ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

This essay – a collection of contributions from 10 scholars working in the field of biosemiotics and the humanities – considers nature in culture. It frames this by asking the question ‘Why does biosemiotics need the humanities?’. Each author writes from the background of their own disciplinary perspective in order to throw light upon their interdisciplinary engagement with biosemiotics. We start with Donald Favareau, whose originary disciplinary home is ethnomethodology and linguistics, and then move on to Paul Cobley’s contribution on general semiotics and Kalevi Kull’s on biosemiotics. This is followed by Cobley (again) with Frederick Stjernfelt who contribute on biosemiotics and learning, then Gerald Ostdiek from philosophy, and Morten Tønnessen focusing upon ethics in particular. Myrdene Anderson writes from anthropology, while Timo Maran and Louise Westling provide a view from literary study. The essay closes with Wendy Wheeler reflecting on the movement of biosemiotics as a challenge, often via the ecological humanities, to the kind of so-called ‘postmodern’ thinking that has dominated humanities critical thought in the universities for the past 40 years. Virtually all the matters gestured to in outline above are discussed in much more satisfying detail in the topics which follow.
How Can the Study of the Humanities Inform the Study
of Biosemiotics?
Donald Favareau
1
&Kalevi Kull
1
&Gerald Ostdiek
1
&Timo Maran
1
&
Louise Westling
1
&Paul Cobley
1
&Frederik Stjernfelt
1
&
Myrdene Anderson
1
&Morten Tønnessen
1
&Wendy Wheeler
1
Received: 11 February 2017 /Accepted: 15 March 2017 / Published online: 8 April 2017
#Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017
Abstract This essay a collection of contributions from 10 scholars working in
the field of biosemiotics and the humanities considers nature in culture. It
frames this by asking the question Why does biosemiotics need the humanities?. Each
author writes from the background of their own disciplinary perspective in order
to throw light upon their interdisciplinary engagement with biosemiotics. We
start with Donald Favareau, whose originary disciplinary home is ethnomethod-
ology and linguistics, and then move on to Paul Cobleys contribution on general
semiotics and Kalevi Kulls on biosemiotics. This is followed by Cobley (again)
with Frederick Stjernfelt who contribute on biosemiotics and learning, then
Gerald Ostdiek from philosophy, and Morten Tønnessen focusing upon ethics
in particular. Myrdene Anderson writes from anthropology, while Timo Maran
and Louise Westling provide a view from literary study. The essay closes with
Wendy Wheeler reflecting on the movement of biosemiotics as a challenge, often
via the ecological humanities, to the kind of so-called postmodernthinking that
has dominated humanities critical thought in the universities for the past 40 years.
Virtually all the matters gestured to in outline above are discussed in much more
satisfying detail in the topics which follow.
Keywords Semiotics .Biosemiotics .Science .Humanities .Anthropology.
Ethnomethodology.Linguistics .Philosophy.Literature .Critical theory .Ethics .
Evolution .Metaphor .Poetry.Learning
Biosemiotics (2017) 10:931
DOI 10.1007/s12304-017-9287-6
*Wendy Wheeler
w.wheeler@londonmet.ac.uk
1
London Metropolitan University, London, UK
Introduction Wendy Wheeler
As is well known, biosemiotics originated in the coming together of humanities insights
into signs and meaning-making with the scientific study of biological life. Quite
separately initially, semioticians in the humanities and biologists in the life sciences
realised that life, right from the beginning, is concerned with the reading and interpre-
tation of phenomena. Just as human communication has aspects which can appear
mechanical (word and idea habitual associations, for example), so biological responses
can appear mechanical similarly. But the idea of information amongst the living cannot
be a mechanical thing. To be alive is to care, or to mind, about survival, reproduction
and the capacity to adapt to change (more often than not from environmental pres-
sures). This means to care about what appears in your world, or, more specifically, your
umwelt. Care, however, is above all a feeling which must, perforce, be made sense of
(or interpreted). But feelings, as the word suggests, arise in enworlded flesh.
In other words, in order to survive and flourish, organisms must have intentional
experience and purposes. These are relations to objects, but not necessarily to things
(Deely 2009b,2015). And while to have a purpose is not necessarily to have that
purpose consciously (as with all organisms, most of human cognition is not self-
conscious), the having of purposes, in which some outcomes are preferred over others,
means that the organism must attach significance to intentional phenomena appearing
in the umwelt. Another way of talking about purposes and significances is simply to
say that organisms simply must be able to make sense of news about those aspects of
their environments which reach them. They must be able to derive meanings from the
phenomena that Bshine forth^for them (phenomenon, from Gk. phainesthai to shine
forth). The world of our senses does not reveal the whole world to us. Even at the level
of simple objects, we sense only what we need to sense to get on with caring about
being. This means that news of the world arrives in the form of signs that Bstand in for^
the worlds inaccessible plenitude: signs that shine and compel us. The world is opaque
to creatures. It is, as the ancients understood it, veiled. One could say (although this
would be to put things simply) that science begins when humans try systematically to
understand what is hidden behind the veil of Isis. This means inspiration: first in terms
of religion and philosophy, then, later, in theory, and collective rigour in observation
and testing.
It should be obvious to anyone pursuing an evolutionary account of living organisms
that the human use of signs and need for meanings could only be the result of similar
processes in evolutionary history. Where else could human semiosis come from? We
can say with some certainty that human minds are the way they are because they are a
part of the natural world and they share its patterns and habits of evolutionary growth.
Codes and channels, and the information they make possible, do not spring fully
formed from the head of Zeus, appearing only in Homo sapiens. On the contrary, the
species-specific form of human meaning-making (anthroposemiosis) is a particular and
relatively small part of a more general semiotic capacity traceable throughout life all the
way from behaviour to the primary decision-making wrapped into every cell.
But signs, as C.S. Peirce argued, have a structure, i.e. a pattern, common to all that
lives. The articulation of these patterns, and their communication and meaning, in many
different forms of imagining in humans, gods, poetry, myth, and conversation with
humans and nonhumans is what the humanities study. This necessary meaning-
10 Favareau D. et al.
making capacity, common to all organisms and to the cells and systems they are made
of, consists, from its most basic function to its most elaborated manifestations, in the
pattern recognition and redundancy that allows the possibility of information. The
world is not made of discrete and one-dimensional signals eliciting mechanical
responses. The world is full of large and little changes in forms and contexts, thus
potential meanings. Organisms must be able to Bread^i.e. interpret these. Imagining
this being done is what gives humans access to thinking about the possibilities of wider
worlds, the makers and making of meanings, both within us and without us. (A Bmaker
in Gk. is a poetes or poietes.) The most basic form of this news tells us that our
ontology derives from relations between semiotic objects, not simply from things. It is
captured in Gregory Batesons well-known formulation of information as Ba difference
which makes a difference^(Bateson 1972:459).
The basic patterns which shine forth for cognition, therefore, must be patterns of
difference and (it follows) repetition (similarity). Based upon the primary experience of
iconic signs, such patterns are lived forms of analogy, including the sufficiently
analogous similarity and difference that the humanities identity as metaphor (Ricoeur
2003). In his book on metaphor, for example, Paul Ricoeur writes, about linguistic
metaphor, something that we can easily translate into an evolutionary biological form
whether in terms of codes or in terms of morphology:
Can one not say that the strategy of language at work in metaphor consists in
obliterating the logical and established frontiers of language, in order to bring
to light new resemblances the previous classification kept us from seeing? In
other words, the power of metaphor would be to break an old categorization,
in order to establish new logical frontiers on the ruins of their forerunners.
(Ricoeur 2003: 233)
As with biosemioticians after him, Bateson recognised that there must exist a
necessary unity between mind and nature (Bateson 2002). If that is the case, and the
idea of natural metaphor is right, then mind and nature are joined by patterns which are
rather more like poetry (which, like all literature, is semiotically recursive) than linear
mechanical procedures. The more general form of semiotic organisation in which the
book of nature is written (and that includes human bodies and minds, of course) is not
deductive logic, but the much more widely applicable natural forms that Bateson called
syllogisms in grass. Natures logic is informing, relational and poetic semiotic, in
other words. Thus poetry does not derive from anthroposemiosis but lives there because
it belongs to the more general biosemiosis of nature. James A. Shapiro writes, BAt a
time when we pride ourselves for being able to read DNA sequences with increasing
speed, it is salutary to keep in mind that we are still far from knowing how to interpret
the complex overlapping meanings contained in the genomic texts we store in our
databases. DNA, like poetry, often has to be read in several ways^(Shapiro 2012.See
also Lin et al. 2011). And Bateson says similarly:
whether you approve or disapprove of poetry, dream and psychosis, the general-
isation remains that biological data make sense are connected together by
syllogisms in grass. The whole of animal behaviour, the whole of repetitive
anatomy, and the whole of biological evolution each of these vast realms is
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 11
within itself linked together by syllogisms in grass, whether the logicians like it or
not. (Bateson and Bateson 1988:27).
But as we know, evolution builds upon anterior developments. And that must mean
not only that there is a place in scientific thinking for the creativity of metaphor as a real
semiotically causal force of evolutionary change, but also that scientific logic itself
depends, as Peirce claimed it did, upon the abductive, feelingful and aesthetic, insights
born of BIl Lume Naturale^, the fit between human mind and natural mind that
metaphor inscribes in living nature and in culture (Peirce 1891).
This essay a collection of contributions from 10 scholars working in the field of
biosemiotics and the humanities considers nature in culture. It frames this by asking
the question Why does biosemiotics need the humanities?. Each author writes from
the background of their own disciplinary perspective in order to throw light upon their
interdisciplinary engagement with biosemiotics. We start with Donald Favareau, whose
originary disciplinary home is ethnomethodology and linguistics, and then move on to
Paul Cobleys contribution on general semiotics and Kalevi Kulls on biosemiotics.
