ArticlePDF Available

Lacan, Psi and the Trickster: A Psychoanalysis of Parapsychology

Authors:

Abstract

The privileging of physicalist ontologies and rigid experimentalism within parapsychology helps to expose a 'hole' in the praxis of the discipline proper; what psychoanalysis generally refers to as a " lack ". Certain not to fill this hole, using the psychoanalytic approach pioneered by Jacques Lacan (i.e., Lacanian psychoanalysis), the following reading aims to develop theoretically a scene by which parapsychology can come, more self-reflectively, to better take in its scientific practice—the unconscious of its subject, how the discipline has chosen to carve itself out within, what Lacan calls the chaotic, polysemic pool of lalangue, that place where meaning slides around. Indeed, such a return to the unconscious actually opens up the field to more counter-hegemonic phenomena that are typically viewed as fringe. To illustrate this point, I deploy the Lacanian après-coup, otherwise known as retroaction (a causality not from the present time), in conjunction with extrasensory perception research to stage just such an encounter, between the subject of parapsychology and its lack. This not only thwarts the so-called 'source of psi' problem by showing how parapsychology is running from itself, but also reveals a homology between psi and the objet petit a—the little object of desire that must always be tamed. As such, the disciplinary contouring of parapsychological science evokes the wily qualities of the trickster. It follows that, in the future, a further psychoanalysis of parapsychology could work to develop the theoretical insights of this article with some of Lacan's other concepts, such as the jouissance of the body (i.e., the anxious pleasure that animates the subject), and the relationship between drive and desire.
© 2016 AIPR, Inc. Australian Journal of Parapsychology
ISSN: 1445-2308 Volume 16, Number 2, pp. 163-193
163
Lacan, Psi and the Trickster:
A Psychoanalysis of Parapsychology
JACOB W. GLAZIER
Abstract: The privileging of physicalist ontologies and rigid
experimentalism within parapsychology helps to expose a ‘hole’ in the
praxis of the discipline proper; what psychoanalysis generally refers to
as a “lack”. Certain not to fill this hole, using the psychoanalytic
approach pioneered by Jacques Lacan (i.e., Lacanian psychoanalysis),
the following reading aims to develop theoretically a scene by which
parapsychology can come, more self-reflectively, to better take in its
scientific practice—the unconscious of its subject, how the discipline
has chosen to carve itself out within, what Lacan calls the chaotic,
polysemic pool of lalangue, that place where meaning slides around.
Indeed, such a return to the unconscious actually opens up the field to
more counter-hegemonic phenomena that are typically viewed as
fringe. To illustrate this point, I deploy the Lacanian après-coup,
otherwise known as retroaction (a causality not from the present time),
in conjunction with extrasensory perception research to stage just such
an encounter, between the subject of parapsychology and its lack. This
not only thwarts the so-called ‘source of psi’ problem by showing how
parapsychology is running from itself, but also reveals a homology
between psi and the objet petit a—the little object of desire that must
always be tamed. As such, the disciplinary contouring of
parapsychological science evokes the wily qualities of the trickster. It
follows that, in the future, a further psychoanalysis of parapsychology
could work to develop the theoretical insights of this article with some
of Lacan’s other concepts, such as the jouissance of the body (i.e., the
anxious pleasure that animates the subject), and the relationship
between drive and desire.
Keywords: extrasensory perception, Jacques Lacan, physicalism,
psychoanalysis, retroaction, trickster theory.
What could be more convincing, moreover, than the gesture of laying one’s cards
face up on the table? So much so that we are momentarily persuaded that the
magician has in fact demonstrated, as he promised, how his trick was performed,
whereas he has only performed it in still purer form: at which point we fathom the
measure of the supremacy of the signifier in the subject. (Lacan, 1988, p. 36)
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
164
INTRODUCTION
The paradoxical gesture, opening this article, is given by Jacques
Lacan who was a French, twentieth-century psychoanalyst. Most notably,
Lacan is famous for taking traditional Freudian psychoanalytic theory and
applying Saussurean1 structuralist concepts to it. This created a kind of
psychoanalytic practice that took speech, or language more generally, as
most important, over and above some of the other approaches to
psychoanalysis that, in contradistinction to Lacan, preferred conceptualizing
the subject through biology, object-relations, archetypes or the well
adjustment of the ego.
The term subject, in Lacanian psychoanalysis, refers to any being
that possesses an unconscious. In the clinic, during the practice of
psychoanalysis, this being is referred to as the analysand or the one who
desires treatment. More broadly, however, the subject may additionally
refer to a set of practices, rituals and implicit rules that are bundled together
forming, for the purposes of this paper, the discipline called
parapsychology.
Returning to the importance of language for Lacan, the notion of the
subject brings up his theory of the signifier, alluded to in the inaugural
epigraph, which perhaps most clearly elucidates this approach’s emphasis
on language. The signifier, not unlike psi for parapsychology, represents a
privileged category or term. The signifier is the pure, physical and empty
form that carries information allowing for communication and the process
of meaning-making—or, what is also called in semiotics, signification.
Contrast this to the signified, which is the intelligible meaning itself, or the
sense made out of the world by the subject. The import this has for the
sciences applies to how knowledge is produced, or the question of what is
knowable. In other words, the epistemology of the discipline is always
subservient to, or at least dictated by, the logic of the signifier, its stubborn
encasement within the subject, whether that happens to be an analysand or a
scientific discipline.
1 By way of a brief introduction, Saussure was a Swiss linguist whose main contribution was
the scientific formalization of the field, which relied on reducing the sign to its constitutive
parts called the signifier and the signified. A sign is the combination of a concept (mental
processes) and a sound-image (what is heard). Saussure’s (1959) claim is thus “… to retain the
word sign [signe] to designate the whole and to replace concept and sound-image respectively
by signified [signif] and signifier [signifiant]” (p. 67, emphasis in original). Importantly for
Lacanian theory, this dual nature ascribed to the sign allows the further positing that “the bond
between the signifier and the signified is arbitrary” (Saussure, 1959, p. 67). Such an
arbitrariness is another name for the lack or void of every speaking subject.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
165
Such a ‘problematic of meaning’ may nowhere be clearer than in the
parapsychological literature and, precisely put, in regard to how the
discipline understands its scientific practice; for a reasonable spread of
opinion on the matter cf. Alcock, (1981), Braude, (1986), and Glazier,
(2014). In fact, some of these researchers claim that the study of psi
phenomena may actually be a challenge to the hegemony of legendary
science—i.e., the positivist and rigidly quantitative approaches to doing
science. For the purposes of analyzing parapsychology, I want to predicate
this term on assumptions derived from physicalist ontology and their
consequent experimentalist methodologies. Returning to the ‘problematic of
meaning’ hinted at earlier, is psi, by its very definition, an anomaly that
threatens to unravel or reconfigure the project of science as such? Again, is
it the case that psi is perhaps trying to say something, somewhat
mischievously, about its very constitution therein entailing certain
ramifications for the praxis of its study?
Kennedy (2016) puts forth just such a suggestion saying that “the
failure to produce convincingly reliable psi effects after 80 years of
experimental research indicates that fundamental factors are not yet
understood for the operation of psi” (p. 53). The researcher further goes on
to propose George Hansen’s (2001) conception of psi as an iteration on the
trickster as helpful in showing how “psi effects can be striking and reliable
for a period of time, but then seem to actively avoid sustained or useful
effects” (Kennedy, 2016, p. 53).
Trickster theory, as it is known in parapsychology, generally takes its
lead from Hansen’s (2001) book The Trickster and the Paranormal,
wherein the author suggests that paranormal phenomena, or psi specifically,
bear a remarkable resemblance to the trickster anecdotes and mythologies
from around the world. In fact, one of the implications of the theory entails
that the wily characteristics of the trickster may be to blame for the
historical difficulty parapsychology has had rendering its object of study,
psi, as legitimate, valid and scientific. That is to say in more technical
parlance that perhaps due to its ontological composition—the very
beinghood it possesses—psi constitutes an ever-present and unassimilable
threat through its ability to thwart any totalized interpellation into an a
priori model. In earlier terms employed, the epistemological relation
parapsychology has to psi, the bridge between the signifier and the
signified, necessarily invokes the qualities of the trickster. Some of these
qualities Hansen (2016) names as “binary oppositions, liminality, anti-
structure, communitas, betwixt and between, [and] interstitiality” (p. 52).
These are thematic concepts that Hansen uses to talk about the traits that
paranormality and psi share with the figure of the trickster—most seminally
in his book, and more recently during the trickster panel at the 59th Annual
Convention of the Parapsychological Association.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
166
The trickster, for Hansen, is ultimately literary such that his theory
relies on the contextualization of a trope. A trope in this sense is the
development of a literary figure or special motif that aids in helping to
explain the way psi behaves. The former understanding of trope, as a
literary figure, is preferred because it gets at the fleshly materiality and
embodiment of the trickster—even though these are written or verbal
stories, this specific literary figure, in a certain paradoxical manner, has a
peculiar taste for the opposite of language: the sensual and animal aspects of
experience as opposed to the headiness of instrumental rationality. Read as
a figure that cuts across cultural boundaries, then, it does not matter whether
the trope of the trickster is located within a formal theory (the archetypal,
collective unconscious and analytic theory of Jung), communal anecdotes
and mythologies (the coyote stories of the Native Americans or Lucifer of
Paradise Lost), or societal persons or institutions (the shaman of indigenous
cultures or parapsychology proper). As such, Hansen is able to precipitate
or reduce certain commonalities that he finds between the
parapsychological literature and the figural or literary instantiations of the
trickster; as stated previously, these are binary oppositions, liminality, anti-
structure, communitas, betwixt and between, and interstitiality.
