ArticlePDF Available

Abstract and Figures

Background Over 90% of the organs transplanted in China before 2010 were procured from prisoners. Although Chinese officials announced in December 2014 that the country would completely cease using organs harvested from prisoners, no regulatory adjustments or changes in China’s organ donation laws followed. As a result, the use of prisoner organs remains legal in China if consent is obtained. DiscussionWe have collected and analysed available evidence on human rights violations in the organ procurement practice in China. We demonstrate that the practice not only violates international ethics standards, it is also associated with a large scale neglect of fundamental human rights. This includes organ procurement without consent from prisoners or their families as well as procurement of organs from incompletely executed, still-living prisoners. The human rights critique of these practices will also address the specific situatedness of prisoners, often conditioned and traumatized by a cascade of human rights abuses in judicial structures. Conclusion To end the unethical practice and the abuse associated with it, we suggest to inextricably bind the use of human organs procured in the Chinese transplant system to enacting Chinese legislation prohibiting the use of organs from executed prisoners and making explicit rules for law enforcement. Other than that, the international community must cease to abet the continuation of the present system by demanding an authoritative ban on the use of organs from executed Chinese prisoners.
Content may be subject to copyright.
D E B A T E Open Access
Human rights violations in organ
procurement practice in China
Norbert W. Paul
1
, Arthur Caplan
2
, Michael E. Shapiro
3
, Charl Els
4
, Kirk C. Allison
5*
and Huige Li
6*
Abstract
Background: Over 90% of the organs transplanted in China before 2010 were procured from prisoners. Although
Chinese officials announced in December 2014 that the country would completely cease using organs harvested
from prisoners, no regulatory adjustments or changes in Chinas organ donation laws followed. As a result, the use
of prisoner organs remains legal in China if consent is obtained.
Discussion: We have collected and analysed available evidence on human rights violations in the organ procurement
practice in China. We demonstrate that the practice not only violates international ethics standards, it is also associated
with a large scale neglect of fundamental human rights. This includes organ procurement without consent from
prisoners or their families as well as procurement of organs from incompletely executed, still-living prisoners. The
human rights critique of these practices will also address the specific situatedness of prisoners, often conditioned and
traumatized by a cascade of human rights abuses in judicial structures.
Conclusion: To end the unethical practice and the abuse associated with it, we suggest to inextricably bind the use of
human organs procured in the Chinese transplant system to enacting Chinese legislation prohibiting the use of organs
from executed prisoners and making explicit rules for law enforcement. Other than that, the international community
must cease to abet the continuation of the present system by demanding an authoritative ban on the use of organs
from executed Chinese prisoners.
Keywords: Organ procurement, Prisoners, Human rights, Medical ethics, China
Background
Before a pilot organ donation program was introduced
in 2010, at least 90% of the transplanted organs in China
were procured from prisoners [1]. China is the only
country in the world that systematically uses organs
from prisoners for transplantation [2]. After decades of
denial, China finally admitted the practice in 2005 [3, 4].
However, organ procurement from executed prisoners
continued.
In December 2014, the Chair of the China Organ Dona-
tion and Transplant Committee and former Vice-Minister
of Health, Huang Jiefu, announced that the country would
completely cease the use of prisoner organs for transplant-
ation in China after 2015. Surprisingly, this announcement
has not been followed by any changes to Chinas organ
donation laws or regulations (see website of PRC National
Health and Family Planning Commission: http://
en.nhfpc.gov.cn/regulations.html). The use of prisoner
organs remains legal, if so-called consent is obtained from
the prisoners [5, 6]. Such consents,however,eventhoseac-
tually signed by the prisoners, are not accepted by inter-
national organisations such as The Transplantation Society
(TTS) [7]. Because of the restrictions on liberty in a prison
environment, it is unlikely that prisoners are truly free to
make independent decisions and thus an autonomous
informed consent for donation cannot be obtained [7].
Organ harvesting from executed prisoners violates inter-
national principles of medical ethics [8]. The compromised
autonomy of all prisoners as an ethical restriction regarding
the process of informed consent had historically been de-
rived from a thorough analysis of crimes against humanity
performed by physicians during the German Nazi regime
mostly on prisoners in German concentration camps. In
Asia, crimes against humanity performed during World
WarIIwereshamefullynotprosecutedinasimilarwayas
* Correspondence: alli0001@umn.edu;huigeli@uni-mainz.de
5
School of Public Health, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, USA
6
Department of Pharmacology, Johannes Gutenberg University Medical
Center, Obere Zahlbacher Strasse 67, 55131 Mainz, Germany
Full list of author information is available at the end of the article
© The Author(s). 2017 Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0
International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and
reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to
the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver
(http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11
DOI 10.1186/s12910-017-0169-x
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
the Nuremberg Military Tribunals. The vivisections and
experimental atrocities performed by Japanese biological
warfare Unit 731 against occupied Chinese and prisoners of
war in Manchuria were not raised, addressed nor prose-
cuted during the Tokyo Trials [9, 10].
The unethical practice of organ procurement from
executed prisoners in China has lasted for decades [5].
Moreover, this practice is associated with large scale abuse
and severe human rights violations. In part, the transgres-
sion of ethical boundaries in the case of organ harvesting
is triggered by an ever growing local and global demand
for transplantable organs associated with the emergence
of a global (black) market [1113]. This heavily impacts
human rights, ethics and justice far beyond ideas calling
for regulated markets for organs [14].
In a prior publication, we explored the historical develop-
ment and status of organ procurement from death-row pris-
oners in China [5]. In the present article, we more closely
examine transgressions of human rights (mainly focusing on
legal considerations of human rights), contradictory frames
offered in justification, conditions claimed for consent of this
most vulnerable of populations, issues of brain death criteria
in the context of China, and several specific examples.
Organ procurement from executed prisoners
without consent
From the 1970s, organs were simply taken from executed
prisoners in China without asking for the permission of
the prisoners or their families. In 1984, the first Interim
Rules on Using the Body or Organs of Executed Crimi-
nals[15] (also translated as Provisional Regulation on
the Use of Dead Bodies or Organs from Condemned
Criminals[16]) officially allowed, for the first time, organ
harvesting from executed prisoners, under the condition
that either the body is not claimed; or the prisoner volun-
teers for organ donation; or the family consents.
As prescribed by the 1984 Rules, the use of the dead
bodies or organs from condemned criminals must be kept
strictly confidential. [] the operation vehicles from
medical institutions can be allowed entry into the execu-
tion grounds to remove organs, but vehicles with the logo
of medical institutions are not to be used, and white clinic
garments are not to be worn. The execution ground
should be guarded against before the operation is com-
pleted. After the dead bodies are used, the crematory shall
assist the [medical] units in timely cremation[16]. In
many cases, the families receive only the cremains without
being informed what has happened with the body of their
loved ones.
Recently, it has been repeatedly admitted by Chinese
transplant officials that organs from executed prisoners
had been procured without consent [1719]. For ex-
ample, a Chinese medical official admitted in 2013 that
previously, authorities used executed criminalsorgans
without their consent, while permission has been re-
quired in recent years[17]. In 2014, when Hong Kong
newspaper Mingpao asked the question whether
prisoners and their families are informed and consent
obtained before organ procurement, Huang Jiefu admit-
ted that we have not been able to achieve this, but we
will soon[18]. In 2015, Huang Jiefu admitted that the
problem with Chinas organ transplantation system was
that the laws were not obeyed: Although the law
provides that the use of prisoner organs must be from
voluntary donation, but there are still loopholes in the
law enforcement[19]. All of these statements strongly
suggest that organs were procured in China largely with-
out consent of the prisoners or their families.
