ArticlePDF Available

Language in a New Key

Authors:

Abstract

Much of Noam Chomsky's revolution in linguistics—including its account of the way we learn languages—is being overturned
70 Scientific American, November 2016
LANGUAGE
LINGUISTICS
November 2016, ScientificAmerican.com 71
KEY
T
             —
famously espoused by Noam Chomsky of the Massachusetts Institute of Technology—
has dominated linguistics for almost half a century. Recently, though, cognitive scien-
tists and linguists have abandoned Chomsky’s “universal grammar” theory in droves
because of new research examining many dierent languages—and the way young chil-
dren learn to understand and speak the tongues of their communities. That work fails
to support Chomsky’s assertions.
The research suggests a radically dierent view, in which
learning of a child’s first language does not rely on an innate gram-
mar module. Instead the new research shows that young children
use various types of thinking that may not be specific to language
at all—such as the ability to classify the world into categories
(people or objects, for instance) and to understand the relations
Illustration by Owen Gildersleeve
Much of
Noam Chomsky’s
revolution in
linguistics—
including
its account
of the way we
learn languages—
is being overturned
By Paul Ibbotson
and Michael Tomasello
LANGUAGE
LINGUISTICS
IN A NE W
IN BRIEF
Noam Chomsky has been a towering
giant in the eld of linguistics for many
decades, famed for his well-known the-
ory of universal grammar.
Chomsky’s idea of a brain wired with
a mental template for grammar has been
questioned, based on a lack of evidence
from eld studies of languages.
The theory has changed several times
to account for exceptions that run coun-
ter to its original postulations—marking
a retreat from its ambitious origins.
Alternatives to universal grammar
posit that children learning language
use general cognitive abilities and the
reading of other people’s intentions.
72 Scientific American, November 2016
Paul Ibbotson is a lecturer in language development
at the Open University, based in England.
Michael Tomasello is co-director of the Max Planck
Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology in Leipzig, Germany,
and author, most recently, of A Natural History of Human
Morality (Harvard University Press, 2016).
among things. These capabilities, coupled with a unique hu man
ability to grasp what others intend to communicate, allow lan-
guage to happen. The new findings indicate that if researchers
truly want to understand how children, and others, learn languag-
es, they need to look outside of Chomsky’s theory for guidance.
This conclusion is important because the study of language
plays a central role in diverse disciplines—from poetry to artifi-
cial intelligence to linguistics itself; misguided methods lead to
questionable results. Further, language is used by humans in
ways no animal can match; if you understand what language is,
you comprehend a little bit more about human nature.
Chomsky’s first version of his theory, put forward in the mid-
20th century, meshed with two emerging trends in Western intel-
lectual life. First, he posited that the languages people use to com-
municate in everyday life behaved like mathematically based lan-
guages of the newly emerging field of computer science. His
research looked for the underlying computational structure of
language and proposed a set of procedures that would create
“well-formed” sentences. The revolutionary idea was that a com-
puterlike program could produce sentences real people thought
were grammatical. That program could also purportedly explain
the way people generated their sentences. This way of talking
about language resonated with many scholars eager to em brace a
computational approach to. .. well .. . everything.
As Chomsky was developing his computational theories, he
was simultaneously proposing that they were rooted in human
biology. In the second half of the 20th century, it was becoming
ever clearer that our unique evolutionary history was responsi-
ble for many aspects of our unique human psychology, and so
the theory resonated on that level as well. His universal gram-
mar was put forward as an innate component of the human
mind—and it promised to reveal the deep biological underpin-
nings of the world’s 6,000-plus human languages. The most
powerful, not to mention the most beautiful, theories in science
reveal hidden unity underneath surface diversity, and so this
theory held immediate appeal.
But evidence has overtaken Chomsky’s theory, which has
been inching toward a slow death for years. It is dying so slowly
because, as physicist Max Planck once noted, older scholars
tend to hang on to the old ways: “Science progresses one funer-
al at a time.”
IN THE BEGINNING
   of universal grammar in the 1960s
took the underlying structure of “standard average European”
languages as their starting point—the ones spoken by most of
the linguists working on them. Thus, the universal grammar
program operated on chunks of language, such as noun phrases
(“The nice dogs”) and verb phrases (“like cats”).