On this account, the trickster has a taste for the inversion of
opposites—for example, the sacred and profane, food and excrement,
intelligence and foolishness—that undergird communal relations. Such
reversals allow the trickster to maintain a state of liminality or interstitiality,
a certain desire not to get caught, thereby situating it in the betwixt and
between or middle ground. Its intention is always obscure, as Hansen notes,
in the sense that intentionality depends on the type of trickster, some are
more mischievous while others may be trying to help the established order
through a reciprocal playfulness. In relation to textual playfulness and
imposture, Tiffany (2013) formalizes this quality as a “Luciferian drama of
inversion . . . man becomes woman, living art becomes dead kitsch, good
becomes evil, true becomes false. And no one can tell the difference” (p. 80,
emphasis in original). This is inherently a form of anti-structure, the
creation of an antagonism within the authoritarian edifice. Communitas
often then follows as a result of the trickster’s mischief, a term along with
anti-structure that Hansen takes from Victor Turner, which is the creation of
a more unmediated, raw or egalitarian relation among the participants of the
social hierarchy.2
While I accept Hansen’s premise that posits a fruitful analogizing of
psi and the trickster, in contradistinction, however, I am proposing a more
2 My intention is not to provide an exhaustive account of the foregoing ideas but, rather,
merely to highlight them, cursorily, with the hope that the reader will delve further into the
literature.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
167
technical and theoretical conceptualization of the trickster nature of psi
thereby not necessarily aligning with the literary character of ‘trickster
theory’ per se —how it may look or appear within a situated context. As a
result, my hope is that the conceptual tools I put forth, via Lacan, will be
applicable regardless of the social, historical or even theoretical context. In
other words, it could be said that I am universalizing trickster theory using
Lacanian psychoanalysis.
To pivot to psychoanalysis as opposed to scientific models that
parapsychology has generally preferred requires some justification. Indeed,
the debate between philosophers of science and psychoanalysts reaches
back to the latter discipline’s infantile years. Charges of pseudoscience, that
the logic of psychoanalysis resembles a conspiracy theory, or that it merely
works to replicate itself, have all been levelled. Perhaps one of the best
known of these critiques, within the philosophy of science, was given by
Karl Popper. To state the idea briefly, the claim is that psychoanalysis is not
falsifiable in a strictly scientific sense. This means, for Popper, that the
principle of induction, proceeding from a state of affairs to a general law,
runs amok, so to speak, such that it would automatically fulfil all the criteria
that would make it sufficient. Grünbaum (1977) articulates this point in the
following way, “claiming that psychoanalysis has much more in common
with astrology than with the genuine sciences, Popper considers his own
criterion of demarcation to be far superior to that of inductivism” (p. 336).
This widely circulated notion that psychoanalysis is not falsifiable is
countered by Grant and Harari (2005) on both logical and empirical
grounds, through the abundance of clinical data and recent research that has
subjected analytic treatment to quantitative measures.
Furthermore, given that some of these critiques reach back before the
final formation of Lacanian theory (Lacan died in 1981) says something
about their datedness. Indeed, contextualizing French psychoanalysis with
some of its critical theory relatives, such as deconstruction, Foucauldian
genealogy and Deleuze and Guattari’s immanentism, sheds light on how
notions of ‘what counts as science’ is fundamentally problematic, how it
may contain secret assumptions or unconscious alliances. One does not
even need to go outside of the discipline of parapsychology to find a certain
affinity for tracing these historical and entrenched discursive chains of
power. Case in point, Rhea White (1994) suggested incorporating more of a
feminist approach to studying psi, which would no doubt shift the
coordinates of science for the discipline. In a similar critical spirit, Lacanian
psychoanalysis offers its unique take on scientificity and what it means to
actually study or analyze a being.
The thesis of this article is that parapsychology can be read as a
science of ‘lack’ insofar as it takes as its object of inquiry the forever
elusive being that sheds and escapes meaning in an indefinite play of
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
168
difference, that being which parapsychology calls psi. The argument is
presented through Lacanian theory that works to undergird, using Lacan’s
own concepts, how the science of parapsychology, and psi specifically,
interlink with the qualities of the trickster as outlined by Hansen (2001).
The end result, it is hoped, will add to the limited work that has been done
on a precisely theoretical psychoanalysis of parapsychology; cf. Evrard
(2014).
It should be noted that lack, here, is not employed pejoratively such
that there is something ‘deficient’ with the parapsychological discipline or
even its traditionally experimental methodology; rather, the term is taken
from Lacan himself and is used as a descriptor of the relation the subject
has, in this case parapsychology, to the object it seeks to analyze. This is an
important line of thought to pursue because, if it is the case that
parapsychology is aligned in such a way, then this could account for various
experimental and theoretical short-falls inherent within its literature and
history. For example, the discipline has focused on defining what psi is,
explicitly in terms of a preordained relation to its lack; that is to say, a
faithfulness to an ontology that premises itself on neat experimental
frameworks and the very elucidation of signification, the providing of ‘clear
meaning’ which is principally different in kind to rigor.
THE ‘HOLE IN PHYSICALIST MODELS
As a case in point, some researchers in parapsychology (e.g., Radin,
2006) believe that advances in the natural sciences—most notably, quantum
theory—offer the best hope of giving paranormal events the same reality
status as other psychological phenomena; or, in a stronger sense following
the logic of Radin, becoming a function of physics and quantum ontology
generally. That is to say, the ability of ‘how’ information can be known at a
distance via unconventionally conceived means can be explained, according
to these proponents, through concepts like quantum entanglement, non-
locality, etc. It is therefore, in this sense, that many parapsychologists,
following Radin’s lead, still pursue such a physics-based path with the hope
that an eventual experimental finding vis-à-vis quantum theory and
parapsychology in general will come to prove, scientifically, once and for
all the so-called empirical truth of psi.
Such a finding would be invaluably helpful for parapsychology, it is
claimed, partially because the discipline remains deficient with regard to
any such agreed upon guiding agenda (Felser, 2001). Quantum theory
would, therefore, not only render clear how physical processes through the
body and brain are connected, non-locally in ways that have hitherto been
viewed as paranormal, perhaps providing a coherent predictive,
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
169
explanatory, and physicalist model, but it would also help sediment
parapsychology’s ontology, thereby guiding research practices, theoretical
debates, and other disciplinary structures.
What this strain of reasoning fails to account for, however, is how
any such sedimentation can occur to begin with in that it presupposes the
very nature of meaning-making—what Lacan called, through his theory of
the signifier, signification. In this way, to adjourn to quantum theory is, in
the very gesture, to create two kinds of antagonisms. First, it further
confuses the category of parapsychology as a science: is it psychological,
physical, eclectic, etc., thereby entailing that Radin et al. are actually doing
physics? Or, put in other words, where are the disciplinary boundaries that
contour and mark out ‘parapsychology’ as a separate field of empirical
research? Incorporating the phenomenological sense by which psi displays
its trickster qualities would help ground parapsychology within its
disciplinary parameters as opposed to marking it out as a purely physicalist
science, which represents a certain impossibility and limit. In other words,
the ‘slipperiness’ of psi that the trope (or literary figure) of the trickster
signifies is the surplus by which pure experimentalism strictly cannot
signify. It is therefore not a matter of choosing between two false choices
(e.g., a physical science or social science approach), nor even trying to
synthesize the two (e.g., pluralistic qualitative and quantitative research),
but of trying to hold the aporic (dichotomous) nature of psi together.
Second, the move toward quantum theory, still remains decidedly
scientific, in the sense that it relies, at least methodologically, on notions
from legendary science such as statistical analyses, control and the
adjudication of findings against some pre-established set of practices. This
is not necessarily ‘bad’ insofar as it contributes to the growing literature
(Tressoldi, Storm & Radin, 2010) that supports “spooky” action at a
distance; what used to be considered the paranormal. It is, however,
anathema to the central premise of my argument, which understands psi
through its originary ‘trickster’ manifestations making it therefore not
amenable to such an easy kind of agreement—i.e., quantum theory as a
paragon explanatory model.
I am using the term trickster here in the sense that Hansen develops it
because his thematic analysis produces variables that, I will later claim,
parallel the process of signification. In other words, it is not the case that
‘trickster’ is used somehow to describe all of the aberrant or non-
experimentally conducive aspects of psi—the scraps leftover by the
application of physical models or experiments. On the contrary, as Lacan’s
concepts will go to show, trickster theory can be developed to cover the
entire ontology of psi, pointing out the way it behaves globally and not just
within the confines of the laboratory.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
170
An important step in achieving this is accounting for the
directionality of psi processes or how they, by their very nature, seem to be
guided either by the claimant or by some unknown force. Rhine, Pratt,
Stuart, Smith and Greenwood (1940) put the issue this way, “it has been
established that the ESP process … is, first, voluntary in its dirigibility. In
fact, if this were not the case, it is difficult to see how an experimental
demonstration of ESP would be possible at all” (p. 319, emphasis in
original). The term dirigibility is well-selected in that it keeps the teleology
of psi an open question, neither relegating it to past, present or future
determinisms. The very fact that psi is tied to a subject in some way—that it
is ‘directed’—can be explained, I will argue, through the Lacanian concept
of temporality known as après-coup (cf. the section “Extrasensory
Perception and the Après-Coup of Lalangue”). The kind of dirigibility this
requires is not so much ‘conscious’ in the sense of intentionality, since
Lacan’s temporality is structured by an afterwardness that is retrocausal but
not necessarily in a serially diachronic or future-to-present sense; but,
nevertheless, it does unequivocally arise from the subject itself.
Broadly stated now, psi rooted in the process of meaning-making or
signification, in the strictest sense, bucks any attempt to reduce it down to
the logics of the domain of the natural sciences, the psychological,
biological or physical.3 Lacan sometimes generally refers to such an
impossibility as lack or the empty ‘hole’ by which all meaning comes into
being. This can be more specifically put by appealing to precise concepts
within Lacanian theory as, for example, through lalangue,4 the pool of
signifiers held within the unconscious that gives rise to systems, processes
and practices of signification and, as alluded to earlier, Lacan’s
understanding of temporality.