Although organ procurement without consent is illegal
according to Chinese laws, the practice appears to be
tolerated by the authorities in China.
Organ procurement from incompletely executed
prisoners
At a European Parliament hearing on 29 January 2013,
Enver Tohti testified that he was ordered in 1995 to harvest
organs from an incompletely executed, still-living prisoner
in China [20]. More details were revealed in his interviews
with ABC [21], BBC [22] and journalist Ethan Gutmann
[23, 24]. When Enver Tohti got the body of the executed
prisoner, he noticed, however, that the prisoner was not
dead. The gunshot, gun wound was on his right chest. So,
I guess that was deliberately to make this prisoner not die
immediately to allow some time for us to remove that
organ when he is still alive[21]. When Tohti kept making
attempts to follow normal procedure sterilize, minimal
exposure, sketch the cut - the chief surgeon told him to
hurry up. No anesthesia, no life support,we are working
against time. Finally, Tohti extracted the liver and the
kidneys from the still-living prisoner [23, 24].
Unfortunately, this was not the only case reported. An
early case has been documented in the book Chinaseyes
[25]. In 1978, Zhong Haiyuan, a schoolteacher from the
Jiangxi Province, was sentenced to death for her counter-
revolutionarythoughts. The execution was performed by
three officers from the Peoples Armed Police Forces on
April 30, 1978. Two officers fixed Zhong while the third
officer put the gun against her back on the right side and
fired the bullet [25]. Years later, one of the officers told the
booksauthor that the order was not to kill Zhong imme-
diately. The kidneys must be harvested before she dies,
because the army doctors wanted high quality kidneys,
kidneys from a living person[25].
More recently, Mr. Wang, who currently lives in
Canada, revealed that he was once a member of a team
extracting organs from a still-living person. The incident
happened in the 1990s when Wang was an intern doctor
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11 Page 2 of 9
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
at the urology department of the Shenyang Military
General Hospital in Liaoning Province [26].
In March 2015, Jiang Yanyong told to Hong Kong jour-
nalists that corruption, illegal transplantation and organ
trade were common in military hospitals [27, 28]. Jiang
elaborated on the case of Li Shiyong, director of the
Department of General Surgery of the Beijing Military
General Hospital. With no prior experience in transplant-
ation and without asking for permission of the hospital
director, Li founded a liver transplantation center in 2005
and appointed himself as the director. Because Li had
found ways to obtain donor livers, he could serve as the
director (see Additional file 1: Table S1).
In the same TV interview, Jiang also revealed that many
of the prisoners used for organ harvesting were shot but
not completely killed [27, 28]. The purpose was for organ
harvesting while the prisoners were still alive in order to
keep the warm ischemic time of the sourced organs as
short as possible (see Additional file 1: Table S1).
Jiang as a source is, we contend, credible based on his
personal story within the Chinese medical system. He was
a chief physician of the 301 Military Hospital (Peoples
Liberation Army General Hospital) in Beijing where he
witnessed the results of the trauma inflicted on the
students during the Tiananmen Square Massacre of 1989.
Jiang was also the person who publicized the cover-up of
the Severe Acute Respiratory Syndrome (SARS) epidemic
by the Chinese government in 2003.
Unfortunately, the strength of these examples is con-
strained by the fact that the number of executions and
the detailed techniques used are state secrets in China;
empirical data cannot be generated. There are no statis-
tics available on the incidence of the practice of incom-
plete executions in China. A systematic international
investigation into this issue is needed in the interest of
(overdue) justice for the victims.
The medical and ethical function of brain death
and its implementation in China
In most Western cultures, treating a person only as a mere
means to an end of another is a challenge to core concepts
of human dignity as Immanuel Kant and other 18th cen-
tury philosophers argued [29]. Even from a contemporary
perspective, ethicists have always argued that transferring
organs to another person either from a living donor or
from post mortem procured organs must be contextualized
in a way that a) human dignity, b) autonomy and c) social
justifiability in the light of shared values are not endan-
gered [30, 31].
Here, human dignity is understood to be an applied
concept. Based on the notion of phenomenological dignity
it is cognition that enables humans to identify themselves
and to perceive others as human beings which are to be
treated with the same respect (dignity) that one would
expect for oneself. This concept is fostered by a reflexive
mode of dignity in which the constant (re-)evaluation and
adjustment of actions is put in place by relating both,
intentions and consequences to commonly accepted
values, like those which constitute our understanding of
human rights. Finally, the mutual appreciation of humans
together with a value based evaluation and adjustment of
interaction turn dignity into a relational concept which
ought to be the guiding principle of human coexistence.
Especially the relational dimension of dignity is addressed
in discourses on brain death when it comes to evaluations
of those values, moral concepts and needs which need to
be reflected for both, donors and recipients of organs [32].
Only this clarification could lead to a situation in which
the concept of brain death established the medical basis
and justification to switch from life-sustaining care setting
to considering a deceased person as a cadaver organ donor.
Ethically, brain death is the fine line on which dignity of a
living and acting person changes into the dignity of a de-
ceased person, and respecting autonomy of a living person
shifts over into respecting an advanced directive or declared
will to donate organs. In this context, the justifiability of
organ procurement is derived from the fact that the brain-
dead person can donate organs without suffering from vital
consequences caused by organ removal (e.g. pain and
death), since he or she is already dead. Intensive care is pro-
vided only to protect the organs of the deceased.
It is this integration of medical and ethical functions of
brain death which makes organ procurement a widely ac-
cepted practice in Western culture. This is especially true
because of the potential for other procurement strategies,
such as procurement from non-heart-beating donors (Do-
nation after Circulatory Death - DCD), which require
careful, detailed and transparent protocols, in order to as-
sure the avoidance of even the potential for conflict of
interest regarding treatment, and verification of the death
of the donor [33, 34]. Circulatory death is, if not clearly
defined as the irreversible cessation of cardiovascular
circulation, potentially reversible. Furthermore, it can be
prognostically highly dependent on a number of arbitrary,
concomitant circumstances (time, temperature, cause),
thus requiring strict protocols, including electrocardiog-
raphy and blood pressure monitoring to assure death has
occurred, and is permanent. DCD donation may also lead
to decreased quality of recovered organs, because of
prolonged ischemia, or reduced number of organs that
can be procured. It thus has to be seen as a procedure
only applicable in an environment with reliable clinical
standard operating procedures (SOPs) which have to be
implemented in an evidence-based mode by well-trained
medical personnel [34, 35].
However, there is yet no brain death legislation in
China and circulatory death is the legal standard despite
the absence of evidence-based and reliable SOPs [36].
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11 Page 3 of 9
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
China lacks any state issued official guidelines to diag-
nose brain death.
In 2003, the Ministry of Health drafted Brain Death
Determination Criteriaand Brain Death Determination
Technical Specifications(comment drafts). In 2009, the
Ministry of Health revised the two documents. In March
2012, the National Health and Family Planning Commis-
sion (NHFPC, the former Ministry of Health) assigned
Xuanwu Hospital of Capital Medical University as the
Brain Injury Quality Control Evaluation Center. In 2013,
the Center further revised and combined the two docu-
ments into Brain Death Determination Criteria and
Technical Specification (Adult Quality Control Version)
[37]. These Criteria and Technical Specifications repre-
sent a suggested medical standard; it is not a standard
procedure, a mandatory guideline for medical practi-
tioners or an administrative regulation. Above all, the
standard is not legally binding. As stated in the Editors
Note accompanying its publication, the Center has re-
vised and improved the above-mentioned documents on
the basis of 10 years of clinical practice and research on
brain death determination, and hopes that the new
document serves as the medical standard to promote
the brain death determination in our country to develop
orderly and normatively[37].
