ChapterPDF Available

Love - According to Simone de Beauvoir

Authors:

Abstract

Beauvoir discusses various kinds of personal love in her work, including maternal love, lesbian love, friendship, and heterosexual love. In her portrayal of heterosexual love, she draws a distinction between two main types, inauthentic and authentic. Authentic love is “founded on mutual recognition of two liberties,” always freely chosen and sustained. It requires that the lovers maintain their individuality, while at the same time acknowledging each other's differences. Inauthentic love is portrayed in a highly gendered fashion; it is based on submission and domination which prevents either gender from experiencing freedom, comradeship and the “miracle achieved, by love alone.” This chapter explores the distinction between the two types of love, and argues that it is applicable to not only heterosexual love. It also discusses why inauthentic love is unethical and destined to fail, and argues that Beauvoir's portrayal of authentic love foreshadows the contemporary feminist notion of relational autonomy.
A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir, First Edition. Edited by Laura Hengehold and Nancy Bauer.
© 2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. Published 2017 by John Wiley & Sons Ltd.
160
Love, a topic among philosophers since Plato, has a prominent role in Simone de
Beauvoir’s philosophy. According to Beauvoir, love is a universal human experience
capable of bringing about the highest form of freedom, joy, and fulfillment, as well as
grave misery, dependency, and exploitation. Beauvoir discusses various kinds of
personal love in her work, including maternal love, lesbian love, friendship, and hetero-
sexual love. In her portrayal of heterosexual love, she draws a distinction between two
main types, inauthentic and authentic. Authentic love is “founded on mutual recogni-
tion of two liberties,” always freely chosen and sustained. It requires that the lovers
maintain their individuality, while at the same time acknowledging each other’s differ-
ences. Inauthentic love is founded on inequality between the sexes, on submission and
domination. It prevents both women and men from experiencing freedom, comradeship
and the joy of loving. This distinction is, I argue, applicable also to other types of love.
Unlike Sartre, Beauvoir believes authentic love is possible. I contrast their respective
views. Towards the end, I consider Beauvoir’s idea of authentic love in light of her
concept of moral freedom, and argue that Beauvoir’s authentic love foreshadows the
feminist notion of “relational autonomy.”
1. Inauthentic Love
Beauvoir portrays inauthentic love in a highly gendered fashion. “The word ‘love’ has
not at all the same meaning for both sexes,” she writes in The Second Sex, “and this is
a source of the grave misunderstandings that separate them” (TSS 683/LDS II:477).
In a patriarchal society, both sexes will experience inauthentic love. Although
Beauvoir focuses more on how this phenomenon is manifested by women, a close
reading also reveals the obstacles that prevent men from experiencing authentic
love(Mundy 2015).
13
Love–According toSimone de Beauvoir
TOVE PETTERSEN
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
LOVE – ACCORDING TO SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR
161
One of the most salient expectations with regard to women’s way of expressing love
is the demand made for their devotion and self‐sacrifice. In Diary of a Philosophy Student
(1926–27), the 18‐year‐old Beauvoir–who at the time believed she would marry her
cousin Jacques Champigneulles–is torn between her passion for Jacques and her desire
to study. The self‐sacrifice she thought would be required of her in marriage seemed
impossible to reconcile with studying and living an autonomous life: “[H]e will simply
introduce me to his life, but nothing will be changed. As for me, I am gambling all of
myself!” (2006, 135).
The manifestation and consequences of these gendered expectations of love are
analyzed and discussed in The Second Sex. Men, even the most passionate of lovers,
Beauvoir points out:
never abandon themselves completely […] they remain sovereign subjects; the woman they
love is merely one value among others; they want to integrate her into their existence, not
submerge their entire existence in her. By contrast, love for the woman is a total abdication
for the benefit of a master. (TSS 683/LDS II:477–8)
These expectations permeate human life in all its aspects; norms, practices, and interac-
tions. They also inform how women and men perceive themselves, as well as how they
judge and what they demand of the opposite sex. In a traditional marriage, for example,
women are expected to become part of the man’s world by taking his name, joining
hisreligion, following him where he wants to live; “she is annexed to her husband’s
universe” (TSS 442/LDS II:199).
This situation, and the norms pertaining to it, have a profound influence on the
character and behavior of both genders. What is commonly seen as typical for
women–such as “her convictions, values, wisdom, morality, tastes and behavior–is
explained by her situation” (TSS 661/LDS II:451). Beauvoir also explicates the gen-
dered expressions of desires by way of social constructions: “he wants her to be the
Other […] she makes herself object” (TSS 653/LDS II:441). A woman in love is like a
“praying mantis” (Beauvoir 2015a, 76).1
The construal of women’s love as a demand for self‐sacrifice and devotion does not
pertain to romantic love alone. As mothers, daughters, and nurses, the demands are the
same. “From childhood woman is repeatedly told she is made to bear children, and the
praises of motherhood are sung” (TSS 532/LDS II:299). Motherhood is said to be one of
her “sacred rights” and her “ultimate end,” and many mothers are guilty of what she
calls “masochistic devotion.” They turn “themselves into slaves of their offspring,” and
“they give up all pleasure, all personal life, enabling them to assume the role of victim:
and from the sacrifices they derive the right to the deny the child all independence”
(TSS, 567–9, 559/LDS II:339–41, 329).
Owing to the all‐consuming focus on the other, it is not only the loss of a romantic
love that causes a strong reaction in women. The loss of any object of her devotion will
lead her to despair. “The mother,” Beauvoir writes in “Pyrrhus and Cineas” (1944),
“who contemplates her grown son, like the volunteer nurse who contemplates her cured
patients, says with regret, ‘You no longer need me!’ This regret often takes the form of a
reproach” (Beauvoir 2004, 118). Women’s ways of expressing love for other people–be
it a lover, a child, or a patient–are marked by the affinity for devotion and self‐sacrifice.
