ChapterPDF Available

The language organism: The Leiden theory of language evolution

Authors:
9
The
language
Organism:
The
leiden
Theory
of
Language Evolution*
1.
language
is an Organism
George van Driem
Leiden University
Language
is
a symbiotic organism. Language
is
neither an organ,
nor
is
it
an
instinct. In
the
past
two
and
a half million years, we have
acquired a genetic predisposition
to
serve as the
host
for this
symbiont. Like any true symbiont, language enhances
our
reproductive fitness. We
cannot
change the grammatical structure
of
language
or
fundamentally change its lexicon by
an
act
of
will, even
though
we might be able
to
coin a
new
word
or
aid
and
abet the
popularity
of
a
turn
of
phrase. Language changes,
but
not
because
we
want
it to.
We
are inoculated
with
our
native language in
our
The following
is
a synoptic statement on the Leiden theory
of
language
evolution which I presented in a talk
at
the
2nd
Workshop
and
Language
Acquisition, Change
and
Emergence
at
the City University
of
Hong
Kong on
24
November
2001
at
the kind invitation
of
Bill Wang. The Leiden theory
of
language emergence
is
presented in greater detail in my
handbook
(van
Driem, 2001b).
331
332 Language Acquisition, Change and Emergence
infancy. Like any other life form, language consists
self-replicating core.
The
units
of
this self-replicating core are
mt:mef:<
and
their neural correlates.
The
Leiden theory
of
language evolution was developed in
early
1980s
by
Kortlandt
(1985)
and
is
further developed in
handbook
of the greater
Himalayan
region (van Driem, 2001
Meaning
is
the basis
of
language.
The
nature
of
understood
in terms
of
the intuitionist set theory
or
mathematics developed by L.E.J. Brouwer,
is
a function
neuroanatomy
and
their behavior as units in the
Darwinian
of
neuronal
group
selection.
The
Leiden conception of
evolution provides a linguistically informed definition
of
the
(van Driem,
2000a,
2000b,
2001a). Previous characterizations
the meme by Dawkins (1976), Delius (1991)
and
Blackmore (199
fall
short
of
identifying
the
fecund high-fidelity replicators
extra-genetic evolution.
The
Leiden
approach
to
linguistic forms
vehicles for the
reproduction
of
meaningful elements in the ·
brain
differs fundamentally from
both
the functionalist
or
structuralist conception
of
language, whereby linguistic forms
seen as instruments used
to
convey meaningful elements,
and
formalist
or
generative
approach,
whereby linguistic forms
treated as
abstract
structures
which
can
be filled
with
·
elements.
Naming
and
syntax
can
be
shown
to
be
two
faces
of
same phenomenon.
2.
A Meme
is
a Meaning, Not a Unit
of
Imitation
What
precisely
is
a meme?
The
Oxford
English Dictionary
meme as
'an
element
of
culture
that
may
be considered
to
be
on
by non-genetic means, esp. imitation'. This
is
a
lexicographer's recapitulation
of
Richard
Dawkins'
original
com~tge
I
think
that
a
new
kind
of
replicator has recently
emerged
on
this very planet.
It
is
staring us in the face.
It
is
still in its infancy, still drifting a
bout
in its
The Language Organism: The Leiden Theory
of
Language Evolution 333
primaeval soup,
but
already it
is
achieving evolutionary
change
at
a rate
that
leaves
the
old gene
panting
far
behind.
The
new
soup
is
the
soup
of
human
culture. We
need a
name
for the
new
replicator, a
noun
that
conveys
the idea
of
a
unit
of
cultural transmission,
or
a unit of
imitation. (1976: 206).
This
Oxford
definition
of
the meme
is
incomplete
and
linguistically
uninformed. Charles
Darwin
came closer
to
the Leiden definition of
the meme
when
he
wrote
that
'the
survival
or
preservation
of
certain
favoured
words
in the struggle for existence
is
natural
selection'
(1871,
I:
60-61).
By
contrast, Susan Blackmore's memetics
is
essentially a linguistically naive view:
Whether
a particular
sound
is
copied because it
is
easy
to
remember, easy
to
produce, conveys a pleasant
emotion,
or
provides useful information, does
not
matter.
...
There
is
no
such
problem
as the symbolic
threshold
with
the memetic
theory
of
language.
The
critical step was the beginning
of
imitation
....
