ArticlePDF Available

The minimum age of criminal responsibility in continental Europe has a solid rational base

Authors:

Abstract

The focus this article takes is on the proposition that the age of criminal responsibility is a meaningful term. It will be stated that there is no proof that today's young children have a greater understanding of the world than children had in the past. The article wants to make clear that the principle that children below a certain age are too young to be held responsible for breaking the law can be based on strong scientific evidence. It argues that it is unacceptable in the light of these empirical findings to decide not to have a national minimum age of criminal responsibility (MACR) and to leave the decision to prosecute a child under a certain age to the Lord Advocate.
The minimum age of criminal responsibility
in continental Europe has a solid
rational base
IDO WEIJERS*
Utrecht University School of Law
NILQ 67(3): 301–10
Abstract
The focus this article takes is on the proposition that the age of criminal responsibility is a meaningful term.
It will be stated that there is no proof that today’s young children have a greater understanding of the world
than children had in the past. The article wants to make clear that the principle that children below a certain
age are too young to be held responsible for breaking the law can be based on strong scientific evidence. It
argues that it is unacceptable in the light of these empirical findings to decide not to have a national
minimum age of criminal responsibility (MACR) and to leave the decision to prosecute a child under a
certain age to the Lord Advocate. It is stated that there is sufficient scientific ground to conclude that a
realistic MACR would be at age 14 or 15.
Introduction
Considering the age of criminal responsibility implies an assessment of juvenile justice
systems. The significant diversity that is typical of this field worldwide is striking.
Countries vary far more widely in juvenile than in adult justice systems.1Juvenile justice
systems vary in their age boundaries, as they do in their sentences and educational measures.
At first sight there seems to be a rather modest variety of upper age jurisdictions. These
vary between 15 and 18, with the exception of Japan, where youths can only be brought
before the adult criminal court once they are aged 20 or older. In fact, these small margins
of upper age limits of juvenile justice systems are profoundly relativised by a wide variety
of options to transfer or waive young offenders to adult criminal courts in some countries.2
Comparing continents concerning the minimum age limits of criminal responsibility
(MACR) worldwide, however, we find far more extreme contrasts. In Europe, the
absolute lower age limit below which children cannot be held criminally responsible varies
NILQ autumn 2016
* Professor of Law, Willem Pompe Institute for Criminal Law and Criminology.
1 Michael Tonry and Anthony Doob (eds), Youth Crime and Youth Justice: Comparative and Cross-National Perspectives
(University of Chicago Press 2004).
2 See Ido Weijers, An Nuytiens and Jenneke Christiaens, ‘Transfer of Minors to the Criminal Court in Europe:
Belgium and the Netherlands’ in Josine Junger-Tas and Frieder Duenkel (eds), Reforming Juvenile Justice (Springer
2009) 105–24.
from 8 (Scotland and Greece), 9 (Malta), 10 (England and Wales) to 15 (Czech Republic,
Poland, the Scandinavian countries) and 16 (Belgium).3
Notwithstanding the contrasting lower age limits within this continent, there is a
dominant European picture represented by the large group of countries on the European
continent where 14 or 15 is the age of criminal responsibility. Overall, this results in 13
years being the average and typical age of criminal responsibility in Europe. If we take a
worldwide view, it may be concluded that Europe has by far the highest average MACR
of all continents.4
There are significant difficulties, though, in establishing the MACR. Firstly, Table 1
makes clear that several European countries, like Scotland, Ireland and Poland, have a
standard minimal age for ‘common’ criminal cases involving young offenders (12, 13, 14,
16 or 17) and a deviant, lower age limit concerning ‘extreme cases, like murder,
manslaughter, rape (8, 9, 10, 12, 14 and 15). Actually, these lower age limits must be
interpreted as implying the bottom-line and absolute MACR, and not the other way
round, as is sometimes the interpretation. France, on the contrary, has a standard minimal
age of 13, which means that young offenders may be subjected to punishment (peine) from
that age, but at the same time it has a minimal age of 10 concerning minor offenders, who
may receive educational treatment (sanction éducative). The Netherlands had a comparable
sanction (Stop) for minor offenders younger than 12 between 2001 and 2010. England
Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly 67(3)
302
3 In Belgium, children cannot normally be held criminally responsible before their 18th birthdays, but in the
case of murder or manslaughter they can be held criminally responsible from their 16th birthdays.
4 The juvenile codes in most of the USA do not indicate a minimum age of jurisdiction for delinquency cases
– see Donna M Bishop and Scott H Decker, ‘Punishment and Control: Juvenile Justice Reform in the USA’
in Josine Junger-Tas and Scott H Decker (eds), International Handbook of Juvenile Justice (Springer 2006) 3–35.
CCoouunnttrryy
YYoouunnggeesstt aaggee::
j
juuvveenniillee ccoouurrtt
CCoouunnttrryy
YYoouunnggeesstt aaggee::
j
juuvveenniillee ccoouurrtt
Scotland
8 (12)
Georgia
14
Greece
8 (13)
Germany
14
Malta
9 (14)
Italy
14
England & Wales
10
Latvia
14
Ireland
10 (12)
Liechtenstein
14
Northern Ireland
10
Lithuania
14
Switzerland
10
Macedonia
14
Andorra
12
Moldova
14 (16)
Hungary
12 (14)
Montenegro
14
Netherlands
12
Romania
14 (16)
Portugal
12
Russian Federation
14 (16)
San Marino
12
Serbia
14
France
13 (10)
Slovakia
14
Monaco
13
Slovenia
14
Albania
14
Spain
14
Armenia
14 (16)
Ukraine
14 (16)
Azerbaijan
14 (16)
Czech Republic
15
Austria
14
Denmark
15
Belarus
14
Finland
15
Bosnia-Herzegovina
14
Iceland
15
Bulgaria
14
Norway
15
Croatia
14
Poland
15 (17)
Cyprus
14
Sweden
15
Estonia
14
Belgium
16
Table 1: MACR for juvenile court jurisdiction in Europe
introduced the Child Safety Order for children younger than 10 under the Crime and
Disorder Act in 1998, designed for ‘nipping crime in the bud’. All three deviations are (or
were) incompatible with the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child (UNCRC).