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
TOVE PETTERSEN
162
This act of surrendering resembles religious behavior. The religious woman and
the woman in love both long to dedicate and submit themselves to the other. In its
most extreme form, inauthentic feminine love finds its clearest expression in the love
of the religious mystic for her celestial spouse (TSS 709/LDS II:508). The religious
woman who tortures her flesh, “drinking the water in which she had just washed the
leper’s hands and feet” and cleaning the “sick person’s vomit with her tongue” (TSS
714–15/LDS II:514–15), expresses her love of Jesus and her neighbor. Apparently,
she performs these deeds with pleasure. Such extremes could be pathological, Beauvoir
points out, “[b]ut there is this inextricable confusion in many devotees between man
and God” (TSS 710/LDS II:510). In behaving like this, the religious woman “tries to
connect with the lover using the usual technique of a woman in love: annihilation”
(TSS 714/LDS II:514).2
This gendered behavior has been explained by asserting that altruism (Schopenhauer
1851), masochism, passivity, and narcissism (Freud 1995[1924]; Deutsch 1944),
are naturally occurring traits of the female character. Beauvoir rejects gender
essentialism. The way women express love has nothing to do “with a law of nature,”
Beauvoir declares, whether it is expressed as a tendency to be more other‐regarding
than men or to enjoy pain inflicted by others: “It is the difference in their situations
that is reflected in the conceptions men and women have of love” (TSS 684/LDS
II:478). Let us take a closer look at how Beauvoir explains the behavior of women in
(inauthentic) love.
Initially, women and men share the same desire for transcendence. This desire
plays a prominent role in Beauvoir’s philosophy, and she views it as a non‐gendered
human trait. To Beauvoir, a person is by definition transcendence: “No existent ever
renounces his transcendence, especially when he stubbornly disavows it,” she says
(TSS 469/LDS II:229). It is through transcendence, through the free choice of pro-
jects and interaction with other free beings, that individuals can achieve a mean-
ingful and ethical life (Pettersen 2015). In most cultures, however, women’s freedom
to transcend has been, and still is, limited by their situation. Women usually do not
see themselves as their male partners’ equal, nor do men typically view them as such.
What a woman aspires to, by devoting herself to her beloved, is a union with the
superior being, an alliance with the person having the power and possibility to
transcend. This brings her, via another, closer to transcendence. Not only does this
explanation elucidate woman’s devotion and self‐sacrifice towards her male partner
or god, it also sheds light on maternal love. Through her son, the mother can experi-
ence transcendence:
The house she did not build, the countries she did not explore, the books she did not read,
he will give to her. Through him she will possess the world: but on the condition that she
possesses her son. (TSS 560/LDS II:331)
Not so with the daughter. As the daughter is not a member of the “chosen caste,” the
mother “seeks a double in her. She projects onto her all the ambiguity of her relationship
with herself; and when the alterity of this alter ego affirms itself, she feels betrayed” (TSS
561/LDS II:332). Through this explanation, Beauvoir rejects traditional explanations
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
LOVE – ACCORDING TO SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR
163
according to which females by nature have submissive character traits. The expression of
inauthentic love is a response to women’s subordinated position, to being confined to
immanence; it is a strategy to cope with oppression.3 For many women, love is the “only
opportunity” to “enlarge or overturn their universe” (Beauvoir 2015b, 100).
Women’s attempt to gain transcendence through another person explains another
behavioral tendency of women in love. That is her persistent attempt to get the beloved
to dedicate himself completely to her. The woman seeks a timeless union with him, and
demands of him that his feelings are absolute and eternal. The reason women so
passionately desire to lock the man into a timeless union is precisely why they want to
devote themselves to him in the first place. A union with a man represents a way out of
the immanence in which she is trapped, by way of an indirect transcendence. This is
also why a woman in love is ready to serve and satisfy his needs. By making herself a
necessary part of his life, “she will be integrated into his existence, she will be part of his
value, his worth, she will be justified” (TSS 691/LDS II:486). This is why the
lovingwoman becomes “a jailer.” It is also why the mother clings to her children with a
“tyrannical devotion” that obstructs their independence (TSS 560–2/LDS II:331–4).
Aloving woman wants to imprison a free being, bolt free existence onto her imma-
nence, so that her contact with transcendence will be secured. Of course, this is destined
to fail; a free being cannot be owned (TSS 698/LDS II:495).
Her desire to achieve complete union with the loved one through devotion implies
that the woman “lets her own world founder in contingence; she lives in his universe”
writes Beauvoir (TSS 693/LDS II:489). Herein lies one of the many paradoxes of inau-
thentic romantic love. The woman in love seeks the approval of her being as something
irreplaceable, a confirmation that her life has a unique meaning. Nevertheless, in order
to gain this approval, she eradicates her individuality and aspires to become one with
her partner, eliminating as a result the differences between the two. This is what even-
tually kills the love between them. On Beauvoir’s view, it is precisely the uniqueness of
the other that draws the two together in the first place, and also what can prolong and
uphold the attraction (Beauvoir 2015a, 79; 2015b, 101). However, in her attempt to
become one with the beloved, she makes herself part of the other’s facticity. The sexual
act is “no longer an intersubjective experience where each goes beyond himself, but
rather a kind of mutual masturbation” (TSS 467/LDS II:226–7). The sexual relation-
ship becomes inauthentic and “bestial” (TSS 458/LDS II:216).
Not only does her attempt to become one destroy their love, such union is also uneth-
ical in Beauvoir’s philosophy. A woman who devotes herself completely to her partner
does not take responsibility for herself and her own life– as Beauvoir’s existentialist
ethics requires (Pettersen 2007, 2015). Women’s self‐denial and subjugation are not
entirely positive from a male perspective either. Since the woman, on entering into the
relationship, adores and idolizes him, she does not see his vulnerability or the threat to
his projects. She is not his companion, and he is not allowed to fail (TSS 695/LDS
II:491–2). But eventually, when she discovers his fallibility, she begins to despise him.
Everything he does from now on is wrong: “The chevalier who embarks on new feats of
prowess offends his lady; but she scorns him if he stays seated at her feet” (TSS 698/LDS
II:698). This is another of the painful paradoxes of inauthentic love: a captive god is
shorn of his divinity (TSS 698/LDS II:495). Although privileged, neither can the man in
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
TOVE PETTERSEN
164
an inauthentic romantic relationship realize his full human potential as a free being
without an equal partner. He will not be “healed of his egoistical pride,” nor experience
self‐negation and devotion (Beauvoir 2015a, 78), nor the benefits of comradeship.
Inaddition, if his masculine identity and dominant position are dependent on women’s
subordination, he is not free (Gunnarsson 2013, 165; Mundy 2015). If the man in love
is governed by conventional masculine ideals, he too lives an inauthentic and unethical
life, unable to experience authentic love.
The lack of equality between women and men also manifests itself in the way
jealousy is experienced and expressed. Men are jealous simply because of their “will to
exclusive power,” writes Beauvoir. A sleeping woman does not represent a threat to him.