Once
imitation evolved, something like
two
and
a half
to
three million years ago, a second replicator, the meme,
was born. A spoken grammatical language resulted
from
the success
of
copyable sounds. (1999:
103-104,
107)
,,,L.au;e.u''"'"
is
more
than
just copyable sounds. A unit
of
imitation
is
a
and
a mime does
not
meet the criteria
of
fecundity,
replication
and
longevity required
to
qualify as a
life-sustaining replicator. There
is
an
essential difference
between pre-linguistic mimes, such as
the
rice washing
of
Japanese
ues,
and
post-linguistic mimes, such as music, clothing
and
dancing styles,
which
are able
to
evoke a myriad
of
in the
realm
of
memes. However, the theme
of
!'{,,,_~,~''"~
s
9th
symphony
is
a mime,
not
a meme.
Language exists
through
meaning.
The
Leiden school defines
as meanings in the linguistic sense. Grammatical memes, i.e.
334 Language Acquisition, Change and Emergence
the meanings of grammatical categories, are the systemic memes
any given language
and
are demonstrably language-specific.
meanings
of
words, morphemes
and
fixed idiomatic expressions
lexical memes. Some lexical memes are systemic
and
structural
given language. Some are free-wheeling
and
parasitic. Some
an
intermediate status. The idea
that
America
is
one nation
God, indivisible with liberty
and
justice for all,
is
not
a meme. It
syntactically articulate idea composed
of
a number of
co1rrstttu:
lexical
and
grammatical memes,
and
this idea
and
its
r-.-
..
,n~t-;..,;,
parts are subject
to
Darwinian natural selection.
Researchers in the field
of
Artificial Intelligence fail
to
the problem
of
meaning when they resort
to
the propositional
developed by the English mathematician George Boole.
adequacy
of
this approach
is
claimed as long as the variables
'grounded'.
By
grounding, logicians mean
that
there
ts
determinate way in which variables
or
symbols refer
referents. Yet natural meaning does
not
obey the
Aristotelian logic or Boolean propositional calculus. A
thrives by virtue of its applications, which
cannot
be deduced
its implications. The implications of a meaning must be
nP'~'"'"n'"
its applicability, rather
than
the other way around.
By
conseq
a meaning has the properties
of
a non-constructible set in
mathematical sense.
The behavior of the English meaning open
is
such
that
door is open' can be said
of
a shut
but
unlocked door, in
that
door is
not
locked. Likewise,
of
the same door
it
can be said
'The door is
not
open', for
it
is
shut. It
is
a cop-out
to
polysemy
to
clarify such usages because the meaning of English
remains unchanged in either case. The same situation can
truthfully referred
to
by a linguistic meaning
as
well as by
contradiction. Yet there
is
no
way
of
formalising a
traditional logic because
of
the principle
of
the excluded
uu•.1u""'
tertium non datur. This principle, which dates back
to
renders classical logic a powerful tool
and
simultaneously
classical logic a mode of thought which
is
at
variance
with
the
of natural language. The insight
that
meaning operates
ac<~ordillL~
The Language Organism: The Leiden Theory
of
Language Evolution 335
mathematics
of
non-constructibJe sets was set forth by Frederik
Kortlandt in 1985 in a seminal article entitled
'On
the parasitology
of non-constructible sets'. The insight
that
human
language operates
of
the principle of the excluded middle was
by the Dutch mathematician L.E.J. Brouwer when he
intuitionist set theory in the first quarter
of
the
20th
Brouwer rejected the principle of the excluded middle for
and
went
as far as
to
warn
mankind
that
-mediated ideas
and
language itself were inherently
Tertium Datur
fact
that
meanings have the nature
of
non-constructible sets
not
mean
that
meanings are fuzzy. Rather, meanings
to
sets which are indeterminate in
that
there
is
no a
way of saying whether a particular referent can
or
cannot be
as
a member of a set.
If
a homeless person in Amsterdam
a cardboard
box
a house,
that
box
becomes a referent
of
the
house by his
or
her very speech act. The first bear most
are likely
to
see today
is
a cuddly doll from a toy store
and
a member
of
a species of the Ursidae family. Errett Bishop, chief
u"'"''"'"u
of
the school of constructivist mathematics which grew
intuitionist set theory, also rejected the principle
of
the
middle.