Secondly, what does the minimum age of criminal responsibility exactly tell us about
the age at which children can be prosecuted? There is a remarkable differentiation
between the age of criminal responsibility and the age of prosecution in several countries.
The age of criminal responsibility is understood in general as denoting a complete bar to
prosecution; but this does not necessarily mean that youths will be prosecuted from that
age. Many countries do not prosecute youths as soon as they reach this minimum age.
They operate a typical compromise, combining two different age levels with more or less
discretion. They use the age of criminal responsibility as the upper limit of absolute
criminal incapacity and as the beginning of a period of conditional criminal responsibility.5
A well-known formula for this solution is the doli incapax presumption. According to
this presumption, youths will not be prosecuted in principle until they have reached a
certain age, some years after the age of criminal responsibility. In jurisdictions where the
presumption operates, there are significant differences, both in the period of the
presumption and in its actual application.
In some countries, such as the Netherlands, there has never been a period of conditional
criminal responsibility. The Netherlands introduced a special juvenile justice system in
1901 and there was no minimum age of criminal responsibility until 1965. The MACR
was settled at the age of 12. Notwithstanding the implementation of the MACR, 12- and
13-year-olds are rarely prosecuted in criminal courts in the Netherlands. In practice, most
are punished via a police referral (HALT) and young, repeat or more serious offenders by
the prosecutor (Strafbeschikking).
The doli incapax presumption was abolished in England and Wales by the Crime and
Disorder Act 1998.6The Home Secretary, Jack Straw, made clear that he wanted to break
with the history and philosophy of youth justice in England and Wales, which he branded
as an ‘excuse culture’.7The consequence is that children in England and Wales have
become accountable for their offending at age 10.
In contrast, a classical version of the doli incapax presumption can be found in Ireland.
The age of criminal responsibility is currently 12 years, but the presumption applies to
children from the ages of 10 to 14. On raising the minimum age to 12 (previously 8 and
then 10) with the introduction of the Children Act 2001, this presumption was implied
for children aged over 12 but under 14, despite this aspect never being formally enacted.
Ireland retains significant discretion in terms of prosecution and the court, with few
exacting rules regarding how the presumption may be rebutted.8
The situation in Germany is comparable, albeit that the age of criminal responsibility is
higher. The age of absolute criminal incapacity ends at the age of 14. Full criminal
responsibility starts in Germany at 18 years of age. What is particularly important here is
The minimum age of criminal responsibility in continental Europe 303
5 Thomas Crofts, The Criminal Responsibility of Children and Young Persons: A Comparison of English and German Law
(Ashgate 2002).
6 In 1994 Laws J had published fierce criticism of it ([1994] 3 All ER 190, 197), quoted in Julia Fionda, Devils
and Angels. Youth Policy and Crime (Hart 2005) 15. New Labour responded in Tackling Youth Crime: A Consultation
Paper (Home Office 1997) in England and Wales suggesting that this presumption prevented youths being held
accountable for their actions. One year later, the Home Office paper, No More Excuses: A New Approach to
Tackling Youth Crime (Home Office 1997), announced the abolition of the presumption.
7 Anthony Bottoms and James Dignan, ‘Youth Justice in Great Britain’ in Tonry and Doob (n 1) 21–183.
8 Mairead Seymour, ‘Transition and Reform: Juvenile Justice in the Republic of Ireland’ in Junger-Tas and
Decker (n 4) 117–143.
that variations of the German model can be found all over continental Europe, in the West
and in the East. In the Czech Republic, for instance, the age of criminal responsibility is 15,
but responsibility from age 15 is conditional, depending on individual maturity.9
Slovenia, to take another example, similarly applies two age limits. Yugoslavia’s first
Criminal Code and Criminal Procedure Code (1929) contained provisions pertaining to
young offenders. They were divided into two groups: younger (14–17) and older juveniles
(17–21). The younger ones were considered relatively irresponsible, which implied that
the court could impose a sentence or educational measures only if their maturity was
proven. This division remained intact after the Second World War and it was further
expanded into four categories in 1995 under the new Criminal Code: children under 14,
who could never be held criminally responsible; young minors (14–16) against whom only
educational measures may be applied; older minors (16–18) and young adults (18–21).10
In short, this means that the average age at which children can actually be held
criminally responsible and be prosecuted in Europe is 14.
Consensus and debate
The curious thing is that there exists broad consensus that children below a certain age
are too young to be held responsible for breaking the law, but there is an extreme variety
of MACRs worldwide and there is continuing debate as to the advisable age of criminal
responsibility. There exists a set of rules, guidelines and court decisions that presuppose
or clarify the implications of an MACR. For example, the Beijing Rules provide a
framework and model for national juvenile justice systems.11 These rules state that the
MACR ‘shall not be fixed at too low an age level, bearing in mind the facts of emotional,
mental and intellectual maturity’ (rule 4.1).12 The UNCRC similarly articulates that
children below a certain age cannot be held criminally responsible. The UNCRC calls for
nations to establish a minimum age ‘below which children shall be presumed not to have
the capacity to infringe the penal law’ (Article 40, II.7a). It was not until 2007, however,
that the UN Commission on the Rights of the Child settled on an MACR, which, in its
opinion, has to be at least 12 years.13
In 2007 the European Ministers of Justice decided that European guidelines on child-
friendly justice should be prepared. Three years later Guidelines on Child-Friendly Justice were
published by the Committee of Ministers of the Council of Europe, providing practical
guidance to member states of the Council of Europe regarding the adaptation of juvenile
justice systems to accommodate the specific rights and needs of children. The guidelines
require ‘due consideration to the child’s level of maturity and understanding . . . justice
that is accessible, age appropriate’ and that ‘the rights of the child including the rights to
due process, to participate in and to understand the proceedings’ are respected (para IIc).
Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly 67(3)
304
9 Helena Valkova, ‘Restorative Approaches and Alternative Methods: Juvenile Justice Reform in the Czech
Republic’ in Junger-Tas and Decker (n 4) 277–318.
10 Katja Filipcic, ‘Welfare Versus Neo-Liberalism: Juvenile Justice in Slovenia’ in Junger-Tas and Decker (n 4)
397–413.
