusionary effects; 3) dissatisfaction with such lists and the names they include has been ongoing since these naming systems began; 4) important flexibilities exist in conjunction with these communication systems that enhance local and regional communication (e.g., alternative names in English and other languages); and 5) cultural values, important as they are, are neither universally shared nor constant, and thus risk bringing divisiveness and instability when used as a central reason for change. Consideration of standardized lists of bird names as communication systems in the fuller context of history, language, and culture will improve our management of these systems and their continued utility in fostering inclusion. With standardized, stable naming systems acting as a skeleton, proactively building outwards, both within and among languages and cultures, offers a positive and productive way to increase inclusion and to improve cultural and biodiversity conservation.
... Thus, more funding should be focused on faunistic data assemblage studies. In contrast to Garnett and Christidis (2017), we believe that taxonomy does not hinder conservation biology, but instead makes conservation possible, since when unaware of the existence of a species (whether species are considered as real entities or not-see Raposo et al. 2017), it is impossible to protect it. Therefore, trailing the voices of those who advocate for a better incorporation of taxonomy in conservation (Dubois 2003;de Carvalho et al. 2007;Boero 2010;Andreone et al. 2022) while acknowledging its innate value (Engel et al. 2021), we passionately call for an extensive taxonomic and faunistic scrutiny of Cretan Arthropod biodiversity. ...
Article
Full-text available
Arthropod decline has been globally and locally documented, yet they are still not sufficiently protected. Crete (Greece), a Mediterranean biodiversity hotspot, is a continental island renowned for its diverse geology, ecosystems and endemicity of flora and fauna, with continuous research on its Arthropod fauna dating back to the nineteenth century. Here we investigate the conservation status of the Cretan Arthropods using Preliminary Automated Conservation Assessments (PACA) and the overlap of Cretan Arthropod distributions with the Natura 2000 protected areas. Moreover, we investigate their endemicity hotspots and propose candidate Key Biodiversity Areas. In order to perform these analyses, we assembled occurrences of the endemic Arthropods in Crete located in the collections of the Natural History Museum of Crete together with literature data. These assessments resulted in 75% of endemic Arthropods as potentially or likely threatened. The hotspots of endemic taxa and the candidate Key Biodiversity Areas are distributed mostly on the mountainous areas where the Natura 2000 protected areas have great coverage. Yet human activities have significant impact even in those areas, while some taxa are not sufficiently covered by Natura 2000. These findings call for countermeasures and conservation actions to protect these insular environments, especially mountain species that lack the space to further escape from threats affecting their habitat.
... Particularly in vertebrates (and more recently not only), probably due to the many "authorities" but also due to the fact that many vertebrate species are more considered by conservation and wildlife observations, there is a tendency of a wish of democratically or autocratically (by the scientific community and key users) decided taxonomies (expressed as lists of accepted taxa, e.g., [38,[40][41][42][43]). Such ideas are opposed by calls for an only science-based taxonomy on the other hand [44]. ...
Article
The use of DNA has helped to improve and speed up species identification and delimitation. However, it also provides new challenges to taxonomists. Incongruence of outcome from various markers and delimitation methods, bias from sampling and skewed species distribution, implemented models, and the choice of methods/priors may mislead results and also may, in conclusion, increase elements of subjectivity in species taxonomy. The lack of direct diagnostic outcome from most contemporary molecular delimitation approaches and the need for a reference to existing and best sampled trait reference systems reveal the need for refining the criteria of species diagnosis and diagnosability in the current framework of nomenclature codes and good practices to avoid nomenclatorial instability, parallel taxonomies, and consequently more and new taxonomic impediment.
... Furthermore, all records are combined in a single report (together with the 2004 report) with the latest references of additional reports since 2004 which will be very helpful to new researchers. Even though taxonomy is a living subject with "refutable scientific hypotheses" (Raposo et al. 2017) and changes in taxonomy can always be expected (especially in large families like Lernaeopodidae), the current report will be a good starting point for anybody interesting in marine symbiotic siphonostomatoids off Southern Africa. Although there is an improvement in the reported biodiversity it is unfortunate that numbers are still very low compared with accepted numbers of species (Walter & Boxshall 2024), especially considering the diversity of possible hosts (vertebrates and invertebrates) occurring off Southern Africa. ...