He
observed
that
'a
choice function exists in
mathematics because it is implied by the very meaning
existence' (1967: 9). Even though Willard Quine adhered
to
the
of
the excluded middle throughout his life because of its
as
'a
norm
governing efficient logical regimentation', he
on<~edled
that
this Aristotelian tenet was
'not
a fact of life',
and
was
fact 'bizarre' (1987: 57).
Classical logical analysis requires the identifiability
of
u•;o,uauH::
elements as belonging
to
the same set. In the case
of
extensional definition, it presupposes a sufficient degree of
336 Language Acquisition, Change and Emergence
similarity between the indicated
and
the intended elements. In the
case of
an
intentional definition, it presupposes the applicability of a
criterion, which depends
on
the degree
of
similarity between the
indicated property
and
the perceptible characteristics of the intended
objects. The constructibility
of
a set is determined by
identifiability of its elements. Language does
not
generally
this fundamental requirement
of
logic.
Ever since Gottlob Frege, logicians have focussed
on
problems
of
truth
in their attempt
to
understand meaning
and
language,
this approach has been inherently flawed from the very outset.
Frege
had
defined a Gedanke
as
something which
can
be subject
logical tests
of
truth
(1918: 64), he was inexorably led
to
·
grammatical sentences in language which cannot be reinterpreted
logical prepositions
and
therefore embody
no
Gedanke (1923: 3
The inadequacy
of
classical logic for coming
to
terms
with
uu)'.uJL~uc:
meaning underlies the failure
of
both
the earlier
and
the
Wittgenstein to understand the workings
of
language. Instead,
remained perplexed by the nature
of
linguistic meaning
lUJ.uLtl!.lJLu
his life and saw the whole of philosophy
as
a battle against
bewitching
of
reason by language (1953: 47).
The nature
of
meaning is a direct function
of
its
microanatomy
and
the way neurons branch
and
establish their
of
circuitry in
our
brains. The parasitic nature of
.,·
..
F.
..... o
.........
au
mediated meanings does
not
mean
that
there is no such thing
invariant meanings
or
Gesamtbedeutungen of individual lexical
grammatical categories within a given speech community.
meanings are functionally equivalent within a speech
and can be empirically ascertained through Wierzbickian
semantic analysis. Language began
to
live in
our
brains
as
organismal memetic symbiont when these brains became host
to
first replicating meaning. The difference between a meaning
signal such as a mating call or the predator-specific alarm calls
vervet monkeys is
that
a meaning can be used for the sake
argument, has the properties of a non-constructible set
and
has
temporal dimension.
The Language Organism:
1;he
Leiden Theory
of
Language Evolution
337
4.
Syntax
is
a Consequence of Meaning
Syntax arose from meaning. Syntax did
not
arise from combining
labels
or
names for things. Syntax arose when a signal was first split.
Hugo Schuchardt
had
already argued
that
the first utterance arose
from the splitting of a holistic primaeval utterance,
not
from the
concatenation
of
grunts
or
names.
He
argued
that
the first
word
was
abstracted from a primordial sentence
and
that
the first sentences
did
not
arise from the concatenation
of
words (1919a, 1919b).
First-order predication arose automatically when the first signal was
split. For example, the splitting
of
a signal for 'The baby has fallen
out of the tree' yields the meanings
'That
which has fallen
out
of the
tree
is
our
baby'
and
'What
the baby has done
is
to fall
out
of
the
tree'.
Maria
Ujhelyi has
considhed
long-call structures in apes in
this regard. The ability
to
intentionally deceive
is
a capacity
that
we
share
with
other apes
and
even with monkeys. In using an utterance
for the sake of argument, the first wordsmith went beyond the
capacity
to
deceive.
He
or
she used
an
utterance in good faith,
splitting a signal so
that
meanings arose, yielding a projection of
reality with a temporal dimension.
Since when has language resided in our brains? The idea
that
the
Upper Palaeolithic Horizon is the terminus ante quem for the
emergence of language dates back
at
least
to
the 1950s. The sudden
emergence of art, ritual symbolism, glyphs, rock paintings and
animal
and
venus figurines 60,000
to
40,000 years ago set the world
ablaze with new colours and forms. The collective neurosis
of
ritual
activity
is
an
unambiguous manifestation
of
linguistically mediated
thought. However, rudimentary stages
of
language existed much
earlier.
