Content uploaded by Mark Benton
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Mark Benton on Sep 12, 2017
Content may be subject to copyright.
Introduction
In the pursuit of solutions to economic and demographic problems during the early to mid-
twentieth century, St. Louis city planner Harland Bartholomew destroyed black neighborhoods,
displaced their residents without assistance, and created racial segregation (Schindler, 2015;
Rothstein, 2014; Gordon, 2014; Bartholomew, 1922; Kanovsky, 2015; Marcuse, 1997; Heathcott,
2005b; Lai, 2014). Citing concerns of public health, unfair municipal tax contributions, and
deurbanization, he was motivated to alter the built environment to secure urban growth
(Bartholomew, 1920; Bartholomew, 1937a; Bartholomew, 1935; Bartholomew, 1914-1929;
Bartholomew, 1914-1929a; Bartholomew, 1940; Bartholomew, 1937; Cooper-McCann, 2016;
Heathcott, 2005a; Brown, 2005). His concerns were rational. Many slum residences did not have
running water, adequate sunlight, reasonable living space, and were next to polluting industries
(Bolin, Grineski, & Collins, 2005; Lopez, 2012; Fischler, 1998; Bartholomew, 1920a; Fukuo,
2009; Lopez, 2009; Heathcott, 2015; Rothstein, 2014). Slums created negative externalities by
consuming more than they paid in municipal taxes (Heathcott, 2015; Lovelace, 1993;
Bartholomew, 2003; Gordon, 2014). White populations were beginning to deurbanize from the
central city into the suburbs (Sandoval, 2004). Bartholomew’s concerns were founded, his
analyses correct; but, his solutions ignored the lives of black slum populations.
This paper will argue that in the pursuit of solutions, Harland Bartholomew committed
administrative evil. This was legal, which does not diminish its status as cruelty. It was done after
analyzing the sources of urban problems, and from those analyses it made sense. Slum clearance
was considered to be the first step in urban renewal, a process that would help the city at large.
Urban renewal proved to be a process that displaced populations under the guise of progress.
This paper is no apology for the evil of slum clearance in St. Louis. Its harm cannot be justified
by any urban problem. It will explain how the demolition and displacement of black
neighborhoods was cast as good and necessary.
Urban planning was used to alter the built environment of St. Louis to the detriment of black
residents. Bartholomew’s slum clearance did not consider the effect that the program would have
on their neighborhoods. It is one thing to see a black neighborhood as blighted, or in bad shape,
but another thing to recommend destroying it without considering displaced families. This period
was one where discrimination was common, but the effects that slum clearance had go beyond
discrimination. Entire communities were destroyed and their populations were displaced. Those
who could not afford new housing in the city had little choice but to emigrate. Neighborhoods
that had spent years building strong social ties were dispersed. The displacement of black
populations in St. Louis was a policy of exodus.
Administrative Evil
Administrative evil is defined by Guy Adams and Danny Balfour (2014) as when people “engage
in acts of evil unaware that they are in fact doing anything at all wrong,” with evil defined as
“the actions of human beings that unjustly or needlessly inflict pain and suffering and death on
other human beings.” Their definition of administrative evil is adequate, but their definition of
evil is somewhat vague in its exactness of when cruelty is just or needed, and of when unethical
behavior moves into the realm of actual evil. More contemporary descriptions of evil
characterize it as existing on a spectrum, with the inconsequential lie being far before the point
that immorality becomes evil and mass murder existing past that point (Adams & Balfour, 2015;
Jurkiewicz & Grossman, 2015). Others will point out that there is an equity component to evil,
and that deeds committed within patterns of inequity carry additional weight when considering if
a deed is evil (Fredrickson, 2015). A better definition of evil describes it as between the lie-to-
mass murder spectrum, with weight added to actions that fit in with patterns of inequity.
Not all evil is administrative. People committing evil often understand what they are doing
and why they are doing it. When evil is recognized for what it is, it can be perceived as
unavoidable or enabling a greater good (Zanetti & Adams, 2000). Sometimes people committing
evil are unaware of what they are contributing to, and this is when evil becomes administrative.
The defining characteristic that separates evil from administrative evil is that it is masked to
perpetrators.
Administrative evil is masked – administrative evil-doers do not have evil intentions.
Administrative evil may be so masked that it is impossible to recognize and is often perpetrated
by people fulfilling their professional roles in an organization (Adams & Balfour, 2007; Adams
& Balfour, 2014; Adams & Zanetti, 2000). With time and cultural distance, administrative evil
becomes easier to unmask (Barth, 2010; Adams & Balfour, 2014; Molina, 2015; Tschundi, 2008;
Adams & Zanetti, 2000). The most named mask administrative evil is technical rationality, a
phenomenon that arose from early twentieth century approaches to problem solving.