The first documented brain death diagnosis in China was
performed on 25 February 2003, in Wuhan, Hubei Province
[38]. The brain death determination was carried out ac-
cording to the published 2003 draft. In November 2003, the
kidneys of a boy diagnosed as brain dead were used for
transplantation with the consent of the parents [39]. Both
events were considered breakthroughs in Chinese trans-
plant medicine. Both were nominated by major Chinese
media to be among the top 10 medical stories of 2003 [40]
(Fig. 1). Since then, there have been reported increasing
numbers of organ donations after brain death, although it
is illegal to take organs from the brain-dead for transplant
purposesin China, as acknowledged by China Daily [41].
Even though no brain death legislation has been effectu-
ated in China, the Chinese Classification of Deceased
Organ Donation has been recently formulated as follows:
China Category I: Organ donation after Brain Death;
China Category II: Organ Donation after Circulatory
Death; China Category III: Organ Donation after Brain
Death followed by Circulatory Death[36]. The ambiguity
of this classification together with the absence of SOPs,
guidelines, regulations and legislation leads to a situation
in which legal, medical and ethical uncertainty continues.
Execution by organ explantation?
The medical journal Henan Medical Research published
a research paper titled The experience of homologuous
orthotopic heart transplantation(Fig. 2). The operation
was allegedly performed in a hospital of the Peoples
Armed Police Force in 2001 and the paper published in
2003 [42]. The 32-year-old male recipient died from
infection 46 days after the heart transplantation [42].
In the section 2.1 of this research paper, the major
points of donor heart removalincluded: systemic
heparinization (2 mg/kg); delivery of cold cardioplegia to
the heart through the aortic root until the heart stopped
beating; cut of the superior vena cava at 4 cm above
right atrium …” (Fig. 2). Besides blood type and heart
weight, no other information about the donor was pro-
vided in the paper.
The fact that systemic heparinization was performed
and heart beating was stopped by cold cardioplegia im-
plies that the blood was circulating and the heart was
functional before the explantation procedure. Logically,
one of the following two scenarios are applicable to
describe the heart explantation: (i) the donor was a brain
death patient and a brain death diagnosis was performed
as it would have in most confirmatory brain death diagno-
ses based on neurological standard operating procedures
(e.g. in the EUROTRANSPLANT region); (ii) the donor
was not a brain death patient and the cardiac death was
induced by the cold cardioplegia delivered by the medical
professionals.
In this context, it is important to re-emphasize that
there is no brain death legislation in China and circula-
tory death is still the legal standard in China [36]. As
mentioned above, the first brain death determination in
China was performed in 2003 (Fig. 1) [38]. The heart
transplantation in this publication, however, was per-
formed in 2001 and the concept of brain deathis not
mentioned. This therefore raises the question as to
whether the donor was brain dead, especially given that
the paper was published at a time where the diagnostic
procedure alone would have captured the attention of
the Chinese medical community and would have con-
tributed positively to the scientific impact of the paper.
It is thus reasonable to assume that the delivery of cold
cardioplegia served the purpose of execution and
explantation at the same time.
Human rights: grounding and violations
On 26 June 1945 in San Francisco, the Republic of
China (ROC), first in suffering Axis aggression, was also
first to sign the United Nations Charter and Statute for
the International Court of Justice, which entered into
force on 24 October, establishing the United Nations.
The latter date followed the Double Tenth Agreement
(10/10/1945) between Chaing Kai-Shek and Mao
Zedong wherein the Chinese Communist Party (CCP)
acknowledged the Republics Kuomintang government
as legitimate and the Kuomintang the CCP as a legitim-
ate opposition party. Full scale civil war resumed 26
June 1946. Before Mao proclaimed the Peoples
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11 Page 4 of 9
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Republic of China on 1 October 1949, the ROC en-
dorsed the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (10
December 1948). The mainland PeoplesRepublicwas
not a party to UN human rights instruments before
1971 but reaffirmed the UN Charter and UDHR after
the Republic of China was unseated. The PRC is now
party to at least 17 international instruments [43].
The United Nations Office of High Commissioner for
Human Rights characterizes universal human rights as in-
terrelated, interdependent and indivisibleoften expressed
Fig. 1 The first brain death determination in China. Shown is an Expert Opinion paper published in National Medical Journal of China (Zhonghua
Yi Xue Za Zhi), a top medical journal in China, by Chen & Qiu [40]. Text in left box: At the beginning of 2003, the drafting group of the Ministry
of Health completed the Brain Death Determination Criteria (for adults). According to these criteria, the Brain Death Coordinating Group of the
Tongji Hospital at the Tongji Medical College, Huazhong University of Science and Technology, completed the first brain death determination
and treatment cessation in China on 25 February 2003. Text in right box: The animal model of brain death, the first brain death determination in
adults, and the first brain death in children followed by unpaid organ donation these three pioneering works were nominated by 10 major
Chinese media to be among the top ten medical news of 2003, ranking from 3 to 7, respectively
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11 Page 5 of 9
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
in treaties, customary international law (i.e. implicit norms)
or general principles. Documents comprise moral declara-
tions, which implicitly presuppose a concept of human
flourishing, and derivative binding treaties (covenants, con-
ventions, protocols). The troika of the 1948 UDHR and the
complementary international covenants on Economic, So-
cial and Cultural Rights (ICESCR) and Civil and Political
Rights (ICCPR), respectively opened for signature in paral-
lel in 1966, comprise the so-called Bill of Human Rights,
with others building upon them.
China is a full party to the ICESCR (signed 1997, rati-
fied 2001); the Convention against Torture and Other
Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment
(CAT, ratified 1988); the Convention on the Prevention
and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (signed 1949,
ratified 1983); and the United Nations Convention
against Transnational Crime (ratified 2003) whose con-
cerns include organ trafficking (albeit patients rather
than prisoner organs have comprised the transnational
element in China).
Fig. 2 Questionable heart explantation. The operation was performed on 19 October 2001 in the hospital of the Peoples Armed Police Forces in
Zhengzhou City, Henan Province. That was two years before the first documented brain death determination was performed in China. Underlined
text: Major points of donor heart removal: systemic heparinization (2 mg/kg); delivery of cold cardioplegia to the heart through the aortic root
until the heart stopped beating. The first page of the publication by Guo et al. in the medical journal Henan Medical Research is shown [42]
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11 Page 6 of 9
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
China also signed, but has not ratified, the ICCPR in
October 1998. While formally not bound by ICCPR provi-
sions until ratification or accession, China is obliged not to
defeat its general purpose. Per the Foreign Ministry at the
time, Chinas 1998 signature demonstrates its firm deter-
mination to promote and protect human rightsas well as
concretely commemorating the UDHRs 50th anniversary,
acknowledging a coherence bridging moral and legal rights.
It also emphasized flexibility in prioritization: the principle
of the universality of human rights must be respected, but
the specific conditions of each country must also be taken
into consideration in observing this principle,highlighting
economic development successes against poverty. The tone
markedly contrasts more recent ideological tightening con-
tra Western ideas, expressly against universal values of
human rights, parallel to an anticorruption campaign short
on procedural protections [44].
China domestically has circulated alternatively phrased
translations of signed human rights conventions rather
than the UNs official Chinese text, according to one
source providing an interpretive buffer while also impri-
soning those who ask for the ICCPR to be ratified [45].