She belongs to nobody” (TSS 696–7/LDS II:493). But to women, even a sleeping man is
a threat. Why? Because when he sleeps, he doesn’t think about her (TSS 698/LDS
II:493–4). Whatever he looks at that is not her, she experiences as threatening:
[A]s soon as he looks at something other than her, he frustrates her; everything he sees, he
steals from her; far from him, she is dispossessed both of herself and of the world; even
seated at her side, reading, writing, he abandons her, he betrays her. (TSS 696/LDS II:493)
The woman who tries to preserve her own transcendence by surrendering to a man, is
witnessing her transcendence not being brought out into the world every time he is not
aware of her (TSS 698/LDS II:495). As he is her link to the world, she sinks into imma-
nence without his attention.
Beauvoir’s grim description of inauthentic love is essentially a portrayal of how het-
erosexual love manifests itself on patriarchal terms of human interaction. It is described
in Beauvoir’s philosophy as a distorted, degenerate, and unethical form of love, doomed
to fail. Traditional marriages commonly epitomize inauthentic love, since the relation
between the spouses in such relationships is based on domination as opposed to com-
panionship, and because the other is not recognized as an irreplaceable, unique being.
Additionally, if the marriage is not freely chosen and continually renewed, this further
contributes to the marriage’s unethical arrangement. Consequently, adultery can
sometimes manifest authentic love and moral freedom.
Lesbian love can take many forms and also be inauthentic, but nevertheless holds a
greater potential for overcoming the patriarchal structures entrenched in the tradi-
tional heterosexual love. Two women in love will not so easily be trapped in conven-
tional femininity. In a culture where femininity “means mutilation” (TSS 421/LDS
II:175), lesbian love allows women to “free themselves of the chains attached to femi-
ninity” (TSS 424/LDS II:178), to experience love without becoming the Other. This is
precisely why it provokes; lesbian love acknowledges women as sovereign subjects and
consequently challenges the gender hierarchy: “As an ‘erotic perversion’ feminine
homosexuality elicits smiles; but inasmuch as it implies a way of life, it provokes scorn
or scandal” (TSS 434/LDS II:189).
However, inauthentic love is not the only form of love possible between women and
men. Authentic love between the sexes is achievable–but only when they acknowledge
each other as equals and as unique. Hence, while inauthentic love can be described as
patriarchal, authentic love can be labeled post‐patriarchal since sexism must be eradi-
cated for authentic relationships to flourish.
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
LOVE – ACCORDING TO SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR
165
2. Authentic Love
Authentic love contains two components that are missing in the inauthentic version.
First, there is mutual recognition of each other’s differences; second there is the mutual
recognition of each other’s equality. Aspiring to both difference and equality might
sound like a contradiction, but it is actually in harmony with Beauvoir’s existentialist
ontology, which sees ambiguity as part of the human condition (Beauvoir 1976, 7–8).
“Human nature is only worth its salt when it brings together these two natures,” writes
Beauvoir, and “love given and love received” are the “most powerful aid in bringing this
paradoxical synthesis” (2015a, 77). Let us inspect these two significant features of
authentic love.
2.1. Recognition ofdifferences
An authentic love,” writes Beauvoir, “should take on the other’s contingence, that is,
his lacks, limitations, and originary gratuitousness; it would claim to be not a salvation
but an inter‐human relation” (TSS 694/LDS II:491). It is vital to perceive love as a
human interaction. If the individuality of one of the partners–usually the woman–is
curbed, if she is regarded as a mere extension of her male partner, she cannot be loved
for her uniqueness. Sexuality in relationships where the individual differences have
been eradicated is unethical, she writes. This is because physical love in such relation-
ships is not justified by individuals, but by God or society, and then “the relationship of
the two partners is no more than a bestial one” (TSS 458/LDS II:216). Consequently,
“an authentically moral erotic life” is possible only when the other is recognized as a
unique individual. Here we see exactly what differentiates authentic and inauthentic
physical love. Authentic physical love is based on the lovers’ full consent and on their
acknowledgment of each other’s uniqueness. Inauthentic physical love–typical of tra-
ditional marriage–gives sex “an instrumental, thus degrading character” as they are
doomed to know each other in their generality, that is, as bodies, not as persons
(TSS465/LDS II:225).
Failing to recognize the individual differences not only makes sexuality unethical, it
is, according to Beauvoir, also the biggest turn‐off in a romantic relationship. The
reason is that “[e]roticism is a movement towards the Other, and this is its essential
character; but within the couple, spouses become, for each other, the Same; no exchange
is possible between them anymore, no giving, no conquest” (TSS 467/LDS II:226). It is
the lack of individuality, the absence of mutual recognition of each other’s uniqueness,
which, according to Beauvoir, kills the traditional marriage. Sexuality, romance, and
love are drowned in boredom when one of the partner’s perspectives and opinions are
mere repetitions of the other’s. Authentic love therefore requires both maintaining
their individuality and self‐respect, and acknowledging the differences between them.
2.2. Recognition ofequality
A necessary but insufficient condition to achieve true love is for the individuals to
acknowledge their differences. Additionally, they must also recognize each other as
equals. To recognize the other as an equal is to acknowledge the other as a free being.
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
TOVE PETTERSEN
166
Only then can love for the woman as for the man become “the source of life and not a
mortal danger” (TSS 708/LDS II:708):
Authentic love must be founded on reciprocal recognition of two freedoms; each lover
would then experience himself as himself and as the other; neither would abdicate tran-
scendence, they would not mutilate themselves; together they would reveal values and
ends in the world. (TSS 706/LDS II:505)
In an authentic love relationship, each party must choose to respect their own freedom
as well as that of the other, Beauvoir emphasizes. By respecting the other’s freedom, one
refrains from dominating, controlling, and suppressing the other. But equally impor-
tant; by respecting one’s own freedom, one rejects a submissive role and refrains from
seeking to devote oneself to another–as is the case in inauthentic love. For a woman to
achieve authentic love, she must essentially exist as pour‐soi – for‐herself–as men do.
This means that she must be financially independent, “project herself toward her own
ends,” and transcend herself towards the world without using a man as an agent (TSS
707/LDS II:506).