11 Geraldine van Bueren, ‘Child-Oriented Justice: An International Challenge for Europe’ (1992) 6 International
Journal of Law and the Family 381–99.
12 At the time of drafting the Beijing Rules a broad consensus on a minimum age of criminal responsibility
among the UN states parties was hoped for, but that appeared to be impossible: Don Cipriani, Children’s Rights
and the Minimum Age of Criminal Responsibility: A Global Perspective (Ashgate 2009).
13 UN Commission on the Rights of the Child, General Comment No 10: Children’s Rights in Juvenile Justice
(CRC/C/GC/10 2007) para 30.
Several important European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) rulings have also
elucidated particularly crucial procedural implications of an MACR, most notably the
notorious Bulger case arising in England and Wales.14 Two 10-year-old boys kidnapped and
beat to death 2-year-old James Bulger. The two minors (who at the time of trial had turned
11 years old) were prosecuted on indictment in the Crown Court, in public, before a judge
and 12 jurors. The trial caused national and international outrage, with hostile crowds
gathered outside the court building and a packed public gallery in the courtroom. After three
weeks, both defendants were found guilty by the trial jury. The ECtHR maintained the view:
. . . that it is essential that a child charged with an offence is dealt with in a manner
which takes full account of his age, level of maturity and intellectual and
emotional capacities, and that steps are taken to promote his ability to understand
and participate in the proceedings (para 84).
It concluded that the defendants had been ‘unable to participate effectively in the criminal
proceedings against him and was, in consequence, denied a fair hearing’ (para 89).
This statement was further considered in SC v UK.15 Despite special arrangements,16
the ECtHR concluded that 11-year-old SC ‘was unable fully to comprehend or participate
in the trial process’ (para 26). The court explained that Article 6 European Convention
on Human Rights does not imply that a juvenile defendant should understand every legal
detail during the criminal trial. However, he or she should have:
. . . a broad understanding of the nature of the trial process and of what is at
stake for him or her, including the significance of any penalty which may be
imposed. It means that he or she . . . should be able to understand the general
thrust of what is said in court.17
An alternative point of view has been expressed by the Scottish Law Commission. In
Scotland the lower age limit of criminal responsibility remains at 8 years, strikingly low in
comparison to other European countries. However, instead of recommending a higher
minimum age, the Commission proposed abolition of the rule that a child has no criminal
capacity below a certain age. Surprisingly, this recommendation was clearly not inspired
by a call to be more tough on youth crime: the Commission confirmed the characteristic
rule in Scottish criminal law that no child under the age of 16 should be prosecuted for
any offence except on the instructions of the Lord Advocate (Criminal Procedure Act
1995, c 46, s 42).
The Commission advanced three arguments in support of this proposal. First, it
argued that today children of eight years of age have a greater understanding of the world
than children of this age had in the past. This might suggest, in its opinion, that there
could be a case for further lowering the age.18 Second, if an age of criminal responsibility
was a matter of applying developmental psychology, then why was there such disparity in
The minimum age of criminal responsibility in continental Europe 305
14 T and V v UK App nos 24724/94, 24888/94 (ECtHR, 16 December 1999.
15 SC v UK App no 60958/00 (ECtHR, 15 June 2004).
16 The hearing in the Crown Court was adjusted to the child’s age insofar as the defendant was accompanied by
a social worker: he was not required to sit in the defendant’s dock, judges did not wear wigs and gowns and
frequent breaks were taken.
17 ‘The defendant should be able to follow what is said by the prosecution witnesses and, if represented, to
explain to his own lawyers his version of events, point out any statements with which he disagrees and make
them aware of any facts which should be put forward in his defence . . .’ (para 29). More recently (2009) the
court has repeated in its judgment in the case of a 15-year-old Turkish boy, who complained that he had been
deprived of a fair trial because he was not able to participate effectively: Güveç v Turkey App no 70337/01
(ECtHR, 20 January 2009).
18 Gerry Maher, ‘Age and Criminal Responsibility’ (2005) 2 Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 493-512.
the ages adopted in different countries? Finally, it noted, relying on the findings of the
well-known Kilbrandon Committee, that the principle that children below a certain age
are too young to be held responsible for breaking the law was not based on any empirical
data concerning their understanding:
The legal presumption by which no child under the age of 8 can be subjected
to criminal proceedings is not therefore a reflection of any observable fact . . .
It is clear, therefore, that the ‘age of criminal responsibility’ is largely a
meaningless term.19
This article adopts the opposite view. Its main focus is on the proposition that the age of
criminal responsibility is far from being a meaningless term and that there is convincing
evidence available which makes clear that the age of criminal responsibility is indeed
meaningful. This argument is advanced in four parts. First, there is no evidence that today’s
young children have a greater understanding of the world than children had in the past;
secondly, the principle that children below a certain age are too young to be held responsible
for breaking the law, as stated in the UNCRC and other international standards, is based on
strong scientific evidence; thirdly, it is unacceptable in the light of these empirical findings
to reject a national MACR, leaving the decision to prosecute a child under a certain age to
a Lord Advocate, or a comparable person or institution; finally, there is sufficient scientific
grounds to conclude that a realistic MACR would be at age 14 or 15.
The level of understanding held by young children
The peremptory tone with which it is alleged that young children have more
understanding of the world than children in the past is staggering. The Anneveldt
Commission in 1982 argued that we should take account of the ‘empirical fact that
‘young people adopt more mature and independent attitudes at a younger age than they
did twenty years earlier’.20 However, there is simply no empirical basis to this assertion.
Worse still, all scientific evidence suggests otherwise.
The idea of more mature children who have a greater understanding of the world may
have emerged, at least partly, from popular psychology, which has paid much attention to
early manifestations of puberty. Puberty may start as early as 8 in girls and 9 in boys in
Western countries (while generally the range for the first signs is still taken as 14 for girls
and 16 for boys). Early puberty, however, seems to be a typical cultural phenomenon,
dependent on factors like diet and lifestyle, endocrine disrupters and obesity, which seem to
have had an epidemic character in the recent decades in jurisdictions such as the USA.21
Puberty is simply one element in the many physical changes children experience. More
importantly, there exists no systematic relationship between the timing of puberty and the
intellectual and emotional development of adolescents.22 As every paediatrician, pedagogue
and experienced teacher knows, there is little correlation between physical development and
mental and emotional development in adolescents.
Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly 67(3)
306
19 Committee on Children and Young Persons Scotland, Report of the Committee on Children and Young Persons
(HMSO 1964) 73.
20 Anneveldt Commission, Sanctierecht voor jeugdigen (Staatsuitgeverij 1982).
21 Marcia E Herman-Giddens, Paul B Kaplowitz and Richard Wasserman, ‘Navigating the Recent Articles on
Girls’ Puberty in Pediatrics: What Do We Know and Where Do We Go from Here?‘ (2004) 113(4) Pediatrics
911–17.
22 Laurence Steinberg and Robert G Schwartz, ‘Developmental Psychology Goes to Court’ in Thomas Grisso
and Robert G Schwartz (eds), Youth on Trial: Developmental Perspectives on Juvenile Justice (University of Chicago
Press 2000) 9–31.
It is true that the intellectual abilities of children develop markedly during
adolescence. Young children are not able to think in abstract ways, while adolescents are
often able to think in more advanced, abstract, efficient and effective ways.23 Logical
reasoning skills gradually increase between the ages of 11 and 16. From approximately
their 12th birthday, young people acquire the ability to reflect on more abstract issues.
Matters such as poverty, justice, fairness and love attract significantly more attention from
young adolescents around the age of 12.24 They start to become interested in knowledge
of the world, in social relations, rights, news, politics. Step-by-step young adolescents start
to reflect on relationships and on themselves as persons with a past, present and future.25
Nevertheless, there are no indicators that suggest major changes in children’s cognitive
development in contemporary times, as compared to years ago. Children still act without
considering the consequences of their behaviour in any (real) detail. Some may be able to
repeat political slogans, others may show outstanding practical abilities in using laptops or
smartphones, some can recite an impressive list of television stars, heroes in sport or
pharaohs, but since they still lack the ability to think in abstract and reflexive ways, they
do not act more maturely nor do they understand more of the world.26
Young children ought not to be held responsible for breaking the law
There is strong scientific evidence that children below a certain age are too young to be
held responsible for breaking the law. Children, studied from an objective, mature
perspective, do not fully know what they are doing. This is a conceptual, political–
philosophical consideration, implying that they may know what they are doing in that they
are correctly apprised of the relevant facts, but they simply are unable to grasp the moral
and legal importance of these facts.27
Young children cannot fully perceive themselves as citizens, or as subject to the law. If they
do something wrong, they perceive this as a wrong against their parents, the wider family or
their teacher, their neighbour or their friend. Their reasoning is not yet adequate; their notions
of the law, an offence, criminal court, state and citizenship are typically childish and need
further maturation; and they lack experience with things like the law, the state, etc.28
The minimum age of criminal responsibility in continental Europe 307
23 Laurence Steinberg, Adolescence 5th edn (McGraw Hill 1999); Steinberg and Schwartz (n 22).
24 They also start to think experimentally and are fascinated by hypothetical thoughts, (endlessly) considering all
sorts of possibilities and solutions to a problem. Abstract thinking develops gradually over the course of
adolescence until around the age of 17 or 18, when this ability no longer notably improves. See Laurence
Steinberg and Elizabeth Cauffman, ‘Maturity of Judgment in Adolescence: Psychosocial Factors in Adolescent
Decision-Making’ (1996) 20 Law and Human Behavior 249–72; Laurence Steinberg, The Science of Adolescent
Risk-Taking (National Academies Press 2011).
25 Generally, only by mid-adolescence do the formal cognitive capacities resemble those of adults. See Elizabeth
Scott and Laurence Steinberg, Rethinking Juvenile Justice (Harvard University Press 2008).
26 A good example is provided by the difference between what is called ‘digital literacy’ and ‘digital skills’. Whereas
digital skills refers to practical abilities in using digital devices, digital literacy refers to a range of digital skills,
knowledge of the basic principles of computing devices and skills in using computer networks, as well as to an
ability to engage in online communities and social networks while adhering to behavioural protocols, to an ability
to find, capture and evaluate information and, what’s more, to an understanding of the societal and ethical issues
raised by digital technologies and to an ability to think critically about these technologies.
27 David Archard, ‘Philosophical Perspectives on Childhood’ in Julia Fionda (ed), Legal Concepts of Childhood (Hart
2001) 43–56.
28 Joseph Adelson, ‘The Political Imagination of the Young Adolescent’ (1971) 100 Daedalus 1013–50; Anna
Emilia Berti and Alessandra Andriolo, ‘Third Graders’ Understanding of Core Political Concepts (Law, Nation-
State, Government) before and after Teaching’ (2001) 127 Genetic Social and General Psychology Monographs
346–77; Martin D Ruck, Rona Abramovitch, and Daniel P Keating, ‘Children’s and Adolescent’s Understanding
of Rights: Balancing Nurturance and Self Determination’ (1998) 69 Child Development 404–17.
Young children lack the capacity to form criminal intent or to fully understand the
moral and legal implications of their actions. They may understand (or not) that what they
are doing or have done may be naughty or mischievous, but they are unable to fully
understand their actions as a criminal offence, that is, as actions contrary to the law. They
do understand themselves as children who have to obey their parents and teachers, but
not the law or the state. Criminal responsibility requires a perception of the law, of acting
and wrong-doing. It requires a capacity to grasp the legal impact of actions, ‘to know what
we are responsible for and what our prospective responsibilities are’.29
There are several psychosocial factors that can explain the unsophisticated
judgements made by children and young adolescents. Peer pressure is a significant
environmental factor affecting value judgements. From around the age of 8, children
begin to focus on associating with peers. During this period, making friends is of crucial
importance to children and there seems to be less motivation to associate with adults.30
This is especially relevant with regard to antisocial behaviour, since peer pressure blocks
young adolescent’s recently acquired ability (and interest) in hypothetical reflection. Warr
suggests that a crucial factor influencing children’s behaviour is ‘fear of ridicule’. Young
adolescents tend to conform to their peers’ behaviour, even peers who encourage
antisocial behaviour, in order to avoid ridicule and rejection.31
Another important factor pertains to emotional development. Volatility of mood
(i.e. mood swings or moodiness) is considered to be a characteristic for young
adolescents.32 When negative emotionality is part of the temperament of a child, it is
associated with higher levels of aggression and externalising problems. These children
tend to deal less constructively with perceived feelings of anger which, in combination
with lower levels of impulse control, can lead to delinquent behaviour.33
Children also have difficulty in perspective-taking. Skills associated with a developed
sense of identity include the ability to form interpersonal relationships, to reflect on one’s
own behaviour and to be able to morally reason on a higher level. Perspective-taking
ability gradually increases until the age of 16. This ability enables the young person to
understand how decisions or actions are viewed by other persons, even if that is not the
persons’ own view. Perspective-taking is closely related to being able to have feelings of
empathy towards others.34 Empathy is the result of emotional as well as cognitive
processes. The emotional state of another person has to be understood by the adolescent
and the adolescent must be able to share in the emotional state of that other person,
thereby adequately regulating his or her own emotions. Empathy decreases the probability
Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly 67(3)