Legally binding, however, are the official UN language
versions, not CCP state paraphrases.
Human rights violations ending in organ harvesting from
prisoners are, like human rights, also interrelated and inter-
dependent. Violation cascades one violation increasing
probability of another given the substantive interrelationship
of rights - increase vulnerability cumulatively whether in a
specific person or in a targeted population. Rights violations
via detention schemes and a death penalty regime subject to
manipulation with lack of sufficient representation or appeal
[46] precondition the subsequent act of forced organ extrac-
tion: risk accumulates to a specific subject and identifiable
population. In this sense, the implication of the title of this
paper is extensive and systemic, not simply perioperative.
De jure and de facto factors, frequently in violation of inter-
national human rights standards, lead to and condition the
supply of prisoners being solicited before execution or
simply exploited in the first instance.
Specifically concerning the death penalty, variability
includes bringing charges across 46 potentially capital of-
fenses; death sentences and executions waxing and waning
during strike hardcampaigns; and executions increasing
before the new year. Furthermore, judges in China are not
unaware that executees are the mainstay of transplantation.
Beyond the design of preserving public order and social
control through execution is added the exogenous influ-
ence of medical demand for execution as the chief gateway
to a social good (organs for transplantation), at times
indirectly abetted by the international community (e.g. The
Transplantation Societyspolicysupportingprovidingtrain-
ing to Chinese transplant surgeons under the banner of in-
fluencing eventual reform while simultaneously expanding
capacity, as in the TTS Ethics Committee Letter of 6 No-
vember 2006 to TTS members [47]). It is notable that the
initial 1984 Rules officially allowing organ harvesting from
executed prisoners cited the initiative of medical personnel,
not the state, as seeking to exploit this context for organ
sourcing [16].
The practice of organ procurement in China that we
have described violates freedom from torture and other
cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment
(UDHR, CAT, ICCPR Art. 7). Nowhere is an individual
as subject to state power than in prison, and nowhere in
prison than when awaiting execution. However, it is the
contiguous context, not merely local choice
, that is
proper object of the human rights critique, exposing the
step-wise cumulative vulnerability of prisoners at risk of
being exploited in and through execution. This is aided
and abetted by medical demand by an occupation that
first pushed for exploiting execution for organ harvest-
ing, and by a citizen population willing to rely upon,
benefit from, and exploit the bound population - evident
from ongoing reticence to participate in voluntary donor
registration, yet seeking transplantation surgeries.
In general, an alibi of system reform has been counte-
nanced too long. After over a decade of reform claims
and the redefinition of the status of prisoners, the ethical
outcome respecting human rights in China, here
conforming with international medical ethical standards,
is categorical cessation of organ sourcing from prisoners.
Practically, this would remove the perverse incentives
shared and relied upon by medical and judicial establish-
ments, and by the general population. Given the nature
of the violations and delay, justification of gradually real-
izing an ethical practice fails. This recognition should
hold for actors and institutions of influence outside of
China now in possession of over a decade of knowledge.
While human rights violations in China span systemic
structural preconditions, augmented by political whim,
the most proximate point of intervention still lies with
the medical community and professional societies.
Admitting the failure of gradualism, and increasing,
rather than decreasing, professional sanctions, may more
quickly realize the intent: Cessation of prisoner organ
sourcing generally; reducing perverse incentives in death
penalty demand (moral hazard); and confronting the
general population with two ethical alternatives: sup-
porting or declining voluntary organ transplantation as a
system, while bearing the cost of either choice.
Conclusion
The unethical practice of organ procurement from exe-
cuted prisoners in China is associated with a large scale
of abuse and a cascade of severe human rights violations,
including, we contend, organ explantation from still-
alive human beings, and, upstream, conditioning the
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11 Page 7 of 9
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
supply of prisoners exploited per se or then solicited to
freelyoffer organs as atonement for real or supposed
crimes. Those involved in organ harvesting from still-
alive prisoners must be prosecuted. The unethical prac-
tice of lethally procuring vital organs from the living
must be prevented by a law prohibiting use of prisoner
organs generally, supporting change in the practical
legal, medical and popular culture surrounding trans-
plantation in China. Finally, greater influence may be
exerted by international institutions through change of
strategy.
Additional file
Additional file 1: Table S1. Jiang Yanyong Interview in March 2015.
This additional file provides further information on Jiang Yanyongs
statements (including English translation) in his interview by Hong Kong
journalists. (PDF 439 kb)
Abbreviations
CAT: Convention against torture and other cruel, inhuman or degrading
treatment or punishment; CCP: Chinese Communist Party; DCD: Donation
after circulatory death; ICCPR: International covenant on civil and political
rights; ICESCR: International covenant on economic social and cultural rights;
PRC: Peoples Republic of China; ROC: Republic of China; SARS: Severe acute
respiratory syndrome; SOP: Standard operating procedure; TTS: The
Transplantation Society; UDHR: Universal declaration of human rights
Acknowledgments
We thank the BMC Medical Ethics reviewers and editors for their comments
and suggestions that helped us substantially to revise this article.
Funding
This work was partly supported by the grant Graduiertenkolleg (GRK) 2015/1
Life Writing - Life Sciencesfrom the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft
(DFG), Bonn, Germany.
Availability of data and materials
The datasets supporting the conclusions of this article are included within
the article and its additional file. Some reports (e.g. references [19] and [41])
are additionally archived on a publicly accessible server (https://archive.is).
The web addresses of the archived reports are provided at the end of the
references.
Authorscontributions
NWP drafted the manuscript and critically revised the manuscript. AC helped
to draft the manuscript and critically revised the manuscript. MES helped to
draft the manuscript and critically revised the manuscript. CE helped to draft
the manuscript and critically revised the manuscript. KCA drafted the
manuscript and critically revised the manuscript. HL drafted the manuscript
and critically revised the manuscript. All authors read and approved the final
manuscript.
Competing interests
The authors declare that they have no competing interests.
Consent for publication
Not applicable.
Ethics approval and consent to participate
Not applicable.
Author details
1
Institute for History, Philosophy and Ethics of Medicine, Johannes
Gutenberg University Medical Center, Mainz, Germany.
2
Division of Medical
Ethics, School of Medicine, New York University, New York, NY, USA.
3
Department of Surgery, Rutgers - New Jersey Medical School, Newark, USA.
4
Department of Psychiatry, University of Alberta, Edmonton, Canada.
5
School
of Public Health, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, USA.
6
Department of
Pharmacology, Johannes Gutenberg University Medical Center, Obere
Zahlbacher Strasse 67, 55131 Mainz, Germany.
Received: 8 May 2016 Accepted: 24 January 2017
References
1. Huang J, Mao Y, Millis JM. Government policy and organ transplantation in
China. Lancet. 2008;372(9654):19378.
2. Delmonico F, Chapman J, Fung J, Danovitch G, Levin A, Capron A, Busuttil R,
O'Connell P. Open letter to Xi Jinping, President of the People's Republic of
China: China's fight against corruption in organ transplantation.
Transplantation. 2014;97(8):7956.
3. Macartney J. China to tidy uptrade in executed prisonersorgans. The
Times. 3 Dec 2005. http://www.thetimes.co.uk/tto/news/world/asia/
article2612313.ece . Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
4. Sharif A, Singh MF, Trey T, Lavee J. Organ procurement from executed
prisoners in china. Am J Transplant. 2014;14(10):224652.