Technical rationality, an epistemology that emphasizes scientific analysis, efficiency, and
technological progress, is the most cited mask of administrative evil (Adams & Balfour, 2014;
Adams, 2011a; Adams, Balfour, & Reed, 2006). Technical-rational specialists apply their skills
in pursuit of a goal, separated from the context of its use. The specialist has little say in their
goals—there is only the expectation of science and efficiency (Dillard & Ruchala, 2005). A
specialist uses technical means to reach specified ends; in this way, it appears to professionals
that ends dictate means as being whatever is most efficient, rather than people dictating their own
means and ends (Chwastiak, 2001). Some have argued that technical rationality is not necessary
for evil to occur and that there are other explanations for evil committed by administrators
(Koven, 2011). This is true; however, technical rationality is sufficient to mask evil and has been
noted as an area of interest in public administration for decades (Adams, 2011).
Legalism has also been identified as a common mask of administrative evil. (Hoffman, Pyne,
& Gajewski, 2012). Legalism entails a perspective that the following of laws is sufficient for
fulfilling moral obligations (Shklar, 1964). Laws can justify immorality—if one knows her
auctions are legal, it is easy to see herself as doing good (Molina, 2015). In the eyes of
perpetrators, evil performed pursuant to the law becomes legitimate (Balfour, 1997). While law
often aims to be a perfect reflection of morality, that reflection can sometimes become opaque.
The law can be insufficient for defining moral action (Granfield & Koenig, 2003), immoral
governance can fall within the bounds of the law (Anechiarico, 2016), and the legal profession
has undergone moral decline (Derthick, 2015; Quill, 2014). There are times if, when the
following of a law would result in a profound evil, that the expectations of the administrator
must be to overcome immoral laws (King, 1963). Without that expectation, the legal status of an
action can mask the evil it entails.
A third mask of administrative evil is moral inversion. During moral inversion an evil, for
example the displacement and segregation of blacks, is recast as a good, for example helping the
city grow. The moral inversion is convincing and believable, it is not a rationalization that people
seek actively (Adams & Balfour, 2014; Adams & Balfour, 2008; Balf, 2016). When the
population that evil is being performed upon is defined as dangerous to a community’s economic
sustainability or physical security, evil committed to them can be recast as good for helping the
community (Bartholomew, 1922; Bartholomew, 1935; Bartholomew, 1937; Adams et al., 2006).
Believing oneself to be doing good works to mask evil. Overcoming the moral inversion may be
the most difficult aspect of avoiding administrative evil; the rejection of cruelty when faced with
victimhood can engender a sense of cynicism and misanthropy with the realization that the
cruelty of others will continue even in a society that refuses to respond in kind (Shklar, 1982).
Evil can be masked through the creation and dehumanization of surplus populations, which
are groups without substantive roles in the society they live in (Adams et al., 2006; Samier, 2008;
Dillard, Ruchala, & Yuthas, 2005; Rubenstein, 1983). In modern capitalism, surplus populations
do not contribute economically (Rubenstein, 1983). Economic surplus populations are reduced to
their quantitative attributes measured in dollars (Bauman, 1989). From the perspective of
efficiency-minded technical rationality seeking an economic end, surplus populations are
inefficient inputs. In general, economic deprivation works to define populations as less-than-
human out groups (Tschundi, 2008; Adams & Balfour, 2008). The economic problems created by
black surplus populations in St. Louis were not considered intentional, but rather a natural
characteristic of blackness (Lee, 2000; Tillotson, 2014; Stone, 2012). Slum conditions were
synonymous with black residency, they could only be alleviated by the removal of the surplus
population rather than through the improvement of their conditions—black residency was seen to
cause slums, and conditions could only be improved in their absence.
Evil can be masked using euphemisms. What is now often called slum clearance was referred
to as a step in urban renewal (Fainstein, 2005; Berry, 2005; Lipman, 2009; Kanovsky, 2015).
This euphemism shifted the actions of planners from the clearance of slum neighborhoods to the
rest of the city, which stood to benefit. Words like blight and slum were used to describe black
neighborhoods, and blacks themselves were thought to spread blight, and financial and insurance
risk (Kanovsky, 2015; Tillotson, 2014). Describing a neighborhood as risky, blighted, or slum,
was synonymous with calling it black (Lee, 2000). In St. Louis, Harland Bartholomew rarely
made references to race explicitly unless in passing, and preferred to talk about blight and slum
(Bartholomew, 2003; Riley, 1926-1964).
Evil can be masked on a spectrum. Some evil is hidden from the people committing it, some
have a vague understanding, and some people are aware of what they are doing. Evil tends to be
mostly if not entirely unmasked at executive level positions. There, evil is calculated and chosen
as supportive of a larger goal (Adams & Balfour, 2014). Organizational support roles tend to be
susceptible to masked evil (Balf, 2016; Adams et al., 2006). City planners fall within this level as
specialists—they make recommendations, to inform decision makers. Lower level practitioners
can also recognize evil around them. They may do nothing about it for fear of arousing the ire of
their bosses, or because they do not believe their personal agency appropriately extends to the
situation (Samier, 2008).