Fairly soon, however, linguistic comparisons among multiple
languages began rolling in that did not fit with this neat schema.
Some native Australian languages, such as Warlpiri, had gram-
matical elements scattered all over the sentence—noun and verb
phrases that were not “neatly packaged” so that they could be
plugged into Chomsky’s universal grammar—and some sentenc-
es had no verb phrase at all.
These so-called outliers were dicult to reconcile with the
universal grammar that was built on examples from European
languages. Other exceptions to Chomsky’s theory came from the
study of “ergative” languages, such as Basque or Urdu, in which
the way a sentence subject is used is very dierent from that in
many European languages, again challenging the idea of a uni-
versal grammar.
These findings, along with theoretical linguistic work, led
Chomsky and his followers to a wholesale revision of the notion of
universal grammar during the 1980s. The new version of the theo-
ry, called principles and parameters, replaced a single universal
grammar for all the world’s languages with a set of “universal”
principles governing the structure of language. These principles
manifested themselves dierently in each language. An analogy
might be that we are all born with a basic set of tastes (sweet, sour,
bitter, salty and umami) that interact with culture, history and
geography to produce the present-day variations in world cuisine.
The principles and parameters were a linguistic analogy to tastes.
They interacted with culture (whether a child was learning Japa-
nese or English) to produce today’s variation in languages as well
as defined the set of human languages that were possible.
Languages such as Spanish form fully grammatical sentenc-
es without the need for separate subjects—for example, Tengo
zapatos (“I have shoes”), in which the person who has the shoes,
“I,” is indicated not by a separate word but by the “o” at the end
of the verb. Chomsky contended that as soon as children
encountered a few sentences of this type, their brains would set
a switch to “on,” indicating that the sentence subject should be
dropped. Then they would know that they could drop the sub-
ject in all their sentences.
The “subject-drop” parameter supposedly also determined
other structural features of the language. This notion of universal
principles fits many European languages reasonably well. But
data from non-European languages turned out not to fit the
revised version of Chomsky’s theory. Indeed, the research that
had at tempted to identify parameters, such as the subject-drop,
ultimately led to the abandonment of the second incarnation of
universal grammar because of its failure to stand up to scrutiny.
More recently, in a famous paper published in Science in
2002, Chomsky and his co-authors described a universal gram-
mar that included only one feature, called computational recur-
sion (although many advocates of universal grammar still prefer
to assume there are many universal principles and parameters).
This new shift permitted a limited number of words and rules to
be combined to make an unlimited number of sentences.
The endless possibilities exist because of the way recursion
embeds a phrase within another phrase of the same type. For
example, English can embed phrases to the right (“John hopes
Mary knows Peter is lying”) or embed centrally (“The dog that the
cat that the boy saw chased barked”). In theory, it is possible to go
November 2016, ScientificAmerican.com 73Illustration by Lucy Reading-Ikkanda
on embedding these phases infinitely. In practice, understanding
starts to break down when the phrases are stacked on top of one
another as in these examples. Chomsky thought this breakdown
was not directly related to language per se. Rather it was a limita-
tion of human memory. More important, Chomsky proposed that
this recursive ability is what sets language apart from other types
of thinking such as categorization and perceiving the relations
among things. He also proposed recently this ability arose from a
single genetic mutation that occurred be tween 100,000 and
50,000 years ago.
As before, when linguists actually went looking at the varia-
tion in languages across the world, they found counterexamples
to the claim that this type of recursion was an essential property
of language. Some languages—the Amazonian Pirahã, for in -
stance—seem to get by without Chomskyan recursion.
As with all linguistic theories, Chomsky’s universal grammar
tries to perform a balancing act. The theory has to be simple
enough to be worth having. That is, it must predict some things
that are not in the theory itself (otherwise it is just a
list of facts). But neither can the theory be so sim-
ple that it cannot explain things it should. Take
Chomsky’s idea that sentences in all the world’s
languages have a “subject.” The problem is the
concept of a subject is more like a “family
resemblance” of features than a neat category.
About 30 dierent grammatical features define
the characteristics of a subject. Any one language
will have only a subset of these features—and the sub-
sets often do not overlap with those of other languages.