308
29 Peter Cane, Responsibility in Law and Morality (Hart 2002) 54.
30 Susceptibility to peer pressure peaks around the age of 14 and then declines. This implies that sometime between
the ages of 12 and 16 peer pressure is highest and declines gradually thereafter: Scott and Steinberg (n 25).
31 Mark Warr, ‘Making Delinquent Friends: Adult Supervision and Children’s Affiliations’ (2005) 43(1)
Criminology 77–106.
32 Scott and Steinberg (n 25). Research sug gests that a positive mood can increase risk-taking behaviour to a
certain extent. When risks are low, they are taken more easily when in a positive mood. But when risks are
perceived to be high, individuals do not want to have their good mood destroyed by taking risks and tend to
be more conservative in decision-making. See Steinberg and Cauffman (n 24).
33 Nancy Eisenberg, ‘Emotion, Regulation and Moral Development’ (2000) 51 Annual Review of Psychology 665–97.
34 Eisenberg has defined empathy as ‘an affective response that stems from the apprehension or comprehension
of another’s emotional state or condition and is similar to what the other person is feeling or would be
expected to feel’: ibid 671.
of certain types of criminal behaviour, while a lack of empathy is assumed to have a
facilitating influence on offending.35
The conclusion that children below a certain age are too young to be held responsible
for breaking the law does not imply that the child should simply be viewed in law as
completely irresponsible. On the contrary, children must be viewed as beings with
‘evolving capacities’ (UNCRC Article 5), with a growing responsibility and a growing
awareness of their position as legal subjects. Our modern view of childhood is a
developmental one. The normal youth acquires moral and legal autonomy step by step,
developing from extreme dependence and vulnerability in infancy to near independence,
partial self-sufficiency and growing maturity in adolescence.
Rejecting an MACR would result in the gravity of the crime being decisive
It is unacceptable not to have a national MACR and to leave the decision to prosecute a
child under a certain age to the Lord Advocate, or a comparable person or institution.
The standard implication of the absence of a minimum age of criminal responsibility
means the gravity of the crime will be decisive for bringing (very) young defendants into
the juvenile justice system and for punishing (very) young offenders according to this
system, while this system also presupposes that the participants can be held responsible
(albeit, that responsibility is deemed to be reduced) for their actions.
It is essential to adopt a bright-line rule that very young offenders should not (normally)
be handled in a juvenile justice system. We should not accept the idea that these same very
young offenders should go to the youth court if they are suspected of something very
serious, like manslaughter, murder or rape. A very young person has an insufficient degree
of capacity to form criminal intent, no matter what crime he or she commits.
A realistic age of criminal responsibility is 14 or 15
Holding children responsible for breaking the law requires an assessment of their
adjudicative capacities.36 Juvenile defendants have to be competent to be brought before
a court for adjudication. The legal concept of competence to stand trial (or the capacity
to defend) in the USA – which is defined as ‘sufficient ability to consult with his attorney
with a reasonable degree of rational understanding as well as factual understanding of the
proceedings against him’37 requires that the defendant has sufficient ability to
understand and to recognise the importance of criminal proceedings and to assist his or
her lawyer in the defence.38
The UN Committee on the Rights of the Child states that, when an accused juvenile
is brought before court, he or she should be capable of participating in criminal
proceedings. When the young person is not capable of participating in and understanding
the proceedings, he or she should not be criminally charged and prosecuted.39 As noted
above, according to the ECtHR (T and V v UK (1999); SC v UK (2004); Güveç v Turkey
(2009)) and the European Guidelines on Child-Friendly Justice, it is essential that a child
charged with an offence is dealt with in a manner which takes full account of his or her
The minimum age of criminal responsibility in continental Europe 309
35 Darrick Jolliffe and David P Farrington, ‘Empathy and Offending: A Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis’
(2004) 9 Aggression and Violent Behavior 441–76.
36 Richard J Bonnie and Thomas Grisso, Adjudicative Competence and Youthful Offenders’ in Grisso and
Schwartz (n 22) 73–103.
37 Dusky v United States 362 US 402 (US Supreme Court, 18 April 1960).
38 Thomas Grisso, ‘What We Know about Youths’ Capacities as Trial Defendants’ in Grisso and Schwartz (n 22)
139–72.
39 CRC/C/GC/10, 25 April 2007, para 46.
age, level of maturity and intellectual and emotional capacities and that steps are taken to
promote his or her ability to understand and participate in the proceedings. The minor
should be able ‘to understand the general thrust of what is said in court’.
In the last 20 years, several studies have been conducted on children’s understanding
of the nature of criminal proceedings.40 From these studies, it can be concluded that
juveniles below the age of 14 or 15 are unlikely to be familiar with trial-related
information.41 Grisso concludes that, generally, young people around 14 years of age are
able to form an adequate conception of what it means to appear before a judge in court.42
Many young people between the ages of 14 and 16 who have to appear in court, though,
are not yet capable of forming accurate ideas about what they can expect or what is
expected of them, partly because of individual differences in maturity and partly because
of the range of problems they may experience.43 The stress of having to appear before
a judge and being sentenced in court can impact upon their understanding of the youth
court hearing even more.