Some take issue with the descriptor of evil entirely—it has moral implications, which are
often considered to be subjective and outside of the realm of social science. Many academics
have shied away from this kind of research, opting to merely describe ethical theories or to
rename evil as something less controversial (Quill, 2014; Adams & Balfour, 2014).
Evil can be overnamed, or often used to refer to something less than evil. Overnaming
diminishes the power of the word evil, especially when it is used to describe displacement,
murder, and taking candy from a baby. Evil can also be undernamed when it is not used to refer
to something that is clearly evil. Referring to displacement as ‘bad’ could undername its severity
(Boedy, 2015). This paper takes the position that some things are accurately described as evil.
Having defined evil and administrative evil, both can be discussed in a descriptive manner.
The next section discusses Harland Bartholomew, city planner in St. Louis from 1916 to
1953. Bartholomew was an advocate for slum clearance, both in St. Louis and across the country.
First, a broad overview of Bartholomew’s work will be given. Then a more specific discussion of
Bartholomew’s planning will be presented and matched to masks of administrative evil.
Harland Bartholomew
This section relies on literature describing the life and work of Harland Bartholomew. In addition
to books and articles, it also relies on the Washington University’s Harland Bartholomew
Archives. This archive contains many of Bartholomew’s personal records. Through the idea of
slum clearance Bartholomew did a great deal of harm to the populations he displaced. Rational
city planning became popular in the early 20th century, which coincides with Bartholomew’s
entrance into the profession, and he serves as a good case study for urban planning of the period.
Bartholomew entered the city planning profession in 1912 with the firm of E.P. Goodrich as a
city planning engineer. Goodrich would later partner with the firm of George Ford to plan
Newark, New Jersey in 1913. In 1914 Ford and Goodrich left Newark to work on other projects,
leaving Bartholomew to finish the plan. The Newark plan commission hired Bartholomew as the
first full time city planner in the United States. By 1915, Bartholomew completed the United
States’ first comprehensive city plan. Later that year, at age 26, he took an offer from St. Louis to
be their director of planning. In 1947 he prepared a city plan for St. Louis highlighting
neighborhoods as slums, in danger of blight, or stable. He stayed in St. Louis until 1953 while
also managing his firm Harland Bartholomew and Associates. The firm worked across America
creating city plans. In 1953 Bartholomew sold his interests in the firm to focus on his role as the
chair of the National Planning Committee in Washington D.C., which he had participated in
since 1922. While in D.C., he became close to Dwight Eisenhower and proposed a
transportation plan that planted the seeds of the D.C. Metro train system (Heathcott, 2005;
Heathcott, 2007; Lovelace, 1993; Johnson, 1963).
Prior to the 20th century, the focus of city planning was on the beauty of the city,
monuments, public parks, and invoking a sense of awe. This planning focus was known as city
beautiful or city ascetic. This approach appeared impractical to Bartholomew; for example,
beauty is often considered subjective and the feelings that people have when viewing a city
cannot be measured well. Bartholomew’s planning prioritized function over form, entailed
formal education, focused on economic and social conditions, understood municipal finance, and
cared about automobiles. This newer style of city planning was known as city scientific
(Johnson, 1963).
Presence of Masking in Bartholomew’s Planning
As one of the first city scientific planners, Bartholomew’s planning style was steeped in technical
rationality. He considered the historical background of the city. His plans included the city’s
social and economic characteristics. He measured and analyzed demographics, land use,
transportation, and street use. He made recommendations for financing improvements. He helped
pioneer zoning, and abhorred on-the-spot zoning as the antithesis of the planned city. Within the
city scientific planning paradigm, each step of the planning process was intended to manipulate
society—transportation was to move as many people as possible as quickly as possible, parks
were to give recreation, and neighborhoods were to ensure that residents had access to civic
buildings, shopping, and workplaces. Harland Bartholomew frequently recommended slum
clearance as an efficiency-focused way of rebuilding slum neighborhoods (Lovelace, 1993;
Bartholomew, 1935; Bartholomew, 1963; Johnson, 1964; Heathcott, 2005; Fairfield, 1992).
Bartholomew’s planning divided the city into neighborhood units, based on the work of city
planner Clarence Perry. Ideal neighborhoods were city sub-units with access to schools, civic
buildings, shopping, and places of employment within walking distance. Wide streets bounded
them to direct the flow of automobile traffic past them. Internal streets were for slower traffic to
keep residents safe from cars, and to funnel them to larger streets (Bartholomew, 1951; Perry,
1951; Heathcott, 2011). Bartholomew thought so highly of the neighborhood unit concept that he
abstracted its elements to create a neighborhood quality score, which compared the degree of
conformance of real cities to cities with ideal neighborhoods. He reported that his abstraction
was good at predicting property values, but usually kept scores private to avoid publicly
offending low-scoring cities (Lovelace, 1993). Bartholomew’s planning focus was on economics
and demographics, and he tried to use his planning to secure economic and demographic ends for
the city. He worked systematically and compared reality to a pre-defined ideal. By using
technical-rational planning and focusing on quantitative outcomes, Bartholomew created
conditions to detach himself from the effects that his planning had on black neighborhoods.