What
the Upper Palaeolithic Horizon offers
is
the first clear
evidence
of
the existence of God. God
is
the quintessential prototype
of the non-constructible set because it can mean anything. This
makes God the meme almighty. The British anthropologist Verrier
Elwin quotes the Anglican bishop Charles Gore:
I once
had
a talk
with
Bishop Gore and told him
that
I
had
doubts about, for example, the
truth
of the Bible,
338 Language Acquisition, Change and Emergence
the Virgin Birth
and
the Resurrection. "All this, my
dear boy,
is
nothing. The real snag in the Christian, or
any other religion,
is
the belief in God.
If
you can
swallow God, you can swallow anything." (1964: 99)
The brain of
our
species has grown phenomenally
as
compared
with
that
of gracile australopithecines or modern bonobos, even
when we make allowances for
our
overall increase in body size.
Initially the availability of a large brain provided the green pastures
in which language could settle
and
flourish. Once meanings began to
reproduce within the brain, hominid brain evolution came to be
driven by language
at
least as radically as any symbiont determines
the evolution
of
its host species. Language engendered a sheer
tripling
of
brain volume from a mean brain size
of
440
cc
to
1400 cc
in just two
and
a half million years. At the same time, the
increasingly convoluted topography of
our
neocortex expanded the
available surface area
of
the brain.
The role
of
innate vs. learned behavior in the emergence of
language
is
an artificial controversy when viewed in light
of
the
relationship between a host and a memetic symbiont lodged in its
bloated brain.
In
the
past
2.5 million years,
our
species has evolved
in such a way as to acquire the symbiont readily from earliest
childhood.
Our
very perceptions
and
conceptualization
of
reality are
shaped and moulded by the symbiont
and
the constellations of
neuronal groups which language sustains
and
mediates.
References
Bishop, Errett. (1967) Foundations
of
Constructive Analysis.
New
York:
McGraw-Hill.
Blackmore, Susan. (1999) The Meme Machine. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Darwin, Sir Charles Robert. (1871) The Descent
of
Man and Selection in
Relation to Sex
(2
v9ls.). London:
John
Murray.
The Language Organism: The Leiden Theory
of
Language Evolution 339
Dawkins, Richard. (1976) The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Delius, Juan D. (1991) The nature of culture. In Marian Stamp Dawkins,
Timothy R., Halliday and Richard Dawkins (Eds.) The Tinbergen Legacy
(pp. 75-99). London: Chapman and Hall.
van Driem, George. (2000a) De evolutie van
taal:
Beginselen van
de
biologische
taalwetenschap. Public lecture delivered in Paradiso, Amsterdam, 16 April
2000.
--.
(2000b) The language organism: A symbiotic theory
of
language. Paper
presented at the Belgian-Dutch Workshop on the Evolution
of
Language
held
at
the Atomium in Brussels, 17 November 2000.
(2001a) Taal
en
Taalwetenschap. Leiden: Research School
of
Asian,
African and Amerindian Studies
CNWS.
(2001b) Languages
of
the Himalayas:
An
Ethnolinguistic Handbook
of
the Greater Himalayan Region with
an
Introduction to the Symbiotic
Theory
of
Language
(2
vols.). Leiden: Brill.
--.
(Forthcoming) The Language Organism.
Elwin, Verrier. (1964) The Tribal World
of
Verrier Elwin. London: Oxford
University Press.
Frege, Gottlob. (1918) Der Gedanke, eine logische Untersuchung. In Arthur
Hoffmann and
Horst
Engert (Eds.) Beitrage zur Philosophie
des
deutschen
Idealismus (pp. 58-77), 1. Band,
1.
Heft (1918-1919). Erfurt: Verlag der
Keyser'schen Buchhandlung.
--.
(1919) Die Verneinung, eine logische Untersuchung. In Arthur Hoffmann
and
Horst
Engert (Eds.) Beitrage zur Philosophie
des
deutschen
Idealismus (pp. 143-157), 1. Band, 2. Heft (1918-1919). Erfurt: Verlag
der Keyser'schen Buchhandlung.
--.
(1923) Logische Untersuchungen. Dritter Teil: Gedankengefuge. In Arthur
Hoffmann (Ed.) Beitrage zur Philosophie
des
deutschen Idealismus
(pp. 36-51), 3. Band, 1. Heft. Erfurt: Verlag Kurt Stenger.