Article
Siphonostomatoida (Copepoda) consists of 40 families of symbionts infecting vertebrates (17 families) and invertebrates (23 families) found mostly in marine habitats. In 2004, a list was compiled of all the reported families, genera and species symbiotic with marine fish in Southern African waters. Since this was done 20 years ago, it is necessary to re-evaluate the progress made in 20 years regarding our knowledge of the diversity of marine siphonostomatoids. To assess the current knowledge, the 2004 list was updated with reports published since 2004 as well as with new host and locality records including species with changes in taxonomy. Additionally, species collected but unreported as well as species previously reported but with new hosts and/or localities were also added. Currently reports include 16 families, 75 genera and 234 species. However, amongst these are reports of only two families (3 species) infecting invertebrates. Even though the report includes 71 additional species it still compares poorly with the about 2 274 accepted species, especially regarding species infecting invertebrates. Considering South Africa’s wealth in possible marine host species, examination of more hosts (especially marine teleosts and invertebrates) will definitely result in an increase in the current knowledge about the biodiversity of marine siphonostomatoids off Southern Africa.
Preprint
Full-text available
The Mammal Diversity Database (MDD) is an open-access resource providing up-to-date taxonomic, nomenclatural, and geographic data for global mammal species. Since its launch in 2018, the MDD has transformed the traditionally static process of updating mammalian taxonomy into regular online releases reflecting the latest published research. To build on this foundation, we here present version 2.0 of the MDD (MDD2), which catalogues 6,759 living and recently extinct mammal species, representing net increases of 4.1% and 24.8% over MDD version 1.0 and Mammal Species of the World, 3rd edition (MSW3), respectively. Additionally, we identify a net increase of 68.8% (+2,754; 3,149 splits + de novo, 395 lumps) species since 1980 at a rate of ~65 species/year based on past totals from 14 mammalian compendia, leading to projections of ~7,084 species by 2030 and ~8,382 by 2050 if these trends continue. Key updates in MDD2 include: (i) codings of US state, country, continent, and biogeographic realm geographic categories for each species; (ii) a comprehensive nomenclatural dataset for 50,230 valid and synonymous species-rank names, curated with type locality and specimen information for the first time; and (iii) integration between the MDD and the databases Hesperomys and Batnames for greater data accuracy and completeness. These updates bridge critical gaps in the taxonomic and nomenclatural information needed for ongoing revisions and assessments of mammalian species diversity. Using these data, we evaluate temporal and geographic trends over the past 267 years, identifying four major time periods of change in mammalian taxonomy and nomenclature: (i) the initial monographic description of traditionally charismatic species (1758-1880); (ii) the peak of descriptive taxonomy, describing subspecies, and publishing in journals (1881-1939); (iii) the shift toward revisionary taxonomy and polytypic species (1940-1999); and (iv) the current technology-driven period of integrative revisionary taxonomy (2000-present). Geographically, new species recognition since MSW3 has been concentrated in equatorial, mountainous, and island regions, highlighting areas of high mammal endemism (e.g., Madagascar, Philippines, Andes, East Africa, Himalayas, Atlantic Forests). However, gaps in 21st century taxonomic activity are identified in West and Central Africa, India, and some parts of Indonesia. Currently lagging conservation assessments are alarming, with 25% of the MDD2-recognized mammal species allocated to the "understudied" conservation threat categories of Data Deficient (11%) or Not Evaluated (14%), underscoring the need for greater taxonomic integration with conservation organizations. Governance advancements in MDD2 include the establishment of external taxonomic subcommittees to guide data collection and curation, a rewritten website that improves access and scalability, a cross-platform application that provides offline access, and new partnerships to continue linking MDD data to global biodiversity infrastructure. By providing up-to-date mammalian taxonomic and nomenclatural data--including links to the text of original name descriptions, type localities, and type specimen collections--the MDD provides an integrative resource for mammalogists and conservationists to more easily track the status of their study organisms.