Authentic love is (ideally) non‐possessive and non‐submissive. Consequently, the
differences between the parties, such as gender, race, class, and age, will not allow one
to enjoy, unjustifiably, more freedom, power, and possibilities than the other – or to
renounce one’s own freedom. Moreover, authentic love is always freely chosen,
sustained, and voluntarily renewed. Free, renewed, and reciprocal recognition is a
prominent characteristic of authentic love, and is exactly what makes this, rather than
inauthentic love, ethical. Authentic love expresses moral freedom. Or, in the words of
Nancy Bauer:
genuine love is an expression of the highest of moral laws: when I love another person
genuinely I both exercise my existential freedom and evince the highest respect for the
freedom of other, on which, I understand, my own freedom rests. (Bauer 2001, 164–5)
Regardless of gender, race, and class, authentic love requires a reciprocated recognition
of both differences and equality. But is this applicable to maternal love? As the mother–
child relationship is asymmetrical, a full‐blown reciprocity cannot take place.
Nevertheless, maternal love can also be authentic. First, “since maternal love has
nothing natural about it” “the relation of parents to children, like that of the spouse,
must be freely chosen” (TSS 566–7/LDS II:338–9). Second, the mother must respect
her own freedom, as well as her child’s. Consequently, she will not justify her existence
through motherhood alone, but must also pursue other freely chosen projects. Nor will
she hamper the independence of her children, instead aiming to create a situation from
which “the child’s freedom can transcend” (TSS 568/LDS II:340).
It would obviously be better for the child if his mother were a complete person and not a
mutilated one, a woman who finds in her work and her relations with the group a self‐
accomplishment she could not attain through his tyranny; and it would be preferable also
for the child to be left infinitely less to his parents than he is now, that his studies and
amusements take place with other children under the control of adults whose links with
him are only impersonal and dispassionate (TSS 568/LDS II:340).
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
LOVE – ACCORDING TO SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR
167
Obviously, authentic love requires more than mutual recognition – which Beauvoir
alsoterms moral freedom. Whether or not the agents are capable of recognizing the
freedom of self and others is also dependent on the situation. Social and economic
circumstances shape people’s understanding of love and impact if and how their desires
can be carried out. If, for example, birth control and abortion are inaccessible, if same‐
sex relationships are forbidden, if dominant cultural myths depict women as submissive
and men as sexually aggressive, love will be deformed. In addition to reciprocated
recognition, authentic love also requires concrete freedom. Concrete freedom refers to
the measure of freedom people possess in a particular situation. Whether we enjoy
political rights, have sufficient material resources to exercise our freedom, or live instead
in “bad faith,” these situational attributes affect the agent’s capacity to make free
choices and act thereon also when it comes to love.
3. Beauvoir’s View onLove Contrasted withSartre’s
The publication of Beauvoir’s Diary has been an invaluable contribution to Beauvoir
scholarship, in particular with regard to the debate about the influence of Jean‐Paul
Sartre, and the exchange of ideas between them. What Diary demonstrates is that
central ideas of her later philosophy are prefigured in these very early writings–several
years before she even met Sartre. A close reading of Beauvoir’s works shows that the
position she developed on topics related to love departs distinctly from Sartre’s.
As already mentioned, Beauvoir is indeed conscious in Diary of the demand that
women sacrifice their own interests and autonomy on entering into a traditional
heterosexual relationship. In addition to these early reflections of what she would later
term inauthentic love, she also foreshadows the type of love she would term authentic.
The love she aspires to in Diary, “is not a subordination, and leaves the one who loves
the care of seeking his own directions, of leading an independent, individual life”
(Beauvoir 2006, 76). The idea that authentic love must contain the apparently ambig-
uous element of difference and equality is expressed in her ideas about a future partner
for whom she will not have to give up her own life: “One must love him in this very
difference without seeing it as an inferiority, which would be unjust for oneself” (2006,
77). Since the two individuals in love are separate and different, they cannot merge and
be one–even though they might reach out for it. It would be “absurd,” because the
“union of the souls” is “impossible” (2006, 76). Nevertheless, even if a complete union
cannot be achieved, the two lovers need not live their lives completely separated.
Beauvoir seeks a middle way between being merged and being divided: the lovers can
live parallel lives. Envisaging a marriage that differs from the traditional one, the 18‐
year‐old Beauvoir writes: “They are going to continue their life, side by side, but out-
wardly far from one another, and this, whatever their love may be, if they evolve in
parallel, is perfect” (2006, 78). This echoes Beauvoir’s later portrayal of authentic love,
as, for instance, in The Ethics of Ambiguity, where she writes: “To love him genuinely is
to love him in his otherness and in that freedom by which he escapes” (1976, 67). It also
resembles The Second Sex’s claim that love must be “founded on the recognition of two
freedoms” (TSS 520/LDS II:286), as well as her assertion in “It’s about time women put
on a new face on love” (1950), that “the miracle achieved by love alone” will only
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
TOVE PETTERSEN
168
happen if one can “cherish in the individual what gives him his difference and still
accord him the universal rights that are every human being’s” (2015a, 77). Throughout
Beauvoir’s entire output “it is this love that is the most complete relationship possible
with another person” (2015a, 78).
According to what Sartre writes in Being and Nothingness (1943), such love is not
possible.4 There are two fundamental attitudes toward the other, he contends. One is
“to transcend the Other’s transcendence,” the other is “to incorporate that transcen-
dence within me without removing from it its character as transcendence” (Sartre
2005, 385). The two attitudes conflict. In fact, as he himself claims, “each attempt is
the death of the other” (2005, 385). For Sartre, our freedom as individuals is at risk
whenever we encounter others, including–or especially–others with whom we form
a romantic relationship. The two attitudes toward the concrete others imply that love
takes place within a subject–object relationship involving an unavoidable battle over
who is to occupy the role of object or of subject. The reason one jeopardizes one’s free-
dom in relations with others is that one has to deal, intellectually, with the structure of
being‐for‐the‐other–which, in a romantic relationship, means one of the two has to
become an object.
When two are in love, each will attempt to adjust to the beloved’s look, by trying to
look at the beloved in the same way the beloved looks at them. In doing so, people in love
surrender their uniqueness and renounce their freedom. They will try to seduce the
beloved into loving them as something they are not–which, to Sartre, is an act of bad
faith. If the one does not submit, and both look at each other, “the struggle of two free-
doms confronted as freedoms” will be out in the open (Sartre 2005, 401). There will be
a battle between the two freedoms until it is established which is the subject and which
the object in this relationship. For Sartre, there is no way of transcending the subject–
object relationship; either you lose your own freedom or you deny the other theirs. In
fact, the problem of being‐for‐the other “remains without solution” (2005, 398).