This is followed by Cobley (again) with Frederick Stjernfelt who contribute on
biosemiotics and learning, then Gerald Ostdiek from philosophy, and Morten
Tønnessen focusing upon ethics in particular. Myrdene Anderson writes from anthro-
pology, while Timo Maran and Louise Westling provide a view from literary study. The
essay closes with Wendy Wheeler reflecting on the movement of biosemiotics as a
challenge, often via the ecological humanities, to the kind of so-called postmodern
thinking that has dominated humanities critical thought in the universities for the past
40 years. Virtually all the matters I have gestured to in outline above are discussed in
much more satisfying detail in the topics which follow.
Ethnomethodology Donald Favareau
BHow can the study of the humanities inform the study of biosemiotics?^seems like an
odd question to ask, given how deeply interwoven the former is with the history and
emergence of the latter. After all, Peirce was a philosopher, Sebeok was a linguist,
Bateson was an anthropologist, and even Uexkülls seminal contributions were at-
tempts to experimentally explore the ideas of Kant.
Taking a contemporary biologists point of view, however, one can see how the
question could reasonably arise: Humans whose ways of being are, of course, the
subject of the humanities constitute one of the tiniest, most recent (and, in many
ways, most anomalous) categories of Bbiological being^: What light could the study of
such an unusual and highly specific way of life throw upon the more general and
widespread processes of living being in toto?
What such biologists fail to realize, of course, is that for at least thirty years now, the
position of biosemiotics beginning with Sebeok and as most vociferously articulated
by Deely (Deely et al. 1986;Deely2009a)has been to argue against a pars pro toto
conflation of anthroposemiotic phenomena and processes with semiosis per se.
Terrence Deacon captures the reasoning well when he warns that BThere is a serious
problem with using language as the model for analyzing other speciescommunication
in hindsight. It leads us to treat every other form of communication as exceptions to a
12 Favareau D. et al.
rule [that is, in fact, itself] based on the one most exceptional and divergent case. No
analytic method could be more perverse^(Deacon 1997:52).
That said, no biosemiotician believes that anthroposemiosis has arisen de novo, nor
that many of its fundamental processes and principles are not direct extensions and
carry-overs of more general forms of semiotic organization. Moreover, because the
practices and principles of anthroposemiosis are more immediately accessible and
intelligible to us than are those of other species, researchers in the humanities (in which
we will include the social sciences, who are also researchers into anthroposemiosis)
have often been far ahead of their counterparts in the natural sciences in discovering
and understanding both those aspects of semiosis that are unique to human semiosis,
and those that are common across one or more species. This finding should come as no
surprise, since the humanities are concerned, by definition, with understanding the
workings of Bthe symbolic species^, and thus unlike, say, 17th to twentieth century
physics and chemistry have had no choice but to investigate the unique nature of sign
relationships per se.
Andwhattheyhavediscoveredinthatregardisincreasinglyconvergentwithwhat
even non-semiotically inclined biologists have been discovering about the nature of
biological activity in toto i.e., that it is processural, multi-causal, multiply intercon-
nected, and demonstrates a recursivity of enacted, embodied, embedded and emergent
(bottom up) and downwardly causal (top down) interaction that is distributed,inthat
must be actively accomplished, at almost every level of its expression.
Yet long before biologists were thinking that way, many in the social sciences and
the humanities were already doing so, and my own first introduction to these ideas
came not from reading Hoffmeyer, Kauffman, Deacon, Wilden, Waddington or
Bateson, but from studying the findings and methods of Conversation Analysis, a still
relatively obscure field founded by the sociologists Emanuel Schegloff (1937)and
Harvey Sacks (19351975). For much in the same way that the development of
Biosemiotics was a response to the reductionist Dawkinsian notion of the innate, all-
controlling Selfish Gene, the development of Conversation Analysis, too, was a
response to the then equally dominating and reductionist Chomskian paradigm of an
innate, language-controlling and individual-brain-instantiated Universal Grammar.
Rigorously empirical and devoted to an explication of how language-using agents
themselves display to each other their understandings of what they are doing as they are
collaboratively making meaning (as opposed to how theoreticians of such meaning-
making may interpret those same displays analytically), the nascent disciplines of
Conversation Analysis and Talk-in-Interaction constituted a radical departure from
the formal and the neo-positivist reductionism so often prevalent in the domain of
language study. Researchers in these fields have compiled compelling evidence dem-
onstrating that it is the active co-participation of situated speakers in creating contexts
of relevancy, constraint and possibility for each others immediately subsequent actions
which provides the emergent structure upon which social understanding and (later)
Blanguage^ultimately rests, rather than the isolated mental computations of referential
tokens within the bounds of some predetermined, category-structuring syntax.
It was this understanding that meaningis predicated on all points by situated
interaction between agents, objects and their sign systems, and that such a triadic
relation was not only irreducible, but mutually constitutive, being an objectively
empirical aspect of reality, and not an individualistic mental ghost of itthat primed
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 13
my own later receptivity to the same triadic co-constitution that Biosemiotics rightly
shows us is the hallmark of not only all organismic interaction with world, but with all
biological being per se.
Not only have the concepts that I leaned from Conversation Analysis structured
much of my thinking about biological interaction, but they have also provided the basis
of my own attempts to situate such research and its findings within the broader study of
meaning-making among living agents that is the goal of Biosemiotics. There I have
attempted to show how the former can well illuminate the latters efforts to explicate the
principles whereby not only our human social worlds but our very biological world
itself comes into being not as a pre-givenin the furniture of the universe, but as a
locally organized, massively co-constructed, participant-fashioned accomplishment in
that universe instead (Favareau 2008,2015a,b).
Nor do I think that my experience in this regard is at all unique, given the number of
philosophy, literature, linguistics, psychology and other social science or humanities
trained practitioners who now find themselves part of the community of
biosemioticians. Such scholars often come already primedor pre-setto understand
and accept the concepts of Biosemiotics, because they are already familiar with the
real-life workings of sign phenomena, and so can fit those concepts into their already
existing structures of thought. For practitioners who have been trained in only the
physical sciences, however, this is not always the case. Which is precisely why, in my
opinion, Biosemiotics like all the biological sciences needs the humanities in order
to be able to see beyond its own conceptual limitations, just as the humanities need the
sciences for the same reason.
Semiotics Paul Cobley
The number of times I encounter the term biosemiosisis, thankfully, small. I have
heard it spoken in public and recently saw it in a largely non-semiotic volume on
advertising where a discussion of biosemiotics made up about 1% of a theoretically rich
book. Of course, the proper term is semiosis: the action of signs anywhere and
anytime - as all card-carrying biosemioticians know. The prefix, biois thus spurious:
in an uncharitable reading, it is thrown in to say Look at me Imbeingscientific;
more charitably, it is a mistake made in over-enthusiastic recognition of the sea change
in semiotics over the last thirty years. Either way, my point here is not to upbraid
biosemiotic rookies; rather, it is to emphasize that biosemiotics, historically, could not
have existed without semiotics and, in the future, may not even need its prefix.
Odd though it may seem, it was semiotics’‘levelling of the playing fieldof culture
in the second part of the twentieth century which facilitated the birth of biosemiotics.
That is to say, in its interrogation of culture, semiotics led the way in de-valorising all
cultural artefacts, including those which have been said to have been born with,
achieved or had greatness thrust upon them. Semiotics is a matter of understanding
how sign systems of all kinds - work. As this endeavour originally had a cultural
focus, so one of the key concepts of semiotics, invented concurrently by Roland
Barthes (1977a) and Juri Lotman (1974) in the early 1960s, was the text(Marrone
2014). The term established a principle of neutralitywhereby questions regarding the
value of cultural artefacts shifted towards extended enquiries into the means by which
14 Favareau D. et al.
they worked. Although first-person experience tended to get bracketed in the initial part
of this shift, the gains associated with an approach that allowed all manifestations of
culture to be treated in the same way constituted semioticsprimary bequest. This
massive, but simply stated, remit is sometimes difficult for the lay reader to grasp
owing to a range of historical and institutional determinations, as well as a general
anthropocentrism that there is no space to discuss here (see Cobley 2016:1728).
Semioticsapplication to all kinds of sign systems without bias towards one or the other
finally overturned the hierarchy of highand popularculture, a major landmark in the
challenge to authority that was mounted across culture and social life, with varying
degrees of success, in the last century.
Yet, the culture warsthat were ignited by the opening up of interpretation by
semiotics were not unproblematic (Eco 1990;Dunant1994) and semiotics
undermining of the bourgeois hierarchies of culture and mythsoon seemed stale.
By 1971, Barthes was able to declare, in evaluating his Mythologiques fourteen years
after its publication in French, that Bdenunciation, demystification (demythification)^
(Barthes 1977b: 166) of the bourgeois and the petit bourgeois had become, itself, a
mythological doxa.Mythoclasmwas to be succeeded by semioclasm,heclaimed,a
far-reaching interrogation of all sign systems and a challenge to their very basis. This
would not simply entail unravelling the connection of denotation and connotation that
sustained certain cultural hierarchies as natural, but a more thorough assault on the
mechanics of meaning at the very level of the sign itself.
Barthescall for semioclasm came shortly after the formation of the International
Association for Semiotic Studies in 1969, where semioticians such as Thomas A.
Sebeok broadened the entire agenda of sign study by encouraging its application to
the whole of life. Barthessubsequent retreatinto highly personalized writing, taken
in this context, was not entirely without its political co-ordinates. However, the project
of semiotics continued, with the uncovering of sign processes throughout the living
world. This was not just a matter of finding more objects for semiotics. Unsurprisingly,
following the fashionable moment of semiotics in the West during the 1970s and early
1980s, when semiotic analysis still had the flavour of magic, the commitment to
semioclasm even in hitherto unexplored realms for such analysis seemed to some
to amount to no more than further sterile analyses of different phenomena. In addition,
it probably seemed to the casual observer that such analysis reveals very little about
humans and what impinges on them in the polis. Such a view, of course, constitutes a
grave error. Biosemioticsinfusion into general semiotics means that analysis no longer
promises to reveal simply what the messages that humans send are like: how they are
constituted and structured. Semiotics, now casting its net to analyse sign systems in the
whole of nature, is thus concerned with how humans operate amidst signs, what
distinguishes their cognition and their being as endosemiotic phenomena among other
organisms and in the cosmos. The new horizon for semiotics that arises with the
infusion of biosemiotics is analogous to the principle of neutrality that blew apart the
divisions in culture. These latter had hitherto impeded not only analysis of human
endeavours but also occluded a view beyond ossified and oppressive self-created
human edifices.