Chomsky tried to define the components of the essential tool
kit of language—the kinds of mental machinery that allow hu -
man language to happen. Where counterexamples have been
found, some Chomsky defenders have responded that just be -
cause a language lacks a certain tool—recursion, for example—
does not mean that it is not in the tool kit. In the same way, just
because a culture lacks salt to season food does not mean salty is
not in its basic taste repertoire. Unfortunately, this line of reason-
ing makes Chomsky’s proposals dicult to test in practice, and in
places they verge on the unfalsifiable.
DEATH KNELLS
   in Chomsky’s theories is that when applied to language
learning, they stipulate that young children come equipped with
the capacity to form sentences using abstract grammatical rules.
(The precise ones depend on which version of the theory is in -
voked.) Yet much research now shows that language acquisition
does not take place this way. Rather young children begin by
learning simple grammatical patterns; then, gradually, they intu-
it the rules behind them bit by bit.
Thus, young children initially speak with only concrete and
simple grammatical constructions based on specific patterns of
words: “Where’s the X?”; “I wanna X”; “More X”; “It’s an X”; “I’m
X-ing it”; “Put X here”; “Mommy’s X-ing it”; “Let’s X it”; “Throw
X”; “X gone”; “Mommy X”; “I Xed it”; “Sit on the X”; “Open X”;
“X here”; “There’s an X”; “X broken.” Later, children combine
these early patterns into more complex ones, such asWhere’s
the X that Mommy Xed?”
Many proponents of universal grammar accept this charac-
terization of children’s early grammatical development. But then
THEORIES OF LANGUAGE
Noam-enclature
Noam Chomsky took the linguistics community by storm more
than 50 years ago. The idea was simple. Underlying language is
a set of rules innate to every child that generates grammatical
sentences from the earliest age. Chomsky set out to dene those
rules and how they work. Without this universal grammar, he
thought, it would be impossible for a child to learn any language.
In the ensuing years, Chomsky’s theory has gradually been chal-
lenged by new theories asserting that language is acquired as
children discern patterns in the language they hear around them.
Sentence
Noun
phrase
Verb
phrase
Determiner
Adjective
Noun
Verb
Noun
phrase
the nice dogs like
cats
wants
?
“wants”
“The dog
wants the ball.
“The dog
wants food.
Chomsky’s Universal Grammar
Chomsky’s universal grammar equipped the child with rules that worked on
phrases (“the nice dogs”) and rules for transforming those phrases (“Cats
are liked by the nice dogs”). The theory has evolved in recent years but still
retains the essential idea that children are born with the ability to make words
conform to a grammatical template.
Usage-Based Learning
New approaches to linguistics and psychology suggest that children’s natural
ability to intuit what others think, combined with powerful learning mechanisms
in the developing brain, diminishes the need for a universal grammar. Through
listening, the child learns patterns of usage that can be applied to dierent
sentences. The word “food” might replace the word “ball” after the phrase
“The dog wants. Studies show that this theory of building up knowledge
of word meaning and grammar approximates the way that two- and three-
year-olds actually learn language.
Sentence
Noun
phrase
Verb
phrase
Determiner
Adjective
Noun
Verb
Noun
phrase
the nice dogs like
cats
wants
?
“wants”
“The dog
wants the ball.
“The dog
wants food.
The
brain’s innate
sentence-diagramming
machine, according to
Chomsky, would t words
into correct grammatical
slots—“nice” (adjective),
“dogs” (noun).
they assume that when more complex constructions emerge,
this new stage reflects the maturing of a cognitive capacity that
uses universal grammar and its abstract grammatical categories
and principles.
For example, most universal grammar approaches postulate
that a child forms a question by following a set of rules based on
grammatical categories such as “What (object) did (auxiliary)
you (subject) lose (verb)?” Answer: “I (subject) lost (verb) some-
thing (object).” If this postulate is correct, then at a given devel-
opmental period children should make similar errors across all
wh-question sentences alike. But children’s errors do not fit this
prediction. Many of them early in development make errors
such as “Why he can’t come?” but at the same time as they make
this error—failing to put the “can’t” before the “he”—they cor-
rectly form other questions with other “wh-words” and auxilia-
ry verbs, such as the sentence “What does he want?”