5. Allison KC, Caplan A, Shapiro ME, Els C, Paul NW, Li H. Historical
development and current status of organ procurement from death-row
prisoners in China. BMC Med Ethics. 2015;16(1):85.
6. Trey T, Sharif A, Schwarz A, Singh MF, Lavee J. Transplant Medicine in
China: Need for Transparency and International Scrutiny Remains. Am J
Transplant. 2016; 16(11):3115-3120. doi: 10.1111/ajt.14014.2016.
7. The Transplantaton Society. Policy & Ethics. https://www.tts.org/index.php?option=
com_content&view=article&id=11&Itemid=223. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
8. Caplan A. The use of prisoners as sources of organsan ethically dubious
practice. Am J Bioeth. 2011;11(10):15.
9. Watts J. Victims of Japan's notorious Unit 731 sue. Lancet. 2002;360(9333):628.
10. Hickey D, Li SS, Morrison C, Schulz R, Thiry M, Sorensen K. Unit 731 and
moral repair. J Med Ethics. 2016. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2015-103177.
[Epub ahead of print.]
11. Jafar TH. Organ trafficking: global solutions for a global problem. Am J
Kidney Dis. 2009;54(6):114557.
12. MacKellar C. Human organ markets and inherent human dignity. New
Bioeth. 2014;20(1):5371.
13. Starzl T, Teperman L, Sutherland D, Sollinger H, Roberts J, Miller C, Merion R,
Matas A, Marsh JW, Langnas A, et al. Transplant tourism and unregulated
black-market trafficking of organs. Am J Transplant. 2009;9(6):1484.
14. Surman OS, Saidi R, Burke TF. Regulating thesaleofhumanorgans:adiscussionin
context with the global market. Curr Opin Organ Transplant. 2008;13(2):196201.
15. Ding C. Latest development of legal regulations of organ transplant in
China. J Int Bioethique. 2008;19(4):6181. 162.
16. Provisional regulations on the use of dead bodies or organs from
condemned criminals (1984). in: Organs for sale: Chinas growing trade and
ultimate violation of prisonersrights: hearing before the Subcommittee on
International Operations and Human Rights of the Committee on
International Relations, House of Representatives, One Hundred Seventh
Congress, first session, June 27, 2001. p50-53. https://babel.hathitrust.org/
cgi/pt?id=pst.000045422089;view=1up;seq=3. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
17. Robertson M. Chinese medical official admits that organs were
extracted without consent. Epoch Times. 2013. http://www.
theepochtimes.com/n3/263294-chinese-medical-official-admits-that-
organs-were-extracted-without-consent/. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
18. High official admitting that prisoner organs are still being used - without
consent of the prisoners or their families (in Chinese). Mingpao.com. 2014.
http://archive.is/N4qaf#selection-1157.1-1157.58. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
19. Former Vice-Minister of Health: foreigners have demonized Chinese doctors
because of use of prisoner organs (in Chinese). CCTVnews. 2015. http://m.
thepaper.cn/newsDetail_forward_1293555. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
20. Religious persecution by China: A horror story. UNPO. 2013. http://www.
unpo.org/article/15404. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
21. China promises prisoner organ donation phasing out. ABC.net.au. 20 May 13.
http://www.abc.net.au/7.30/content/2013/s3763410.htm. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
22. Organ harvesting in China. BBC. 2013. http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/
p017k033. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
23. Gutmann E. The Xinjiang procedure. Weekly Standard. 2011. http://www.
weeklystandard.com/thexinjiang-procedure/article/610145. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11 Page 8 of 9
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
24. Gutmann E. The slaughter : mass killings, organ harvesting, and China's
secret solution to its dissident problem. Amherst: Prometheus Books; 2014.
25. Hu P. Chinas eyes (Chinese Edition ISBN: 9787539168944). Nanchang City:
21th Century Publishing House; 2011.
26. Yi L. Former Chinese Hospital Intern Recounts a Live Organ Harvest. Epoch
Times. 2015. http://www.theepochtimes.com/n3/1277305-former-chinese-
hospital-intern-recounts-a-live-organ-harvest/. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
27. Retired military doctor Jiang Yanyong: trading of organs from executed
prisoners common in militaryhospitals (in Chinese). https://news.powerapple.
com/she-hui-qi-wen/2015/3/7/2103371.html. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
28. Military Doctor of Conscience Jiang Yanyong denounced serious corruption in
the army (in Chinese). 6 Mar 2015. http://cablenews.i-cable.com/webapps/
news_video/index.php?news_id=453447. Video 6 Mar 2015https://www.
facebook.com/icablenews/videos/360349840823757/. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
29. Kant I, Gregor MJ, Timmermann J. Groundwork of the metaphysics of
morals : a German-English edition. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge
University Press; 2011.
30. Caplan AL, McCartney JJ, Reid DP. Replacement parts : the ethics of
procuring and replacing organs in humans. Washington: Georgetown
University Press; 2015.
31. Truog RD. The ethics of organ donation by living donors. N Engl J Med.
2005;353(5):4446.
32. Veatch RM, Ross LF. Transplantation ethics. 2nd ed. Washington:
Georgetown University Press; 2015.
33. Verheijde JL, Rady MY, McGregor J. Presumed consent for organ
preservation in uncontrolled donation after cardiac death in the United
States: a public policy with serious consequences. Philos Ethics Humanit
Med. 2009;4:15.
34. Potts Jr JT, Herdman R. Non-Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation: Medical
and Ethical Issues in Procurement. Washington: 1997.
35. Cerutti C. Donation after cardiac death: respecting patient autonomy and
guaranteeing donation with guidance from Oregon's Death with Dignity
Act. Albany Law Rev. 2012;75(4):2199222.
36. Huang J, Millis JM, Mao Y, Millis MA, Sang X, Zhong S. Voluntary organ
donation system adapted to Chinese cultural values and social reality. Liver
Transpl. 2015;21(4):41922.
37. NHFPC Brain Injury Quality Control Evaluation Center. Brain Death
Determination Criteria and Technical Specification (for Adults; Quality Control
Version) (in Chinese). Zhonghua Shen Jing Ke Za Zhi. 2013;46(9):63740.
38. Chen ZH, Zhang SM, Bu BT, Jiang YP, Wang JX, Yin XP, Tang ZP, Li W-H, Shu P,
Qiu FZ. [Brain death pronouncement and practice, 1 case]. Zhonghua Yi Xue
Za Zhi. 2003;83:17234.
39. Chen ZH, Zhang SM, Lei T, Zheng Z, Zeng FJ, Chen ZS, Wang HY, Zhou HM,
Jiang JP, Wei L, et al. [China's first brain death determination in children and
free organ donation and transplantation]. Zhonghua Yi Xue Za Zhi. 2004;
84(8):61920.
40. Chen ZH, Qiu FZ. [Brain death and organ donation: the ultimate
combination of modern science and humanism]. Zhonghua Yi Xue Za
Zhi. 2004;84(8):618.
41. Juan S. Health authorities to define legal brain death. China Daily. 2007.
http://www.chinadaily.com.cn/china/2007-08/23/content_6037065. Accessed
28 Jan 2017.
42. Guo H-X, Liu S-Y, Jiang R-T, Wang Y-W, Bai H-C, Zhang Y-Q, Yang Q-Z. The
experience of homologuous orthotopic heart transplantation (in Chinese
with english abstract). Henan Med Res. 2003;12(2):1313.
43. Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Peoples Republic of China. The Signing of
the International Convention on Civil and Political Rights By the Chinese
Government. 2014. http://www.fmprc.gov.cn/mfa_eng/ziliao_665539/3602_
665543/3604_665547/t18041.shtml. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
44. Buckley C. China takes aim at Western ideas. New York Times. 2013. http://
www.nytimes.com/2013/08/20/world/asia/chinas-new-leadership-takes-hard-
line-in-secret-memo.html?_r=0. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
45. Suppressed in translation: How Chinese versions of UN covenants gloss
over human rights. Economist. 2016. http://www.economist.com/news/
china/21695095-how-chinese-versions-un-covenants-glossover-human-
rights-suppressed-translation. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
46. Lan R. False promises of fair trails. Pacific Basin Law J. 2010;27(2):153212.
47. The Transplantation Society. TTS Ethics Commitee Policy Statement -
Chinese Transplantation Program. 2006. https://www.tts.org/images/stories/
pdfs/StatementMembs-ChineseTXProg.pdf. Accessed 28 Jan 2017.
We accept pre-submission inquiries
Our selector tool helps you to find the most relevant journal
We provide round the clock customer support
Convenient online submission
Thorough peer review
Inclusion in PubMed and all major indexing services
Maximum visibility for your research
Submit your manuscript at
www.biomedcentral.com/submit
Submit your next manuscript to BioMed Central
and we will help you at every step:
Paul et al. BMC Medical Ethics (2017) 18:11 Page 9 of 9
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
Terms and Conditions
Springer Nature journal content, brought to you courtesy of Springer Nature Customer Service Center GmbH (“Springer Nature”).
Springer Nature supports a reasonable amount of sharing of research papers by authors, subscribers and authorised users (“Users”), for small-
scale personal, non-commercial use provided that all copyright, trade and service marks and other proprietary notices are maintained. By
accessing, sharing, receiving or otherwise using the Springer Nature journal content you agree to these terms of use (“Terms”). For these
purposes, Springer Nature considers academic use (by researchers and students) to be non-commercial.
These Terms are supplementary and will apply in addition to any applicable website terms and conditions, a relevant site licence or a personal
subscription. These Terms will prevail over any conflict or ambiguity with regards to the relevant terms, a site licence or a personal subscription
(to the extent of the conflict or ambiguity only). For Creative Commons-licensed articles, the terms of the Creative Commons license used will
apply.
We collect and use personal data to provide access to the Springer Nature journal content. We may also use these personal data internally within
ResearchGate and Springer Nature and as agreed share it, in an anonymised way, for purposes of tracking, analysis and reporting. We will not
otherwise disclose your personal data outside the ResearchGate or the Springer Nature group of companies unless we have your permission as
detailed in the Privacy Policy.
While Users may use the Springer Nature journal content for small scale, personal non-commercial use, it is important to note that Users may
not:
use such content for the purpose of providing other users with access on a regular or large scale basis or as a means to circumvent access
control;
use such content where to do so would be considered a criminal or statutory offence in any jurisdiction, or gives rise to civil liability, or is
otherwise unlawful;
falsely or misleadingly imply or suggest endorsement, approval , sponsorship, or association unless explicitly agreed to by Springer Nature in
writing;
use bots or other automated methods to access the content or redirect messages
override any security feature or exclusionary protocol; or
share the content in order to create substitute for Springer Nature products or services or a systematic database of Springer Nature journal
content.
In line with the restriction against commercial use, Springer Nature does not permit the creation of a product or service that creates revenue,
royalties, rent or income from our content or its inclusion as part of a paid for service or for other commercial gain. Springer Nature journal
content cannot be used for inter-library loans and librarians may not upload Springer Nature journal content on a large scale into their, or any
other, institutional repository.
These terms of use are reviewed regularly and may be amended at any time. Springer Nature is not obligated to publish any information or
content on this website and may remove it or features or functionality at our sole discretion, at any time with or without notice. Springer Nature
may revoke this licence to you at any time and remove access to any copies of the Springer Nature journal content which have been saved.
To the fullest extent permitted by law, Springer Nature makes no warranties, representations or guarantees to Users, either express or implied
with respect to the Springer nature journal content and all parties disclaim and waive any implied warranties or warranties imposed by law,
including merchantability or fitness for any particular purpose.
Please note that these rights do not automatically extend to content, data or other material published by Springer Nature that may be licensed
from third parties.
If you would like to use or distribute our Springer Nature journal content to a wider audience or on a regular basis or in any other manner not
expressly permitted by these Terms, please contact Springer Nature at
onlineservice@springernature.com
... Traditional questions of moral enhancement and violence have tended to center on three issues: (a) enhancing warfighters with beta-blockers to depress feelings of guilt and shame after killing in war [19,20], (b) accepting organ donations from prisoners [21], a practice explicitly prohibited by international human law [22], and (c medicalized punishment/ treatment to reduce prison terms, such as chemical castration [23]. By contrast, I focus on the ethics of neuroenhancements for prisoners of war (hereafter, 'POWs'). ...
... As a thesis, Therapy is quite modest in that biological properties that decrease lifespans or result in incarceration are pro tanto bad for people's health. 22 This prompts a second argument: ...
... It is a tool used to diagnose a threat to the State in the same way that a physician utilizes a blood test to diagnose a threat to the body [101]. 22 My thanks to Tom Douglas for comments that improved my formulation of Therapy. 23 Does routine medical treatment of unjust POWs require their consent? ...
Article
Full-text available
Moral agential neuroenhancement (MANE) can transform us into better people. However, critics of MB raise four central objections to MANEs use: (1) It destroys moral freedom; (2) it kills one moral agent and replaces them with another, better agent; (3) it carries significant risk of infection and illness; (4) it benefits society but not the enhanced person; and (5) it’s wrong to experiment on nonconsenting persons. Herein, I defend MANE’s use for prisoners of war (POWs) fighting unjustly. First, the permissibility of killing unjust combatants entails that, in cases where MANE is equally or more likely as termination to reduce moral recidivism in unjust combatants, then MANE is morally justified. Second, the relevant infections and illnesses caused by MANE are less bad than death, so MANE leaves unjust POWs better off than the alternative. Third, just as incarceration is often permissible despite benefitting society but not the incarcerated, the same holds for unjust POWs. Fourth, we should accept a broader construal of “benefit” that includes moral benefits. Thus, 3 and 4 are false when applied to unjust POWs. Fifth, medical experimentation likely to help nonconsenting persons is sometimes permissible. Because MANE is likely to help unjust POWs irrespective of their consent or lack thereof, its use is permissible. Sixth, basic principles of proper medical care support the use of MANE on unjust POWs as pro tanto morally obligatory. I conclude that militaries should therefore begin to employ MANE for unjust POWs.
... Evidence suggestive of such behavior has emerged over many years from the People's Republic of China (PRC). [8][9][10][11][12][13][14] To investigate these reports, this paper uses computational methods to examine 2838 Chinese transplant-related medical papers published in scientific journals, systematically collecting data and testing hypotheses about this practice. By scrutinizing the clinical procedures around intubation and ventilation of donors, declaration of brain death, and commencement of organ procurement surgery, we contribute substantial new evidence to questions about the role of PRC physicians in state executions. ...
... During our review, we also came across papers that give clear Organization to Investigate the Persecution of Falun Gong, and others. [9][10][11]13,14,78 These sources have highlighted anecdotal and textual accounts of apparent DDR violations by surgeons. Our study, using systematic computational methods, corroborates them. ...