Bartholomew dehumanized blacks in St. Louis as economic drains. At several points,
Bartholomew advocated for racial segregation to preserve neighborhood property values. One
source quotes him as admitting that one intent of his planning in St. Louis was to prevent the
migration into “finer residential districts…by colored people.” Another source quotes him saying
that he intended to contain blacks to prevent the spread of neighborhoods “where values have
depreciated [and] homes are either vacant or occupied by colored people or boarding houses”
and thereby prevent the migration of “our people out into the suburban districts.” In Richmond,
Virginia Bartholomew’s planning was described as having “coincided with the prevailing local
attitudes toward the proper social division in cities” and blacks “bear the brunt” of
Bartholomew’s slum clearance. In Armourdale, Kansas Bartholomew’s style was described as
“allowing for a higher degree of social segregation” (Rothstein, 2014; Gordon, 2014; Silver &
Moeser, 1995; Brown, Morris & Taylor, 2009; Heathcott, 2005a; Bartholomew, 1927).
Bartholomew was well versed in laws surrounding urban planning—he knew how planning
was legally justified, how planning could and could not be used to segregate, and for what
purposes government could use planning to acquire land (Bartholomew, 1948). He authored
Chapter 353 of the Missouri Constitution, which created urban redevelopment corporations. This
law gave corporations tax abatements when developing blighted neighborhoods as well as the
legal power to take property that had been declared blighted (Lovelace, 1963). Bartholomew
knew the laws surrounding city planning and that his was legal—as was much of the
discrimination that has taken place in the United States. The legal status of Bartholomew’s
planning does not excuse its discrimination, but it can explain one way in which it was masked.
Adams and Balfour (2014) suggest that the medical subtext of describing neighborhoods as
blighted implies the need for experts to find and remove disease and the ‘infected’ populations
causing it. Early twentieth century viewpoints saw slums and blight as an inherent problem of
blackness (Rothstein, 2014; Gordon, 2014; Lai, 2014; O’Hara, 2011; Bartholomew, 1941;
Fullilove, 2001; Stone, 2012). Furthermore, Bartholomew mostly discussed urban renewal in lieu
of slum clearance, focusing on the city at large rather than specific neighborhoods. With his
references to the need for urban renewal and his regular use of blight metaphors, masking
euphemisms were present in Bartholomew’s planning.
Despite Bartholomew’s discrimination, his legal knowledge, his use of euphemisms, and his
technical-rational methods, Bartholomew’s planning was not motivated by racial discrimination
as much as much it was motivated economics. Although discriminatory, the quantity of his
comments about race and segregation pale in comparison to his discussions of neighborhood tax
contributions (Bartholomew, 1914-1929; Bartholomew, 1914-1929a; Bartholomew, 1935:
Gordon, 2014; Lovelace, 1993; Heathcott, 2008; Heathcott, 2005). Bartholomew discussed the
bad living conditions in slums much more often than he discussed their race (Bartholomew,
1922; Bartholomew, 1920a). When Bartholomew did discuss race, it was usually in the context
of preserving neighborhoods. More than discriminating, Bartholomew tried to help St. Louis
thrive. More than trying to disadvantage blacks, Bartholomew recommended slum clearance to
gain advantage for Saint Louis. He was not motivated to fix the conditions of slums to create a
more equitable city for slum residents—he was motivated to clear slums and convert them to
more economical use to help the city at large.
As a city planner in the early to mid-twentieth century, Bartholomew’s job was to further the
social and economic needs of the city (Fairfield, 1992). He wanted the city to be financially
solvent, healthy, safe, and populated. Using technical rationality, he identified the problems of
the city as economic surplus populations. He recommended slum clearance, and convinced
others with euphemisms of urban renewal and blight. Using his legal knowledge, he devised
ways to begin slum clearance. Motivated by the moral inversion to do good, Bartholomew
created victims of slum clearance.
People committing administrative evil do not see themselves as committing evil acts—often
they see themselves as helping. Administrative evil resembles professionals doing what is
expected. By creating neighborhood maps, calculating neighborhood tax contributions, citing
public health concerns, noting population changes, and then advocating for slum clearance,
Bartholomew was doing what was expected of a city scientific planner. He concluded that the
most efficient way of improving St. Louis was destroying black neighborhoods and starting over.