Article
Ecological niche divergence is generally considered to be a facet of evolution that may accompany geographic isolation and diversification in allopatry, contributing to species’ evolutionary distinctiveness through time. The null expectation for any two diverging species in geographic isolation is that of niche conservatism, wherein populations do not rapidly shift to or adapt to novel environments. Here, I test ecological niche divergence for a widespread, pan-American lineage, the avian genus of martins ( Progne ). The genus Progne includes migrant and resident species, as well as geographically restricted taxa and widespread, intercontinentally distributed taxa, thus providing an ideal group in which to study the nature of niche divergence within a broad geographic mosaic. I obtained distributional information for the genus from publicly available databases and created ecological niche models for each species to create pairwise comparisons of environmental space. I combined these data with the most up-to-date phylogeny of Progne currently available to examine the patterns of niche evolution within the genus. I found limited evidence for niche divergence across the breeding distributions of Progne , and much stronger support for niche conservatism with patterns of niche partitioning. The ancestral Progne had a relatively broad ecological niche, like extant basal Progne lineages, and several geographically localized descendant species occupy only portions of this larger ancestral niche. I recovered strong evidence of breeding niche divergence for four of 36 taxon pairs but only one of these divergent pairs involved two widespread species (Southern Martin P. elegans vs . Gray-breasted Martin P. chalybea ). Potential niche expansion from the ancestral species was observed in the most wide-ranging present-day species, namely the North American Purple Martin P. subis and P. chalybea . I analyzed populations of P. subis separately, as a microcosm of Progne evolution, and again found only limited evidence of niche divergence. This study adds to the mounting evidence for niche conservatism as a dominant feature of diversifying lineages, and sheds light on the ways in which apparently divergent niches may arise through allopatry while not involving any true niche shifts through evolutionary time. Even taxa that appear unique in terms of habitat or behavior may not be diversifying with respect to their ecological niches, but merely partitioning ancestral niches among descendant taxa.
Preprint
Full-text available
Ecological niche divergence is generally considered to be a facet of evolution that may accompany geographic isolation and diversification in allopatry, contributing to species' evolutionary distinctiveness through time. The null expectation for any two diverging species in geographic isolation is that of niche conservatism, wherein populations do not rapidly shift to or adapt to novel environments. Here, I test ecological niche divergence for a widespread, pan-American lineage, the avian genus of martins (Progne). Despite containing species with distributions that go from continent-spanning to locally endemic, I found limited evidence for niche divergence across the breeding distributions of Progne, and much stronger support for niche conservatism with patterns of niche partitioning. The ancestral Progne had a relatively broad ecological niche, similar to extant basal Progne lineages, and several geographically localized descendant species occupy only portions of the larger ancestral Progne niche. I recovered strong evidence of breeding niche divergence for four of 36 taxon pairs but only one of these divergent pairs involved two widespread, continental species (Southern Martin P. elegans vs. Gray-breasted Martin P. chalybea). Potential niche expansion from the ancestral species was observed in the most wide-ranging present-day species, namely the North American Purple Martin P. subis and P. chalybea. I analyzed populations of P. subis separately, as a microcosm of Progne evolution, and again found only limited evidence of niche divergence. This study adds to the mounting evidence for niche conservatism as a dominant feature of diversifying lineages. Even taxa that appear unique in terms of habitat or behavior may still not be diversifying with respect to their ecological niches, but merely partitioning ancestral niches among descendant taxa.
Article
Full-text available
The classification of complex organisms is in chaos. Stephen T. Garnett and Les Christidis propose a solution.
Article
Full-text available
We discuss the philosophical tenets underpinning the current debate among taxonomists as to the need for a physical holotype in support of new species, or whether, as some scientists argue, photographs should be considered equally acceptable. At present, the International Code of Zoological Nomenclature does not stipulate that the deposition of a physical specimen is required, but many taxonomists have recently called on the Commissioners of the International Commission of Zoological Nomenclature to modify the text of the Code on these issues in its forthcoming, fifth edition. We discuss considerations that motivate both sides in this argument, all of which pertain to philosophical and historical issues: (1) misconceptions about science; (2) a fear of the loss of control over zoological nomenclature; and (3) the difficulty inherent in making the system developed by Linnaeus for a natural world originally perceived as static, compatible with the constantly shifting one outlined by Darwin and Wallace. In conclusion we argue that the best means to understand the question is rooted in a broader comprehension of the history of taxonomy and the kind of science it represents.