Article
Full-text available
The dead donor rule is fundamental to transplant ethics. The rule states that organ procurement must not commence until the donor is both dead and formally pronounced so, and by the same token, that procurement of organs must not cause the death of the donor. In a separate area of medical practice, there has been intense controversy around the participation of physicians in the execution of capital prisoners. These two apparently disparate topics converge in a unique case: the intimate involvement of transplant surgeons in China in the execution of prisoners via the procurement of organs. We use computational text analysis to conduct a forensic review of 2838 papers drawn from a dataset of 124 770 Chinese‐language transplant publications. Our algorithm searched for evidence of problematic declarations of brain death during organ procurement. We find evidence in 71 of these reports, spread nationwide, that brain death could not have properly been declared. In these cases, the removal of the heart during organ procurement must have been the proximate cause of the donor's death. Because these organ donors could only have been prisoners, our findings strongly suggest that physicians in the People's Republic of China have participated in executions by organ removal.
... China's Policy on Human Rights. China has been known for its human rights abuse, from organ procurement practice (Paul et al., 2017), to religious persecution of minority groups (Potter, 2003;Clarke, 2010), and suppression of political dissent (Conrad and Ritter, 2019). In 2017, Secretary of State Rex Tillerson publicly condemned China for having the lowest ranking on human trafficking issues (Gramer and Allen-Ebrahimian, 2017). ...
Article
This paper examines US public opinion after the drastic changes in US–China relations during the Trump presidency. I argue that the perceived China threat influences Americans' evaluation of the China–Taiwan tension. Based on the US dataset of the 2018 Survey on Global Attitudes and Trends by the Pew Research Center, Americans tend to perceive the China–Taiwan tension as a serious problem for the USA when Americans identify China as a major threat and its military strength as a concern. As US public opinion shapes the US foreign policy on China, the findings shed light on the public support for the ongoing US–China conflict.
... 13 This may surprise given the history of abuse in Chinese transplantation including sourcing organs from prisoners and forced organ harvesting. 14 , 15 Ding et al. claimed that the ethics committee approval was unnecessary given publication of criteria in national journals "which represent the legal status of this evaluation" and established clinical practice for component steps (although families were informed). 16 The first documented brain death diagnosis in China was performed on February 25, 2003, in Wuhan, Hubei Province. ...
Article
Full-text available
Organ donation after brain death has been practiced in China since 2003 in the absence of brain death legislation. Similar to international standards, China’s brain death diagnostic criteria include coma, absence of brainstem reflexes, and the lack of spontaneous respiration. The Chinese criteria require that the lack of spontaneous respiration must be verified with an apnea test by disconnecting the ventilator for 8 min to provoke spontaneous respiration. However, we have found publications in Chinese medical journals, in which the donors were declared to be brain dead, yet without an apnea test. The organ procurement procedures started with initiating “intratracheal intubation for mechanical ventilation after brain death,” indicating that a brain death diagnosis was not performed. The purpose of the intubation was not to resuscitate the patient but rather was directly related to facilitating the explantation of organs. Moreover, it was unmistakably stated in two of these publications that the cardiac arrest was induced in these patients without brain death determination by cold St. Thomas cardioplegic solution or other cold myocardial protection solutions. This means that the condition of these donors neither met the criteria of brain death nor that of cardiac death. In other words, the “donor organs” may well have been procured in these cases from living human beings. Thus, brain death definition is abused in China by some individuals for organ harvesting, and a systematic investigation is needed to clarify the situation of organ donation after brain death in China.
... Financial incentives and manipulation of transplant systems, as seen in South Africa in 2002, and in Germany in 2013 resulted in dramatic decreases in donor numbers (36,51). In China, unethical procurement of donor organs from prisoners without informed consent has disrupted the public trust to organizations (52). ...
... [36,51] In China, unethical procurement of donor organs from prisoners without informed consent has disrupted the public trust in organizations. [52] It was reported in 2007 that up to 10% of organ transplants worldwide are involved in organ trafficking or patients who travel abroad to buy organs from vulnerable people. [45,53] Declaration of Istanbul was developed to prevent human organ trafficking and to prevent the exploitation of poor individuals/countries being organ donors to recipients of wealthy individuals/countries in 2008. ...
Article
Full-text available
With the increasing incidence and prevalence of end-stage liver disease, demand for donor grafts continues to increase. Approaches on maximizing the potential donor grafts vary depending on the region. This review aims to summarize the current practice of liver transplantation with an emphasis on challenges encountered in developing countries.
... This includes stroke, TIA, carotid stenosis, vertebral and intracranial stenosis, aneurysms, and vascular malformations. [40] Etiologies of TIA and stroke were classified according to the modified TOAST (Trial of ORG 10172 in Acute Stroke Treatment) criteria [41]. These criteria were the same throughout the period of analysis. ...
Article
Peritumoral brain edema (PTBE) is seen in 40-78% of all cases of intracranial meningiomas. It may vary in shape and size, occasionally being two to three times larger than the tumor. We present a case of a 62-year-old female patient, suffering from seizure and progressive headache. She was diagnosed with left medial sphenoid wing meningioma and referred for treatment to Uzhhorod Regional Center of Neurosurgery and Neurology. The patient had no major focal neurological deficit and Karnofsky Performance Scale (KPS) of 70 on admission. The preoperative magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) with and without contrast showed a 2.1×2.2×2.5 cm solid mass at the inner third of the left sphenoid wing, with homogenous enhancement and encasement of middle cerebral artery (MCA). In addition, there was a disproportionately extensive PTBE in the left cerebral hemisphere that caused midline shift and mass effect. The patient underwent left pterional craniotomy and gross total resection of the mass. The postoperative course was without complications or new neurological deficit, MRI within 48 hours revealed gross total tumour resection with residual brain edema and the patient was discharged with a KPS of 80 on day 7. Based on several studies, significant correlation between PTBE and tumor volume was observed: larger tumors cause larger PTBE. This particular case had a very large hemispheric PTBE, which was disproportionate to the small size of the meningioma. Most likely, the PTBE in this patient was caused by venous congestion, but this had no influence on surgical outcome. Therefore, the presence of a large PTBE does not necessarily indicate a poor prognosis and isn’t always the reason of surgical complications.
Article
Organ trafficking in all its various forms is an international crime which could be entirely eliminated if healthcare professionals refused to participate in or be complicit with it. Types of organ trafficking are defined and principal international declarations and resolutions concerning it are discussed. The evidence for the involvement of healthcare professionals is illustrated with examples from South Africa and China. The ways in which healthcare professionals directly or indirectly perpetuate illegal organ transplantation are then considered, including lack of awareness, the paucity of both undergraduate and postgraduate education on organ trafficking, turning a blind eye, advocacy of organ commercialism, and the lure of financial gain.
Chapter
As The People’s Republic of China has become more accessible to Western scholars, evidence has mounted that the country suffers from a wide range of upper-class criminality. Some features unique to the country, such as its numerous state-owned enterprises, exacerbate the problem. In China, SOEs represent a sizable part of the overall economy; there are 109 Chinese corporations listed on the Fortune Global 500, but only 15% are privately owned. The effects of white-collar and corporate crime mirror those of street crime; profit-seeking behavior can result in both financial loss and violence for victims. Though just as injurious, strained system capacity makes detecting and sanctioning major financial crimes more difficult. The following summaries of known cases of lawbreaking from information contained in both domestic and international media accounts over the past 20 years highlight these points in the causation and reactions to various forms of offending, which are also categorized by crime type.