3 The argument I am making is not a transcendental one in the traditional philosophical sense.
That is, Lacanian psychoanalysis and the theoretical milieu it grew out of, mid twentieth-
century French thought, take aim at precisely such universalizing gestures and discursive
postures, often seeing them imbued with unfair and unjustified power dynamics (e.g.,
phallogocentrism, heteronormativity, etc.). In fact, the turn to literary theory, genealogical
analyses and certain forms of historicism may be seen as working toward particularizing the
subject matter as opposed to describing a ‘beyond’ that somehow intercedes in the situated and
contextualized state of affairs. The history of science and metaphysical philosophy is rife with
such a beyond, and it is because of this that much of twentieth-century Continental philosophy
can be seen as a reaction to anything that lies outside of the system.
4 On a stylistic note, the technical terms Lacan developed will retain their original French
designations as opposed to trying to translate them, somewhat haphazardly and impiously, to
English. Along with consistently displaying them in italics, it is hoped this will aid the reader
in tracking their progression and use.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
171
THE ERUPTION OF LALANGUE
What is unique to any psychoanalytic intervention, or any
articulation of the discipline proper, theoretical, practical or otherwise, is
the privileged place the unconscious plays. As a result, it should be no
surprise then, when it comes to putting parapsychology on the couch, that
which remains implicit within scientific inquiry is of the most interest to the
analyst. Lacan makes this clear by using the readily accessible example of
communication; that is to say, to put in terms of general semiotics and our
earlier discussion of the theory of the signifier, the possibility of a signifier
to return to its signified. Lacan articulates this in the following way,
Communication implies reference. But one thing is clear—language is
merely what scientific discourse elaborates to account for what I call
llanguage [lalangue]. Llanguage serves purposes that are altogether
different from that of communication. That is what the experience of the
unconscious has shown us, insofar as it is made of llanguage, which, as
you know, I write with two l’s to designate what each of us deals with, our
so-called mother tongue (lalangue dite maternelle), which isn’t called that
by accident. (Lacan, 1998, p. 138, emphasis in original)
Why the emphasis on the mother tongue, Lacan non-rhetorically asks
us? In one sense, Lacan’s point is that science presupposes an incomplete,
non-rigorous or at least correspondence theory of communication, which, as
per the logics of the unconscious, holds something of a secondary character;
namely, that the ‘superficial’ character of language in the everyday sense of
the term falls within the realm of the sciences as opposed to the more
primary and underlying stratum of lalangue. This is the analogous ‘like’
structure that Lacan (1998) refers to in saying that “the unconscious is
structured like a language” (p. 48, emphasis in original). In other words,
lalangue is that which precipitates (but does not casually determine) various
meanings through the relationship the subject has to the signifier—to put it
somewhat illustratively, it is the primordial pool we are swimming around
in. Indeed, this Lacanian technical term lalangue speaks to the polysemic
(single words with multiple meanings) and homophonic (the sliding of the
sound of the signifier in relation to meaning) substrate of the unconscious
upon which ‘communication’ or the discourse of the sciences rests.
This is important for two reasons: first, lalangue creates space to
polemicize the hegemony of scientific knowledge, its essentially
epistemological character since lalangue gives rise to the latticework of
connections that frame any kind of epistemology or discourse. One way to
understand this is through Lacan’s emphasis on the literality of the idiom
lalangue dite maternelle (the language of the mother tongue). Of course, the
mother tongue refers to not only the subject’s so-called native language
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
172
handed down through early life, social and cultural development (e.g.,
English or French as a first language), but also the special connection the
child has to its real life mother and how this comes to be diagnostically
resolved or not. Lacanian theory sometimes collapses these two aspects of
language formation into the term (m)Other. In slightly more technical terms,
the (m)Other in the Lacanian clinic provides a certain mediatory bridge,
sine qua non, for the development of the divided subject; both in its Oedipal
(familial) configurations, typically, and more generally in relation to the
larger social or symbolic order into which the subject is hailed into being
through naming (Žižek, 1989). The family of origin of the analysand during
therapy and the larger social and cultural institutions necessarily determine
the development of the subject—not just one or the other.
The idea here, in relation to the sciences, is even simpler than a
clinical case: the language of the mother tongue covers over, obfuscates and
muddles the ‘purity’ of lalangue, even if this purity has a seditious and
destructive quality to its power. Lacan adjudicates this process through the
developmental trajectory of the subject such that this ‘covering over’ occurs
at the precise moment when the subject starts using language, acquiring this
ability from its social context. This is necessary in a certain sense since the
subject must come, eventually, to relate socially with other subjects,
communicate and engage in discourses of knowledge, participate in the
everydayness of the world and do other like things. Put differently, when
language is in use, there is always a split between the signifier and the
signified—the subject is estranged from its original relation to lalangue.
The parapsychological literature provides an excellent example of
this. That is, the phenomenon of xenoglossia or, more generally, glossolalia
indicate, I suggest, the ‘underlying’ (or overlaid but still typically
unconscious) stratum of lalangue. The former term, xenoglossia, is usually
taken in a stricter sense such that the speaker is allegedly able to speak in a
semantically intelligible foreign (alien) language that, at least according to
legendary empirical science, would be impossible for the speaker to have
learned. On the other hand, the latter term, glossolalia, is non-intelligible
babble (i.e., speaking in tongues, gibberish), even though the speech may
have a syntactic structure that resembles normal human languages. In an
anecdotal sense, the work of Ian Stevenson (1984) regarding reincarnation
cases and claimants of a past lives is interesting in not only stretching-out
the Lacanian Oedipal structures to reach through longer spacetimes than is
typically accepted, but also in helping to demonstrate Lacan’s concept of
lalangue. Following this logic, the split between the signifier and the
signified, I referred to earlier, would be a certain lostness in the world of
meanings going in the opposite direction of the xenoglossic, at least in
terms of the singular subject, pool of signifiers found in lalangue.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
173
In this way, such a scattering of the chaotic sliding around of
meaning and interconnectedness of lalangue with worldliness leaves the
subject alienated from its ownmost being or, in the terms of Lacanian
theory, the subject is, almost always, a divided subject. The forgoing
emphasis on alienation may be said to be a hallmark of Lacan’s
conceptualization of subjecthood and language development in the sense
that it is precisely because of this lack, the sheer fact that the subject is cut
through the incisiveness of the signifier, that paves the way for how
lalangue may become structured—i.e., the creation of special categories,5
epistemologies, discourses, etc. Since, for Lacan, the subject of analysis is
necessarily a speaking subject, predicated on its ability or failure to signify
its desire, the meaning of lalangue, then it is a matter of enticing the
subject, through various technologies of intervention, to speak as closely as
possible to the real of its territory held within lalangue. Simply,
epistemological coverings—for example, science, religion, idle talk, etc.—
inhabit the domain of this analytic work.
Second, and perhaps even more importantly, insofar as there is a
more originary substance—namely, lalangue—from which knowledge as
such is derived, analysis has as its task not the mere suturing of the subject’s
lack, its alienation of its unconscious desire, but a radical exposure to
precisely this lack—a certain reacquaintance with lalangue. This has the
benefit of opening up the field of ‘communication’ or more broadly,
intersubjectivity, to different epistemological modes of expression and
enunciation; for example, non-local, retroactive, etc. This is not to say that
Lacan, intentionally or not, envisioned the application of analytic practice to
induce such fringe, counter-hegemonic or post-epistemological means of
making sense. I am arguing that, on principle, the confrontation with the
real of the object cause of desire necessarily induces a signification that is
‘beyond’, or at least post-scientific, insofar as the unconscious does not
preclude such a reality.
Just such a point, albeit not in terms of parapsychology, is made by
Lacan, “it is in the sense that the effects of lalangue, already there qua
knowledge, go well beyond anything the being who speaks is capable of
enunciating” (Lacan, 1998, p. 139). This beyond, it would appear, is
everything such that it not only grounds the desire of the subject’s
unconscious, in an idiographic and singular way, but also forms the very
5 While not explicitly referenced in this article, it may be prescient to invoke the concept of the
master-signifier familiar to Lacanians and many readers of Lacan. In brief, the master-signifier
is the stopgap in the chain of signifiers that can only have a tautological or self-referential
meaning binding the chain it holds together to a certain empty symbol. Every subject has these,
but there exists, certainly, a difference between various master-signifiers: for example, the
fascist nationalism of national socialism or the commodity fetish of capitalism.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
174
basis by which any form of communication, scientific or otherwise, can
become articulated—when as flush with lalangue as possible, the signifier
becomes truly ‘golden’, carried over the abyss of reference by newly
formed associations streaking across the unconscious. In other words, this
represents a certain synchronistic instance, in the most austere Jungian
sense, whereby the subject and its unconscious meet-up resulting in a kind
of de-alienation, no matter however brief this may be. It may be helpful to
return to the earlier example of the xenoglossic relation the subject has to its
lalangue. Put in this way, the golden signifier I referred to earlier would be
a random syncing together of the subject with its lack that still retains
otherness—not the obliteration of the subject or its aphanisis
(disappearance), but a sublimation—engendering a ‘moment of psi’; one
that gives access to processes that usually remain hidden.
Mentioning, specifically, the emphasis Lacan places on the signifier,
it follows that knowledge practices, and legendary science by extension,
suffers by way of the agency of the signifier. Put into the concept of
lalangue I have been defining, Lacan moves ‘one step out’ explicitly calling
forth the signifier now:
That [scientific] knowledge, insofar as it resides in the shelter of llanguage,
means the unconscious … my hypothesis is that the individual who is affected
by the unconscious is the same individual who constitutes what I call the
subject of a signifier. That is what I enunciate in the minimal formulation that a
signifier represents a subject to another signifier. The signifier in itself is
nothing but what can be defined as a difference from another signifier. It is the
introduction of difference as such into the field, which allows one to extract
from llanguage the nature of the signifier (ce qu’il en est du signifiant). (Lacan,
1998, p. 142, emphasis in original)
Difference, especially in relation to the last clause of the quotation,
foregrounds, through its being marked out by the signifier, the relation
between lalangue and knowledge as such. It is, therefore, in this sense, that
the subject of science can only be defined precisely in terms through its
deferral, the very fact that the signifier represents nothing (i.e., the subject
of science) other than another signifier. This adage articulates the way in
which Lacan understands meaning creation and connection, through the
stringing together of signifiers into relational chains. It is precisely because
the signifier is a certain absence that allows for it to be filled eventually by
meaning. The creation of difference and deferral, the perpetuated filling-in
of meaning, in this way, generates other categories that we are accustomed
to seeing used in the scientific and philosophical literature—e.g., space,
time, identity, otherness, etc.