Experimental studies confirm that children produce correct
question sentences most often with particular wh-words and aux-
iliary verbs (often those with which they have most experience,
such as “What does .. . ”), while continuing to make errors with
question sentences containing other (often less frequent) combi-
nations of wh-words and auxiliary verbs: “Why he can’t come?”
The main response of universal grammarians to such find-
ings is that children have the competence with grammar but that
other factors can impede their performance and thus both hide
the true nature of their grammar and get in the way of studying
the “pure” grammar posited by Chomsky’s linguistics. Among
the factors that mask the underlying grammar, they say, include
immature memory, attention and social capacities.
Yet the Chomskyan interpretation of the children’s behavior is
not the only possibility. Memory, attention and social abilities
may not mask the true status of grammar; rather they may well
be integral to building a language in the first place. For example,
a recent study co-authored by one of us (Ibbotson) showed that
children’s ability to produce a correct irregular past tense verb—
such as “Every day I fly, yesterday I flew(not “flyed”)—was asso-
ciated with their ability to inhibit a tempting response that was
unrelated to grammar. (For example, to say the word “moon”
while looking at a picture of the sun.) Rather than memory, men-
tal analogies, attention and reasoning about social situations get-
ting in the way of children expressing the pure grammar of
Chomskyan linguistics, those mental faculties may explain why
language develops as it does.
As with the retreat from the cross-linguistic data and the
tool-kit argument, the idea of performance masking compe-
tence is also pretty much unfalsifiable. Retreats to this type of
claim are common in declining scientific paradigms that lack a
strong em pirical base—consider, for instance, Freudian psy-
chology and Marxist in terpretations of history.
Even beyond these empirical challenges to universal grammar,
psycholinguists who work with children have diculty conceiving
theoretically of a process in which children start with the same
algebraic grammatical rules for all languages and then proceed to
figure out how a particular language—whether English or Swahi-
li—connects with that rule scheme. Linguists call this conundrum
the linking problem, and a rare systematic attempt to solve it in
the context of universal grammar was made by Harvard Universi-
ty psychologist Steven Pinker for sentence subjects. Pinker’s ac -
count, however, turned out not to agree with data from child de -
velopment studies or to be applicable to grammatical categories
other than subjects. And so the linking problem—which should be
the central problem in applying universal grammar to language
learning—has never been solved or even seriously confronted.
AN ALTERNATIVE VIEW
    ineluctably to the view that
the notion of universal grammar is plain
wrong. Of course, scientists never give up on
their favorite theory, even in the face of con-
tradictory evidence, until a reasonable alter-
native appears. Such an alternative, called
usage-based linguistics, has now arrived. The
theory, which takes a number of forms, pro-
poses that grammatical structure is not in -
nate. Instead grammar is the product of his-
tory (the processes that shape how languages
are passed from one generation to the next) and human psychol-
ogy (the set of social and cognitive capacities that allow genera-
tions to learn a language in the first place). More important, this
theory proposes that language recruits brain systems that may
not have evolved specifically for that purpose and so is a dier-
ent idea to Chomsky’s single-gene mutation for recursion.
In the new usage-based approach (which includes ideas from
functional linguistics, cognitive linguistics and construction
grammar), children are not born with a universal, dedicated tool
for learning grammar. Instead they inherit the mental equiva-
lent of a Swiss Army knife: a set of general-purpose tools—such
as categorization, the reading of communicative intentions, and
analogy making, with which children build grammatical catego-
ries and rules from the language they hear around them.
For instance, English-speaking children understand “The cat
ate the rabbit,” and by analogy they also understand “The goat
tickled the fairy.” They generalize from hearing one example to
another. After enough examples of this kind, they might even be
able to guess who did what to whom in the sentence “The gazzer
mibbed the toma,” even though some of the words are literally
nonsensical. The grammar must be something they discern
beyond the words themselves, given that the sentences share lit-
tle in common at the word level.