Article
Full-text available
The use of ranks and nominal-series in zoological nomenclature has recently been challenged by some authors who support unranked systems of nomenclature. It is here shown that this criticism is based on a double misunderstanding: (1) the confusion between nomenclatural ranks and taxonomic categories; (2) the request for a monosemic nomenclatural system, not for scientific reasons, but to please non-taxonomists, especially customers of the web. It is here argued that nomenclatural ranks and taxonomic categories should be clearly distinguished and designated by different terms, and that the Code should be modified in order to make this distinction clear. Whereas taxonomic categories have biological definitions, nomenclatural ranks do not, as they express only a position in a taxonomic hierarchy. If used consistently (which is not always the case), the system of nomenclatural ranks is very useful for the storage and retrieval of taxonomic and phylogenetic information. Taxa referred to a given rank in different groups cannot therefore be considered equivalent by any criterion, so that using ranks for comparisons between taxa (e.g., for biodiversity richness assessment) is irrelevant and misleading. Although the current Code needs to be improved in several respects, the superiority of this nomenclatural system, which is theory-free regarding taxonomy as it relies on ostensional allocation of nomina to taxa rather than on intensional definitions of nomina, is again stressed. It is suggested that all taxonomists should follow the Code for the allocation and validity of nomina, whatever taxonomic theory they favour, and in particular whatever kinds of definitions or diagnoses they wish to use for taxa. This would avoid the considerable loss of manpower, ime and energy that would be required by the implementation of a new nomenclatural system (e.g., in order to require "phylogenetic definitions" for nomina, or to make nomenclature fully monosemic), and the confusion that would result for most users of nomina. The new paradigm imposed to biology by the combination of the taxonomic impediment and of the biodiversity crisis requires from taxonomists, who are already considerably much less numerous than required by this new situation, to concentrate on what should be their priority at the beginning of the century of extinctions, namely the inventory of the living species of our planet before they get extinct.
Article
Full-text available
The scientific names (nomina) of higher-ranked taxa (above the superfamily) of animals are not regulated by the International Code of Zoological Nomenclature, but by "consensus" among workers. However, when there exists no real consensus, a frequent situation, some criteria must be used to establish which nomen should be considered valid for any given taxon. With the multiplication of taxa that follows the development of cladistic analyses, the implementation of such rules will become more and more necessary and important. To be acceptable by all zoologists worldwide, today and tomorrow, these rules should be independent from the philosophy of taxonomy adopted, but should allow unambiguous, automatic and universal allocation of a single nomen to each higher taxon, within the frame of any taxonomy, including "phylogenetic" ones. This first paper is devoted to the detailed discussion of general theoretical and terminological problems related with this question. It is here argued that it is misleading and dangerous to try and make nomenclature artificially "simple". The problems posed by the naming of millions of kinds of organisms, related through evolution and that have been studied for two and a half century under different approaches, are indeed complex: this complexity should be acknowledged, and the discipline in charge of this study should be recognized as a specific technical field, with its own methods, concepts and terms. Among various proposals made in this paper, it is suggested to definitely abandon the misleading term "type" in taxonomy and nomenclature, objective categories for the "usage" of nomina are defined for the first time, and a distinction is made between taxonomic "categories" and nomenclatural "ranks". © Publications Scientifiques du Muséum national d'Histoire naturelle.