The Victims of Slum Clearance
In the years following Bartholomew’s recommendations for slum clearance, St. Louis displaced
at least 70,000 mostly black residents. 16,000 of those came from the Mill Creek neighborhood;
others, from parts of the city identified as slums or deindustrialized (Gordon, 2014;
Bartholomew, 1914-1929b). The negative externalities that slum clearance policy created for
slum residents were hardly accounted for—less than a quarter received relocation assistance
(Gordon, 2014). In solving the externalities that slums created for the city, a new set of
externalities were created for slum residents that were not addressed.
After slum clearance, black communities with strong social ties disintegrated and residents
scattered (Gordon, 2014; Alkadry & Blessett, 2010). Hundreds of black businesses and religious
institutions were destroyed (Heathcott & Murphy, 2005). Bartholomew’s attitude on slums in St.
Louis stayed relevant to St. Louis urban planning into 1975. Then, planners continued the bad
treatments of slum neighborhoods by recommending that they be allowed to decline without
intervention—a policy of “benign neglect” (Cooper-McCann, 2016).
Some displaced residents were pushed into segregated communities outside of the urban core
(Rothstein, 2014; Gordon, 2014). Twelve thousand residents, because they could not afford new
housing, were forced into segregated public housing like Pruitt-Igoe (Rothstein, 2014; Aoki,
1992). That housing complex, planned for integration but segregated as a consequence of white
deurbanization, became known for crime, poverty, low quality building materials, and the death
of modernism in city planning (Grimshaw, 2011; Bristol, 1991). In 1970, the United States
Commission on Civil rights declared St. Louis’s slum clearance program nothing more than an
“evasion of responsibility” and “a race clearing program” (USCCR, 1970). Slum clearance
destroyed communities, displaced residents, and provided inadequate aid for relocation. In the
name of economy and urban renewal, black residents were made to emigrate.
Displacement seems to fall closer to evil than it does the inconsequential lie. Rubenstein
(1983) and Arendt (1963) point out that in firmly established acts of historical evil, displacement
and segregation hold places on the road to genocide. Bartholomew’s actions never amounted to
genocide nor did they aspire to, but the displacement of surplus populations certainly lends itself
to defining action as evil. Furthermore, Fredrickson’s (2015) addition of weight to equity
concerns has a place in defining Bartholomew’s actions—St. Louis’s surplus population was
black, historical victims of inequity in St. Louis and the United States. While Bartholomew’s
actions were not the greatest of all evils, it is not difficult to imagine them crossing the hazy line
that separates immorality from evil. Because Bartholomew’s recommendations were masked by
moral inversion and other factors, if his actions were evil it is not far-fetched to characterize
them as administrative evil.
Conclusion
Even today, municipalities assemble and clear private parcels to enable economic development
and a more efficient city. Some might argue that this is necessary for a city’s growth, that urban
development will not occur but for the assembly of large parcels, and that in modern times urban
development does not happen without this municipal participation. If that is the case, the evils of
the past must still be avoided.
City planning has a dark history. To their credit, many planning practitioners acknowledge
the past, and steps have been taken to transform the discipline. Today city planning takes a
broader approach than it once did and considers human resources development, mixed income
housing, mixed use neighborhoods, and equitable transportation. Moreover, if evil can be
avoided, development itself can be a good. But economic approaches to city planning cannot be
allowed to invert the morality of planners such that victimized populations are displaced without
assistance. Care must be taken to ensure that the allure of economy and urban renewal do not
overcome other moral considerations.
Several solutions to the problem of administrative evil have been suggested and could be
applied to city planning. Judith Shklar’s (1982) concept of “putting cruelty first” is an approach
that presumes that the public at large is willing to prevent the most extravagant instances of evil
if they are willing to accept a public ethic that prioritizes avoiding cruelty. H. George
Fredrickson (2002) points out that some cultures have selected administrators on the basis of
their conformance to moral virtues and ability to embody correct social roles.
Others point to the power of democratic deliberation to involve surplus groups whose views
might otherwise be ignored (Adams & Balfour, 2014; Stone, 2012), though such approaches do
not take into account that administrative evil is masked and may be so even during inclusive
deliberation. The results of inclusive democratic deliberation may be collective consensus, but
that consensus may still be aimed at a rationally argued for evil. Certainly, giving those that slum
clearance displaced a greater voice in the process could have alleviated their suffering—in 1973
St. Louis, public participation prevented a planning policy of ‘benign neglect’ from becoming
official policy (Cooper-McCann, 2016)—but on issues involving groups outside of the
community, collective consensus advocating for evil may still be reached.