The precise point is that these categories, and others, are ancillary
insofar as they rely on an iteration, or play, on the lalangue of the
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
175
unconscious; what Lacan calls the “[extraction] from llanguage the nature
of the signifier” (1998, p. 142). This is by no means easy or even
exhaustible such that the infinite productivity of the unconscious ultimately
forecloses its own mastery, any kind of meta-language; hence the famous
Lacanian formula “there is no Other of the Other” (Lacan, 2006, p. 668)—
cf. a master narrative or, very generally, in science studies, a theory of
everything. This is perhaps why Lacan, eventually, comes to situate,
formally, the semiotic structure of science within the aptly named hysteric’s
discourse (Glynos & Stavrakakis, 2002). That is, now within relation to the
other three structures—the discourse of the university, master, and
analyst—the hysteric’s discourse incites, questions, and interrogates the
real, leading to further knowledge production, novelty, scientificity and
ultimately meaning.
To further explain this, the aim of a scientific discourse is the
suturing of the subject as opposed to exposing or forcing the subject to
confront its lack. The suturing gesture of science is inexhaustible and
infinite, which produces a teleology that is structured precisely by trying to
signify further and further meaning. Science is this way because every time
it tries to use a signifier to bridge or suture the gap between the subject and
its lack, science ‘forgets’ and carries the subject’s original lack, via the
signifier, repetitiously into the next signifier. It is in this sense that
Verhaeghe (2002) notes that “the subject of science believes that nature will
reveal to him the final meaning” (p. 137). So, when Lacan calls the
discourse of the science hysteric’, he is not trying to pathologize the
scientist but is drawing out an analogy between how the hysteric in the
clinic incessantly questions the master (e.g., psychiatrist, psychologist,
therapist, etc.) by forcing it to legitimate itself and produce meaning.
Ultimately, however, it is impossible for the master to produce the final
signifier that gives its authority or even being self-consistency, just like
nature cannot produce a final knowledge that will totally encapsulate and
enframe it. The scientist is, therefore, in the position of the hysteric relative
to the natural world—posing questions, interrogating and looking for a
signifier to suture its subject.
In contradistinction, the discourse of the analyst, and psychoanalysis
by extension, tries to do the exact opposite. That is, as opposed to the
gesture of suturing, the analyst uses various interventions, techniques and
strategies to try to first ‘hystericize’ the analysand and then to subvert the
role of the master that the analysand has then placed the analyst in—as the
sujet supposé savoir or the subject supposed to know. To put this into
broader disciplinary terms, a psychoanalytic reading of science
demonstrates how science’s discourse is by its very nature inexhaustible,
how the discipline is hysteric in relation to its object, and then how the
actual analysis ‘turns’ the discourse of the science back on itself to show
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
176
how it presupposes a certain lack. What is unique to parapsychological
science, I suggest, is that psi engages in a kind of auto-analysis of its
discipline, unlike any other scientific discourse. This auto-analysis is
demonstrated by psi’s alikeness to the trickster and as I have tried to
envision it, more technically, in relation to Lacanian theory. As such,
parapsychology is in a unique position to offer commentary on all
methodological forms—what it means to be a science—including not only
legendary empirical science but also formal qualitative measures.
We can now see how this is a very different structural relation
between the analyst and the scientist; namely, whereas science, by its
relation to knowledge, ‘forces’ the real to produce more meaning through
acts of interrogative questioning, pushing toward the suture of the real with
the symbolic, the analyst, on the other hand, stages a confrontation with the
lack of the subject. This, as we have seen, also results in a form of
knowledge production, yet one that is radically less normative, symbolically
mediated and, to put it somewhat bluntly, practical. As such, the analytic
encounter is able to crack open, and give a signifier to, the usually
concealed homogeneity of the signified, which is to say more eruditely, the
lalangue of the unconscious.
In a specific way, this would fulfill, most completely at the end of
treatment, the Lacanian ethical maxim that “the only thing one can be guilty
of is giving ground relative to one’s desire” (Lacan, 1992, p. 321). Yet,
parsed now with figures from parapsychology, it also engenders the subject
to reconnect with its web of significations, the primordiality of lalangue, in
a way that remains truer, less structured by social, scientific, religious, etc.,
knowledges, to its ontological character thereby opening up the
‘possibilities of psi’—its fluid temporal-spatial meaning. The point is that
Lacanian psychoanalysis is an anti-normative intervention that does not aim
for the subject’s functioning, adaptiveness, happiness, coherence or even
wellbeing. Extending this form of psychoanalysis into parapsychological
research, on principle, can re-subjectivize the subject onto modes of
knowing and even being that align more closely to what is normatively
called paranormal or anomalous.
In a contradistinctive sense, the so-called physicalists fail to account
for the antagonism of studying a subject that takes itself as its object, e.g.,
psychology, psychoanalysis, parapsychology or the humanities more
generally, ultimately viewing the findings of the human sciences as
supervening on a more fundamental, mathematical reality. In a counter-
critique, Lacan (2006) writes that “psychical phenomena are thus granted no
reality of their own: those that do not belong to "true" reality have only an
illusory reality. This true reality is constituted by the system of references
that are valid in already established Sciences” (p. 63). This presupposed
‘system of references’ may be likened to what I have, in clinical terms,
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
177
described as the suture of the subject from its lack. Put differently, the
human sciences are subordinate in the sense that the scientific
characteristics that mark them out, such as precision, explanation,
prediction, etc., ultimately defer themselves toward further and further
refinement; i.e., to physics. Lacan says just as much,
The role of psychology is merely to reduce psychical phenomena to this
system and to verify the system by determining through it the very
phenomena that constitute our knowledge of it. It is insofar as this
psychology is a function of this truth that it is not a science. (Lacan, 2006,
p. 63)
At this point, it is certainly old hat to call into question the
scientificity of psychology or the humanities in general. Yet, to be less
polemical and more conceptual, the point, for Lacan, is that the above logic
is misguided precisely because of the relation the sciences have to the
unconscious. Or, putting it differently, theorists in parapsychology that
partake of this exact logic are falling into a trap, leaving themselves
exposed to not only analytic interventions, but also to a kind of symbolic
obliteration of their very object of inquiry, what I have proposed in stark
theoretical terms, following Lacan, to be lalangue.
An excellent example within parapsychology, I suggest, for
illustrating a particular closeness to lalangue would be the semi-literary
character of Louisa Rhine’s extensive case study collection at the Rhine
Research Center (J. Kruth, personal communication, June 14, 2013). These
were not collected under the strictures of a formal research methodology
but, instead, were unsolicitedly delivered over to her, typically with the full
force of the subject behind the narrative—in a kind of abundant, organic
and phenomenological spirit containing all the surplus meaning that this
entails. In similar but more structured sense, as another example, the history
of parapsychology is also ripe with case studies, a form of descriptive data,
which have been used, as Alvarado (1998) has pointed out, to look at the
signification of psi in relation to individual lives.
In a more formal sense, within the qualitative framework proper,
parapsychology has slowly begun to embrace systemic approaches to the
investigation of lifeworld phenomena through the use of pre-established
qualitative methodologies. Some examples of this qualitative and systematic
scholarship include descriptive phenomenological analysis (Glazier, Beck,
& Simmonds-Moore, 2015; Heath, 2000), grounded theory (Simmonds-
Moore, Rhine-Feather, & Hamilton, 2008), and discourse analysis (Wooffitt
& Allistone, 2005). These findings go to show not only the expanded
experimental sense of psi as a legitimate being, the reality of the empiricism
of qualitative data in general, but also the breadth of meaning or territory psi
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
178
covers. The latter point is indicative of, I have suggested, the psychoanalytic
emphasis on the unconscious: more specifically, the way in which lalangue
may become dressed-up in various epistemological garments.
EXTRASENSORY PERCEPTION AND THE APRÈS-COUP OF LALANGUE
Yet, are not these very coverings necessary in order to code the
meaning the subject gives to them—the opposite of the nakedness of
lalangue? Indeed, I suggest that a specific parapsychological concept,
namely extrasensory perception (ESP), exposes a certain ‘sham(e)’ in
regard to the concept of psi in general. This is evident, in one respect, with
regard to the fact that there has been very little formal qualitative work done
on ESP as opposed to its relative psychokinesis (PK)6 (for methodological
qualitative work on PK, cf. Glazier, Beck, & Simmonds-Moore, 2015;
Heath, 2000, and on ESP cf., Matschuck, 2011 even this latter study on ESP
employs a methodology that is more idiosyncratic than the qualitative work
that is standardized within the social sciences). In a paradoxical fashion, this
is odd because it would seem that experimentalism or physicalism, of any
approach, would have trouble rendering ESP amenable to its
methodological analysis—i.e., to measurable observation; conversely, with
PK or mind-matter interaction there are clear, observable effects that can be
operationalized and subjected to scientific and statistical analysis.
The paradox of ESP is, therefore, that it contains ipso facto an
ephemeral variable that remains beyond the explicit and overt analysis
demanded by legendary empiricism. Could it be that ESP makes the
unconscious conscious, the implicit explicit, by demonstrating the difficulty
parapsychology has with its own object of study? ESP introduces, in this
way, what has historically troubled parapsychological practices into the
equation: the very fact that psi is dependent, to a degree, upon the care,
concern or meaning it has with regard to its effects. In words that Lacan
would use, giving a signifier to lalangue not only structures the unconscious
thereby allowing for the formation of meaning, but also creates a relation
(or discourse) between the signifying subject and its presupposed signified.