Kortlandt, Frederik Herman Henri. (1985) A parasitological view of
non-constructible sets. In Pieper and Stickel (Eds.) Studia linguistica
diachronica et synchronica: Werner Winter sexagenario anno
MCMLXXXIII gratis animis
ab
eius collegis, amicis discipulisque oblata
(pp. 477--483). Berlin:
Mouton
de Gruyter.
Quine, Willard Van Orman. (1987) Quiddities:
An
Intermittently Philosophical
Dictionary. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Schuchardt, Hugo. (1919a) Sprachursprung. I (vorgelegt am 17. Juli 1919).
Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften XLII,
716-720.
340 Language Acquisition, Change and Emergence
--.
(1919b) Sprachursprung.
II
(vorgelegt am 30.
Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der
863-869.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig Josef Johann. (1953) [posthumous].
Untersuchungen. London: Basil Blackwell.
. Introduction
10
Taxonomy, Typology and
Historical Linguistics
Merritt
Ruhlen
Stanford University
decade has witnessed a renewed interest in historical
as the various controversies surrounding Amerind,
ostratic,
and
even broader proposed
taxa
well attest. Yet this
renewed interest seems
to
have revealed
as
much the current state
of
confusion within historical linguistics as the validity of any of the
newly proposed families. I will argue here
that
the comparative
method was misunderstood by historical linguists in the twentieth
century, with the result
that
the discovery of new genetic
relationships among languages effectively ground
to
a halt -with
the significant exceptions of the
work
of
Joseph Greenberg and the
Nostraticists.
What
is
equally distressing
is
that
the borders between
three distinct
fields-
taxonomy, typology, and historical linguistics
-have become blurred. Each
of
these fields has its
own
goals and
its
own
methodology,
and
they are
not
the same. This in no way
implies
that
these fields are completely disconnected from one
another. Certainly Greenberg's enormous knowledge of diachronic
typology informed his classification
of
Eurasiatic languages in many
ways, most spectacularly in the explanation
of
the origin of the
341
... One still encounters, for example, statements to the effect that language change is not an instance of Darwinian evolution but 'only' a metaphor, because languages are not organisms; or, conversely, that since language instantiates Darwin's algorithm, it must be categorized as an organism -a virus or symbiont (e.g. Van Driem, 2005). In other words, some crucial components of the conceptual innovation have yet to invade the entire population of linguists; this is different from the situation in biology, where one can nowadays not become a new member of this community without a thorough understanding of population level processes as causally distinct from individual level ones. ...
Article
Full-text available
Conceptual innovations in science (‘paradigm shifts’ in the sense of Kuhn) come with changes in the meaning of basic terminology in that field. Linguistics is no exception. But linguistics is in the peculiar position that it comprises the study of the meaning of linguistic items, and the way these meanings change. Some basic ideas of cognitive semantics, especially the concept of metonymy, shed light on the risk of miscommunication in a scientific field in a period of innovation. Paradoxically, these risks are instantiated in a controversy in the field of linguistics itself that was triggered by the then new, Darwinian understanding of evolution. The paper ends by exploring a recent theoretical innovation (the ‘usage-based’ approach, especially its most recent variants) that holds a promise for overcoming the controversies, provided theoretical linguists accept that terminology also in their own field is to be semantically more precise than in everyday language use.
... Kortlandt (1985 Kortlandt ( , 1998 Kortlandt ( , 2003) and Wiedenhof (1996) conceive language to be a parasite, based on the correct insight that natural meanings have the properties of non-constructible sets in the mathematical sense. Symbiosism , however, distinguishes the mutualist nature of language as such from the workings of individual meanings (van Driem 2001avan Driem , 2001bvan Driem , 2003van Driem , 2004van Driem , 2005 ). Language has greatly augmented our reproductive fitness to the detriment of countless other macroscopic species. ...