The meaning in language emerges through an interaction
between the potential meaning of the words themselves (such
as the things that the word “ate” can mean) and the meaning of
the grammatical construction into which they are plugged. For
example, even though “sneeze” is in the dictionary as an intran-
sitive verb that only goes with a single actor (the one who sneez-
es), if one forces it into a ditransitive construction—one able to
In the new usage-based approach,
children are not born with a universal,
dedicated tool for the learning of
grammar. Instead they inherit the
mental equivalent of a Swiss Army knife.
Watch Tomasello give a talk on human communication at ScienticAmerican.com/nov2016/tomasello
SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN ONLINE
November 2016, ScientificAmerican.com 75
take both a direct and indirect object—the result might be “She
sneezed him the napkin,” in which “sneeze” is construed as an
action of transfer (that is to say, she made the napkin go to him).
The sentence shows that grammatical structure can make as
strong a contribution to the meaning of the utterance as do the
words. Contrast this idea with that of Chomsky, who argued
there are levels of grammar that are free of meaning entirely.
The concept of the Swiss Army knife also explains language
learning without any need to invoke two phenomena required by
the universal grammar theory. One is a series of algebraic rules for
combining symbols—a so-called core grammar hardwired in the
brain. The second is a lexicon—a list of exceptions that cover all of
the other idioms and idiosyncrasies of natural languages that
must be learned. The problem with this dual-route approach is
that some grammatical constructions are partially rule-based and
also partially not—for example, “Him a presidential candidate?!”
in which the subject “him” retains the form of a direct object but
with the elements of the sentence not in the proper order. A native
English speaker can generate an infinite variety of sentences using
the same approach: “Her go to ballet?!” or “That guy a doctor?!” So
the question becomes, are these utterances part of the core gram-
mar or the list of exceptions? If they are not part of a core gram-
mar, then they must be learned individually as separate items.
But if children can learn these part-rule, part-exception utteranc-
es, then why can they not learn the rest of language the same
way? In other words, why do they need universal grammar at all?
In fact, the idea of universal grammar contradicts evidence
showing that children learn language through social interaction
and gain practice using sentence constructions that have been
created by linguistic communities over time. In some cases, we
have good data on exactly how such learning happens. For exam-
ple, relative clauses are quite common in the world’s languages
and often derive from a meshing of separate sentences. Thus, we
might say, “My brother. . . . He lives over in Arkansas . . . . He likes
to play piano.” Because of various cognitive-processing mecha-
nisms—with names such as schematization, habituation, decon-
textualization and automatization—these phrases evolve over
long periods into a more complex construction: My brother,
who lives over in Arkansas, likes to play the piano.” Or they
might turn sentences such as “I pulled the door, and it shut”
gradually into “I pulled the door shut.”
What is more, we seem to have a species-specific ability to de -
code others’ communicative intentions—what a speaker intends to
say. For example, I could say, “She gave/bequeathed/sent/loaned/
sold the library some books” but not “She donated the library
some books.” Recent research has shown that there are several
mechanisms that lead children to constrain these types of inap-
propriate analogies. For example, children do not make analogies
that make no sense. So they would never be tempted to say “She
ate the library some books.” In addition, if children hear quite
often “She donated some books to the library,” then this usage pre-
empts the temptation to say “She donated the library some books.”
Such constraining mechanisms vastly cut down the possible
analogies a child could make to those that align the communica-
tive intentions of the person he or she is trying to understand.
We all use this kind of intention reading when we understand
“Can you open the door for me?” as a request for help rather
than an inquiry into door-opening abilities.
Chomsky allowed for this kind of “pragmatics”—how we use
language in context—in his general theory of how language
worked. Given how ambiguous language is, he had to. But he
appeared to treat the role of pragmatics as peripheral to the
main job of grammar. In a way, the contributions from usage-
based approaches have shifted the debate in the other direction
to how much pragmatics can do for language before speakers
need to turn to the rules of syntax.
Usage-based theories are far from oering a complete ac -
count of how language works. Meaningful generalizations that
children make from hearing spoken sentences and phrases are
not the whole story of how children construct sentences either—
there are generalizations that make sense but are not grammati-
cal (for example, “He disappeared the rabbit”). Out of all the pos-
sible meaningful yet ungrammatical generalizations children
could make, they appear to make very few. The reason seems to
be they are sensitive to the fact that the language community to
which they belong conforms to a norm and communicates an
idea in just “this way.” They strike a delicate balance, though, as
the language of children is both creative (“I goed to the shops”)
and conformative to grammatical norms (“I went to the shops”).