This, of course, does not preclude ESP from experimental
interrogation while making it more agreeable to qualitative analysis, with
6 At the time of this writing, the formal qualitative work available through various academic
databases decidedly favors the analysis of PK. I am counting established and systematized
methods that have been deployed in other disciplines besides parapsychology. These include
descriptive phenomenological analysis, grounded theory and discourse analysis. I am not
considering, however, less systemized and more anecdotal accounts such as personal
narratives, letters or interviews.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
179
the former needing to appropriate signification in terms closer to
mathematics and the latter being able to explore, perhaps more
metaphorically, the process of meaning-making. This is just to say that ESP
seems, prima facie, amenable to qualitative measures in that it presupposes,
at least to a more explicit degree, a subject of signification.
My point is to highlight the antagonism inherent within the trajectory
of parapsychology’s philosophy of science, which has caused it to overlook
one of its own concepts, i.e., ESP, that may help make it more adaptable to
psychoanalytic inquiry; and, even perhaps, given the growth of qualitative
measures in recent years within the American Psychological Association
(Lyons, 2009), provide it more legitimacy in the eyes of the mainstream
scientific community. It is as if, as Braude (1986) points out,
parapsychology research has proceeded along two distinct paths, which, in a
sense, have remained parallel to each other, without any kind of adequate
meeting or convergence.
Precisely here, within this break, I want to introduce the Lacanian
theoretical concept of après-coup, sometimes translated as deferred-action
or retroaction, but more literally meaning afterwardness. Lacan explains this
concept in the following way,
The retroactive effect of meaning in sentences, meaning requiring the last
word of a sentence to be sealed [se boucler]. Nachträglichkeit (remember
that I was the first to extract it from Freud’s texts) or deferred action [après-
coup], by which trauma becomes involved in symptoms, reveals a temporal
structure of a higher order. (Lacan, 2006, p. 711, emphasis in original)
To interpret Lacan, this ‘temporal structure of a higher order’ that he
spoke about above acts as a quasi-mechanism in assuring the consistency
and flow of temporal possibilities. For example, when I think about what I
want to do next, when I develop an intention, I am first swimming in the
pool of signifiers held by lalangue where all possibilities for my next move
exist. However, it is only when I actually select a signifier, when my next
possibility becomes an actuality, that I engage in temporality. The move
from possibility to actuality is always, according to Lacan, a matter of
retroaction or afterwardness since I have to apply the signifier to my action
after it has already passed and since my ‘original’ experience is swimming
around in the chaotic meaning pool of lalangue.
Lacan meant this in a diachronic sense, which means that après-coup
may intercede either from the future or the past. At the same time, the
trauma, or more abstractly, the lack of the subject, refers to the ontological
void in the present that permits the après-coup to take place at all—put into
terms discussed earlier, the lack of the subject is precisely its participation
in temporality, which shows how it is already ahead of itself, so to speak.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
180
This demonstrates, synchronically, to the subject its own cut or emptiness—
the very place that allows for the generation of acts of sublimation,
creativity and signification. The après-coup in this way is the ‘blank’ time
the subject takes to apply meaning to its experience or produce new forms
of knowledge. In the strictest possible sense, the afterwardness of
temporality can never formally coincide with the subject that experiences it
since such a reunion would mark the end of its existence—i.e., another
name for this is death. This is why we have the experience of temporality,
according to Lacan; precisely because such an alignment can only occur
secondarily through the signifier.
The second point, what Lacan calls clinical trauma, or, for the
purposes of this article, the general lack intrinsic to scientific
epistemologies, is articulated by Ruti (2012) in the following way, “it is
because the subject cannot fill its inner void, undo its alienation, in any
definitive manner that it persists as a creature of continued creative
capacity” (p. 128). The issue at stake for the sciences is that this is always
an a priori with respect to any signifying process; that is, on a
psychoanalytic account, the very formation of subjecthood belies such a
kernel of emptiness, a subject of lack, in order to produce something
substantive and meaningful at all. Again, returning to the notion of deferral
or the blank time of après-coup, this gives the subject space, so to speak, in
order to bring into being certain signifiers as opposed to others. Hence, the
notion of science for Lacanian theory is strictly relative insofar as it is one
discursive practice among others, albeit one with a lot of social, financial
and technological power.
Returning to the first point and, specifically, its applicability to
parapsychology, the après-coup of the subject, the afterwardness of
meaning, offers a theoretical device for the phenomenon of ESP,
specifically with regard to its retroactive effects and the parallel this has to
certain ESP research. Stated plainly, since ESP generally deals with the
acquisition of anomalous meaning and Lacanian psychoanalysis provides
structures in which to understand how meaning is generated from the
unconscious, then it follows that Lacan’s theory of the signifier may apply
to the anomalous production of meaning categorized by ESP. In this way,
the afterwardness of meaning explains how a space can be generated—the
wait the subject has between retroactively selecting signifiers (the
experience of temporarily, in general)—that allows for the intrusion of non-
normative or paranormally retrieved signifiers, which is what happens with
ESP. The point is that this possibility is not foreclosed, according to Lacan,
as it may be with other theories that rely on more normative structures or
‘scientific’ metaphors. In fact, it may even be that, given the staunchly anti-
normative nature of Lacanian theory, such paranormal ways of making
meaning are more originary insofar as they challenge everyday notions of
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
181
experience and get the subject back to the interconnectedness of the
signifiers called lalangue.
In other words, when the subject comes to know itself in relation to
the world, or its discursive positioning, it retroactively ‘steals’ signifiers,
carrying information, data, affects, etc., from the ‘temporal structure of a
higher order’ (après-coup) which is to say the space it has marked out in the
unconscious, its singular appropriation of lalangue. The subject may be
either an individual subjectivity or a bundle of practices and knowledges
found in various scientific disciplines. To suggest a methodological protocol
for researchers given the forgoing analysis, perhaps the incorporation of the
burgeoning field of Lacanian Discourse Analysis (Parker, 2005) might aid
in demonstrating this theoretical work in the laboratory or during
methodological inquiry. To offer a more precise tip, the experience of a
subject or individual, when under study, should be kept as pristine as
possible and the researcher must be sure not to add any signifiers to the
subject’s experience. This would be keeping in line with the previous
discussion of Lacan’s four-discourse schema thereby shifting the scientist
away from the hysteric’s discourse and more towards the discourse of the
analyst.
Returning to the theoretical analysis of temporality, it is no surprise
to parapsychologists in the field that retroactive effects, in regard to ESP,
have been demonstrated experimentally, perhaps most notably by Bem
(2011). Bem’s study undertook nine experiments with over 1000
participants that time-reversed traditional psychological experiments such
that the participants’ data were collected prior to the introduction of the
causal stimulus. Across all nine experiments, Bem found statistically
significant results for this retroactive influence. As if to buttress the
malleability of the Lacanian signifier, it is not the case that retroactivity is
exclusively cognitive; as Bem (2011) argues, it doesn’t matter “whether
those responses are conscious or nonconscious, cognitive or affective” (p.
408) just so long as they are meaningful.
The findings of Bem’s paper, however, have come under scrutiny
and even rejection from his colleagues in the psychological and
parapsychological community. Most notably, Alcock (2011) claims that the
Bem study contained lax experimental methodology and, as a result,
concludes the results to be dubious at best. Furthermore, Ritchie, Wiseman,
and French (2012) attempted to replicate three of Bem’s original nine
experiments and discovered no statistical significance in their findings and,
as a result, the researcher’s concluded that they did not find evidence for
psychic abilities or ESP.
If we leave the experimentalists to debate methodological polemics,
then what is so enthralling about the findings of Bem is that they seem to
bring into view a long-standing issue within the parapsychological
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
182
literature: the need for a theoretical structure to elucidate how such
retroaction occurs. As a helpful interlocutor to further illustrate this,
VanOver also relates just such a matter, in a note by Jung:
How could an event remote in space and time produce a corresponding
psychic image when the transmission of energy necessary for this is not even
thinkable? However incomprehensible it may appear, we are finally
compelled to assume that there is in the unconscious something like an a
priori knowledge or an “immediacy” of events which lacks any casual basis.
(Jung, 2014, p. 3403; cited in VanOver, 1972, p. xxv, emphasis in original)
In the above quotation, the a priori knowledge of the unconscious
goes to show the mechanism of après-coup that delivers over its retroactive
discursive placement. In the sense of temporality taken from Lacan, this a
priori knowledge is not knowledge in the substantive or formative sense
such that it contains ‘positive’ meaning. Rather, it is the negativity of
afterwardness that creates a ‘blank’ space into which anything like an
immediacy of events, a synchronistic sense of meaning, can take place in
the first place—it is the funneling of the pool of signifiers found in lalangue
into the signifying chain created by the subject. Taking this away from the
clinic and applying it to science studies, the degree of the subject’s
particularity, that is to say, using the two key examples from this article,
either subjectivity or the psychoanalysis of parapsychology, is
fundamentally irrelevant because the same temporal structure is presumed
by any being with an unconscious. To put this into stricter Lacanian terms,
the symbolic order, or the social-historical culture that divides the subject
through the incision of the signifier, also has as its temporality the very
same mode of retroaction.
As though to accord with Lacan on this point, Nelson and Bancel
(2006) conducted an eight-year study of archive data from random number
generators (RNG) and looked at the data from around the time of large scale
disasters and events such as earthquakes. The analysis revealed statistical
significance in regard to a shift toward orderliness in the RNG necessarily
prior to the actual event occurrence. The researchers concluded that this was
evidence of not only a form of ESP, but also a kind of retroaction or
retrocausation.