Effectively, contemporary semiotics marks the continuation of the semiotic project
whose latest guise is biosemiotics. Where human artefacts were the focus of post-1945
semiotics delineating its field as Bthe text^,the focus of contemporary semiotics has
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 15
delineated its field as Bnature^, embracing the human and its artefacts, as well as all
other life as connected. For me, what is taking place is certainly a further articulation of
the same project rather than a Bbranch^of the original enterprise. Fifteen years ago,
Thomas A. Sebeok noted that.
The present terminological requirement to subsume a semiotics of culture, or just
plain semiotics, under a semiotics of nature, or biosemiotics, might have been
obviated decades earlier. As things are going now, the boundaries between the
two are already crumbling, giving way to a unified doctrine of signs embedded in
a vast, comprehensive life science (Sebeok 2001:159).
A comprehensive science of life is not a new idea, although the idea has fallen into
disuse. Articulation of that science through a unified doctrine of signs, however,
remains as radical as it did when Sebeok started to outline it and when Barthes
attempted to come to terms with it. In a following paragraph, Frederik Stjernfelt and
I make suggestions for the same in our noting of the discontinuities of terminology and
study that are placed on continuous processes. That is, we call for a continuous doctrine
as opposed to the numerous compartmentalizing approaches to nature and culture.
Does this mean that biosemiotics can afford to ignore (general) semiotics because,
eventually, semiotics will become biosemiotics? The answer has to be: not at all for a
number of institutionalised reasons that are not to be resolved here. More importantly,
though, perhaps the question of why biosemiotics needs semiotics is ill-phrased. Most
humans, when asked what they need, will refer to food, shelter, reproduction; a less
likely answer is Boxygen^. Semiotics is biosemioticsoxygen. This is not to say that
biosemiotics has to reference every last mythoclasmic intervention into advertising or
every Greimassian analysis of Islamic design. However, it does have to remain vigilant
in case such analyses ever run out. If semiosis remains the object of semiotics, then
biosemiotics = semiotics. Biosemiotics bio+something else.
Biosemiotics and Humanities: A Manifesto Kalevi Kull
What connects biology with the humanities is exactly and precisely semiotics (Perron
et al. 2000).
1
Semiotician and cultural theorist Juri Lotman focused his studies on poetics. He
emphasised that the arts are those practices in which the process of creating new
information is most clearly expressed and fully developed (Lotman 2011 [1967]).
2
This is important because the increase in information (not just its transfer) is what
1
With this formulation, and with this collective manifesto as a whole, we attempt to specify and develop the
thesis on Bsemiotics as a bridge^, which has been argued for on several earlier occasions. (See, for e.g., Perron
et al. 2000.)
2
B[...] Art means mastering the world (modelling the world) in a conditional situation. [...] Works of art [...]
can increase the amount of information stored in them. This unique characteristic of works of art makes them
similar to biological systems and gives them an extremely special place among everything created by the
mankind. [...] Artistic models are a unique combination of scientific and play-type models, which simulta-
neously organize both the intellect and behaviour. In comparison to art, play is without content, while science
is without effect^(Lotman 2011 [1967]: 265; 268; 269).
16 Favareau D. et al.
characterises semiosis. Deduction (the logical ideal in the natural sciences) is a me-
chanical transformation, while the tool of an artist to create new meanings is abduction.
The problem of novelty, the question of the source of diversity and new information, is
one of most fundamental questions in biology, in understanding life. Therefore, finding
the poetic or poetic-like processes in living systems is what biosemiotics is about, and
this is exactly where we need the humanities, the specialists in the arts (Kull 2015).
3
This is what can be seen as a central point of our manifesto.
The integration of theories of biological evolution and cultural evolution cannot be
based on reduction to simple biological models (of natural selection) that would be a
biologization of cultural studies and the humanities. The amplification of random
mutations which is the mechanism neo-Darwinism is based on, and which was
extended to cultural processes via the concept of memes, which also change through
the random mutations and amplification is a fundamentally different process than
semiosis; it does not serve as a mechanism of meaning-making. Consequently, knowl-
edge in the humanities, which is largely the description of various aspects of semiosis,
can serve as a set of guidelines in our search for truly semiosic aspects of non-human
life. Here is where biosemiotics needs the humanities. The contemporary paradigm
shift in the theory of evolution, from the Modern Synthesis to the Extended Synthesis,
is basically a shift from a reductionist genocentric view to more holist epigenetic and
agent-based views. In other terms, this is a shift towards biosemiotic models (Kull
2016). An integration of theories of biological evolution and cultural evolution has to
be based on semiotic models.
In order to professionally use semiotic models or theories, one inevitably
requires a good orientation in the semiotic conceptual apparatus. Due to the
current situation in semiotics, the theoretical heterogeneity is extraordinary large.
Most of contemporary semiotic theory has been developed on the basis of a
humanities background. There is therefore a need for a link to the humanities
link for any semiotician. Semiotics itself cannot have a congruent theory without a
well worked out relationship between biological semiotics and humanities semi-
otics. In this, much work has yet to be done.
A case of the role of the humanities for biosemiotics can be drawn from the
experience of the Department of Semiotics of the University of Tartu. This department
(which provides the full curriculum of semiotics for bachelors, masters, and doctoral
students) carries a strong humanities tradition, as developed in the Tartu school of
semiotics by Juri Lotman. At the same time, it covers a large scope of semiotic
disciplines, among these biosemiotics. Thus for biosemioticians (particularly with a
biological background) who are working in this department (e.g., Kalevi Kull, Timo
Maran, Riin Magnus, and others), the immediate intellectual atmosphere is certainly
deeply informed by the humanities (the department belongs to the Faculty of Philos-
ophy which includes all philologists). These scholars can bear witness to the case that,
without these humanities surroundings, they would not only have hardly had access to
systematic knowledge in semiotics, but it would also have been much harder for them
to achieve. Frequent discussions with philologists have led them to a much clearer
understanding of their own biological field.
3
That Lotmans approach to semiotics of culture can be productively used for deriving the principles for
biosemiotics, has been demonstrated (e.g., in Kull 2015).
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 17
Together with the question of the role of the humanities for biosemiotics, we could
also ask what is the role of biosemiotics for the humanities (Cobley 2016). A short
answer would be that this is the use of biological knowledge without biologization.
There are several examples in the history of science where the application of biological
models in the humanities led to vulgarization or even tragic results due to political
consequences. As a result, the humanities caution in regard to biology has its historical
reasons (Tallis 2011). Only if the life of other organisms is understood beyond mechan-
ical explanations, can it become naturally integrated with human life in its broadest
experience. Contemporary semiotics provides this possibility (Favareau and Kull 2015).
A reason for the establishment of the unnecessary boundaries (and not only between
sciences or cultures) is an oversimplification of differences. There certainly are differ-
ences, but not for the denial of the other, but for the diversification of understanding.
This is the source of our semiotic program for the conceptualization of biosemiotics in
its relationships to the humanities.
Biosemiotics and Learning - Paul Cobley and Frederik Stjernfelt
There has been a great deal written in the field of biosemiotics which is both
philosophically nuanced and sensitive with respect to issues of art, culture and human
endeavour in general. From The Garden in the Machine (Emmeche 1994)through
Signs of Meaning in the Universe (Hoffmeyer 1996)toIncomplete Nature (Deacon
2012), and in consonance with the polymath offerings of Thomas A. Sebeok, writing
by scientists in biosemiotics has eschewed simplistic mechanism in the process of
presenting biologically-inflected observations on the domain of culture.
Yet, there is an understandable tendency in current biosemiotic discourse to privilege
functional approaches in accounts of development in the natural world. The concepts of
semiotic freedom, scaffolding and agency tend to be described in functionalist terms in
extant accounts of their procedures. This tendency is the modus operandi of strong
tendencies in biology and social science and, since biosemiotics is in direct dialogue
even if that dialogue is, to some degree, one-sided at present with such sciences, it is
hardly surprising that biosemiotics sometimes has functionalist overtones. At first sight,
the humanitiespredominant concern with material that often has no immediate
function nor discernable utility seems to offer a contrast in that it appears to be less
wed to functionalism in the narrow sense. Yet, these observations require qualification.
So, let us add, firstly, that we recognize that there are large domains of nature which are
mostly mechanical in their operations. A small part of that mechanism is functional in
the narrow sense. However, higher life has evolved from this functional substrate
through a continuous and protracted process and this is something to which any amount
of discontinuous dualism should not blind us. The evolutionary continuity of nature up
to and through human affairs is one very pressing reason why the realm of life should
not be studied through a lens promoting discontinuities (Cobley 2016). Secondly, it is
not only the hard end of the sciences that has taken mechanicism as its cue. The
humanities, too, has itself periodically employed functionalist and teleological concep-
tions in many of its branches. We are increasingly compelled, then, to avoid making
quite so special a case for culture, as well as a special case for the study and expansion
of culture through the humanities. A vision of the study of nature and the study of
18 Favareau D. et al.
culture as two iron fortresses is untenable. Diltheyan attempts at securing a special
enclosure for the humanities, taken as completely different from the sciences in bearing
and focus are, clearly, part of the problem rather than the solution.