To love the other as a freedom and at the same time remain a free being, is an impos-
sible achievement in Sartre’s framework because one cannot love another without
falling into a relationship of object to subject. Although Beauvoir is certainly aware of
relationships dominated by the conflict between subject and object, she still believes in
the possibility of a relationship in which both consider the other as subject: “The conflict
can be overcome by the free recognition of each individual in the other, each one pos-
iting both itself and the other as object and as subject in a reciprocal movement” (TSS
159/LDS I:232). This is what authentic love requires. Within the framework of
Beauvoir’s ethics, authentic love exists when both have achieved moral freedom, while
in Sartre’s Being and Nothingness only inauthentic love is possible.
To explain the differences between Beauvoir’s and Sartre’s respective views on
romantic love, we need to look at their different ontologies. Sartre’s ontology is
pessimistic in its view of human relationships. Others are essentially hostile and antag-
onistic, a threat to my freedom. Unlike Sartre, Beauvoir does not believe our relation-
ships are always antagonistic. Nor does she believe that being with others necessarily
has to be a struggle between two minds, each seeking to dominate the other. For
Beauvoir, a human being is present in the world as a being connected with others. In
her own words: “I concern others and they concern me. There we have an irreducible
truth. The me–others relationship is as indissoluble as the subject–object relationship”
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
LOVE – ACCORDING TO SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR
169
(Beauvoir 1976, 72). In addition to not seeing being‐in‐the‐world as a fundamentally
antagonistic state vis‐à‐vis others, Beauvoir does not understand individual humans as
separate from others’ being‐in‐the world. For Beauvoir, being is my‐and‐your‐being‐in the
world, it is our being‐in‐the‐world–it is being‐with (Mitsein) (TSS 17/LDS I:32). Where
Sartre’s ontology is individualistic, Beauvoir’s is relational (Pettersen 2008; 2010).
Another relevant difference between Beauvoir and Sartre is the fact that Beauvoir
emphasizes the ambiguity of the human condition far more than he does. For Beauvoir
it is both‐and, not either‐or. As a result, she does not dichotomize to the same extent as
Sartre (Bergoffen 1999). Sartre’s dichotomous approach in his analysis of our per-
ceptions of others–as either subject or object, unfree or free (at the cost of an other’s
freedom)–leaves little possibility for harmonious relationships in which the lovers can
acknowledge each other’s freedom. In Beauvoir’s ontology, humans are both mind and
body, both entirely free and restricted, both separate and interdependent. For her, bad
faith is the result of ignoring, denying, masking, and resisting ambiguity. By accepting
ambiguity, we can capture the complexity of human interaction, and avoid the problem
that occurs in Sartre’s philosophy that makes it impossible to establish a subject–subject
relationship. Beauvoir’s approach to our‐being‐in‐the‐world, anchored in ambiguity
and intersubjectivity, departs from the dichotomous and individualistic ontology of
many traditional philosophers–including existentialist philosophers such as Sartre,
Kierkegaard, and Camus (Pettersen 2008; 2010). Beauvoir’s ontology is what opens up
the prospect of authentic love in her philosophy, a possibility she consistently defends
throughout her entire output. Additionally, her unique ontology and her understanding
of authentic interaction foreshadow tenets in contemporary feminist philosophy.
4. Relational Autonomy
Acknowledgement of one’s own and the other’s freedom and otherness, which Beauvoir
asserts is mandatory to authentic love, is closely related to having autonomy or being
autonomous. When Beauvoir describes the interaction in authentic love relationships,
she is actually portraying people with autonomy. They have their own reasons, their
self‐defined goals, and they are both responsible for their own decisions and actions.
However, it has been regarded as one of the many paradoxes of love that the lovers
are strongly motivated to form and constitute a “we,” while they also desire to remain
autonomous–an antagonism Beauvoir describes both in Diary and The Second Sex. In
her depictions of authentic love Beauvoir, nevertheless (and contrary to Sartre) sur-
passes this supposed antagonism between self‐determination and cooperation, between
independence and attachment when she describes a romantic relationship in which the
parties manage to establish a “we”–without losing their individuality or erasing the
boundaries between their two selves. In this sense, she rejects the view that a complete
union must be the goal or is the nature of true love, and also the view that we are des-
tined to remain solitary and isolated if we do not want to be dominated or dominating.
According to Beauvoir, although couples in an authentic love relationship do not
merge into complete union, obliterating their separate ego‐boundaries, they can still
form a “we.” There are, indeed, significant differences between the “we” constituted in
authentic and inauthentic relationships. In an authentic relationship, says Beauvoir,
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
TOVE PETTERSEN
170
the couple should not be considered as a unit, or “a closed cell,” but instead as free indi-
viduals capable also of participating in society and forming relationship with other free
persons. And, she continues:
This balanced couple is not a utopia; such couples exist, sometimes even within marriage,
most often outside of it: some are united by a great sexual love that leaves them free in their
friendships and occupation, others are linked by a friendship that does not hamper their
sexual freedom, more rarely there are still others who are both lovers and friends but
without seeking in each other their exclusive reason for living. (TSS 520/LDS II:286)
The differences between the two types of “we” are worth exploring, as they shed light on
an interesting understanding of autonomy in Beauvoir’s philosophy. The authentic
“we” is not understood as if joined by a mysterious, natural, divine or conventional
intervention; external forces do not bind them. What constitutes an authentic “we” is
the voluntary decision of the two to set common goals, create values and share some
experiences together. This consensus forms an autonomous “we.”
However, as autonomy has traditionally been understood in terms of separation,
non‐interference, and self‐determination, the concept does not grasp such shared
agency. Beauvoir’s authentic love includes reciprocity, discussion, connectedness, and
collaboration. Therefore, it represents a challenge to the traditional concept of
autonomy. Under the traditional view of autonomy, one of the persons in an inau-
thentic relationship, usually the woman, has to give up his or her autonomy in order to
constitute a “we,” while both individuals in an authentic relationship have to abandon
their autonomy to become a “we” in which they are equal. Given this perspective on
autonomy, the woman who wants to live an autonomous life would seem obliged to give
up any idea of being in a heterosexual relationship, while the man will only keep his
autonomy in an inauthentic relationship. What is needed is a new concept of autonomy
with space for the type of reciprocity and connectedness that we find in authentic love
relationships–but without forfeiting self‐determination or freedom.
As Beauvoir is not willing to choose between individual self‐determination and the
possibility of authentic love, we find what is needed to reconceptualize autonomy in her
version of authentic love. Beauvoir gives us an alternative understanding of autonomy
because the self she portrays as capable of authentic love is both separate and relational,
with the capacity to cooperate and to self‐legislate. It is not a self that dominates others,
nor does it allow itself be dominated or torn apart. Based on such selves, the “we”
formed in authentic love is a democratic relationship in the sense that it is freely chosen
and maintained by equals, with the capacity and space for genuine, open and mutual
consultation, debate, and (dis)agreement (Westlund 2005, 30).