This paper advocates that a solution for dealing with the problem of administrative evil is to
lionize ‘bureaucratic courage’ in public administration education. Some argue that historical
practitioners of administrative evil did not show courage in the face of evil (Arendt, 1963). This
paper defines bureaucratic courage as: when an administrator, during their day to day work,
consciously chooses to commit acts of heroic good. By lionizing bureaucratic courage, it can be
brought to the attention of future practitioners that even mundane bureaucratic action can have
moral consequences. Consider the case of Chiune Sugihara—during the Holocaust, this Japanese
diplomat signed thousands of visas for Jewish people trying to escape Europe. In defiance of his
superiors, Sugihara worked tirelessly signing visas between July 31 and August 28, 1940. His
visas allowed 6,000 people to escape Europe. It is estimated that their descendants number
between 40,000 and 100,000. Sugihara, through the simple act of signing papers, saved
thousands of lives (“Sugihara’s List,” 2013).
Sugihara disobeyed his government, but Rosemary O’Leary (2014) points out several other
examples of bureaucratic valor from which case studies may be drawn. In addition to
disobedience, O’Leary profiles several other archetypes of bureaucratic valor: the lawsuit
dissenter, the transparency dissenter, the media dissenter, the rule-skirting dissenter, the whistle-
blowing dissenter, the networking dissenter, the lobbying dissenter, and the ‘play dumb’
dissenter. Case studies of each type should be taught to students during public administration
education, when their actions were able to prevent evil in public administration. One pattern
among practitioners of bureaucratic valor, and especially the whistle-blower, is that dissent
harms careers when managers refuse to incorporate it. To teach in good faith, public
administration education must include the reality that preventing evil can be damaging to careers
and is still worthwhile.
Prudent solutions to administrative evil will combine these approaches. The consequences of
administrative evil can be so great that multiple approaches seem most productive. The
cultivation of a liberal society that abhors cruelty will help lessen administrative evil, as will
bureaucrats chosen for their virtue, as will inclusive and earnest democratic deliberation, as will
a focus on the study of practitioners of bureaucratic courage. Public administration must consider
many approaches to alleviate the harsh consequences of administrative evil.
Today’s administrative evil is also masked. What appears to be a professional doing his job
may only be understood as evil when divorced from time and culture. Technical rationality
cannot be put back to bed, and some aspects of it can be desirable when applied properly. The
evils that it allows must be abated. Ethics must be reinforced as a priority in public
administration education, and arguments in favor of ethical public administration must be
stronger if they can ever hope to overcome administrative evil. Arguments from morality will at
times have to overcome arguments motivated from technical rationality.
References
Adams, G. & Balfour, D. (2007). Leadership, administrative evil, and the ethics of
incompetence: Lessons from Katrina and Iraq. Leading the Future of the Public Sector: The
Third Transatlantic Dialogue.
—. (2008). ‘Expiating evil’: Authors’ response. Public Administration, 86(40).
—. (2014). Unmasking Administrative Evil, Fourth Edition. Armonk, New York: M.E. Sharpe,
Inc.
—. (2015) The dynamics of administrative evil in organizations. In C. Jurkiewicz (Ed.), The
Foundations of Organizational Evil. New York, NY: Routledge.
Adams, G. & Zanetti, L. (2000). In service of the leviathan: Democracy, ethics, and the potential
for administrative evil in the new public management. Administrative Theory and Praxis,
22(3).
Adams, G. (2011). Reply to Professor Koven. Public Integrity, 14(1).
—. (2011a). The problem of administrative evil in a culture of technical rationality, Public
Integrity 13(3).
Adams, G., Balfour, D., & Reed, G. (2006). Abu Ghraib, Administrative evil, and moral
inversion: The value of ‘putting cruelty first.’ Public Administration Review, 66(5).
Alkadry, M. & Blessett, B. (2010). Aloofness or dirty hands? Administrative culpability in the
making of the second ghetto. Administrative Theory & Praxis, 32(4).
Anechiarico, F. (2016). Introduction: what’s corrupt? In F. Anechiarico Legal but Corrupt: A
New Perspective on Public Ethics. Landham, MD: Lexington Books.
Aoki, K. (1992). Race, space, and place: The relation between architectural modernism, post-
modernism, urban planning, and gentrification. Fordham Urban Law Journal 20.
Arendt, H. (1963). Eichmann in Jerusalem: A report on the banality of evil. New York NY:
Viking Press.
Balf, M. (2016). Why did U.S. Healthcare professionals become involved in torture during the
war on terror? Journal of Bioethical Inquiry, 13(3).
Balfour, D. (1997). Historiography of the holocaust: A cautionary tale for public administration.
The American Review of Public Administration, 27(2).
Barth, T. (2010). Crisis management in the Catholic church: Lessons for public administrators.
Public Administration Review, 70(5).
Bartholomew, H. (1914-1929). City planning in Newark, New Jersey. For American Magazine.
Washington University Special Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection,
Series 10 Box 1 Folder 1.
—. (1914-1929a). To rebuild our cities. Washington University Special Archives, Harland
Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box 1 Folder 2.