There is much work to be done by usage-based theorists to
explain how these forces interact in childhood in a way that
exactly explains the path of language development.
A LOOK AHEAD
   the Chomskyan paradigm was proposed, it was a rad-
ical break from the more informal approaches prevalent at the
time, and it drew attention to all the cognitive complexities in -
volved in becoming competent at speaking and understanding
language. But at the same time that theories such as Chomsky’s
allowed us to see new things, they also blinded us to other aspects
of language. In linguistics and allied fields, many researchers are
be coming ever more dissatisfied with a totally formal language
approach such as universal grammar—not to mention the empir-
ical inadequacies of the theory. Moreover, many modern re -
searchers are also unhappy with armchair theoretical analyses,
when there are large corpora of linguistic data—many now avail-
able online—that can be analyzed to test a theory.
The paradigm shift is certainly not complete, but to many it
seems that a breath of fresh air has entered the field of linguistics.
There are exciting new discoveries to be made by investigating the
details of the world’s dierent languages, how they are similar to
and dierent from one another, how they change historically, and
how young children acquire competence in one or more of them.
Universal grammar appears to have reached a final impasse.
In its place, research on usage-based linguistics can provide a
path forward for empirical studies of learning, use and histori-
cal development of the world’s 6,000 languages.
MORE TO EXPLORE
Constructing a Language: A Usage-Based Theory of Language Acquisition.
Michael Tomasello. Harvard University Press, 2003.
Constructions at Work: The Nature of Generalization in Language. Adele Gold-
berg. Oxford University Press, 2006.
Language, Usage and Cognition. Joan Bybee. Cambridge University Press, 2010.
FROM OUR ARCHIVES
The “It” Factor. Gary Stix; September 2014.
scientificamerican.com/magazine/sa
... 10 For a disparaging use of the term 'armchair linguistics' see Ibbotson and Tomasello (2016), and for a response see this entry on the knitting and sewing blog of Allison Cameron, a former undergraduate student of mine: http://woolandpotato.com/2016/10/05/scientific-american-says-universal-grammaris-dead-a-response/. then all that lab work will also be built on a shaky foundation. ...
... 13 For example, the former Director of Research at Google, Peter Norvig (2011) says that "one more reason why Chomsky dislikes statistical models is that they tend to make linguistics an empirical science." Similarly, Ibbotson and Tomasello (2016) claim that "evidence has overtaken Chomsky's theory, which has been inching toward a slow death for years." Such comments not only ignore the massive literature of sophisticated analyses of many, many languages produced by generative linguists, not least by Chomsky himself, but also they ignore Chomsky's explicit endorsement of applying the methods of the natural sciences in linguistics, as in papers like "Language as a natural object" (Chomsky, 2000a). ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Universal Grammar is usefully viewed as a postulate that allows empirical work to proceed. I describe eleven overlapping Empirical Argumentation Devices that theoretical linguists use, often tacitly.
... In this context, the data made available by researchers adopting socio-pragmatic approach also appears quite significant in the sense that it also tends to challenge the Chomskyan assumption that children are endowed with adult-like linguistic competence. For instance, studies reviewed by Tomasello and his coworkers tend to go against Chomskyan claims because they entail that children use many cognitive strategies that are not specific to learning of language (Ibbotson & Tomasello, 2016). The Chomskyans have also been found to have grossly overestimated children's early linguistic competence (Goldberg, 2006, Ibbotson et al., 2012, Ibbotson & Tomasello, 2016, Tomasello, 2000. ...
... For instance, studies reviewed by Tomasello and his coworkers tend to go against Chomskyan claims because they entail that children use many cognitive strategies that are not specific to learning of language (Ibbotson & Tomasello, 2016). The Chomskyans have also been found to have grossly overestimated children's early linguistic competence (Goldberg, 2006, Ibbotson et al., 2012, Ibbotson & Tomasello, 2016, Tomasello, 2000. Tomasello's review of data shows that "young children's early language is more concrete and item-based" than is usually admitted by the Chomskyans (2000, p. 211 & p. 237). ...