Not only is the ability to enter into such a relation a precondition for forming and
maintaining the kind of relationship Beauvoir portrays as an authentic love rela-
tionship. We can also read her understanding of authentic love as a forerunner of
feminist philosophy’s remodeling of the traditional concept of autonomy, which pro-
ceeded from what is termed an “individual” understanding to a “relational” under-
standing. Beauvoir’s authentic relationship is based on “comradeship:” it is not
“parasitic.” Authentic love “presupposes friendship;” hence it “may be platonic as
well as sexual,” she admits. Still, physical love is commonly a significant part of
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
LOVE – ACCORDING TO SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR
171
authentic love, as it is often what gives the “beloved its matchless value” and what
maintains “their mutual magic” (Beauvoir 2015a, 78–9).
In the view of feminist ethicists such as Marilyn Friedman (2005), Sarah Hoagland
(1988), Virginia Held (1993), and Eva Kittay (1999), relational autonomy incorpo-
rates, in accordance with Beauvoir’s philosophical concepts, the lived experience of
relationships. Based on many people’s everyday experiences, it is precisely through
interacting with others that one learns how to make decisions. In relationships, one dis-
cusses who will make certain decisions, and from time to time the parties freely agree to
let one or the other do so. This is done without undermining either party’s autonomy, or
curbing their freedom. In fact, their cooperation might strengthen each individual’s
autonomy (Held 1993, 55). Based on an agreement, a joint autonomy is possible. This
reconceptualized notion of autonomy is indeed very different from the traditional
notion that privileges non‐intervention and self‐sufficiency.
Not only does Beauvoir challenge the traditional philosophical conception of love
and autonomy, she lays the foundations for the development of a new concept of
autonomy within contemporary feminist philosophy. In her analysis of the two differ-
ent kinds of love she suggests how it is possible to enter into a genuine love relationship
in which we retain our autonomous lives, while enjoying shared and vibrant lives
together. For love to be experienced in this manner, both sexes must forfeit the patriarchal
view of gender and love. For authentic love to be possible, both women and men must
unconditionally acknowledge themselves and their partner as unique and equal,
and–it goes without saying–they must act accordingly. The friendship, generosity and
love achieved by such mutual recognition of freedoms are, according to Beauvoir,
undoubtedly humans’ highest accomplishment (TSS 159–60/LDS I:232). What is
attained is not only an authentically moral attitude, as well as comradeship and the
“miracle” of love (2015a, 77), but also the revelation of “a new world” (2015b, 100).
Notes
1 Beauvoir also uses literature to explore the traditional gender differences with regard to love.
In her novel The Mandarins (1954), for example, she lets the relationship between Paula and
Henri epitomize gendered, inauthentic love. Paula has given up her own career as a singer to
devote herself completely to her husband Henri–the founder and editor of a newspaper.
Paula’s existence and identity are defined and dependent on her relationship with Henri.
When he leaves her, Paula contemplates suicide. Beauvoir considers the consequences of
inauthentic love also in other works, such as She Came to Stay (1943), and The Woman
Destroyed (1967).
2 Women’s inauthentic love as described in The Second Sex resembles several of Beauvoir’s por-
trayal of the possible inauthentic existences in The Ethics of Ambiguity (1947), such as the
“sub‐man”, the “serious man” and the “passionate man”.
3 In addition, women conforming with traditional gendered expectations are rewarded eco-
nomically, metaphysically, and socially (Beauvoir 2011, 10).
4 It should be mentioned that Sartre appends a footnote in which he says: “These consider-
ations do not exclude the possibility of an ethics of deliverance and salvation. But this can be
achieved only after a radical conversation which we cannot discuss here” (2011, 434, fn. 13).
I nevertheless relate to what is possible based on Being and Nothingness.
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
TOVE PETTERSEN
172
References
Bauer, Nancy. 2001. Simone de Beauvoir, Philosophy, & Feminism. New York: Columbia University
Press, 2001.
Beauvoir, Simone de. 1976. The Ethics of Ambiguity. Translated by Bernard Frechtman. New York:
Citadel Press. English translation of Pour une morale de l’ambiguïté. Paris: Gallimard, 1947.
—. 2004. “Pyrrhus and Cineas.” In Simone de Beauvoir: Philosophical Writings, edited by Margaret
A. Simons, Marybeth Timmermann and Mary Beth Mader, 77–150. Urbana: University of
Illinois Press.
—. 2006. Diary of a Philosophy Student. Volume 1, 1926–27, edited by Barbara Klaw, Sylvie Le
Bon de Beauvoir, Margaret A. Simons, and Marybeth Timmermann. Urbana: University of
Illinois Press.
—. 2011. The Second Sex. Translated by Constance Borde and Sheila Malovany-Chevallier.
New York: Vintage Books. (TSS) English translation of Le deuxième sexe, 2 vols. Paris: Gallimard,
1949. (LDS)
—. 2015a. “It’s About Time Women Put a New face on Love.” In Simone de Beauvoir: Feminist
Writings, edited by Margaret A. Simons and Marybeth Timmermann, 76–80. Urbana:
University of Illinois Press.
—.2015b. “What Love is–and Isn’t.” In Simone de Beauvoir: Feminist Writings, edited by Margaret
A. Simons and Marybeth Timmermann, 99–102. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Bergoffen, Debra B. 1999. “Simone de Beauvoir and Jean‐Paul Sartre: Woman, Man and The
Desire to be God,” in Labyrinth 1(1). http://phaidon.philo.at/~iaf/Labyrinth/Bergoffen.html.
Deutsch, Hélène. 1946. The Psychology of Women: A Psychoanalytic Interpretation, vol. 2. New
York: Grune and Stratton.
Freud, Sigmund. 1995 [1924]. “The Economic Problem of Masochism.” In Essential Papers on
Masochism, edited by Margaret Ann Fitzpatrick Hanly, 274–85. New York: New York University
Press.
Friedman, Marilyn. 2005. “Autonomy, Social Disruption, and Women.” In Feminist Theory:
APhilosophical Anthology, edited by Anne E. Cudd and Robin O. Andreasen, 339–51. Malden,
MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Gunnarsson, Lena. 2013. On the Ontology of Love, Sexuality and Power. Toward a Feminist‐Realist
Depth Approach. Örebro: Örebro University.