Article
Full-text available
At the beginning of the century of extinctions, science has only inventoried a very small proportion of the living species of the globe. In order to face the taxonomic urgency that results from this taxonomic gap combined with the biodiversity crisis, zootaxonomy needs efficient, rigorous and automatic nomenclatural Rules, that allow to spend a minimal time on nomenclatural problems—rather than investing time, energy and money in renaming millions of already named taxa in order to follow alternative nomenclatural systems, e.g., “phylogenetic” ones, that furthermore do not show theoretical superiority to the current Linnaean-Stricklandian one. The current Code, result of a 250-year improvement process, is based on very sound and healthy Rules, being theory-free regarding taxonomy, relying on objective allocation of nomina to taxa by a system of ostension using onomatophores, and on an objective basic Principle, priority, for recognizing the valid nomen of a taxon in case of synonymy or homonymy. Nevertheless, this nomenclatural system is certainly not perfect. It should be modified at least in nine directions: (1) it should adopt a technical terminology avoiding possible misinterpretations from outsiders of the field and even from specialists, and allowing a precise formalisation of its mode of functioning; (2) its plan should be drastically modified; (3) its Principles should be redefined, and some added; (4) material evidence for the allocation of nomina to taxa through specimens deposited in permanent collections should be given more weight; (5) it should incorporate all nomina of higher taxa, providing clear and strict universal Rules for their naming, whereas conserving the traditional nomina largely used in non-specialized systematic literature; (6) it should allow for the recognition of many more ranks at lower nomenclatural levels, i.e., just above genus, between genus and species, and below species; (7) it should provide much more stringent Rules for the protection against priority of “wellknown” nomina or sozonyms; (8) various “details” should be addressed, various Rules and Recommendations changed before a new edition of the Code is published; (9) the procedure of implementations of changes in the Code should be modified in order to involve zootaxonomists of the whole world in the decisions. In several instances, the Rules of the Code should become much more compulsory for all zoologists, editors and publishers, to avoid the publication of endless and sometimes most detrimental discussions among taxonomists which give a poor image of nomenclature and taxonomy among the biological sciences, such as bitter discussions about the “best” nomen to be used under a so-called “usage” philosophy, or about nomina to be applied to higher taxa. Code-compliance in zootaxonomic publications should be highlighted, and editors and publishers should require from authors who follow alternative nomenclatural Rules (or no rule at all) to make it clear by using particular modes of writing their nomina. It is argued here that if the Code of the 21st century does not evolve to incorporate these changes, it will prove unable to play its role in front of several important recent theoretical and practical developments of taxonomy and run the risk of being abandoned by a part of the international community of zootaxonomists. The latter could then adopt alternative “phylogenetic” nomenclatural Rules, despite the severe practical problems and theoretical flaws posed by such projects. This would be most detrimental for all comparative biological disciplines including systematics, and even for the unity of biology. In the course of this discussion, a few recommendations are given concerning the standards and guidelines suggested by recent authors for a good, modern, integrative taxonomy.
Book
Frank E. Zachos offers a comprehensive review of one of today’s most important and contentious issues in biology: the species problem. After setting the stage with key background information on the topic, the book provides a brief history of species concepts from antiquity to the Modern Synthesis, followed by a discussion of the ontological status of species with a focus on the individuality thesis and potential means of reconciling it with other philosophical approaches. More than 30 different species concepts found in the literature are presented in an annotated list, and the most important ones, including the Biological, Genetic, Evolutionary and different versions of the Phylogenetic Species Concept, are discussed in more detail. Specific questions addressed include the problem of asexual and prokaryotic species, intraspecific categories like subspecies and Evolutionarily Significant Units, and a potential solution to the species problem based on a hierarchical approach that distinguishes between ontological and operational species concepts. A full chapter is dedicated to the challenge of delimiting species by means of a discrete taxonomy in a continuous world of inherently fuzzy boundaries. Further, the book outlines the practical ramifications for ecology and evolutionary biology of how we define the species category, highlighting the danger of an apples and oranges problem if what we subsume under the same name (“species”) is in actuality a variety of different entities. A succinct summary chapter, glossary and annotated list of references round out the coverage, making the book essential reading for all biologists looking for an accessible introduction to the historical, philosophical and practical dimensions of the species problem.
Book
A work that "not only treats of irony but is irony," wrote a contemporary reviewer of The Concept of Irony, with Continual Reference to Socrates. Presented here with Kierkegaard's notes of the celebrated Berlin lectures on "positive philosophy" by F.W.J. Schelling, the book is a seedbed of Kierkegaard's subsequent work, both stylistically and thematically. Part One concentrates on Socrates, the master ironist, as interpreted by Xenophon, Plato, and Aristophanes, with a word on Hegel and Hegelian categories. Part Two is a more synoptic discussion of the concept of irony in Kierkegaard's categories, with examples from other philosophers and with particular attention given to A. W. Schlegel's novel Lucinde as an epitome of romantic irony. The Concept of Irony and the Notes of Schelling's Berlin Lectures belong to the momentous year 1841, which included not only the completion of Kierkegaard's university work and his sojourn in Berlin, but also the end of his engagement to Regine Olsen and the initial writing of Either/Or.