—. (1914-1929b). A model housing plan for the district east of grand avenue. Washington
University Special Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box
1 Folder 2.
—. (1920). How Adoption of a zoning plan will affect St. Louis. Washington University Special
Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box 1 Folder 2.
—. (1920a). The case for stringent regulations on building heights in smaller cities. Washington
University Special Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box
1 Folder 2.
—. (1922). The prevention of economic waster by city planning. Washington University Special
Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box 1 Folder 2.
—. (1935). Official city plans obtain new importance. For Civil Engineering. Washington
University Special Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box
1 Folder 2.
—. (1937). A letter concerning urban decentralization. Washington University Special Archives,
Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box 1 Folder 2.
—. (1937a). Need for and some and some practical methods of rezoning urban areas. Washington
University Special Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box
1 Folder 2.
—. (1941). Can home environment be protected? Better Homes and Gardens. Washington
University Special Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 10 Box
1 Folder 2
—. (1948). Discussing Lincolnwood Cir. Ct. 47C 13540. Washington University Special
Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 11.
—. (1951). The plan-its: Preparation, Composition, and form. American planning and civil
annual.
—. (1963). Parks and recreation plan for Albuquerque-Bernalillo County, New Mexico.
Washington University Special Archives, Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection,
Series 8 Sub-Series 4 Box Volume 1 Folder 1.
—. (2003). The American city. Vital Speeches of the day, 7(2).
Bauman, Z. (1989). Modernity and the Holocaust. Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press.
Berry, E. (2005). Divided over diversity: Political discourse in a Chicago neighborhood. City and
Community 4(2).
Boedy, M. (2015). The evil in technical communication: Katz, Ward, Moore, and overnaming.
Journal of Technical Writing and Communication, 45(3).
Bolin, B., Grineski, S. & Collins, T. (2005). The geography of despair: Environmental racism
and the making of South Phoenix, Arizona, USA. Human Ecology Review, 12(2).
Bristol, K. (1991). The Pruitt-Igoe myth. Journal of Architectural Education, 44(3).
Brown, J. (2005). A tale of two visions: Harland Bartholomew, Robert Moses, and the
development of the American Freeway. Journal of Planning History, 4(1).
Brown, J., Morris, E., & Taylor, B. (2009). Planning for cars in cities: Planners, engineers, and
freeways in the 20th century. Journal of the American Planning Association, 75(2).
Chwastiak, M. (2001). Taming the untamable: Planning, programming, and budgeting and the
normalization of war. Accounting Organizations and Society, 26(6).
Cooper-McCann, P. (2016). The trap of: Lessons from the ‘Team Four plan.’ Journal of Planning
History, 15(2).
Dillard, J., Ruchala, L., & Yuthas, K. (2005). Enterprise resource planning systems: A physical
manifestation of administrative evil. International Journal of Accounting Information
Systems, 6(2).
Dillard, J. & Ruchala, L. (2005). The rules are no game: From instrumental rationality to
administrative evil. Accounting, Auditing, & Accountability Journal, 18(5).
Derthick, M. (2015). Lawyers’ Ethics in Decline. In C. Jurkiewicz (Ed.), The Foundations of
Organizational Evil. New York, NY: Routledge.
Fainstein, S. (2005). Cities and diversity: Should we want it? Can we plan for it? Urban Affairs
Review, 41(1).
Fairfield, J. (1992). Alienation of social control: The Chicago sociologists and the origins of
urban planning. Planning Perspectives, 7(4).
Fischler, R. (1998). The metropolitan dimension of early zoning. Journal of the American
Planning Association, 64(2).
Fullilove, M. (2001). Root shock: The consequences of African American dispossession. Journal
of Urban Health: Bulletin of the New York Academy of Medicine, 78(1).
Fredrickson, H.G. (2002). Confucius and the Basis of Moral Bureaucracy. Administration &
Society, 33(6).
Fredrickson, H.G. (2015). Evil in Public Administration: A Contrary Perspective. In C.
Jurkiewicz (Ed.), The Foundations of Organizational Evil. New York, NY: Routledge.
Gordon, C. (2014). Mapping Decline: St. Louis and the Fate of the American City. Philadelphia
PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Granfield, R. & Koenig, T. (2003). It’s hard to be a human being and a lawyer: Young attorneys
and the confrontation with ethical ambiguity in legal practice. West Virginia Law Review 105.
Grimshaw, M. (2011). Religion, Terror, and the end of the postmodern: Rethinking the responses.
International Journal of Baudrillard Studies, 3(11).
Heathcott, J. & Murphy, M. (2005). Corridors of flight, zones of renewal: Industry, planning, and
policy in the making of metropolitan St. Louis, 1940-1980. Journal of Urban History, 31(2).
Heathcott, J. (2005). ‘The whole city is our laboratory’: Harland Bartholomew and the
production of urban knowledge. Journal of Planning History, 4(4).
—. (2005a). Modelling the urban future: Planning, slums, and the seduction of growth in St.