What is so interesting with regard to the work of Nelson and Bancel
(2006) is that their findings seem to be hinting at the existence of a large
scale ‘structure’ that interlinks the thought patterns, emotions and
embodiments on a planetary level—what has been called, most consistently
within the literature, a global consciousness. The main finding of the Global
Consciousness Project (GCP) is the correlation between the meaningfulness
of the disaster or event and the degree of orderliness in the RNGs (Nelson &
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
183
Bancel, 2006). What this suggests is that the generation of signification as
such is structurally primary in any discussion of ESP insofar as it seems the
researchers are lending support for this; retroaction occurs necessarily in
relation to that which is most communally meaningful.
From the perspective of Lacanian theory, this is called the symbolic
order, the symbio-historical field of meaning, allowing for the transmission
of knowledges, relationality and historicity and also arbitrating the
formation of societal institutions such as the law, government, and other
juridical functions of the state (Žižek, 1989). Such a stance is decidedly
non-anthropocentric insofar as meaning is not the sole domain of the human
species. In other words, this is not to suggest some kind of naïve animism or
panpsychism whereby even the inorganic or machinic ‘contributes’ meaning
in some way. Rather, the Lacanian point is one of structure and relation
such that meaning is created precisely in this in-between space; almost
similar to Hansen’s notion of interstitiality.
Furthermore, with regard to the production of subjectivity, it is
precisely the signifiers that are most desirous to the subject, having the
greatest bearing on its being, therein coming to mean the most, which puts
into play the higher order temporality of après-coup. It is in this way,
therefore, that when a natural disaster interferes with human daily life (e.g.,
seeing pictures on the news, feeling sorry for the victims, etc.) then meaning
is going to be given over to the symbolic order most retroactively. While
not getting into the particulars of his theory or findings, Ed May (cf.
Decision Augmentation Theory; May, Utts, & Spottiswoode, 1995)
similarly places an emphasis on the retroactive nature of psi, even going so
far as to suggest that PK can be explained in such a way.
As an interesting case in point to DAT theory, one of the researchers
from the original GCP just mentioned (namely, Bancel) has changed his
position. He now suggests that the data collected supports the notion of a
goal-oriented (GO) mechanism that better explains the fluctuations during
world events. He writes that “while there may be something like GC [global
consciousness] somewhere, there is no evidence for it in GCP data. But
there is good evidence for GO [goal-oriented psi]” (Bancel, n.d., p. 1). Such
a conclusion does not, however, settle the debate since, as Kennedy (2001)
says, “shifting goal-oriented psi may possibly contribute to decline effects
for certain experimenters, but this hypothesis does not appear to be the
major cause of elusive psi” (p. 229). Sticking to the parallelism with DAT
theory hinted at earlier, the pressure that Lacanian theory places on this
problematic is through the very retroactive nature of meaning, its après-
coup, which I have argued helps explain why psi seems so elusive to the
researchers in parapsychology.
Parsing this now as succinctly as possible, I suggest that such
retroactive effects are the sine qua non of what constitutes ESP as
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
184
structurally ‘psychoanalytic’ in the first place, as demonstrating the lack not
only at the centre of identity, but also at the very philosophy of science of
parapsychology.
THE SOURCE OF PSI, OR WHOS DOING THAT?
The shift in Bancel’s premise, from a global consciousness (GC) to
goal-oriented psi (GO), opens up a larger and unsettling topic within the
parapsychological literature in that the source of psi can never, it seems, be
etiologically mapped out. Consequently, researchers question if it is even
possible methodologically to control for this problematic in experiments. As
a case in point, Beischel (2012) phrases the issue in the following terms,
Given the non-local, non-temporal nature of psi, it remains difficult to truly
disentangle the experimenter from the experiment even if the same studies
are conducted by different experimenters or by disinterested researchers. It
seems that no experimental protocol will be able to discern between these
possibilities. (p. 10)
This sentiment is well taken in that, certainly from a purely
physicalist or experimentalist model, the disentanglement that Beischel
alludes to can never be resolved precisely because such an account
presupposes how it becomes meaningful in the first place.
To state openly that belief, in some way, determines the presence of
psi is not saying anything new. Indeed, this phenomenon is known as the
sheep-goat effect in ESP research (Brugger, Landis, & Regard, 1990). The
sheep-goat effect holds that individuals who express a reasonably strong
belief in the existence of psi tend to reliably produce above-chance results
on psi tests. The exact opposite holds true for ‘goats’—namely, those
subjects that are skeptical of psi tend to actually induce psi missing, or psi
below chance, which is still indicative of something anomalous going on
insofar as experimental results should not be predicated on belief,
experimenter or participant, of any kind.
The above line of questioning, however, misses the point by trying to
ascertain a ‘positiveetiological source for psi; in strictly psychoanalytic
terms, a phantasy structure—what I have referred to earlier as the
epistemological ‘garments’ veiling the primordial lack or cut of the subject.
It is, therefore, not the so-called ‘source of psi’ that is the problem; but,
rather, the very fact that researchers have failed to push this phenomenon,
unique to parapsychological science, to its paroxysm. That is, for
researchers to take serious a Lacanian reading of psi would mean,
simultaneously, to avow psi’s radical negativity—how its ‘meaning’
naturally slides around, as we have seen through lalangue, escaping any
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
185
kind of static and totalizing interpretation that would halt this very sliding.
It does this whether we want it to our not, whether we apply quantitative or
qualitative measures to it.
Hansen (2001) points to the trickster as helping to illustrate such a
point. In slight contrast, as I will argue in the following section, pushing the
source of psi to its most extreme conclusion results in the incarnation of the
Lacanian objet petit a, which “designates nothing but the absence, the lack
of the object, the void around which desire turns” (Zupančič, 2000, p. 18).
The interface between Hansen’s more literary theory and Lacan’s abstract
structures helps demonstrate how psi can now be understood as the objet
petit a of parapsychology—its little object of desire.
OBJET PETIT A AS ABSTRACTION OF THE TRICKSTER
Specifically in relation to Lacanian theory, I have attempted to
thematize the technical concept of lalangue within the rubric of
parapsychology; that is to say, the failure or ‘lack’ of its scientific practices
results precisely in not taking seriously the unconscious of the subject, or
what it means to speak. As a consequence, I have suggested, the singular
and free-roaming meaning tentacles of lalangue become encased within
certain pre-determined parameters of symbolic meaning—i.e., a system of
references that are valid. Moving, now, toward a more specific theorization
within this exact same logic, I suggest that there exists a homology between
what Lacan calls the objet petit a and parapsychology’s object of study, psi.
In the following quotation, Lacan articulates a general sense by
which the axiom, a signifier represents a subject to another signifier,
operates by way of not only the self-analyzing subject within the human
sciences, but also encompasses the whole realm of the production of
epistemologies as such.
Let me reiterate that there is something in the status of science’s object that
seems to me to have remained unelucidated since the birth of science . . . the
question probably cannot be answered without the object’s status in science
as such being thereby modified. The object of psychoanalysis [and the
psychoanalysis of science] . . . is no other than what I have already proposed
about the function played in analysis by object a [objet petit a]. (Lacan,
2006, p. 733)
Let me, first, speak to my specificity assertion earlier; namely, that
what Lacan calls objet petit a has more ‘precision’ than the broad
thematization of lalangue. One way to say this is that objet petit a is the
asignificant manifestation of the unconscious of the speaking subject such
that it ‘holds the place for’ the sliding of signifiers across the surface of
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
186
lalangue. Or, as Zupančič (2000) says “the objet petit a can be understood
as a void that has acquired a form” (p. 18, emphasis in original). In this
way, objet petit a is the very remainder of the signifier as such: the
emptiness at the heart of the subject but which is still perceptible. In other
words, it is not pure negativity because its form still shows up in the
semantic field. Applying this to the study of science, the objet petit a can be
said to simultaneously mark out a regional ontology, the beings that the
science purports to study, while generating meaning that such a contouring
brings about. Put in more simple terms, if the study of parapsychology is the
study of psi, then psi is the objet petit a of its scientificity.
Claims, here, of over-simplification are warranted on the grounds of,
say, not vertically making distinctions among its particulars—
“parapsychology does not just study psi.” This seems clear and is not just a
problem of semantics, which is precisely why Lacanian theory is so helpful
here. Objet petit a shows up contextually as a difference, as Lacan (2006)
told us earlier, whereby “the object’s status in sciences as such being
thereby modified” (p. 733). So, it is not so much psi as such that is
problematic but the very nature of a psychoanalysis of parapsychology,
which precipitates the objet petit a from the ‘unconscious’ taken for granted
by parapsychology, its lack or non-fidelity to lalangue.
Lacan (2006) head nods to just such a suggestion when insinuating,
“one senses that this is a tortuously circuitous process akin to taming.
Object a is not peaceful, or rather one should say, could it be that it does not
leave you in peace?” (p. 733). It would appear that, given the unruly and
somewhat jarring sense by which a subject is forced to position itself in
relation to an objet petit a, as Lacan equates to taming, then its very
investigatory processes not only ought to respect this fact, take into account
its disruptiveness, but also self-reflect on its more general status as a subject
of lack. In other words, a precisely analytic confrontation with an objet petit
a has the power to reconfigure the entire approach, both through
knowledges and values, by which it considers itself a subject.
Given, now, that for Lacanian theory, the object of study for
parapsychology, what has traditionally in the literature been referred to as
psi, is equivalent to the objet petit a of psychoanalysis, then it begs the
question of what kind of investigatory strategies, whether methodological,
metaphoric, institutional, etc., can best elicit a ‘favorable’ response from the
objet petit a—a response that generates, of course, what the
experimentalists call reliable or valid results. This is difficult, if the history
of parapsychology is any indication, but does not preclude, in a strict
philosophical sense, the conceptualization of psi.