Article
Objective: The aim: To highlight and analyze the international aspect of the legal regulation of human organs and tissues transplantation, as well as foreign experience of regulation in this area within the relevant national legal systems (for example, US, Germany, Israel, Switzerland, Spain, Argentina, China and India). Patients and methods: Materials and methods: Methodologically, this work is based on the system of methods, scientific approaches, techniques and principles with the help of which the realization of the research aim is carried out. There have been applied universal, general scientific and special legal methods. Conclusion: Conclusions: Thus, the efforts of the international community and the countries under study in the field of transplantation are focused on a wide range of important issues that need to be regulated. The international legal regulation of transplantation covers the results of the activities of such international organizations as the World Health Organization, the Council of Europe, and the World Medical Assembly. The acts adopted by them are mainly of a recommendatory nature (with the exception of some Council of Europe acts on trafficking in human organs) and are addressed primarily to States, offering guidelines and standards for the legal regulation of transplantation within national legal orders. Therefore, the issues of donation and transplantation of human organs and tissues in the respective states are determined by special legislative acts, which comprehensively regulate the procedure for their transplantation.
Article
Full-text available
Previous publications have described unethical organ procurement procedures in the People's Republic of China. International awareness and condemnation contributed to the announcement abolishing the procurement of organs from executed prisoners starting from January 2015. Eighteen months after the announcement, and aligned with the upcoming International Congress of the Transplantation Society in Hong Kong, this paper revisits the topic and discusses whether the declared reform has indeed been implemented. It is noticeable that China has neither addressed nor included in the reform a pledge to end the procurement of organs from prisoners of conscience, nor have they initiated any legislative amendments. Recent reports have discussed an implausible discrepancy of officially reported steady annual transplant numbers and a steep expansion of the transplant infrastructure in China. This paper expresses the viewpoint that, in the current context, it is not possible to verify the veracity of the announced changes and it thus remains premature to include China as an ethical partner in the international transplant community. Until we have independent and objective evidence of a complete cessation of unethical organ procurement from prisoners, the medical community has a professional responsibility to maintain the academic embargo on Chinese transplant professionals. This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
Article
Full-text available
In December 2014, China announced that only voluntarily donated organs from citizens would be used for transplantation after January 1, 2015. Many medical professionals worldwide believe that China has stopped using organs from death-row prisoners. In the present article, we briefly review the historical development of organ procurement from death-row prisoners in China and comprehensively analyze the social-political background and the legal basis of the announcement. The announcement was not accompanied by any change in organ sourcing legislations or regulations. As a fact, the use of prisoner organs remains legal in China. Even after January 2015, key Chinese transplant officials have repeatedly stated that death-row prisoners have the same right as regular citizens to “voluntarily donate” organs. This perpetuates an unethical organ procurement system in ongoing violation of international standards. Organ sourcing from death-row prisoners has not stopped in China. The 2014 announcement refers to the intention to stop the use of organs illegally harvested without the consent of the prisoners. Prisoner organs procured with “consent” are now simply labelled as “voluntarily donations from citizens”. The semantic switch may whitewash sourcing from both death-row prisoners and prisoners of conscience. China can gain credibility only by enacting new legislation prohibiting use of prisoner organs and by making its organ sourcing system open to international inspections. Until international ethical standards are transparently met, sanctions should remain.
Article
Full-text available
Organ procurement from executed prisoners in China is internationally condemned, yet this practice continues unabated in 2014. This is despite repeated announcements from Chinese authorities that constructive measures have been undertaken to conform to accepted ethical standards. While there is unanimous agreement on the unethical nature of using organs from executed prisoners, due to its limitations on voluntary and informed consent, there is insufficient coverage of forced organ procurement from prisoners of conscience without consent. Strategies to influence positive change in China over the last few decades have failed to bring this practice to an end. While organ donation and transplantation services in China have undergone considerable structural changes in the last few years, fundamental attempts to shift practice to ethically sourced organs have floundered. In this article, we discuss the organ trade in China, reflect upon organ procurement from executed prisoners (including both capital prisoners and prisoners of conscience) and provide an overview of contradictory Chinese efforts to halt forced organ procurement from executed prisoners. Finally, we highlight current actions being taken to address this issue and offer comprehensive recommendations to bring this ethically indefensible practice to an immediate end.
Article
Full-text available
Urges President Xi to apply principles of reform (anti-corruption, fairness, openness) to end practices of using executed prisoners as source for organs for transplantation and of serving the needs of paying "transplant tourists" rather than needs of Chinese patients.
Article
Unit 731, a biological warfare research organisation that operated under the authority of the Imperial Japanese Army in the 1930s and 1940s, conducted brutal experiments on thousands of unconsenting subjects. Because of the US interest in the data from these experiments, the perpetrators were not prosecuted and the atrocities are still relatively undiscussed. What counts as meaningful moral repair in this case-what should perpetrators and collaborator communities do decades later? We argue for three non-ideal but realistic forms of moral repair: (1) a national policy in Japan against human experimentation without appropriate informed and voluntary consent; (2) the establishment of a memorial to the victims of Unit 731; and (3) US disclosure about its use of Unit 731 data and an apology for failing to hold the perpetrators accountable.
Article
Purpose of review Insufficient availability of human organs for transplantation has given rise to a flourishing global market. This review addresses current thinking and practical considerations regarding legalization of organ sales. Recent findings Increasing competition for human organs has led to egregious human rights violations. Governmental proscription of organ sales has failed to slow this process. Organ sales in China and the regulated market in Iran have received much attention. Some believe that a regulated market is an ethical vehicle for shortening waiting lists and decreasing illegal organ sales. Others consider it a blow to human dignity and to altruistic donation. There is alternative support toward reimbursing living donors for their financial losses. The World Health Organization advocates increased reliance on cadaver donor transplantation. Some countries have enacted presumed consent laws that have increased cadaver organ donation. In the USA an Organ Breakthrough Collaborative has generated comparable success. Summary Serious discussion continues with regard to regulated sale of human organs. There is increased interest in reimbursement for living organ donation. Research is needed to elucidate workings of the global organ market, and to assess attitudes about stakeholders with regard to proposed changes in transplantation policy.
Article
Organ donation and transplant systems have unique characteristics based on local culture and socio economic context. China's transplant and organ donation systems developed without regulatory oversight until 2006 when regulation and policy was developed and then implemented over the next several years. Most recently the pilot project of establishing a voluntary citizen based deceased donor program was established. The pilot program addressed the legal, financial, and cultural barriers to organ donation in China. The pilot program has evolved into a National program. Significantly it established a uniquely Chinese Donor Classification system. The Chinese Donor Classification recognizes brain death donors (Category I), donation after circulatory death (Category II), and donation after brain death followed by circulatory death (Category III). Through August 2014, the system has identified 2326 donors and provided 6416 organs that have been allocated though a transparent organ allocation system. The estimated number of donors in 2014 is 1147. As China's attitudes towards organ donation have matured and evolved and China, as a nation, is taking its place on the world stage it is recognizing that its past practice of utilizing organs from executed prisoners is not sustainable. It is time to recognize that the efforts to regulate transplantation and provide a voluntary citizen based deceased organ donation have been successful and that China should utilize this system to provide organs for all transplants in every province and hospital in China. This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
Article
It has been suggested that human organs should be bought and sold on a regulated market as any other material property belongingto an individual. This would have the advantage of both addressing the grave shortage of organs available for transplantation and respecting the freedom of individuals to choose to do whatever they want with their body parts. The old arguments against such a market in human organs are, therefore, being brought back into question. The article examines the different arguments both in favour and against the sale of human organs. It concludes that the body and any of its elements is a full expression of the whole person. As such, they cannot have a price if the individual is to retain his or her full inherent dignity and if society is to retain and protect this very important concept.