Where the case of biosemiotics is concerned, we would argue that it is sometimes
involved in a less than explicit functionalist discourse but that some of its key concepts map
a route of escape similar to that taken by the humanities. For example, explaining semiotic
freedom, Hoffmeyer refers to experiments where scientists placed artificial sweeteners
rather than glucose in the environment of a chemotactic bacteria cell. As he writes
(Hoffmeyer 2010: 164), the cell misinterprets such chemical signs of its environment and
Such misinterpretations are dangerous, and natural selection will favor any
solution that helps the organism to better interpret the situations it meets. Indeed,
selection would be expected to favor the evolution of more sophisticated forms of
semiotic freedomin the sense of an increased capacity for responding to a
variety of signs through the formation of (locally) meaningfulinterpretants.
Semiotic freedom (or interpretance) allows a system to readmany sorts of
cuesin the surroundings, and this would normally have beneficial effects on
fitness. Thus, from the modest beginnings we saw in chemotactic bacteria the
semiotic freedom of organic systems would have tended to increase, and although
it has not been easy to prove that any systematic increase in complexity, as this
concept has traditionally been defined, has in fact accompanied the evolutionary
process, it is quite obvious that semiotic complexity or freedom has indeed
attained higher levels in later stages, advanced species of birds and mammals in
general being semiotically much more sophisticated than less advanced species.
Here, interpretanceenriches the concept of natural selection, keeping it from the
one-way street of mechanism. Explaining the concept of semiotic scaffolding,
Hoffmeyer notes that BThe network of semiotic interactions by which individual cells,
organisms, populations, or ecological units are controlling their activities can thus be
seen as scaffolding devices assuring that an organisms activities become tuned to that
organisms needs^(Hoffmeyer 2007: 154). The interactive nature of this process
relativizes the strong opposition of the heredity/environment couplet.
Then, in a general statement about agency in nature, Hoffmeyer describes the way in
which certain cells in a primitive sense remember the bacteria of a disease in question
and are able to initiate the production of antibodies. BI consider the term to remember
appropriate in this context^, he writes (Hoffmeyer 1996:12),
because what we are talking about here is a heavily selective retention of past
events. Fortunately, the one thing the body is best at is erasing its memories,
forgetting. Not everything is remembered, only those things that are of signifi-
cance. Minor wounds heal, tiredness is dispelled by sleep, my own nervous
tension is eased when a nice fat check drops through the mailbox, stress levels
fall and stomach ulcers cease their gnawing once an exam is over, the apathy of a
broken heart is conquered by love of life. Time heals almost all wounds.
The intelligent, agentive process of remembering gives the lie to the assumed
automatic character of immune response.
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 19
Such examples mark a departure from narrow functionalism. They should not be
construed as singling out Hoffmeyer, a particularly sensitive analyst, for opprobrium in
respect of the functionalist inclination. Hoffmeyer inherits from others (for example,
Jerome Bruner, Andy Clark) and bequeaths to others (most individuals operative in the
field of biosemiotics). What is at issue is the level of discourse at which biosemiotics
concepts are couched. This is clearly evident in Hoffmeyers discussion of semiotic
freedom, where the master narrative of fitnesslurks behind the entire discussion. This
is the discourse of teleology albeit a reinvigorated and secular teleology which is
aware of metanarratives. But, like the extended thesis and punctuated equilibrium, it
does not yet offer as pronounced a vision of checks, balances, stops, starts, affordances,
constraints and overdetermination that is indigenous to some traditions in the analysis
of culture. Similarly, the brief description of scaffolding, above, is geared to ecology,
assurances, tuning and needs functionalist categories as opposed to the more flexible
vocabulary of formations, speculations, rough fits and desires that is often necessary in
the humanities.
Yet, consider the observations on agency and remembering. In the service of
rhetoric, and understandably so, they constitute an example of biosemiotics rather
over-egging the pudding of agency in the two decades since Signs of Meaning in the
Universe. Hoffmeyers remarks on memory, however, are ambiguous: BNot everything
is remembered^. Agency is manifested in more than one way. To phrase the matter
slightly differently, there is a hint of overdetermination in this description of memory.
The term overdeterminationcomes, principally, from psychoanalysis but was profit-
ably employed by the Marxist Louis Althusser in his discussions of culture. As in
psychoanalysis, it refers to domains that are not just the product of one determining
force but the many domains that co-exist and complement each other whilst being
determined by multiple forces that are often exerting reciprocal forces on those multiple
determinants. Overdetermination also envisages culture and sociality as radically
uneven, with developments in different domains taking place at different paces.
In the humanities, a range of versions of overdetermination are indigenous -
sometimes for the purpose of allowing credible analysis and sometimes, it has to be
said, to desperately assert the autonomy of culture from nature. Nevertheless, it is
largely taken for granted that spheres of cultural existence do not develop in tandem,
notwithstanding numerous attempts to track artistic movements and to exercise epochal
characterisations. To be sure, biosemioticscontinued dialogue with the sciences
necessitates an alternative re-telling of scientific perspectives on development and
function in the natural world. Yet, if there is to be an epistemological extension and
rearticulation of functionalism, then biosemiotics needs to continue to heed the
overdetermination which some traditions in the humanities necessarily foreground.
Biosemiotics as Philosophy Gerald Ostdiek
Science is too often said to be one thing, and Humanities another. And they are, except
when they are not. It must be said that humanity represents the only species known to
have accomplished much at all with science, and the humanities describes the processes
by which human beings process and document the experience of being human.
Separated, distilled, isolated for the purposes of action, we can call one such process
20 Favareau D. et al.
science, another philosophy, another religion, etc. Through behavior, these processes
come to be expressed as objects theory or technology or art or craft, and as culture
heritages of social interaction, in interaction, that take on life and both exert and suffer
selective pressure. The humanities are biological, and biology radically continuous
(Ostdiek 2012,2015,2016).
4
A living thing is a bordered thing that necessarily seeks outside itself for what it must
ingest, or avoid, or somehow manipulate so as to go on living. This entails semiotics
reading the surroundings by standing one thing for another, so as to profit from the
possible. This involves reshaping the world as selective pressures fit the signer to the
world and the world to the signer; the process is not willed, but reciprocated. What
humanity does differs little from other animals, but it is a little with a large consequence.
We not only mind the world around us, we mind the means by which we mind the world:
we not only read into being the signs that shape us, we also see them. In rare moments of
insight, we see ourselves seeing signs see the world. This not onlyallows for science and
philosophy, it entails them. To be human is to negotiate truth claims about the world.
A truth claim is a proposition a single, momentary aspect of the function circle of a
human person. Truth claims are at once scientific, philosophical and religious.Toposit
that biological mechanisms are semiotically realized is to posit a falsifiable notion that,
if believed (acted upon, actualized), results in the realization of novel methods of
looking, which results in and is novel mechanisms of living that are simultaneously
epistemological and biological. This is ubiquitous to living things and becomes
uniquely human only when each stage comes to life: when signs suffer selection,
science speaks. Biosemiotics proposes to know what life knows, and subjects the self to
science. But science is neither pure minding, nor done by pure minds: it is a conse-
quence of human behavior. As science, biosemiotics methodologically rejects the
notion that science can be done without philosophy.
Science neither commands nor completes the processes by which interpretation
becomes interpretant; it furthers it. In some ways science is a product of reasoning
about the necessity to check the validity of our imagining, and in other ways it is
limited to what a culture makes philosophically available. But these are half-truths. A
truth claim makes sense by performing a semiotic function that (potentially) furthers the
living of the living thing. Science is how we do what all life does.
The behavior that shapes and is shaped by the human niche is not formed simply by
making stuff up and calling it true (all living things assign meaning), but by living by
the strictures of the assigning. Our attention goes not only to the sign object but also the
sign. At our best, we believe our imaginings true but simultaneously see them as
historically contrived fictions. Our best puts science to work. At our worst, we imagine
we have ended the need to check our map against anything that the processes that
generate our mental maps are somehow exact, and our mapping (if not our maps)
4
The musings presented here are developed elsewhere. In Ostdiek (2012), I argue that self-awareness exists as
a consequence of multiple scales of post biotic phenomena exerting selective pressure on the interactions of
living things. In Ostdiek (2016), I argue that symbiosis with post-biotic living things distinguishes human
experience from that of other animals. In Ostdiek (2015), I argue that religion, philosophy and science form a
Neo-Peircean trinity wherein (proto)religion represents the binding of interpretation into interpretant, which
results in and is the presence of mind, which is furthered by checking itself against the objects of the signs of
which it is composed, as well as against itself. Should the argumentation of these essays prevail, the notions I
present here become a mere matter of course.
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 21
complete. Our worst turns word/symbols into fiat decrees such that the invocation of
science or interpretation closes minding, rejects the possible, and leads us into an
epistemic and evolutionary cul-de-sac.
Our niche is more a product of our minding of the world than that of any other
known species (a difference of degree, not kind). It grows as we imagine it into being,
more limited by minding than mattering. And our minding is extensive and accurate:
science works. Yet the territory remains larger than the map. The map, the methods of
mapping, and also the methods of checking the map against the territory remain objects
of semiotic symbiosis, wherein interpretation and actuality forever reconstruct the
other.
So long as the map is not the territory (which is always), the success of a truth
claim will involve acting on propositions, the validity of which will necessarily
involve checking the map against itself for consistency of usage, symbolic coher-
ence, readability, etc. Should a time exist when the territory is so absolutely
mapped and the mapping so absolutely competent that the two have become
one, science and philosophy both will be finished. But this cannot happen, and
science necessarily begins to fail when it begins to argue otherwise. Were the
territory the map, neither philosophy nor science would have consequence, and
religion alone would matter; mere believing (that is, acting in accord with per-
ception to thereby bind a read into being sans sceptical reflection) would shape
human experience. And this defines the realm of animal faith (Santayana 1923),
not human knowing. To reject the continuity of science and philosophy is to reject
what is most unique to humanity.