In this way, to give objet petit a, within the strict limits of
parapsychology, a literary spin, what better rebellious and unruly character
than what Hansen (2001) suggests by the trickster? Indeed, to say this in
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
187
Lacanian terms: psi is a necessary remainder of the process of signification
that is retroactively posited yet internal to the field of meaning as a
placeholder for the real, the objet petit a of parapsychology’s stakes within
lalangue. Flavored by some of the motifs that Hansen presents to us from
trickster stories and their relation to the paranormal, psi invoked as the
trickster inverts binary oppositions allowing for a certain devotion to a state
of liminality. Such qualities imbue the trickster, and psi on this account,
with the position of anti-structure.
As Hansen (2001) says in his own words, “the term anti-structure has
distinct advantages. It evokes the idea of disruption, of the border between
chaos and order [emphasis added], of being anti-establishment, as well as
suggesting a connection with French structuralism and deconstructionism”
(p. 59). It is precisely this ‘border between chaos and order’ that I was
developing earlier in regard to the place carved out in lalangue by the
politics of parapsychology’s scientific practice—put very simply, how does
the discipline make meaning? The ‘how’ can be answered by referring to its
object of analysis, psi, and the effects that it evokes; what Hansen has
proffered in more literary and archetypal terms as the trickster and what I
have suggested in more abstract and theoretical terms as the objet petit a.
I have submitted Lacanian theory as a more abstract, as opposed to
literary, explication of trickster theory. In turn, it follows that some of the
concepts that have been developed may be able to cover a larger domain of
psi research allowing for linkages between various formal methodologies—
e.g., experimental, qualitative, anecdotal, etc. Again, the point is not the
privileging of one method over another but of trying to ‘traverse’ the
different approaches in order to create something new. Such a reading
brings parapsychology closer to the genre of psychoanalysis as opposed to
the mathematical rubric of the so-called hard sciences. It follows that the
hard sciences are not really ‘hard’ at all, on a Lacanian account, since if psi
ontologically comprises a specific kind of lack, then by relegating it to
physicalism, the hole they wish to plug has already been filled with the anti-
signifiers of lalangue, making the failings of privileging a methodological
protocol over another all the more perilous.
IN THE FUTURE
The forgoing analysis worked to develop a theoretically grounded
Lacanian reading of parapsychology and its scientificity that created, in
turn, an additional intervention via the very object of parapsychological
study, psi, challenging the hegemony of physicalism and, by extension, the
privileging of legendary experimentalism. This was initiated by a ‘return to
the unconscious’ of parapsychology and, in particular, the hypostatized
meaning the discipline filters out of Lacan’s concept of lalangue. The use of
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
188
certain ESP research to demonstrate the strategy of après-coup helped to
show how the temporality of meaning may allow for ‘anomalous’ signifiers
to be selected as opposed to those that are more normatively circulated.
Finally, it follows that, given the uncanny correspondences between the
trickster nature of psi phenomena and the objet petit a of the Lacanian
clinic, it may be that psi as such is actually ‘analyzing’ the very discipline
that seeks to study it—playfully eluding, frustrating and even deceiving the
practitioners of parapsychology.
To continue to pursue this line of reasoning, I suggest the
incorporation of other Lacanian concepts vis-à-vis parapsychology or,
perhaps more accurately at this point, the broad study of psi in general—
what has fashionably been referred to as exceptional experiences,
exceptional psychology or anomalous psychology. Just one such concept,
the jouissance7 of the body, may aid in theorizing the relationship between
the production of meaning and the historically and developmentally
determined embodiment of the claimant thereby informing formal
methodological or experimental research. That is, to gloss this briefly, the
agitation (jouissance) of the body through its reaction to the signifier
unlocks, psychoanalytically, non-normative modes of signifying the
unconscious, bringing the subject closer to the truth of its desire. Or, as Ruti
(2012) puts it, “bodily jouissance [is] inherently unrepresentable through
language; jouissance [is] the basic stumbling block of signification, the
riddle in the face of which the signifier falter[s]” (p. 119). On account of the
preceding analysis, using Lacan’s diagnostic schema could help inform psi
researchers by providing a map of the ideographic relationships the
claimants have to their desire and jouissance: typically, these structures are
neurosis, perversion and psychosis. These are not pathological labels but
ways in which subjects, in the laboratory or elsewhere, could be
categorized. This would help researchers understand how psi may function
differently for each of these subjectivities—for example, the pervert’s
jouissance is much less structured by the slippage from signifier to signifier,
the desire for more knowledge, and more by its instrumental position,
7 Lacan’s concept of jouissance is central to understanding how the signifier is tied to or
relates with the body. The majority of Lacanians leave the term untranslated since its precise
meaning depends upon the theoretical context in which it is employed. For my purposes,
jouissance may be rendered as surplus or agitated pleasure. More generally, however, as Bailly
(2009) points out, the “most commonplace meaning has the sexual connotation of ‘orgasm’ . . .
jouissance is also a legal term denoting the right of someone to enjoy the legitimate use of a
property” (p. 118). My motivation for invoking this term in the “In The Future” section has to
do with its elaborate relationship to the body requiring additional work by researchers to situate
how different drive-desire forms of particular or individual claimants, the way they carry their
jouissance, may reveal affinities for psi-like abilities.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
189
becoming an object for the signifier. Understanding these differences may
help reveal ways of coming to knowledge that are decidedly counter-
hegemonic and, what may be more apropos to psi phenomena, that are
fringe, exceptional or anomalous.
To be even more precise, on the level of the body, the way in which
the drive (trieb) is converted into the desire of the signifier, its
alchemicalization, could illustrate how the scientific practice of
parapsychology, or the idiographic productions of subjectivity, correspond
or not to the “pulse of the bodily real” (Ruti, 2012, p. 18)—the Lacanian
ethical injunction that the only thing one can be guilty of is giving ground
relative to one’s desire. Perhaps such a liberation of desire from its normal
place within various kinds of policing frameworks, which work to foreclose
or suture the open-endedness of meaning inherent to the polyvalence of
lalangue, could produce effects that are considered more paranormal. This
would have the benefit of exposing ‘the containment of psi’—that is to say
the normative structures that have kept these modes of meaning at bay—
while, simultaneously, unleashing this fixity held within the body of the
subject. Consequently, developing a proper parapsychological theory of the
relationship between drive and desire, in the psychoanalytic sense, would
take into account embodiment itself thereby helping laboratory or
qualitative researchers better contextualize the subject in front of them.
In the final analysis, then, perhaps it really is psi as such that should
take the lead in teaching us about the nature of paranormal experiences and
scientific methodologies in general. By resisting the urge to contain neatly
the wily filiation psi has to meaning, something profoundly unexpected has
the potential to arise therein recursively informing the technologies of
research, writing or speaking that we bring to bear upon it—thus, the
property of auto-analysis unique to psi and parapsychological inquiry. As
Lacan (1998) intimated to us at the onset, such a fidelity to the fecundity of
psi allows for the repetitious purification of the signifier, in this case the
magician, to perform his trick “in still purer form” (p. 36). By following
suit, we may not be able to uncover the magician’s illusion or subvert the
trickster’s ploy, but we can learn from the reciprocal logic they employ—to
develop a strategy, theory or practice that must be just as cunning, if not
more, than the one used to dupe.
THE AUTHOR
Jacob W. Glazier, PhD ABD is pursuing a degree in Psychology in
Consciousness and Society at the University of West Georgia. Dr. Glazier’s
research tends towards a transdisciplinary approach via theoretical and
philosophical models and includes subjects like critical theory, embodiment,
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
190
and desire as well as their relation to praxis and clinical practice. He is
working on his dissertation, which deploys Lacanian psychoanalysis and
schizoanalysis.
REFERENCES
Alcock, J. E. (1981). Parapsychology, science or magic?: a psychological
perspective. Oxford: Pergamon Press.
Alcock, J. E. (2011). Back from the future: Parapsychology and the Bem
affair. Skeptical Inquirer, 35(2), 31-39.
Alvarado, C. S. (1998). ESP and altered states of consciousness: An
overview of conceptual and research trends. The Journal of
Parapsychology, 62(1), 27-63.
Bailly, L. (2009). Lacan: A beginner’s guide. Oxford, England: Oneworld
Publications.
Beischel, J. (2012). A quarter century of applied research. Journal of
Parapsychology, 76(supplement), 9-10.
Bancel, P. (n.d.). Determining that the GCP is a goal-oriented effect: A
short history. Unpublished manuscript.
Bem, D. J. (2011). Feeling the future: Experimental evidence for anomalous
retroactive influences on cognition and affect. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 100, 407-425.
Braude, S. E. (1986). The limits of influence: Psychokinesis and the
philosophy of science. New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul Inc.
Brugger, P., Landis, T., & Regard, M. (1990). A ‘sheep-goat effect’ in
repetition avoidance: Extra-sensory perception as an effect of
subjective probability? British Journal of Psychology, 81(4), 455-468.
Evrard, R. (2014). Heterodoxies’ merging: Lacanian approaches to
exceptional experiences. Journal of Exceptional Experiences and
Psychology, 2(1), 5-13.
Felser, J. M. (2001). Philosophical sensitives and sensitive philosophers:
Gazing into the future of parapsychology. International Journal of
Parapsychology, 12(1), 53-82.
Glazier, J. W. (2014). A phenomenological evolution of parapsychology’s
philosophy of science. Paranthropology: Journal of Anthropological
Approaches to the Paranormal, 5(1), 32-43.
Glazier, J. W., Beck, T., & Simmonds-Moore, C. (2015). A
phenomenological analysis of the relationship between grief, emotional
stress and anomalous experiences. Mortality, 20(3), 248-262.
Glynos, J. & Stavrakakis, Y. (Eds.). (2002). Lacan & science. New York:
Karnac Books, Other Press LLC.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
191
Grant, D. C. & Harari, E. (2005). Psychoanalysis, science and the seductive
theory of Karl Popper. Australian and the New Zealand Journal of
Psychiatry, 39, 446-452.