Conference Paper
Full-text available
'When I use a word,' Humpty Dumpty said, in rather a scornful tone, 'it means just what I choose it to mean — neither more nor less.' 'The question is,' said Alice, 'whether you can make words mean so many different things.' 'The question is,' said Humpty Dumpty, 'which is to be master — that's all.' Symbiosism is a Darwinian model of language and its emergence. Symbiosism is a variety of Symbiotic Theory, which treats linguistic forms as vehicles for the reproduc- tion of meaningful elements in the hominid brain. The symbiotic view transcends the obsolete discord between the functionalist or European structuralist conception of lan- guage, whereby linguistic forms are seen as instruments used to convey meaningful ele- ments, and the formalist or generative approach, whereby linguistic forms are treated as abstract structures which can be filled with meaningful elements. Symbiotic Theory shows naming and syntax to be two faces of the same phenomenon. Syntax arose from meaning. The first primaeval holistic utterances with a meaning in the linguistic sense inherently constituted a projection of reality with a temporal dimen- sion. First-order predication arose when such a holistic utterance was split. This point of view was argued by Pierre de Maupertuis (1756, III: 444) and Hugo Schuchardt (1919a, 1919b) and contrasts with the naïve view that syntax arose from the concatenation of labels or names. The splitting of a signal for 'The baby has fallen out of the tree' could have yielded meanings such as 'That which has fallen out of the tree is our baby' and 'What the baby has done is to fall out of the tree'. Mária Ujhelyi (1998) has considered long-call structures in apes in this regard. Moreover, Symbiotic Theory operates not on the Oxonian conception of a meme as a 'unit of imitation', but on the Leiden definition of memes as isofunctional neuroana- tomical units corresponding to linguistic signs in the Saussurean sense, corresponding to single morphemes or monomorphemic words. The neuronal correlate of a meaning along with the neuronal representation of its associated phonological form or gramma- tical manifestation is a meme, whereas in Leiden school terminology a unit of imitation is a mime. The symbiotic model of the human mind is based on an understanding of lan-
Book
Compiled in honor and celebration of veteran anthropologist Harold C. Fleming, this book contains 23 articles by anthropologists (in the general sense) from the four main disciplines of prehistory: archaeology, biogenetics, paleoanthropology, and genetic (historical) linguistics. Because of Professor Fleming's major focus on language - he founded the Association for the Study of Language in Prehistory and the journal Mother Tongue - the content of the book is heavily tilted toward the study of human language, its origins, historical development, and taxonomy. Because of Fleming's extensive field experience in Africa some of the articles deal with African topics. This volume is intended to exemplify the principle, in the words of Fleming himself, that each of the four disciplines is enriched when it combines with any one of the other four. The authors are representative of the cutting edge of their respective fields, and this book is unusual in including contributions from a wide range of anthropological fields rather than concentrating in any one of them.
Chapter
Full-text available
This chapter examines the biosemiotic implications of the thesis put forward by C. S. Peirce in 1901 that symbols are living things in more than a metaphorical sense. It argues that this thesis is typical of Peirce’s synechistic approach to scientific inquiry. Peirce did not mean that symbols are biological organisms. Instead, he wanted to convey the insight that they are more than merely similar to organisms, as they share essential features with living beings. Among these features are: Symbols are born (created), survive, but may also die out (become extinct). Like parasites (or symbionts), symbols lead their life in living beings, not only of human, but also of nonhuman nature. Symbols display a certain autonomous, but in a sense vicarious, agency. They spread by self-replication and interpretation. Symbols grow and they have the potential for self-correction against errors, falsity, distortion, and lack of meaning (nonsense). The chapter also examines why Peirce ascribes these characteristics to symbols and not to signs in general.
Article
Full-text available
This paper presents computational experiments that illustrate how one can precisely conceptualize language evolution as a Darwinian process. We show that there is potentially a wide diversity of replicating units and replication mechanisms involved in language evolution. Computational experiments allow us to study systemic properties coming out of populations of linguistic replicators: linguistic replicators can adapt to specific external environments; they evolve under the pressure of the cognitive constraints of their hosts, as well as under the functional pressure of communication for which they are used; one can observe neutral drift; coalitions of replicators may appear, forming higher level groups which can themselves become subject to competition and selection.
Chapter
Full-text available
Niko Tinbergen laid great stress on the essential importance of cultural evolution for the understanding of human behaviour although he never, of course, made it a central subject of his research interests. In a short cautionary note about the future of humanity he wrote for example that ‘our unique position in the modern world is due to the consequences of our cultural evolution, which … has … progressively … superimposed (itself) on our still ongoing genetic evolution’ and that ‘we transfer …, from one generation to the next, not only our genetic heritage but also (our) accumulated non-genetically acquired … experience’ (Tinbergen, 1977, see also Tinbergen, 1976). Niko’s insights into the details of the processes of cultural evolution went much further than his writings reflect, however. A casual but memorable conversation between him and Konrad Lorenz in Stuttgart, Germany in 1959, at which I happened to be present, revealed that clearly. The role of song behaviour as a species-isolating mechanism in some sympatric birds had somehow cropped up. They were considering the selective forces that might have shaped the divergence of song patterns in such situations when Niko raised the important question: Selection of what? Surely not genes since the song of these birds was likely to be learned, not innate.