From these studies it can be concluded that juveniles aged 14 and younger are more
likely than older adolescents and young adults to be impaired in their ability to understand
criminal proceedings.44 Children are only beginning to be capable of understanding enough
of what it means to appear before a judge when they are around 14 or 15 years of age.
Conclusions
The age of criminal responsibility is far from being a meaningless term. Formal cognitive
abilities mature by middle adolescence, many psychosocial abilities mature somewhat later
and brain development may continue (far) into early adulthood. There is no evidence that
children in contemporary society have a greater understanding and more advanced cognitive
abilities than children had in the past, whereas there is enough evidence to recommend 12
as the age below which we should presume absolute lack of criminal responsibility in
general. There is also strong evidence for adolescent immaturity in a range of factors related
to decision-making for adolescents aged 15 and under as a group. This would suggest that,
for the relevant group of delinquent youths, with its high prevalence of mental disorders
and developmental disorders and low intelligence, the appropriate age of criminal
responsibility would be 15 or at least 14.
Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly 67(3)
310
40 Emma Crawford and Ray Bull, ‘Teenagers’ Difficulties with Key Words Regarding the Criminal Court Process’
(2006) 16(6) Psychology, Crime and Law 653–67; Christine Driver and Eve M Brank, ‘Juveniles’ Knowledge
of the Court Process: Results from Instruction from an Electronic Source’ (2009) 27 Behavioral Sciences and
the Law 627–42; Carolyne Greene, Jane B Sprott, Natasha S Madon and Maria Jung, ‘Punishing Process in
Youth Court: Procedural Justice, Court Atmosphere and Youths’ Views of the Legitimacy of the Justice
System’ (2010) 52 Canadian Journal of Criminology and Criminal Justice 527–44.
41 Grisso (n 38).
42 Ibid.
43 Scott and Steinberg (n 25); Ido Weijers and Thomas Grisso, ‘Criminal Responsibility of Adolescents: Youth
as Junior Citizenship’ in Junger-Tas and Dünkel (n 2) 45–67.
44 Ibid.
... In 10 member states, different MACRs depend on the offense (Child Rights International Network, n.d.-b). In short, this means that the average age at which children can be held criminally responsible in Europe is 14, and if compared to the rest of the world, it can be concluded that Europe has by far the highest average MACR of all continents (Weijers, 2016). ...
... In addition, the research also shows that young children may not be able to understand the complexity of criminal proceedings (Grisso et al., 2003). Several studies on children's understanding of the nature of criminal proceedings have concluded that minors under the age of 14 or 15 are unlikely to be familiar with trial-related information (Weijers, 2016). ...
Chapter
On May 3, 2023, Serbia, a country with strict gun regulations, was confronted for the first time with a mass shooting, which took place at an elite school in the capital Belgrade. After the shooting, the Serbian Government introduced measures to prevent such incidents from happening again. This chapter analyzes the measures, focusing on two questions: 1) What did the country, which already has strict gun regulations, established MACR at the level of most European countries, and police presence in schools, do when it was confronted with a school shooting for the first time; and 2) Have the measures of the same content proven effective in current practice in the countries where they were implemented? In this context, the measures introducing innovations in the Serbian legal and education systems are analyzed and the results of previous studies, especially the experiences in European countries and the United States, are discussed in this chapter.
... There is significant diversity worldwide with regards to juvenile justice systems and significant difficulties in establishing a minimal ACR (Weijers, 2016). There is widespread consensus that children below a certain age are too young to be held responsible for breaking the law and the variety of ACRs worldwide attests to a continuing debate within and between countries of what an advisable age should be. ...
Technical Report
Full-text available
For many children who come into conflict with the law, their lives can include varying degrees of adversity, negative experiences, trauma and loss, often underscored by adverse socioeconomic circumstances. These factors can have substantial and sustained consequences for their development, behaviour and future outcomes. How these factors can influence and impact on children who offend, therefore, requires further investigation, particularly in the context of the recent rise in the Age of Criminal Responsibility (ACR) in Scotland to 12 years and Scottish Ministers’ duty to consider a future age of criminal responsibility. This research was carried out, examining 400 children's case files, held by SCRA, to provide evidence on offending by children aged 12 to 15 years to inform the considerations of the Scottish Government’s ACR Advisory Group on a future ACR in Scotland.
... There is significant diversity worldwide with regards to juvenile justice systems and significant difficulties in establishing a minimal ACR (Weijers, 2016). There is widespread consensus that children below a certain age are too young to be held responsible for breaking the law and the variety of ACRs worldwide attests to a continuing debate within and between countries of what an advisable age should be. ...
Research
For many children who come into conflict with the law, their lives can include varying degrees of adversity, negative experiences, trauma and loss, often underscored by adverse socioeconomic circumstances. These factors can have substantial and sustained consequences for their development, behaviour and future outcomes. How these factors can influence and impact on children who offend, therefore, requires further investigation, particularly in the context of the recent rise in the Age of Criminal Responsibility (ACR) in Scotland to 12 years and Scottish Ministers’ duty to consider a future age of criminal responsibility. This research, examining 400 children's case files held by SCRA, was carried out to provide evidence on offending by children aged 12 to 15 years to inform the considerations of the Scottish Government’s ACR Advisory Group on a future ACR in Scotland.
... In most Western jurisdictions, the justification for imposing youth justice interventions is to be found in the suspicion or conviction that a child has committed a criminal offence for which she or he can be held responsible (Cipriani, 2009;Weijers, 2016). The imposed youth justice interventions, in turn, should be proportionate to the crime and the blameworthiness (or culpability) of the child (Steinberg, 2017;Von Hirsch, 2001;Weijers, 2017a). ...
Article
Full-text available
Equality is a fundamental principle, also in youth justice. Nevertheless, children from ethnic minorities, children with disabilities and children from low socioeconomic backgrounds are vastly overrepresented in youth detention populations across the globe. This article combines interdisciplinary theoretical perspectives and empirical findings from interviews with practitioners from two English youth courts to explore the meaning, perceptions and implications of the principle of equality in the specific context of the youth court. Ultimately, this article presents the first contours of a conceptual model of equality in the youth court, which aims to inform policy, practice and future research.