Held, Virginia. 1993. Feminist Morality. Transforming Culture, Society and Politics. Chicago:
TheUniversity of Chicago Press.
Hoagland, Sarah Lucia. 1988. Lesbian Ethics. Toward New Values, Palo Alto: California Institute of
Lesbian Studies.
Kittay, Eva Feder. 1999. Love’s Labor. Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency, New York and
London: Routledge.
Munday, Leo. 2015. “The Question of Men in Love: A Beauvoirian Response to Jørgen Lorentzen.”
Nora–Nordic Journal of Feminist and Gender Research 23(3): 187–202.
Pettersen, Tove. 2007. “Freedom and Feminism in Simone de Beauvoir’s Philosophy.” In Simone
de Beauvoir Studies, Vol. 24, 2007–2008, edited by Yolanda Patterson, 57–65. Menlo Park
California: ISSN 1063.
—. 2008. “La joie existentielle et l’angoisse dans la philosophie morale de Simone de Beauvoir.”
[Joy and Anguish in Simone de Beauvoir’s Moral Philosophy]. In (Re)découvrir l’œuvre de Simone
de Beauvoir Du Deuxième Sexe à La cérémonie des adieux [(Re)discovering the Work of Simone de
Beauvoir through The Second Sex and A Farewell to Sartre], edited by Julia Kristeva, 212–25.
Paris: Le Bord de L’eau.
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
LOVE – ACCORDING TO SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR
173
—. 2010. “Acting for Others: Moral Ontology in Beauvoir’s Pyrrhus and Cineas.” In Simone de
Beauvoir Studies Vol. 26, 2009–2010, edited by Yolanda Patterson, 18–27. Menlo Park
California: ISSN 1063‐2042.
—. 2015. “Existential Humanism and Moral Freedom.” In Simone de Beauvoir – a Humanist
Thinker, edited by Tove Pettersen and Annlaug Bjørsnøs, 69–91. Amsterdam/New York: Brill/
Rodopi.
Schopenhauer, Arthur. 1851. On Women. http://www.theabsolute.net/misogyny/onwomen.
html
Sartre, Jean‐Paul. 2005. Being and Nothingness. Translated Hazel E. Bar nes. London and New York:
Routledge Classics.
Westlund, Andrea. 2009. “Deciding Together.” Philosopher’s Imprint 9(10): 1–17.
Copyright © 2017. Wiley-Blackwell. All rights reserved. May not be reproduced in any form without permission from the publisher, except fair uses permitted under U.S.
or applicable copyright law.
EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) - printed on 3/12/2021 7:04 AM via UIO UNIVERSITY OF OSLO
AN: 1565254 ; Laura Hengehold, Nancy Bauer.; A Companion to Simone De Beauvoir
Account: s9856149
... 5 A publicação de Cahiers de jeunesse de Beauvoir em 2008 mostra que a questão filosófica sobre o amor já estava no centro dos escritos da jovem Simone de Beauvoir (2008). 6 Os dois estudos mais importantes sobre o assunto são: Cleary (2017) e Pettersen (2017). Há também Lacaze (2015); Mcmullin (2011); Klaw (1997); Heinämaa (2006 Desde a primeira página da Introdução, Beauvoir levanta a questão que será fundamental em O Segundo Sexo: "o que é uma mulher?" (Beauvoir, 1986a, p. 9). ...
Article
Full-text available
Neste ensaio, Manon Garcia analisa o lugar da filosofia do amor no argumento geral de Simone de Beauvoir sobre a opressão feminina e defende que, embora o amor pareça desempenhar um papel secundário n’O Segundo Sexo, ele tem papel fundamental para responder à pergunta “o que é uma mulher?”. Garcia defende que o amor é central para a análise que Beauvoir faz da opressão das mulheres, na medida em que constitui o fundamento ideológico da objetificação das mulheres e estrutura as ambiguidades das experiências vividas da opressão. Ao mesmo tempo, Garcia aponta que, para Beauvoir, o amor pode ser um recurso para a emancipação das mulheres no nível individual.
Article
Full-text available
This study analyzed the characteristics of female Filipino youths in selected 21st-century Philippine short stories. This study used the constructivist research paradigm and the feminism theory of Simone de Beauvoir. It limits categorizing the female characters in the stories as narcissists, women in love, and mystics. It employs the descriptive Qualitative Research Method through Content Analysis. The study results showed that female characters are narcissistic and women in love but differ in the major theme of each unique characteristic. Unfortunately, the researcher did not uncover a mystic character in the eight selected short stories. Based on the result, the researcher recommends incorporating the feminist perspective in teaching to improve students' understanding of gender issues and the role played by women in society. Furthermore, a focus on female characters and their experiences could be included in future research. These can help them assess other Filipino female characteristics.
Article
Reading Beauvoir’s descriptions of love in The Second Sex (TSS), one would be forgiven for being pessimistic about the possibility of authentic love. What I will do in this paper is, using Beauvoir’s diagnosis of inauthentic love under patriarchy, construct a set of conditions that an authentic love would be guided by and strive to manifest. I will then defend the importance of Beauvoir’s views by demonstrating its explanatory power. Firstly, I will show how Beauvoir’s account can deal with two common contemporary problems that are often raised as objections against accounts of love that include a moral element. Then, in the third section, I will also show the value of this account by demonstrating its ability to explain why different kinds of love feel differently. The kind I will focus on will be unrequited love; this will be in dialogue with vision-based accounts to highlight Beauvoir’s unique contribution.
Article
Full-text available
The authority of a souverain no longer seems important if one wants to analyse complex modern democratic societies. At the same time, one can observe an increasing desire for authority in social and political life, a longing for orientation and guidance. This paper wants to investigate how authority and gender are intertwined, and how this is expressed in the current crisis of normality. The paper shows why a return to authority cannot solve this crisis. In order to co-create a new normality one needs to accept the ambiguity of existence and the relational character of freedom (see De Beauvoir).
Chapter
Tove Pettersen explores why Simone de Beauvoir was been neglected as a philosopher, and also why she denied calling herself a philosopher. One important reason is, Pettersen argues, the collision between her gendered experiences and the male-dominated philosophical tradition. This antagonism compelled her to transcend the discipline’s boundaries and developed what later has been viewed as an original philosophy, but it also alienated her from the philosophical mainstream. It propelled some methodological obstacles that can shed light both on why she was excluded from the history of philosophy, and also why she denied being part of this tradition. Studying the characteristics of her philosophy may also reveal challenges women still face when doing philosophy, as well as the prejudices and methodological obstacles preventing them to gain their rightful place in the history of philosophy.