Ethics Morten Tønnessen
A dozen to some 20 years ago, two of the most central biosemioticians, first Jesper
Hoffmeyer (1993) and then Kalevi Kull (2001), addressed connections between
biosemiotics and ethics. In the last ten years, a new generation of scholars have started
working out a biosemiotic ethics (see Beever 2011 for an overview). The foundational
idea is that if all living systems are semiotic, then biosemiosis can serve as a basis for
justifying attribution of moral status to human and non-human individuals and to
various ecological entities.
Part of the appeal of biosemiotics within an ethical discourse is that it can serve
as a counterweight to simplistic notions of a moral agent/moral patient dichotomy.
Briefly told, quite a few ethicists, particularly of an analytic philosophy persua-
sion, firmly believe that human beings are the only moral agents on this planet
and, furthermore, that only human beings can function as moral patients. This is
because they assume that the only possible moral relationship is a reciprocal
relationship between moral agents. This is but another exemplification of the old
story about human exceptionalism. A biosemiotic ethics, however, can make the
case that to be a moral patient it suffices to be semiotically sensitive to human
actions in terms of the organisms own wellbeing. In short, if our human sign
exchange directly or indirectly results in better or worse lives for another subject
of biosemiosis, it is morally relevant, and we are morally responsible for how we
affect other lives via our actions.
22 Favareau D. et al.
More progressive ethicists base their ethical accounts on the phenomenon of
sentience. However, a biosemiotic ethics goes beyond sentience (cf. Tønnessen and
Beever 2014), because semiotic agency, which a biosemiotic ethics can take as its
defining morally relevant characteristic, constitutes a wider category in the realm of life
than that of sentience. In this perspective, sentience is but a special case of, and an
aspect of, semiotic agency. Whether a biosemiotic ethics should be regarded as a new
kind of consequentialism, or should be placed within some other tradition, is open for
discussion.
Biosemiotic contributions to meta-ethics, the foundational study of ethics,
include Champagne (2011)andKull(2001), with the latter stating that Bthe origin
of value can be seen as a problem of [...] biosemiotics^(Kull 2001:355).
Champagne, on his side, indicates that normativity has its origin in the very
structure of the Umwelt, and draws on Umwelt theory and Ayn Rands meta-
ethics
5
to show how all valuations ultimately derive from the normativity embed-
ded in our lifeworlds. He thus sees human moral judgements as natural extensions,
as it were, of animal normativity.
With an eye to normative ethics, Kull claims that a required turn to a
biocentric view Bmaymeanthatthevaluingprocessisextendedsothatthe
experiential world of any living being is included^(Kull 2001: 356). If that is
our moral judgement, then it appears that the semiosphere at large (qua bio-
sphere) has intrinsic value, in some sense. This might look like an Uexküllian
view but as a matter of fact, Jakob von Uexküll (18641944) interpreted the
moral consequences of his own Umwelt theory quite differently (see von Uexküll
2013; Beever and Tønnessen 2013). Kull has also suggested the combining of
deep ecology a tradition within radical environmentalism with ecosemiotics
(see Kull 2011 andKulletal.2004). In a similar manner, Tønnessen (2003)
offers a biosemiotic commentary on, and reformulation of, the Deep Ecology
Platform. The common assumption in these texts is that the deep ecological
outlook has a semiotic basis.
As it happens, ethics is not simply about moral conduct, it is about human nature
and the nature of semiosis. As stated in the semiotic meditation,BSigns grow but
should they?^(Tønnessen 2009:78).
Signs can be cultivated. Signs can be grown. How else would we be able to
conquer this planet? [] Who dares to claim that the more signs grow, the better?
[] Wouldntsuchanideabeade facto reproduction of [] our culturesnaive
notion of eternal, unrestricted and unlimited growth? [] Streams and currents of
semiosis flowing freely in the landscape, ruled by its own innate rhythm (down-
hill, upstream; down-hill, upstream), only to be sliced up, packed and sold at the
market place.
What is the nature of semiosis? And what is the culture of semiosis? And what is
our nature, in this world of cultivation? Are we doomed to be [] creatures
constantly and incessantly cultivating all that has anature?
5
Ayn Ra nd ( 190 51982) was a libertarian, and a defender of capitalism and ethical egoism.
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 23
Why do the Humanities Matter for Biosemiotics: Anthropology Myrdene
Anderson
I would find this a more interesting topic were it tweaked, but in two complementary
dimensions:
(1) Why does semiotics matter for biosemiotics?
(2) Why does biosemiotics matter for semiotics?
I could assert that introspection about the relations between semiotics and
biosemiotics motivate the current more particular set of assignments about humanities
and biosemiotics (cf. Sebeok 1984;Deely1992).
Anthropology:
One subject matter, two cultures, three approaches, four fields, five angles .
Launching the above inquiry from my home base of anthropology may be
instructive, provided Banthropology^is understood to be of the holistic North
American, Boasian, Bfour-field^, variety of anthropologyalso dubbed the most
humanistic of the sciences and the most scientific of the humanities. This descrip-
tionmaybeconcretelysourcedtoEricR.Wolf(1964), who was perhaps channel-
ing his ancestors Alfred L. Kroeber (18761960) and/or Clyde Kluckhohn (1905
1960), certainly before the notion of two cultures (essentially of non/pre-science
vis-à-vis science) was popularized by Charles Percy Snow (cf. 1959,1963;
contested in Anderson et al. 1984). Snow anticipated by a generation, and New
York literary agent John Brockman has rendered palpable, a third culture (cf. Brockman
1995), or synthetic approach, via The Reality Club salon of New York intellectuals
commencing in 1981, and coalescing on the web as the Edge Foundation from 1988 on
(cf. Kelly 1998).
The four fields, or subdisciplines, of anthropology gradually crystalized a
century ago: sociocultural anthropology, linguistic anthropology, bioanthropology
(once physical anthropology), and archeological anthropology or prehistory. The
four fields intrinsically, implicitly, yet emphatically overlap; no one has attempted
to justify them deductively; they vary in their relative focus on phenomena
variously situated in space and/or through time. While individual anthropological
professionals almost always specialize in a more finite number of the four fields,
or even something minutely interstitial to two or more of them, these specialists do
so by building on a foundation in all four subdisciplines. A so-called fifth field
covers variations of applied, activist, advocacy, and otherwise practicing anthro-
pologists exploring pragmatic angles across the grain of the original and non-
coordinate four fields; this fifth angle can slide into corporate and governmental
and nongovernmental projects, and will not be discussed here.
Anthropology concerns itself with everything about and every aspect of our
species, Homo sapiens, from evolution through time to dispersal across space to
the imaginings of innerspace. While periodically anthropology has been contorted
by discussions of whether it practices or includes science, these episodes usually
pivot around the extent a particular angle of anthropology feels compelled to
quantify; other inflections of anthropology remain comfortable with the issues
24 Favareau D. et al.
surrounding interpretation, that is, meaning-making, also central to semiotics. Yet,
qualification underlies all quantification (cf. Anderson 2012), and even numbers
demand interpretation. Finally, all data are actually capta, shanghaied by our
conspecifics variously innocent or motivated, and in any case constrained by our
bio-historico-culturo-linguistic selves.
What Comes Naturally: Anthropology and Semiotics
Appearing more broad and holistic than the typical academic disciplines, anthro-
pology might better be dubbed a meta-discipline. So would the discipline/field/
approach of semiotics. Perhaps that explains the affinity many anthropologists feel
with semiotics, and for that matter biosemiotics. But anthropologists find the
distinction between semiotics and biosemiotics overdrawn, even unnecessary.
Could one imagine sociocultural, linguistic, or archeological anthropology without
bioanthropology? Not at all. Nor the reverse. Bioanthropology practitioners are
also socioculturolinguistic members of the human species that is likewise shaped,
though never determined, by its biocultural histories and prehistories, whether
acknowledged or not.
I have argued that individual humans cannot but be both anthropologists and
semioticians, from birth, albeit without being self-conscious about what comes natu-
rally, unburdened by theoretical and methodological pluralism, or even prescriptions
and proscriptions, surrounding issues of evidence.
Biosemiotics Meets Anthropology
Organizationally, biosemiotics might appear as a precipitate of semiotics. Some of its
contributors have indeed been biologists. Also important have been practitioners from
other sciences, social sciences, and humanitiesparticularly philosophy. At the same
time, semiotics itself embraces practitioners from the same unruly breadth of fields, as
does anthropology.
Looking around academe outside of anthropology and semiotics, it is difficult to find
any disciplines that recognize our own human place in the cosmos, saturated as we are
in our bio-historico-culturo-linguistic constitutions. Reflecting on anthropology alone,
it might seem that with its four fields or five angles, this discipline can be autonomous
or hermetically sealed. Not so: anthropology itself must rest on a deeper shared
foundation of particular and general history and philosophy, residing in texts and oral
lore and habit, perhaps summed up as the humanities. So does semiotics, not just
biosemiotics.
I will close paraphrasing Eric Wolf, reflecting on anthropology taken as less a
subject matter than a bond between subject matters in part history, part literature; in
part natural science, part social science striving to study humans and the human
condition both from within and withoutrepresenting both a manner of looking at our
species and also a vision of our futurethe most scientific of the humanities, the most
humanistic of the sciences (Wolf 1964).
Wont this fit semiotics, and biosemiotics, as well as anthropology? Of course the
humanities matter, for everything.
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 25
Why is Biosemiotics Relevant for the Literary Study and Vice Versa? -
Timo Maran and Louise Westling
Biosemiotics could provide an alternative viewpoint for understanding literature and
literary studies. Biosemiotics holds a view that sign processes take place also outside of
human culture at various levels: as intra- and intercellular processes inside an organism,
as signals in animal communication, and as semiotic regulation in ecosystems. Corre-
spondingly, human cultural and literary activities should be interpreted in this wider
context of semiotic processes. Literature preserves layers of the human eco-imaginary
as scaffolding for cultural meanings that parallel biosemiotic scaffolding (Hoffmeyer
2008,2014). These scaffolding layers encode deep species memories, senses of
immersion and interrelations within the plant and animal world, and anxieties about
violation of responsibilities within the biosemiosphere.