... As a result of continuing UK Government policy, it is clear that (see Table 1) MACR in England and Wales has been largely 'out of sync' with a majority of other European countries and is among the lowest in Europe (Bateman, 2012;Goldson, 2013;Hazel, 2008;Weijers, 2016). Should the example of other jurisdictions matter? ...
Article
Full-text available
The minimum age of criminal responsibility, as currently established within England and Wales, remains ten years of age. Despite criticism of the minimum age of criminal responsibility, the Westminster Government is unwilling, in spite of research evidence and growing distance between its and international visions of an acceptable threshold, to countenance change. Drawing upon the views of the United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child and the activities of devolved administrations within the UK, this article explores the need for change to be made to the minimum age of criminal responsibility and considers how holistic approaches, based upon diversion and rights respecting appropriate interventions can create transformative outcomes for children who come into contact with the law.
Article
Full-text available
In the middle of 2023, a thirteen-year-old elementary school student in Lukavac (Bosnia and Herzegovina) shot a teacher with a firearm, causing him life-threatening injuries. It happened just one month after a much more monstrous crime had been committed by his peer in a school in Belgrade. Taking into consideration that in accordance with the positive (juvenile) criminal legislation in the Federation of Bosnia and Herzegovina, young persons of that age cannot be prosecuted by the criminal justice authorities, because the age limit for the onset of criminal responsibility is 14 years, in light of the aforementioned events, one of the vice presidents of the Federation of Bosnia and Herzegovina submitted an initiative to the competent Ministry of Justice to amend the relevant legislation by lowering, or redefining the age limit for the onset of criminal responsibility. The paper presents different models of defining the age limits of criminal responsibility in comparative law, as well as tendencies related to their lowering, i.e. raising in the national laws of countries around the world in the last few decades. After that, the paper analyses the relevant international and supranational legal standards in this area, as well as the results of certain (neuro) scientific research related to this issue. Based on all of the above, it is concluded that the initiative to lower or redefine the age of criminal responsibility in the Federation of Bosnia and Herzegovina does not have a valid scientific and legal foundation and that it represents a kind of moral panic and penal populism.
Article
In criminal matters, the European Union (EU) managed to establish several mechanisms to strengthen and facilitate judicial cooperation over the years but does not clearly nor uniformly define the concepts of ‘criminal matters’, ‘criminal proceedings’, ‘criminal responsibility’ and so on in any of the cooperation instruments themselves. It is however important to know as to what the EU understands by the notion ‘criminal’ because Member States have developed specific rules in response to delinquent behaviour of minors, which are somewhat different from ‘general’ criminal law. The question arises whether the existing cooperation mechanisms only apply to ‘adult’ criminal matters or also include youth justice matters. This article therefore aims to find out whether a consistent and shared view exists on the meaning of the concept ‘criminal’ and to subsequently clarify to what extent the existing EU instruments in criminal matters also apply to juvenile offenders.
Article
Full-text available
RésuméPour ceux qui doivent passer en cour, de nombreux aspects de l'atmosphère de la salle d'audience pourraient sembler désagréables. Des problèmes généraux comme des retards, de la confusion et des comportements non professionnels pourraient mener à des évaluations plus globales de l'ensemble du système de justice, peu importe si les gens sentent qu'ils ont été traités, personnellement, de manière raisonnable par différents acteurs du tribunal. On a exploré ce phénomène en interrogeant des jeunes après leur première comparution en cour et en évaluant indépendamment l'atmosphère d'ensemble de la salle d'audience. On a découvert que peu importe comment les jeunes perçoivent le traitement qu'ils ont reçu, l'atmosphère de la salle d'audience était statistiquement étroitement liée à leur évaluation globale de la légitimité du système de justice pénale. Ceux qui ont perçu de la confusion et un manque de professionnalisme avaient tendance à juger l'ensemble du système de justice comme étant moins valable que ceux qui ont vécu une meilleure expérience.
Article
Full-text available
Testifying in court is a daunting experience for any witness and an understanding of legal terminology can be beneficial. Previous research has found that children under 11 years have significant gaps in their knowledge of court. However, while older children have been found to know more, their misunderstandings warrant further investigation. This study was designed to examine the understanding/misunderstanding of key legal words by older children (aged between 12 and 15 years). Also, it was predicted that within the current sample, participants from a selective school would know more than those from a non-selective school, females would know more than males, and older children would know more than younger children. A total of 111 participants were recruited from two secondary schools in Northern Ireland. This study was a 3×2×2 factorial design (12/13/15 years; female/male; school A/school B). Participants completed a knowledge-of-court questionnaire that asked them (i) if they recognized and (ii) to describe 16 legal terms. School type and age affected recognition and age affected description. Some notable mis-comprehensions were evident in all age groups, in particular for “cross-examination”, “jury” and “defendant”. The practical implications of these findings for witness preparation are discussed.
Article
Full-text available
This chapter reviews the foundation for the legal concept of adjudicative competence and frames questions about juveniles' competence. The first part of the chapter develops the concept of adjudicative competence and describes its legal contours. The second part explores the question of youths' participation in criminal trials from a historical perspective, examining whether and how the concept of adjudicative competence has been applied to youths in the past. It also discusses conceptual problems inherent in applying to juveniles the competence criteria currently used in criminal cases and offers suggestions for dealing with these problems. The final part argues for the application of adjudicative competence in juvenile courts in only a limited range of cases. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2012 APA, all rights reserved)
Article
Full-text available
Children below a certain age are too young to be held responsible for breaking the law. There is wide consensus about this principle, which is spelled out in the Convention on the Rights of the Child and in other international standards, such as the Beijing Rules for juvenile justice. The Convention calls for nations to establish a minimum age “below which children shall be presumed not to have the capacity to infringe the penal law”. And since the beginning of this year (2008) it sets 12 as the minimum age, explicitly. Worldwide, though, there is continuing debate about the appropriate age. This debate too often tends to arise when exceptional cases involving children who have committed heinous offences are given prominent coverage by the media. Sometimes this has far-reaching consequences. In England, children have become fully accountable for offending at 10 since the murder of two-year-old James Bulger by two young boys, both 10, in 1993. In New South Wales, the 1999 manslaughter trial of an 11-year-old boy for throwing his 6-year-old companion into a river attracted widespread comment and the NSW Attorney-General started a review of the age of criminal responsibility of children. In Japan, the minimum age was lowered from 16 to 14 in 2001 following public outrage over the brutal beheading of a little boy by a 14-year-old in 1997. The murder of another youth by a 12-year-old in 2003 in Nagasaki prompted the discussion again. In the USA, the state of Arkansas lowered the age at which young people could be tried as adults for murder to age 11, after an 11-year-old and a 13-year-old killed a youth with rifles at the entrance to their school. In the Czech Republic the minimum age is 15, but the Minister of Justice is considering lowering the age for particularly serious crimes, since in August 2006, six boys under the age of 15 robbed and killed an elderly woman and in February 2007 a 14-year-old boy confessed to the rape and murder of a classmate.