Louis, 1940-1950. Planning Perspectives, 20(4).
—. (2005b). Black Archipelago: Politics and Civic Life in the Jim Crow city. Journal of Social
History, 38(2).
—. (2007). Harland Bartholomew, city engineer. In M. Tranel (Ed.), St. Louis Plans: The Ideal
and Real St. Louis. Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press.
—. (2008). The city quietly remade: National programs and local agendas in the movement to
clear the slums, 1942-1952. Journal of Urban History, 34(2).
—. (2011). In the nature of a clinic: The design of early public housing in St. Louis. Journal of
the Society of Architectural Historians, 70(1).
Hoffman, M., Pyne, J., & Gajewski, M. (2012). The ten masks of administrative evil.
Administrative Theory and Praxis, 34(1).
Johnson, N. (1964). Harland Bartholomew: His comprehensive plans and science of planning.
Dissertation, University of Pennsylvania. Washington University Special Archives, Harland
Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 9, Box 1, Folder 3.
Jurkiewicz, C., & Grossman, M. (2015). Evil at Work. In C. Jurkiewicz (Ed.), The Foundations
of Organizational Evil. New York, NY: Routledge.
Kanovsky, H. (2015). HUD’s general counsel reflects on the department’s fifty-year history.
Journal of Affordable Housing, 24(1).
King, M.L. (1963). Letter from a Birmingham jail.
Koven, S. (2011). Revisiting administrative evil. Public Integrity, 14(1).
Lai, C. (2014). The racial triangulation of space: The case of urban renewal in San Francisco’s
Fillmore District. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 102(1).
Lee, H. (2000). The meaning of blight: A survey of statutory and case law. Real Property,
Probate, and Trust Issues, 35(2).
Lipman, P. (2009). The cultural politics of mixed-income schools and housing: A racialized
discourse of displacement, exclusion, and control. Anthropology and Education Quarterly,
40(3).
Lopez, R. (2009) Public health, the APHA, and urban renewal. American Journal of Public
Health, 99(9).
—. (2012). Poster for housing and health. American Journal of Public Health, 102(8).
Lovelace, E. (1993). Harland Bartholomew and his Contributions to American City Planning.
Urbana IL: Board of Trustees, University of Illinois.
Marcuse, P. (1997). The enclave, the citadel, and the ghetto: What has changed in the post-
Fordist U.S. city. Urban Affairs Review, 22(2).
Molina, A. (2015). Public administration, market values & the public interest: A Kohlbergian
perspective. Public Administration Quarterly, 39(3).
O’Hara, S.P. (2011). ‘The very model of urban decay: Outsiders’ narratives of industry and urban
decline in Gary, Indiana. Journal of Urban History, 37(2).
O’Leary, R. (2014). The ethics of dissent: Managing guerrilla government. Thousand Oaks, CA:
CQ Press.
Perry, C. (1951). The neighborhood Unit. Neighborhood and Community Planning 7.
Quill, L. (2014). Should a communitarian ethic be taught? Society, 51(4).
Rothstein, R. (2014, October 15). The making of Ferguson: Public policy at the root of its
troubles. Economic Policy Institute.
Rubenstein, R. (1983). The age of triage: Fear and hope in an overcrowded world. Boston MA:
Beacon Press
Riley, R. (1926-1964). Letter to Kankakee Illinois. Washington University Special Archives,
Harland Bartholomew and Associates Collection, Series 11 Sub-Series 1 Box 1.
Samier, E. (2008). The problem of passive evil in educational administration: Moral implications
of doing nothing. International Studies in Education Administration, 36(1).
Sandoval, J.S. (2004). Understanding the demographic hurdles to revitalizing Saint Louis. Saint
Louis University Public Law Review, 33.
Schindler, S. (2015). Discrimination and segregation through physical design of the built
environment. The Yale Law Journal, 124(6).
Shklar, J. (1964). Legalism: Laws, morals, and political trials. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
—. (1982). Putting cruelty first. Daedalus, 111(3).
Silver, C. & Moeser, J. (1995). The separate city: Black communities in the urban south, 1940-
1968. Lexington KY: The University Press of Kentucky.
Sugihara’s List. (2013). World War II, 28(1).
Stone, D. (2012). Policy paradox: The art of political decision making. New York, NY: W. W.
Norton & Company Inc.
Tillotson, A. (2014). Race, risk, and real estate: The federal housing administration and black
homeownership in the post world war II home ownership state. DePaul Journal for Social
Justice, 8(1).
Tschundi, F. (2008). A comment on Adams and Balfour: Dignity violations, an alternative view
of ‘administrative evil.’ Public Administration, 86(4).
USCCR (United States Commission on Civil Rights). (1970). Hearing before the United States
commission on civil rights. Hearing held in St. Louis, Missouri, January 14-17, 1970.
Washington, D.C.: U. S. Government Printing Office.