In The Epic of Gilgamesh, for example, both King Gilgamesh and his friend Enkidu
are related to wild bulls, and Enkidu begins his life as a hairy man identified with wild
animals. Fatal punishment comes from the gods when the two heroes cut down the
godssacred forest and kill its guardian associated with the powers of nature. The
metamorphic and transformative powers of the Greek god Dionysos in Euripides
Bakkhai express archaic ecological understandings of permeable species boundaries
and human relations with plants and animals. Similarly the Mayan Popol Vuh scaffolds
human/plant/animal interrelationships that sustain human life (Westling 2014).
Biosemiotics helps support Maurice Merleau-Pontys phenomenological description
of the invisible deep meaning or Logos animating the organic world that writers from all
cultures and eras make explicit and visible in literary works through differing
styles (Merleau-Ponty 1968). Literature can thus be understood as a means of giving
form to semiotic activities and potentials that humans experience in the biosemiosphere.
Many kinds of environmental understandings in literature metaphorically parallel sci-
entific discoveries about semiotic processes in organisms and ecosystems. As authors
and readers we are endowed with different semiotic capacities, including non-verbal
zoosemiotic modelling (Sebeok 1991). Literary depictions and verbal knowledge have
roots in the non-articulated tacit knowledge (Polanyi 1966) and semiotic potentiality of
the environment (Gibson 1986). Literature needs non-literary and nonverbal semiotic
space for its existence in the same way as culture needs non-cultural space as its context
or boundary conditions. Literature represents and tries to make sense of the environment
in many ways. Being rich in different artistic codes, literary works are well equipped to
represent complicated and multifaceted realities, including human-environment rela-
tions (Lotman 1977). In this context, works of nature writing can be seen as models of
human environmental relations of the given culture and environment (Maran 2014a).
By being a process-oriented and dynamic discipline, biosemiotics could also inspire
new modes of literary criticism. Attention could shift to more relation-oriented reading:
how texts relate to particular cultural and environmental settings, how they emerge,
inspire action and if and how they are applied back to the environment. Also the
research process could be reinterpreted as a meta-communication that on its own takes
part in cultural dynamics. There are important underlying ecological implications in
this view as culture is considered to be a particular, local phenomenon and not a formal
system or a static construct. A biosemiotic approach could lead us to reconceptualize
our relations with research subjects by including also the biological context from which
26 Favareau D. et al.
we come: our own personal, cultural and evolutionary histories, human umwelt and
environmental experiences.
Literary studies can provide to biosemiotics a rich understanding about the narrative
strategies used in human culture as well as relations between symbolic modelling and
other modelling types. This would help to better analyze relations between human culture
and the environment, especially the semiotization of the environment, in the course of
which the human cultural forms (e.g. technical designs, mapping, abstract ideas) are used
as a source for changing the physical environment (Maran 2014b). Environment
semiotized by humans may become a source of problems for other animals, as for instance
natural landscape fragmented for agricultural purposes may hinder the communication of
the passerine birds. Literary studies may also be used for discussing ethical and moral
positions of biosemiotics. Being scientifically oriented, biosemiotics is not predominantly
focused on ethical matters. But at the same time, biosemiotics often deals with morally
sensitive topics: agency in other animals, non-cultural component in humans etc. There-
fore, biosemiotics may unwillingly become a part of critical argumentation, and literary
studies may help biosemiotics to develop its own position on these questions.
Critical Theory Wendy Wheeler
The human animal is an evolutionary and meaning-concerned part of an evolutionary
and meaning-concerned living world. Nature-culture is clearly a continuum in which
culture is an evolutionary development of nature in humans, and to some extent in some
other animals also (how could it be otherwise?). But many, if not all, the things which we
think of as culturelong pre-existed humans. The aesthetic dimension studied by much
of the humanities is one such example. We are made in the present of patterns and
relations,natural andcultural, which precede us and which turn up again and again in the
world. In being, and becoming aware of, these patterns, organisms find meaning. This
logic of pattern, which is the species recognition of a natural logic to phenomena, is
essentially repetition and difference (including mimicry. See Maran 2017). Patterns
repeat on the basis of similarity (visual or haptic or chemical or neurochemical, and so
on), but that similarity is capable of containing aspects of difference. Organisms build
their ontological forms and maps in their encounters with the world they live in. Both
form and context act as constraints on ontological expression. In humans, these forms
are expressed not only in evolutionary bio-ontology and in human mind, but also in the
forms and content of the stories human animals tell.
The most straightforward way of understanding the logic these processes obey is to
recognise that they are essentially living metaphors, as Gregory Bateson suggested.
Strung together like beads on a necklace of habit and chance, they form biosemiotic
stories (Wheeler 2016). From an evolutionary perspective, this means not only that we
can derive insights about the present from the past (biologically and culturally), but also
that we can derive insights into cultural patterns from biological patterns. Even more
germane to the topic of this particular essay, and as implied by Roman Jakobson
(Wheeler 2016), we can derive insights about biological expressions and behaviours
from cultural ones. And of course molecular biologists trying to understand the
workings of DNA molecules have, indeed, been obliged to borrow their lexicon from
the languages of semiotics (codes, expressions, reading, transcriptions, translations,
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 27
interpretations, and so on). Like small societies, bacteria interpret conditions and
make decisions through what is aptly called quorum sensing. Similarly, recent
research on viral macrophages indicates that they, too, communicate across the
generations, like humans, by writingchemical messages which are read by
descendants (Calloway 2017).
The culture/nature distinction grows increasingly irrelevant. A biosemiotically in-
formed critical theory of subjects, society and culture might well help us to move
beyond the problems which have driven critical theory in the humanities for the past 35
to 40 years. That formation was largely derived from two sources: a Marxist theory of
false consciousness critical of Enlightenment reason and claims to truth, and the post-
moderntheory which says that all meanings are made by humans and that human
meanings are just a ceaseless circulation of signifiers unanchored from bodies and
Earth. The biosemiotic realisation that meaning-making belongs to all living things, and
that human meaning-making, although distinctive of Homo sapiens, has its roots in the
common descent of non-human semiotic life, indicates that reality is not constructed in
human language. It is experienced in sign relations that are anchored in bodies and in
the shared Earth. All other organisms make meanings too, and human life is lived
amongst those meanings. Organisms continually both shape and are shaped by the
embodied and enminded semiotic relations which both scaffold matter and energy, and
also constitute life and meaning on this planet. Human beings are but a part of that
global semiosis in which the biosphere is at the same time the semiosphere. In the light
of all this, we might conjecture that an environmental ethic of biosemiosis strongly
implies the reality of many different readings among both human and nonhuman
organisms and an imperative to listen and take heed.
The modern sciences and humanities have both tended toward inadequate models of
mind and subjectivity. Computational models produce the problem of mechanistic
genetic determinism versus free will. Computers have no real choice about their inputs.
On the humanities side, tabula rasa models have produced a socio-linguistically
deterministic model of human selves that is both biologically and semiotically shallow.
Critical theory in the humanities has tended to reject scientific accounts as reductive,
and as especially simplistic in their gene-based attempts to explain cultural experience
and meaning-making.
But as biological ideas themselves expand beyond a gene-centric account, contem-
porary ideas of mindand meaningequally require expansion. Mind does not require
a brain. From a biosemiotic point of view, and like the sign itself, mind must be
composed of three necessary aspects: a semiotically active body in a semiotically active
world and some form of (conscious or nonconscious) system capable of memory. DNA
fulfils the latter function in important ways. Its processes, along with evolutionarily and
developmentally subsequent ones in organisms, appear to depend upon on the ability to
register forms of similarity and difference (Wagner 2014;Wheeler2016). This Ba
difference which makes a difference^was, of course, Gregory Batesons basic
definition of information (Bateson 1972: 459). This is the basis of metaphor and also
what Charles Peirce described as abductive guessing. It is what lead Bateson to the
insight that all of nature depends on this form of logic:
It becomes evident that metaphor is not just pretty poetry, it is not either good or
bad logic, but is in fact the logic upon which the biological world has been built,
28 Favareau D. et al.
the main characteristic and organizing glue of this world of mental process that I
have been trying to sketch for you. (Bateson and Bateson 1988:28)
In addition, brains are developmentally specialised and enfolded skin. We can thus
surmise that the forms of encoding found in complex molecular systems within the
primal membranes by which selves are primarily constituted are subsequently evolved
in the sensual relations between bodies and environments, and that these form the basis
of phenomenologically enhanced mind in evolved animals. Eventually, human capac-
ities for abstraction, representation and formal logic build upon these semiotic process-
es. However, the active bases upon which such subsequent levels depend remain
essentially aesthetic forms which are more like natural metaphors, poems and music
than they are like machines. The understanding that the forms, structures and processes
of life begin in sensation and feelings which are thus essentially aesthetic is a very good
reason for biosemiotic science to value the humanities. As Bateson wrote:
On the whole, it was not the crudest, the simplest, the most animalistic and
primitive aspects of the human species that were reflected in the natural phenom-
ena. It was, rather, the more complex, the aesthetic, the intricate, and the elegant
aspects of people that reflected nature. It was not my greed, my purposiveness,
my so-called animal,so-calledinstincts, and so forth that I was recognising on
the other side of that mirror, over there in nature. Rather, I was seeing there the
roots of human symmetry, beauty and ugliness, aesthetics, the human beings
very aliveness and little bit of wisdom. His wisdom, his bodily grace, and even
his habit of making beautiful objects are just as animalas his cruelty. After all,
the very word animalmeans endowed with mind or spirit (animus) (Bateson
2002:4-5).
Acknowledgements I would like to thank the International Society for Biosemiotic Studies for encouraging
the affirmation of the interdisciplinary nature of biosemiotics by suggesting the compilation of this multi-
contributor essay on the importance of the humanities in the scientifically grounded biosemiotic endeavour.