Article
This chapter uses behavioral and social sciences knowledge to review what we know and can infer about youths' capacities for participation in their trials in juvenile and criminal court. The application of legal criteria for competence to stand trial is not the only reason to be concerned about youths' capacities in the trial process. Even those who meet those criteria may present special issues because their immaturity may influence their participation in their trials. The first part of this chapter addresses the distinction between formal competence criteria and broader concerns about youths' participation in their trials. It also identifies the relevant abilities associated with capacities as a defendant, adolescent populations of concern, and areas of theory and research that are relevant for review. The second part reviews research describing youths' capacities relevant for their participation in their trials. The final section identifies what can be inferred from the review and suggests implications for policy, law, and practice. (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2012 APA, all rights reserved)
Article
Although having delinquent friends is one of the strongest known correlates of delinquent behavior, criminologists have been curiously silent as to why some adolescents acquire delinquent friends and others do not. Analysis of data from the national Survey of Parents and Children reveals a strong association between forms of direct and indirect parental supervision and the kinds of friends that adolescents make. Parents who closely monitor their children's affiliations exhibit a variety of traits typical of involved or conscientious parents. Indirect supervision also appears to mediate the effect of attachment to parents, one of the few established correlates of delinquent friendships. These and other findings illustrate the critical role that parent-child relations play in the process of making delinquent friends.
Chapter
The Republic of Ireland has a population of 3.9 million of this figure 29% are under the age of 20 years and 37% are under 25 years. Despite increasing immigration, Ireland still remains a relatively homogenous country with over 90% of individuals categorised as Irish and 88% of the population classified as Roman Catholic (Central Statistics Office, 2002). In April 2005, Ireland had the lowest rate of seasonally adjusted unemployment (4.2%) in the Eurozone compared to an average of 8.9% (Eurostat, 2005). Ireland also had the second lowest rate of youth unemployment (7.9% compared to an average of 19%) in the same period. This chapter focuses on the juvenile justice system in the Republic of Ireland. It documents the background and history to the Children Act of 2001 which is the first major change in juvenile justice legislation in almost 100 years. Trends in youth crime and crime prevention initiatives are discussed before moving on to discuss the main principles and provisions of the Children Act of 2001 including the use of custody as a measure of last resort, the increased use of community-based sanctions and the introduction of restorative justice initiatives into the system. A common theme throughout the chapter is the slow pace at which the new legislation is being implemented and the implications of these delays for young people in the criminal justice system. The chapter concludes with a reflection on the future direction of juvenile justice in the Republic of Ireland.
Article
The purpose of this paper is to report the results of a systematic review and meta-analysis of studies relating measures of cognitive and affective empathy to offending. It was possible to calculate a common measure of effect size (the standardized mean difference) in 35 studies, 21 of cognitive empathy and 14 of affective empathy. Low cognitive empathy was strongly related to offending, while low affective empathy was weakly related to offending. The Hogan Empathy Scale and the Questionnaire Measure of Emotional Empathy produced stronger relationships with offending than the Interpersonal Reactivity Index. The relationship between low empathy and offending was relatively strong for violent offenders, but relatively weak for sex offenders. This relationship was stronger for younger people than for older people. The relationship between low empathy and offending disappeared after controlling for intelligence and SES. More research is needed to investigate the causal links between low SES, low intelligence, low empathy, and offending. Better measures of empathy are needed, and empathy and offending need to be measured using self-reports in prospective longitudinal studies.
Article
Our study first determined what juveniles know about the juvenile court process. Second, it evaluated a DVD designed to be a systematic and simple way to improve this knowledge. A pre- and posttest design was used with two pilot samples and two samples from the population of interest. A sample from a juvenile detention center (n = 118) was the focus of this study. Initial knowledge of the court process was quite low for the detention sample (pretest M = 64.0%, SD = 14.2%). All samples experienced a significant improvement of knowledge after watching the DVD. Youth in the detention sample had a mean improvement from pretest to posttest of 6.4% (SD = 11.9%), with mean scores at posttest being 70.3% (SD = 17.4%). Respondents varied in their performance on different question topics, scoring the lowest on questions related to what happens at juvenile court hearings. The social and demographic variables of age, race, gender, grades in school, number of previous arrests, and the number of times the respondent had been to court were evaluated through regression analysis. Age and race were found to be significantly related to pretest scores, and race was significantly related to improvement scores.
Article
This study examined the development of young people's understanding of nurturance and self-determination rights. One hundred and sixty-nine participants from 5 age groups (8, 10, 12, 14, and 16 years of age) participated in a semistructured interview containing hypothetical vignettes, in which a story character wished to exercise a self-determination right or nurturance right that conflicted with the wishes or practices of those in authority. Participants were asked to decide if they would support the story character's request for rights and to justify their decisions. Younger children (8- to 12-year-olds) were significantly less likely to identify both nurturance and self-determination rights as salient than were older participants (14- to 16-year-olds). The types of reasoning participants exhibited for the two types of rights differed at all ages. Reasoning about nurturance rights did not show an age-related progression from concrete to abstract, whereas reasoning about self-determination rights was more likely to exhibit such a progression. Results suggest that previous attempts to explain the development of understanding of rights in terms of global stages does not fully capture children's and adolescents' reasoning, and, in particular, such a framework may not account for the differences in young people's thinking about the 2 types of rights.