Article
Full-text available
The purpose of this paper is to examine the debate between Chomsky (and his followers) and his opponents which largely includes developmentalists and constructivists in the context of language acquisition. As is well known, Chomskyans have tended to argue that the innate structure is most important in deciding the outcome of developmental processes. The environmental input, for them, is nothing more than a mere ‘trigger’ to kick-start the innate mechanisms responsible for the developmental outcomes1. One of the reasons, among others, for this preference is that an ‘unconstrained learner’ – the learner who is not biased in any way either in favour or against any probable solution to the given problem - cannot arrive at the right kind of solution within realistic time constraints. That is, s/he is not able to take a step towards the solution of the problem in the normally expected time frame (Gold, 1967; Laurence & Margolis ,2001). The developmentalists and their constructivist cousins, on the contrary, consider environment to be playing a crucial role. In so far as the outcome of developmental processes is concerned neither the Chomskyans consider these to be entirely resulting from innate mechanisms nor do their opponents consider everything to be resulting from environmental influences. Researchers belonging to both the camps recognize the role of innate mechanisms as well as the environmental inputs. That is, none of the groups holds an exclusive and exhaustive position with respect to the two -- the innate mechanisms and the environmental factors. What still distinguishes them and fuels the controversy is ‘the extent of control’, and the importance that each group is willing to grant to any one of these two factors (Karmiloff & Karmiloff-Smith, 2001). The controversy, therefore, has boiled down to the relative influence of environment and genetic endowment on developmental processes or to specifying the process by which any such account may actually work: mechanisms, representations, learning algorithms, constraints, biological processes that deliver the constraints. On the basis of the review of research undertaken here, the paper concludes that the available evidence tends to considerably strengthen the developmentalist alternative vis-à-vis strict Chomskyan approach to the topic.
... The belief in the proposal of innateness of Universal Grammar and the dedicated nature of a processing device for its implementation has undoubtedly been most dear to Chomskyans (Chomsky, 1975(Chomsky, , 1980(Chomsky, , 1993Piattelli-Palmarini, 1980;Laurence & Margolis, 2001). However, in recent years this proposal has come under sustained attack from researchers concerned with the issues of investigating the nature of innateness and brain plasticity (Elman et al. 1996;Johnson 1997Johnson & 1999 as well as those working in the broad area of language acquisition (D'Souza & Karmiloff-Smith, 2016;Elman et al., 1996;Ibbotson & Tomasello, 2016;Karmiloff-Smith & Johnson, 1991;Karmiloff-Smith, 1992;Mareschal et al., 2007;Quartz, 1993;Quartz & Sejnowski, 1997). In the context of the present paper, the work of Bates and her colleagues is particularly important for being in the forefront in challenging both the autonomy of grammar from other aspects of language as well as the existence of a dedicated grammar processing device. ...
Article
Full-text available
The present article aims at assessing the role of different communicative factors for their critical role in language acquisition and their implication for Chomskyan nativism. When it comes to Chomskyan position on the question of language acquisition, it is found that they largely tend to legitimize their own position on the basis of imputing non-existent and indefensible positions to their opponents. The vast amount of literature that is reviewed in the present essay has however failed to find evidence for anti-nativists holding any such extreme views. What the anti-nativist theorists (often referred to as developmentalists/ constructivists/ neuro-constructivists, etc.) are generally found to be doing is articulation of their position in terms of constraints and role of experience with linguistic input that facilitate and restrict definite species-specific cognitive achievements rather than swearing by Lockean belief in human mind as a tabula rasa. Such a reasoning can hardly be thought of as the guiding spirit of researchers whose work is discussed and reviewed here. Therefore, Chomskyan nativism is not the only available position when it comes to explaining language acquisition by humans as there is a vast middle ground that falls between the extremes of Lockean tabula rasa approach and Chomskyan nativism. It is one of the endeavors of the present essay to direct our attention to this middle ground and demonstrate this to be more of a viable alternative to the other two extreme positions of radical empiricism and Chomskyan nativism.