References
Anderson, M. (2012). How qualification and quantification meet, or dont, in ethnography. In M. Bockarova,
M. Danesi, & R. Núñez (Eds.), Semiotic and cognitive science essays on the nature of mathematics (pp.
296329). Munich: Lincom Europa.
Anderson, M., Deely, J., Krampen, M., Ransdell, J., Sebeok, T. A., & von Uexküll, T. (1984). A semiotic
perspective on the sciences: Steps toward a new paradigm. Semiotica, 44,747.
Barthes, R. (1977a). From work to text. In S. Heath (Ed. & trans.), Image Music Text (pp. 155164).
London: Fontana.
Barthes, R. (1977b). Change the object itself. In S. Heath (Ed. & trans.), Image music text. London:
Fontana.
Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bateson, G. (2002 [1979]). Mind and nature: A necessary unity. Cresskill: Hampton Press.
Bateson, G., & Bateson, M. C. (1988). Angels fear: Towards an epistemology of the sacred. New York:
Bantam Books.
Beever, J. (2011). Meaning matters: The biosemiotic basis of bioethics. Biosemiotics, 5(2), 181191.
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 29
Beever, J., & Tønnessen, M. (2013). BDarwin und die Englische moral^: the moral consequences of Uexkülls
umwelt theory. Biosemiotics, 6(3), 437447.
Brockman, J. (1995). The third culture: Beyond the scientific revolution. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Calloway, E. (2017). Do you speak virus? Phages caught sending chemical messages: a virus that infects
bacteria listens to messages from its relatives when deciding how to attack its hosts. Nature. 18 January.
http://www.nature.com/news/do-you-speak-virus-phages-caught-sending-chemical-messages-1.21313.
Accessed 25 Feb 2017.
Champagne, M. (2011). Axiomatizing umwelt normativity. Sign Systems Studies, 39(1), 959.
Cobley, P. (2016). Cultural implications of biosemiotics, (biosemiotics 15.). Berlin: Springer.
Deacon, T. (1997). The symbolic species: the co-evolution of language and the brain.NewYork:Norton.
Deacon,T.W.(2012).Incomplete nature: How mind emerged from matter.NewYork:Norton.
Deely, J. N. (1992). Semiotics and biosemiotics: are sign-science and life-science coextensive? In T. A.
Sebeok, D. J. Umiker-Sebeok, & E. P. Young (Eds.), Biosemiotics: the semiotic web 1991 (pp. 4576).
New York: Praeger Publishers.
Deely, J. N. (2009a). Pars pro toto from culture to nature: an overview of semiotics as a postmodern
development, with an anticipation of developments to come. The American Journal of Semiotics,
25(1/2), 167193.
Deely, J. N. (2009b). Purely objective reality. Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Deely, J.N. (2015). Objective reality and the physical world: relation as key to understanding semiosis. In W.
Wheeler, L. Westling (Eds.) Green Letters: Studies in Ecocriticism Special issue on biosemiotics and
culture (Volume 19, Issue 3, pp. 267279).
Deely, J. N., Williams, B., & Kruse, F. (1986). Editors preface: Pars pro toto. In J. N. Deely, B. Williams, & F.
Kruse (Eds.), Frontiers in semiotics (pp. xviiixxxii). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Dunant, S. (Ed.). (1994). The war of the words: the political correctness debate. London: Virago.
Eco, U. (1990). Unlimited semiosis and drift. In The Limits of Interpretation (pp. 2343). Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
Emmeche, C. (1994). The garden in the machine: the emerging science of artificial life. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Favareau, D. (2008). Collapsing the wave function of meaning: The epistemological matrix of talk in
interaction. In J. Hoffmeyer (Ed.), A legacy of living systems: Gregory Bateson as a precursor to
biosemiotics (pp. 169212). Dordrecht: Springer-Verlag.
Favareau, D. (2015a). Symbols are grounded not in things, but in scaffolded relations and their semiotic
constraints. Biosemiotics, 8(2), 235255.
Favareau, D. (2015b). Creation of the relevant next: How living systems capture the power of the adjacent
possible through sign use. Journal of Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 119(3), 588601.
Favareau, D., & Kull, K. (2015). On biosemiotics and its possible relevance to linguistics. In E. Velmezova, K.
Kull, & S. Cowley (Eds.), Biosemiotic Perspectives on Language and Linguistics, (biosemiotics 13.) (pp.
1328). Dordrecht: Springer.
Gibson, J. J. (1986). The ecological approach to visual perception. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Hoffmeyer, J. (1993). Biosemiotics and ethics. In N. Witoszek & E. Gulbrandsen (Eds.), Culture and
environment: interdisciplinary approaches (pp. 152176). Oslo: Centre for Development and the
Environment.
Hoffmeyer, J. (1996). Signs of meaning in the universe (trans: Haveland, B.J.). Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
Hoffmeyer, J. (2007). Semiotic scaffolding of living systems. In M. Barbieri (Ed.), Introduction to
Biosemiotics (pp. 149166). Berlin: Springer.
Hoffmeyer, J. (2008). Biosemiotics: signs of life and the life of signs. Scranton: University of Scranton Press.
Hoffmeyer, J. (2010). Semiotics of nature. In P. Cobley (Ed.), The Routledge companion to semiotics (pp. 29
42). London: Routledge.
Hoffmeyer, J. (2014). The semiome: From genetic to semiotic scaffolding. Semiotica, 198,1131.
Kelly, K. (1998). The third culture. Science, 279(5353) (13 February 1998), 992993.
Kull, K. (2001). Biosemiotics and the problem of intrinsic value of nature. Sign Systems Studies, 29(1), 353
365.
Kull, K. (2011). Foundations for ecosemiotic deep ecology. In T. Peil (Ed.), The space of culture the place of
nature in Estonia and beyond (approaches to cultural theory 1) (pp. 6975). Tartu: Tartu University Press.
Kull, K. (2015). A semiotic theory of life: Lotmans principles of the universe of the mind. Green Letters:
Studies in Ecocriticism, 19(3), 255266.
Kull, K. (2016). What kind of evolutionary biology suits cultural research. Sign Systems Studies, 44(4), 634
647.
30 Favareau D. et al.
Kull, K., Kotov, K., Keskpaik, R. (2004). Semiotic fundamentals of deep ecology. In V. Sarapik (Ed.),
International conference culture, nature, semiotics: locations IV. Abstracts (p. 33). Tallinn: Estonian
literary museum.
Lin, M. F., Kheradpour, P., Washieti, S., Parker, B. J., Pedersen, J. S., & Kellis, M. (2011). Locating protein-
coding sequences under selection for additional, overlapping functions in 29 mammalian genomes.
Genome Research, 21(11), 19161928.
Lotman, J. (1974). The sign mechanism of culture. Semiotica, 12(4), 301305.
Lotman, Y. (1977). The structure of the artistic text. Michigan Slavic contributions 7 (trans: Lenhoff, G. &
Vroon, R.) Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan.
Lotman, J. (2011[1967]). The place of art among other modelling systems. Sign Systems Studies 39(2/4),
249270.
Maran, T. (2014a). Biosemiotic criticism: modelling the environment in literature. Green Letters: Studies in
Ecocriticism, 18(3), 297311.
Maran, T. (2014b). Semiotization of matter. A hybrid zone between biosemiotics and material ecocriticism. In
S. Iovino & S. Oppermann (Eds.), Material ecocriticism (pp. 141154). Bloomington: Indiana University
Press.
Maran, T. (2017). Mimicry and meaning: structure and semiotics of biological mimicry. (biosemiotics 16).
Berlin: Springer.
Marrone, G. (2014). The invention of the text. Milan: Mimesis.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The visible and the invisible (trans: Lingis, A.). Evanston: Northwestern University
Press.
Ostdiek, G. (2012). The self as social artifice: some consequences of Stanislavski. Biosemiotics, 5, 161179.
Ostdiek, G. (2015). Signs, science and religion: a biosemiotic mediation. In D. Evers et al. (Eds.), What is life?
(issues in science and theology 8) (pp. 169178). New York: Springer.
Ostdiek, G. (2016). Towards a post-biotic anthropology. In K. Pauknerova et. al. (Eds.) Non-humans and after
in social science. (pp. 7386) Červený Kostelec CZ: Pavel Mervart Publishing.
Peirce, C. S. (1891). The architecture of theories. The Monist, 1,161176.
Perron, P., Sbrocchi, L. G., Colilli, P., & Danesi, M. (Eds.). (2000). Semiotics as a bridge between the
humanities and the sciences. New York: Legas.
Polanyi, M. (1966). The tacit dimension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Ricoeur, P. (2003 [1975]). The rule of metaphor: The creation of meaning in language.(trans:Czerny,R.,
McLaughlin, K., Costello, J.). London: Routledge.
Santayana, G. (1923). Scepticism and animal faith. New York: Scribners.
Sebeok, T. A. (1984). Signs of life. International Semiotic Spectrum, 2(June 1984), 12.
Sebeok, T. A. (1991). In what sense is language a Bprimary modeling system^?InAsignisjustasign(pp. 49
58). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Sebeok, T. A. (2001). Global semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Shapiro, J.A. (2012). DNA as poetry: multiple messages in a single sequence. The Huffington Post. 24
January. http://www.huffingtonpost.com/james-a-shapiro/dna-as-poetry-multiple-me_b_1229190.html.
Accessed 14 Mar 2016.
Snow, C. P. (1959). The Two Cultures and the scientific revolution. The Rede Lecture. 1959. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Snow,C.P.(1963).The two cultures and a second look. An expanded version of the two cultures and the
scientific revolution (1959). New York: New American Library.
Tallis, R. (2011). Aping mankind: Neuromania, Darwinitis and the misrepresentation of humanity. London:
Acumen.
Tønnessen, M. (2003). Umwelt ethics. Sign Systems Studies, 31(1), 281299.
Tønnessen, M. (2009). Signs grow But should they? Semioethics and the dominant semiosis of Homo
sapiens sapiens (= Meditationes Semioticae I). Hortus Semioticus, 4,8184.