Book
Full-text available
Humans are extraordinary creatures, with the unique ability among animals to imitate and so copy from one another ideas, habits, skills, behaviours, inventions, songs, and stories. These are all memes, a term first coined by Richard Dawkins in 1976 in his book The Selfish Gene. Memes, like genes, are replicators, and this enthralling book is an investigation of whether this link between genes and memes can lead to important discoveries about the nature of the inner self. Confronting the deepest questions about our inner selves, with all our emotions, memories, beliefs, and decisions, Susan Blackmore makes a compelling case for the theory that the inner self is merely an illusion created by the memes for the sake of replication.
Article
In the current resurgence of interest in the biological basis of animal behavior and social organization, the ideas and questions pursued by Charles Darwin remain fresh and insightful. This is especially true of The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex, Darwin's second most important work. This edition is a facsimile reprint of the first printing of the first edition (1871), not previously available in paperback. The work is divided into two parts. Part One marshals behavioral and morphological evidence to argue that humans evolved from other animals. Darwin shoes that human mental and emotional capacities, far from making human beings unique, are evidence of an animal origin and evolutionary development. Part Two is an extended discussion of the differences between the sexes of many species and how they arose as a result of selection. Here Darwin lays the foundation for much contemporary research by arguing that many characteristics of animals have evolved not in response to the selective pressures exerted by their physical and biological environment, but rather to confer an advantage in sexual competition. These two themes are drawn together in two final chapters on the role of sexual selection in humans. In their Introduction, Professors Bonner and May discuss the place of The Descent in its own time and relation to current work in biology and other disciplines.
Article
Alphabet Altruism Anomaly Artificial Languages Atoms Beauty Belief Classes versus Properties Classes versus Sets Communication Complex Numbers Consonant Clusters Constructivism Copula Creation Decimals and Dimidials Definition Discreteness Etymology Euphemism Excluded Middle Extravagance Fermat's Last Theorem Formalism Freedom Free Will Functions Future Gambling Gender Godel's Theorem Ideas Identity Idiotisms Impredicativity Infinite Numbers Inflection Information Kinship of Words Knowledge Language Drift Language Reform Latin Pronunciation Lines Longitude and Latitude Marks Mathematosis Meaning Mind versus Body Misling Natural Numbers Necessity Negation Paradoxes Phonemes Plurals Predicate Logic Prediction Prefixes Prizes Pronunciation Real Numbers Recursion Redundancy Reference, Reification Rhetoric Semantic Switch Senses of Words Singular Terms Space-Time Syntax Things Tolerance Trinity Truth Type versus Token Units Universal Library Universals Usage and Abusage Use versus Mention Variables Zero Index
Article
Wie das Wort "schön" der Aesthetik und "gut" der Ethik, so weist "wahr" der Logik die Richtung. Zwar haben alle Wissenschaften Wahrheit als Ziel; aber die Logik beschäftigt sich noch in ganz anderer Weise mit ihr. Sie verhält sich zur Wahrheit etwa so, wie die Physik zur Schwere oder zur Wärme. Wahrheiten zu entdecken, ist Aufgabe aller Wissenschaften; der Logik kommt es zu, die Gesetze des Wahrseins zu erkennen.
De evolutie van taal: Beginselen van de biologische taalwetenschap
  • George Van Driem
van Driem, George. (2000a) De evolutie van taal: Beginselen van de biologische taalwetenschap. Public lecture delivered in Paradiso, Amsterdam, 16 April 2000.
The Tribal World of Verrier Elwin
  • Verrier Elwin
Elwin, Verrier. (1964) The Tribal World of Verrier Elwin. London: Oxford University Press.
Studia linguistica diachronica et synchronica: Werner Winter sexagenario anno MCMLXXXIII gratis animis ab eius collegis, amicis discipulisque oblata
  • Frederik Herman Kortlandt
  • Henri
Kortlandt, Frederik Herman Henri. (1985) A parasitological view of non-constructible sets. In Pieper and Stickel (Eds.) Studia linguistica diachronica et synchronica: Werner Winter sexagenario anno MCMLXXXIII gratis animis ab eius collegis, amicis discipulisque oblata (pp. 477--483). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.