Article
Full-text available
هدفت هذه الدراسة إلى تعرّف أثر برنامج مقترح مستند إلى نظرية فيرث السياقية في تنمية مهارات اللغة الإنجليزية لدى طلبة الصف الثامن الأساسي في الأردن. وبلغ عدد أفراد الدراسة (53)، طالبًا وطالبة من مدرستي المستندة الثانوية المختلطة، والمستندة الثانوية للبنين التابعتين لمديرية التربية والتعليم لواء القويسمة. ووزّعت الشعب عشوائيًّا على مجموعتين: تجريبية وضابطة درست المجموعة التجريبية وفق البرنامج التعليمي، أمّا المجموعة الضابطة فدرست وفق البرنامج الاعتيادي. وأعدّ الباحثان البرنامج التعليمي، واختبار مهارات اللغة الإنجليزية بعد التأكد من صدقه وثباته. أظهرت نتائج الدراسة وجود فروق ذات دلالة إحصائية عند مستوى دلالة (0.05=α) لدى طلبة الصف الثامن الأساسي في تنمية مهارتي القراءة والكتابة في اللغة الإنجليزية وفقاً للمجموعة (تجريبية، ضابطة) لصالح المجموعة التجريبية حيث بلغت قيمة (ف) (36.678) بدلالة إحصائيّة مقدارها (0.000)، وهي قيمة دالّة إحصائيًّا لصالح المجموعة التجريبية التي درست وفق البرنامج المستند إلى نظرية فيرث السياقيّة. وفي ضوء نتائج البحث، خرجت الدّراسة بعدّة توصيات منها: اعتماد البرنامج المقترح المستند إلى نظرية فيرث السياقية، الذي توصّلت إليه الدّراسة الحالية في تدريس مهارات اللغة الإنجليزية لطلبة الصف الثامن الأساسي في الأردن.
Research
Full-text available
A full journal issue!
Conference Paper
On a daily basis, a human being relies on the ability to perceive, recognize, interpret and reproduce a stream of speech. The language is biologically encoded in our brain since the day we are born. Described briefly as the exchange of thoughts, ideas and knowledge, language was difficult to be precisely localized within the brain for many years. The most important areas of the brain involved in the speech and language systems in the brain have been researched and discussed starting with patients whose brain was damaged and the main effects were speech problems in talking or in comprehension of the speech. Definitions of language, descriptions of functionality and as accurate as can be spoken organization of the main systems within the human brain have been tried to be let in the research field. Looking back in the literature, we can see that the most important role in this field is taken by the latest neuroimaging methods developed over the years and which helped researchers in exploring and mapping the brain.
Article
In this book, Stewart Clem develops an account of truthfulness that is grounded in the Thomistic virtue of veracitas. Unlike most contemporary Christian ethicists, who narrowly focus on the permissibility of lying, he turns to the virtue of truthfulness and illuminates its close relationship to the virtue of justice. This approach generates a more precise taxonomy of speech acts and shows how they are grounded in specific virtues and vices. Clem's study also contributes to the contemporary literature on Aquinas, who is often classified alongside Augustine and Kant as holding a rigorist position on lying. Meticulously researched, this volume clarifies what set Aquinas's view apart in his own day and how it is relevant to our own. Clem demonstrates that Aquinas's account provides a genuine alternative to rigorist and consequentialist approaches. His analysis also reveals the perennial relevance of Aquinas's thought by bringing it to bear on contemporary social and ethical issues.
Chapter
This chapter presents in more detail a contemporary of both Saussure and Chomsky: Mikhail Bakhtin, whose proto-pragmatism sets the scene for a consideration of the contemporary study of pragmatics—language in context. We have attempted to read the work of Bakhtin and his colleagues in a manner free of the Marxist, Christian, semiotic, and poststructuralist prejudices that have led many to misread and appropriate his stunningly original contributions to the study of language. We then turn to the rich pragmatic and cognitive trends in language study that most closely adhere to, derive from, and develop in parallel ways to Bakhtin’s approaches. Particular emphasis is placed on the theory of relevance proposed by Dan Sperber and Deidre Wilson. It is this concept of language as a cognitive tool employed by embodied human agents that, as we suggest, is most useful to literary scholars.
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any references for this publication.