Tønnessen, M., & Beever, J. (2014). Beyond sentience: Biosemiotics as foundation for animal and environ-
mental ethics. In J. Hadley & E. Aaltola (Eds.), Animal ethics and philosophy: questioning the orthodoxy
(pp. 4762). London: Rowman & Littlefield International.
von Uexküll, J. (2013). Darwin and the English morality. Translation of BDarwin und die Englische moral^,
deutsche Rundschau 173: 215242. (trans.) M. Tønnessen, (Ed.), J. Beever. Biosemiotics, 6(3), 449471.
Wagner, A. (2014). Arrival of the fittest: Solving evolutions greatest puzzle. New York: Current.
Westling, L. (2014). The logos of the living world: Merleau-Ponty, animals, and language.NewYork:
Fordham University Press.
Wheeler, W. (2016). Expecting the earth: Life/culture/biosemiotics. London: Lawrence & Wishart.
Wol f , E. R . ( 19 64 ). Anthropology. New York: W.W. Norton.
Humanities in the study of biosemiotics 31
... Thereby, the authors illustrate the dynamic and non-linear nature of genetic and epigenetic influences on the diversity in observable characteristics. These chapters are good examples of the importance of developmental processes and the complex genotype-phenotype relationships in shaping evolutionary trajectories, offering an interpretation that bridges genetic determinism with the interpretative flexibility inherent in living systems that is not inconsistent with biosemiotic views on the interpretative nature of genetic and development (Favareau et al., 2017). ...
Article
Full-text available
This article reviews the edited volume “Evolvability: A Unifying Concept in Evolutionary Biology?” through biological and philosophical lenses. The book provides diverse angles on evolvability, which is affected by various hierarchical levels, timescales, and types of variation, thus moving beyond a purely genomics perspective. Evolvability is important to biosemiotics because understanding the dynamics of topological genotype spaces could help one better comprehend the phenotypic spaces of meaning, as developmental codes and interrelations can influence the emergence of biological novelty over time. This book is successful in provoking thought on evolvability's role as both a product and a driver of evolutionary innovations and explores the philosophical implications of how evolution has the capacity to generate novel forms of meaning.
... At present, the Internet has penetrated into various fields, driving the development of different industries. e best time is to achieve industrial upgrading [11]. e foundation of In-ternet+ is connection, as shown in Figure 2. ...
Article
Full-text available
Humanistic quality refers to the research ability, knowledge level of the humanities, and the human inner quality of the humanities. The purpose of this paper was to make a research on the cultivation of humanistic literacy of nursing undergraduates in the context of the Internet era. This paper first makes a general introduction of the classification of the Internet and the definition of humanistic literacy, analyzes the results of two rounds of expert consultation method, and then obtains the current situation of nursing undergraduates through the questionnaire survey of school nursing undergraduates. The experimental results showed that in the current survey situation, the expert support rate of humanistic care is as high as 90%, indicating that humanistic care is especially important for a nursing undergraduate. The total score of humanistic nursing ability of undergraduate nursing students was 127.03, which is in the middle level higher than that of most domestic studies, but lower than that of American nursing students.
Article
Full-text available
I adopt Conceptual Metaphor Theory (CMT) as a cognitive linguistic concept in a zoosemiotic framework to study behavioral polymorphic deception in Thaumoctopus Mimicus. This offers new analytical tools to zoosemiotics and may inform and underpin CMT from an evolutionary standpoint. The lack of studies on metaphorical thought in non-human animals, despite urgent calls for more diverse multimodal examples exbodying cross-domain mappings, reveals a strong anthropocentric bias in cognitive linguistics. A comprehensive theory of language, however, should be consistent from a diachronic and phylogenetic angle. The paper addresses how and for what metaphor, as an embodied cognitive phenomenon, may have emerged evolutionarily. It is posited that metaphor could have been present in animals before it became engrained in verbal language. This possibility is particularly relevant if we consider that lexical knowledge is not a prerequisite for metaphoric meaning-making, as the basic claim of CMT. I discuss that findings indicating embodied metaphoric processes in animals provide substantiation for cross-domain mappings as residing in cognitive systems.
Chapter
Attending to the 'Cry of the Earth' requires a critical appraisal of how we conceive our relationship with the environment, and a clear vision of how to apprehend it in law and governance. Addressing questions of participation, responsibility and justice, this collective endeavour includes marginalised and critical voices, featuring contributions by leading practitioners and thinkers in Indigenous law, traditional knowledge, wild law, the rights of nature, theology, public policy and environmental humanities.Such voices play a decisive role in comprehending and responding to current global challenges. They invite us to broaden our horizon of meaning and action, modes of knowing and being in the world, and envision the path ahead with a new legal consciousness. A valuable reference for students, researchers and practitioners, this book is one of a series of publications associated with the Earth System Governance Project. For more publications, see www.cambridge.org/earth-system-governance.
Article
Full-text available
We briefly review the impact of Paul Cobley (born 1963) on biosemiotics and list his works on the topic. These have links to communication studies and integrationism. After Thomas Sebeok, John Deely, and several others, Cobley has been a leader of the general semiotics movement, according to which “semiotics’ project is most fully realized on a biosemiotic basis.”
Article
Having been intimately aligned with the research agenda of biosemiotics since his colleague Thomas Sebeok first started using the term in 1992, Paul Cobley has consistently argued against the idea that the primary aim of biosemiotics is to make an intervention in the discourse and epistemology of the life sciences. Instead, he argues for the potential of a biosemiotically informed humanities for refashioning the ways in which we humans come to understand our situation within a world of signs and other organisms – as well as our existential duty of care for preserving the diversity and flourishing of both through the development of an anti-volunteerist ethics. Paul Cobley’s 2016 Cultural implications of biosemiotics fills a much-needed lacuna in the literature of biosemiotics in focusing with laser-like precision on those aspects of our human being – politics and aesthetics, education and ideology – that, Cobley rightly claims, have gone disproportionately under-analyzed and even under-appreciated in biosemiotics, due to its competing emphasis on reformulating biology. As one of the justly accused, I would like to take the occasion of this Festschrift to show the extent to which I now believe that Paul’s more expansive understanding of the purview of biosemiotics is, indeed, the proper one.
Article
Purpose This paper reviews research developments in semiosis (sign activity) as theorized by Peirce, Eco and Sebeok, focusing specifically on the current study of “semiotic threshold zones,” which range from the origins of life through various nonhuman life forms to artificial life forms, including those symbolic thresholds most familiar to library and information science (LIS) researchers. The intent is to illustrate potential opportunities for LIS research beyond its present boundaries. Design/methodology/approach The paper provides a framework that describes six semiotic threshold zones (presemiotic, protosemiotic, phytosemiotic, zoosemiotic, symbolic and polysemiotic) and notable work being done by researchers in each. Findings While semiotic researchers are still defining the continuum of semiotic thresholds, this focus on thresholds can provide a unifying framework for significance as human and nonhuman interpretations of a wide variety of signs accompanied by a better understanding of their relationships becomes more urgent in a rapidly changing global environment. Originality/value Though a variety of semiotic-related topics have appeared in the LIS literature, semiotic thresholds and their potential relationships to LIS research have not been previously discussed there. LIS has traditionally tasked itself with the recording, dissemination and preservation of knowledge, and in a world that faces unprecedented environmental and global challenges for all species, the importance of these thresholds may well be considered as part of our professional obligations in potentially documenting and archiving the critical differences in semiosis that extend beyond purely human knowledge.
Article
Full-text available
Este artículo fue publicado en inglés en Sign Systems Studies (first online, diciembre de 2021; versión impresa, 2022). La presente versión en español cuenta con la autorización de la autora. El artículo presenta los resultados de un estudio de caso centrado en explorar cómo se vinculan los significados de la naturaleza y las relaciones socioecológicas en una población indígena. Los hallazgos revelan que los habitantes de la comunidad configuran los significados sobre la naturaleza desde múltiples referencias de carácter biológico, espiritual, axiológico y cultural, y están frecuentemente representados por el referente "tierra". La noción de naturaleza (como tierra) es creada a partir de experiencias subjetivas y sociales con el ambiente y con el territorio, y a su vez, provee de significado a la identidad biocultural de la población. Sin embargo, los aprendizajes históricos, la visión sobre el mundo y la organización social también emergen como elementos estructurantes de los significados sociales de naturaleza y territorio.
Article
Full-text available
The paper presents a biosemiotic approach to the study of the built environment, its representations and practices in social media. First, it outlines the main developments that make semiotics hold a significant position in the study of urban space and the built environment. It then goes on to overcome the limitations of the binary opposition paradigm: in particular, nature/culture is reconsidered as a category in which the two terms are in a relation of mutual participation rather than being exclusive to each other. Following this, the paper explores three participatory categories that can be useful for the study of the built environment and its social media representations and practices: (a) life/semiosis, (b) natural environment/built environment, (c) text/practice. Finally, it identifies five main topics representing the interplay between the natural and built environment: the interaction of nature and architecture, urban parks, urban agriculture, digital environmentalism and ecotourism.
Article
Full-text available
This article poses the hypothesis that the problem of the intrinsic value of nature that stems from the work of G. E. Moore and is widely discussed in environmental philosophy, bas a parallel in a contemporary discussion in semiotics on the existence of semiosis in nature. From a semiotic point of view. value can be defined as an intentional dimension of sign. This is concordant with a biological interpretation of value that relates to biological needs. Thus. a semiotic approach in biology may provide a useful tool for further analysis of the intrinsic value problem in the biological realm. From an ecosemiotic point of view, the problem is also related to the concepts of bioart and ecoart. Ecoart viz environmental art is that which encompasses the human ambience, e.g., landscape or its components. Bioart call be defined as the art whose material ("clay") is a living body, living matter or communication of organisms (which may include, e.g., genetic engineering). It is concluded that the acceptance of biosemiotic view has implications for a large area of ecological philosophy.