Article
Full-text available
Beauvoir and Sartre share an existential vocabulary. Both invoke the categories of bad faith and the look, both describe consciousness as a transcendence and a freedom, and both refer to freedom as a negating intentionality. Beauvoir’s concept of ambiguity stands between this shared vocabulary. For Sartre, the intentionality of consciousness is an unambiguous negating activity saturated with an unambiguous desire to be that coalesces around the desire to be God, that impossible synthesis of the for-itself-in-itself. For Beauvoir, the intentionality of consciousness is ambiguous. It is the site of a twofold relationship to being and a doubled desire. Employing the logic of the either/or, Sartre assails the bad faith of the desire to be God. Invoking the logic of ambiguity, Beauvoir embraces the failure of this desire. According to The Ethics of Ambiguity, our vain attempt to be God makes us human. It is also a source of joy. 1 Moving from the abstract ethical perspective of The Ethics of Ambiguityto the political-ethical frame of The Second Sex, we discover that the desire to be, as concretely embedded in the everydayness of the lifeworld, is sexed and bodied. Instead of attending to the ways in which the pour-soi’s desire to be is captivated by the abstract idea of God, Beauvoir now attends to the ways in which the embodied desire to be is lured by the particular images of woman and man. She is particularly concerned with the ways in which the image and myth of woman marks the embodied consciousness of women. In turning her attention from our existential-ontological condition to our existential-historical situation and in moving from an analysis of the lure of the desire to be God to the powers and seductions of the myth of woman, Beauvoir alerts us to the fact that the desire to be expresses itself in the objects as well as in the structure of our desire. Structurally, the desire to be takes up its home in mythical thought ‐ thought that essentializes existence. With respect to content, the desire to be embraces eternal objects ‐ objects that cannot exist because they always already are. As structure and content, the desire to be represents a flight from the anxieties of existential freedom and the demands of existential thinking. If it is the case that as concrete men and women our desire to be God is sexed; and if it is the case that as concrete men and women we are not so much seduced by the image of God (an image that in a sense announces its impossibility and therefore the failure of our desire) as we are captivated by the myths of man and woman (images that are more seductive insofar as they present themselves as true
Chapter
Women have historically been prevented from living autonomously by systematic injustice, subordination, and oppression. The lingering effects of these practices have prompted many feminists to view autonomy with suspicion. This book defends the ideal of feminist autonomy. The book proposes that behavior is autonomous if it accords with the wants, cares, values, or commitments that the actor has reaffirmed and is able to sustain in the face of opposition. By this account, autonomy is socially grounded yet also individualizing and sometimes socially disruptive, qualities that can be ultimately advantageous for women. The book applies the concept of autonomy to domains of special interest to women. It defends the importance of autonomy in romantic love, considers how social institutions should respond to women who choose to remain in abusive relationships, and argues that liberal societies should tolerate minority cultural practices that violate women's rights so long as the women in question have chosen autonomously to live according to those practices.
Article
In this paper I develop a conception of joint practical deliberation as a special type of shared cooperative activity, through which co-deliberators jointly accept reasons as applying to them as a pair or group. I argue, moreover, that the aspiration to deliberative “pairhood” is distinguished by a special concern for mutuality that guides each deliberator’s readiness to accept a given consideration as a reason-for-us. It matters to each of us, as joint deliberators, that each party’s (individual) reasons for accepting something as a reason-for-us support a conception of our relationship as one characterized by mutual, non-instrumental concern for one another.
Book
By turns surprising and revelatory, this sixth volume in the Beauvoir Series presents newly discovered writings and lectures while providing new translations and contexts for Simone de Beauvoir’s more familiar writings. Spanning Beauvoir’s career from the 1940s through 1986, the pieces explain the paradoxes in her political and feminist stances, including her famous 1972 announcement of a “conversion to feminism” after decades of activism on behalf of women. Feminist Writings documents and contextualizes Beauvoir’s thinking, writing, public statements, and activities in the services of causes like French divorce law reform and the rights of women in the Iranian Revolution. In addition, the volume provides new insights into Beauvoir’s complex thinking and illuminates her historic role in linking the movements for sexual freedom, sexual equality, homosexual rights, and women’s rights in France. © 2015 by the Board of Trustees of the University of Illinois. All rights reserved.
Article
This book is a novel contribution to contemporary research on Simone de Beauvoir, and a defense of the importance of the humanities. It reveals previously unexplored dimensions of Beauvoir's work by exposing her as a significant and inspiring humanist thinker. These essays argue that her works and influence testify to the transformative potential of humanistic research. © 2015 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. All rights reserved.
Article
In this essay, I engage Jørgen Lorentzen in his search for the man in love. Lorentzen argues that, in research on men and masculinity, men's heterosexual love is rarely a site where men may experience positive social change, offering Shakespeare's Romeo as a literary example of a man in love who undermines both power and patriarchy. Reading Simone de Beauvoir's The Ethics of Ambiguity and The Second Sex together, I argue that Beauvoir's theoretical perspective provides masculinity studies with critical insights that may mediate the ways in which scholars theorize and study the question of men and love. Using Weber's ideal types as a heuristic device, I focus on the conceptual differences between the serious man and the passionate man, arguing that men's ability to remain sovereign in love is a mark of their privileged position, their capacity to move and speak with either the power of the masculine ideal or the power of passionate freedom behind them. Either way, men are still struggling to recognize women as a peer and partner within the current structure of heterosexual relationships. However, unlike research on men and masculinity, Beauvoir's work empowers men to see the specific obstacles in their way, giving men a clear sense of hope in their search for authentic love and thus a movement toward positive social change.
Article
This book is the first of a two-volume study of feminine psychology from a psychoanalytic point of view. It is based upon the author's extensive psycho-analytic and psychiatric experience with all types and degrees of maladjustments and with psychoneurotic and psychotic reactions in girls and women of all ages. The material is organized about three themes, the first of which is the girl's psychological development into womanhood, covered by the chapters on prepuberty, early puberty, puberty and adolescence, and menstruation. The second theme, the organization and types of the feminine personality, is dealt with in chapters on eroticism in the feminine woman, feminine passivity, and feminine masochism. The third theme deals with variations from what is considered feminine, such as the masculinity complex, homosexuality, and the influence of environment. Throughout, illustrative clinical material is cited in detail, and extensive references are made to the literature with footnote references. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2012 APA, all rights reserved)