Grünbaum, A. (1977). Is psychoanalysis a pseudo-science? Karl Popper and
Sigmund Freud. Zeitschrift r philosophische Forschung, 31(3), 333-
353.
Hansen, G. P. (2001). The trickster and the paranormal. United States of
America: Xlibris Corporation.
Hansen, G. P. (2016). The paranormal, the trickster, and structuralist
concepts. In R. Nelson (Chair), Accessing the exceptional, experiencing
the extraordinary. Convention conducted at the first combined
convention of the Parapsychological Association (59th) and the Society
for Scientific Exploration (35th), Boulder, Colorado, USA.
Heath, P.R. (2000). The PK zone: A phenomenological study. The Journal
of Parapsychology, 64, 53-72.
Jung, C. G. (2014). C. G. Jung: The collected works. Volume I-XX (H.
Read, Ed.). New York: Routledge.
Kennedy, J. E. (2001). Why is psi so elusive? A review and proposed
model. The Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 219-246.
Kennedy, J. E. (2016). Coming to terms with the trickster. In R. Nelson
(Chair), Accessing the exceptional, experiencing the extraordinary.
Convention conducted at the first combined convention of the
parapsychological association (59th) and the society for scientific
exploration (35th), Boulder, Colorado, USA.
Lacan, J. (1988). Seminar on “The Purloined Letter”. In J. P. Muller & W.
J. Richardson (Eds.), J. Mehlman (Trans.), The purloined Poe: Lacan,
Derrida & psychoanalytic reading (pp. 28-54). Baltimore, MD: The
John Hopkins University Press.
Lacan, J. (1992). The ethics of psychoanalysis, 1959-1960. The seminar of
Jacques Lacan, Book VII (D. Porter, Trans. & J.-A. Miller, Ed.). New
York: W. W. Norton & Company, Inc.
Lacan, J. (1998). On feminine sexuality, the limits of love and knowledge,
1972-1973. Encore, the seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book XX (B. Fink,
Trans & J.-A. Miller, Ed.). New York: W. W. Norton.
Lacan, J. (2006). Écrits: The first complete edition in English (B. Fink,
Trans.). New York: W. W. Norton.
Lyons, A. (2009). Is the American Psychological Association ready to
accept a division for qualitative inquiry? The Humanistic Psychologist,
37(1), 101-107.
Matschuck, A. (2011). Non-local correlations in therapeutic settings? A
qualitative study on the basis of weak quantum theory and the model of
pragmatic information. Axiomathes: An International Journal in
Ontology & Cognitive Systems, 21(2), 249-261.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
192
May, E. C., Utts, J. M, & Spottiswoode, S. J. P. (1995). Decision
augmentation theory: Toward a model of anomalous mental
phenomena. The Journal of Parapsychology, 59, 195-220.
Nelson, R. D. & Bancel, P. A. (2006). Anomalous anticipatory responses in
networked random data. In D. P. Sheehan (Ed.), Frontiers of time:
Retrocausation experiment and theory (pp. 260-272). American
Institute of Physics Conference Proceedings #863 for the 87th Meeting
of the AAAS Pacific Division, Melville, NY: American Institute of
Physics.
Parker, I. (2005). Lacanian discourse analysis in psychology: Seven
theoretical elements. Theory & Psychology, 15(2), 163-182.
Radin, D. (2006). Entangled minds: Extrasensory experiences in a quantum
reality. New York: Paraview Pocket Books.
Rhine, J. B., Pratt, J. G., Stuart, C. E., Smith, B. M., & Greenwood, J. A.
(1940). Extra-sensory perception after sixty years. New York: Henry
Holt and Company.
Ritchie, S. J., Wiseman, R., & French, C. C. (2012). Failing the future:
Three unsuccessful attempts to replicate Bem’s ‘retroactive facilitation
of recall’ effect. PLoS ONE, 7(3), 1-5.
Ruti, M. (2012) The singularity of being: Lacan and the immortal within.
New York: Fordham University Press.
Saussure, F. (1959). Course in general linguistics (C. Bally & Sechehaye,
A., Eds. & W. Baskin, Trans.). New York: The Philosophical Library,
Inc.
Simmonds-Moore, C., Rhine-Feather, S., & Hamilton, J. (2008). A
qualitative exploration of spontaneous psychokinetic phenomena. In S.
Sherwood & B. Carr (Eds.), The Parapsychological Association, Inc.
51st Annual Convention & The Incorporated Society for Psychical
Research 32nd Annual Convention: Proceedings of presented papers
(pp. 360-363). Winchester, England: The Parapsychological
Association and The Society for Psychical Research.
Stevenson, I. (1984). Unlearned language: New studies in xenoglossy.
Charlottesville, VA: University Press of Virginia.
Tiffany, D. (2013). In the poisonous candy factory. London: Capsule
Editions.
Tressoldi, P. E., Storm, L., & Radin, D. (2010). Extrasensory perception
and quantum models of cognition. NeuroQuantology, 8(4), 581-587.
VanOver, R. (1972). Introduction. In R. VanOver (Ed.), Psychology and
extrasensory perception (pp. viii-xxxii). New York: The New
American Library, Inc.
Verhaeghe, P. (2002). Causality in science and psychoanalysis. In J. Glynos
& Y. Stavrakakis (Eds.), Lacan & science (pp. 119-146). New York:
Karnac Books, Other Press LLC.
Australian Journal of Parapsychology
193
White, R. A. (1994). The need for double vision in parapsychology: The
feminist standpoint. In L. Coly & R. A. White (Eds.), Women and
parapsychology (pp. 241-252). New York: Parapsychology Foundation.
Wooffitt, R. & Allistone, S. (2005). Towards a discursive parapsychology:
Language and the laboratory study of anomalous communication.
Theory Psychology, 15(3), 325-355.
Žižek, S. (1989). The sublime object of ideology. London: Verso.
Zupančič, A. (2000). Ethics of the real: Kant, Lacan. London: Verso.
Department of Psychology
University of West Georgia
1601 Maple Street
Carrollton, GA 30118
USA
Email: jacob.w.glazier@gmail.com
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Article
Full-text available
I've worked on the Global Consciousness Project since 2001. After years of analysis, I have concluded that the GCP effect is a goal-oriented experimenter effect, and that it does not provide evidence of the hypothesized Global Consciousness. Since there was some discussion (apparently) at the recent Convention of the Parapsychological Association, I thought I'd write a summary to explain how I've come to my conclusions, and why, after looking at both sides, this is the only view consistent with the data.
Article
This article is a review of conceptual and research trends regarding the relationship between altered states of consciousness and ESP, and its connection to cultural developments from the middle of the 1800s to the 1990s, with an emphasis on the twentieth century. It is argued that interest in these topics has been shaped in part by their social context, such as the movements of mesmerism, spiritualism and dynamic psychiatry during the nineteenth century. Similarly, in later periods, developments in the relationship between altered states of consciousness and ESP were affected by popular culture's interest in the exploration of consciousness and was shared, to some extent, by psychology, as seen in studies of hypnosis, dreams, the psychedelic state, and other topics. During the modern periods, researchers have conducted systematic research on the subject more than ever before, as is dear from dream, hypnosis, relaxation, and ganzfeld studies. Although it is sometimes assumed that techniques such as the ganzfeld induce alterations of consciousness that affect ESP performance, it is argued that this is not necessarily the case, and that recent research has abandoned the exploration of the interaction between altered states and ESP. The current trend is towards the exploration of multivariate factors affecting ESP performance in the ganzfeld, and this emphasis neglects the study of altered states per se.
Article
There has been a recent increase in qualitative research to help uncover process oriented aspects of performing psi. Informal reports (Isaacs, 1992; Stanford, 1977/1986) and descriptive analyses (Gissurarson, 1997) have revealed a number of factors that seem to correlate with PK performance. This study used the phenomenological method to analyze the spontaneous and intentional experiences of eight participants to try to better understand its meaning and nature. There appears to be one core PK experience, which is far more fluid than normal experience. Rather than discrete elements, there are constituents that form a fluid pattern, organic in quality. Fifteen constituents were found for all PK experiences (with 2 more that appear in intentional PK). They are: 1) the presence of an altered state of consciousness; 2) a sense of connection to the target or other people that involves a transcendent level of interconnectedness; 3) a feeling of dissociation from the individual ego identity; 4) suspension of the intellect; 5) the presence of playfulness and/or peak levels of emotion; 6) a sense of energy, that may have a transcendent quality; 7) the physical state may contribute to, and reflect, PK energy; 8) awareness is focused; 9) release of effort/attention; 10) an altered sense of time; 11) investment; 12) openness to the experience; 13) impact on feelings and/or worldview; 14) a sense of "knowing"; and 15) overlap with ESP. With intentional PK there are also: 16) guiding the process; and 17) trusting the process. This paper briefly reviews some of the more important aspects of these constituents, and how it might impact on our understanding of PK and future research.
Article
Mind-matter interaction (MMI) is understood in most existing literature relevant to the topic as a subjective experience of physical matter being affected by one’s own mind or the mind of another person in an anomalous manner. Much of the scholarship found on this phenomenon was written from a parapsychological perspective and, as such, has primarily utilised methods of research more or less in line with the natural sciences (i.e. statistical analyses). In studying MMI from a qualitative perspective, instead of more traditional types of psychological experimentation, this article suggests that researchers can better understand the contextual, relational and subjective nature of such phenomena. For this study, several written descriptions were analysed using a descriptive, phenomenological method, with the objective of learning more about some ways that MMI is experienced from a psychological perspective, particularly in relation to issues of personal crisis, the significance of death and/or traumatic encounter. Overall, six descriptions of MMI were analysed, with six constituents of MMI presenting themselves as especially salient. These constituents are: (1) overwhelming emotionality; (2) feeling initial surprise or disbelief; (3) meaning-making centred around the metaphor of physical energy; (4) issues centred around personal control and/or agency; (5) meaning around the event is constructed in primarily communal ways; and (6) accompaniment and openness to other anomalous experiences.