ArticlePDF Available

“From Counter-Conduct to Critical Attitude. Michel Foucault and the Art of Not Being Governed Quite So Much”

Authors:

Abstract

In this article I reconstruct the philosophical conditions for the emergence of the notion of counter-conduct within the framework of Michel Foucault's study of governmentality, and I explore the reasons for its disappearance after 1978. In particular, I argue that the concept of conduct becomes crucial for Foucault in order to redefine governmental power relations as specific ways to conduct the conduct of individuals: it is initially within this context that, in Security, Territory, Population, he rethinks the problem of resistance in terms of counter-conduct. However, a few months later, in What is Critique?, Foucault (implicitly) replaces the notion of counter-conduct with that of critical attitude, defined as the particular form that counter-conduct takes in modern times. This notion allows him to highlight the role played by the will (to be or not to be governed like that) in resistance to governmental strategies. But since the notion of counter-conduct is conceptually wider than that of critical attitude, I suggest in conclusion that it could be worth reactivating it as a "historical category which, in various forms and with diverse objectives, runs through the whole of Western history.
7
© Daniele Lorenzini 2016
ISSN: 1832-5203
Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 7-21, June 2016
ARTICLE
From Counter-Conduct to Critical Attitude:
Michel Foucault and the Art of Not Being Governed Quite So Much
Daniele Lorenzini, Université Paris-Est Créteil
ABSTRACT: In this article I reconstruct the philosophical conditions for the emergence of the
notion of counter-conduct within the framework of Michel Foucault’s study of
governmentality, and I explore the reasons for its disappearance after 1978. In particular, I
argue that the concept of conduct becomes crucial for Foucault in order to redefine
governmental power relations as specific ways to conduct the conduct of individuals: it is
initially within this context that, in Security, Territory, Population, he rethinks the problem of
resistance in terms of counter-conduct. However, a few months later, in What is Critique?,
Foucault (implicitly) replaces the notion of counter-conduct with that of critical attitude,
defined as the particular form that counter-conduct takes in modern times. This notion allows
him to highlight the role played by the will (to be or not to be governed like that) in resistance
to governmental strategies. But since the notion of counter-conduct is conceptually wider than
that of critical attitude, I suggest in conclusion that it could be worth reactivating it as a
“historical category which, in various forms and with diverse objectives, runs through the
whole of Western history.”
Keywords: counter-conduct, critical attitude, governmentality, will, resistance
In this article
1
I reconstruct the philosophical conditions for the emergence of the notion of
counter-conduct in Security, Territory, Population,
2
and the reasons for its disappearance in
Michel Foucault’s work after 1978. First of all, I show that the notion of conduct becomes
crucial, within the framework of Foucault’s study of governmentality, because of its intrinsic
ambiguity: the individual can be “conducted” by an external force, but s/he is also able to
“conduct” him/herself. However, according to Foucault, governmental mechanisms of power
rely on the fact that the individual accepts being conducted thusly, since by definition we speak
of government (instead of constraint, domination, and so on) if and only if the individual is
1
I would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers from Foucault Studies for their valuable comments
which helped to improve this article.
2
Michel Foucault, Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1977-1978, edited by Michel
Senellart, and translated by Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007).
Lorenzini: From counter-conduct to critical attitude
8
free to choose to be governed or not to be governed like that. To govern someone means, in
fact, to structure his/her field of freedom―his/her field of possible actions. Hence, the notion
of conduct is fundamental for Foucault in order to redefine (governmental) power relations as
specific ways to conduct the conduct of individuals, and it is precisely in this context that he
rethinks the problem of resistance in terms of counter-conduct. But whereas the notion of
conduct remains at the heart of Foucault’s work until the end of his life, the correlative notion
of counter-conduct quickly disappears.
To explore the reasons for this disappearance, I suggest we should take into account the
strong link existing between Foucault’s 1978 lectures at the Collège de France and the
conference What is Critique? that he gave in May 1978 at the Société française de Philosophie.
3
In particular, I argue that Foucault introduces (implicitly but very clearly) in the latter the
concept of critical attitude as a―or better the―form that counter-conduct takes in modern
societies, realizing at the same time the necessity to raise the question of the will (to be or not
to be governed like that) in order to rethink resistance within the framework of governmental
strategies. Thus, if in Security, Territory, Population Foucault does not take into account the role
played by the will in pastoral counter-conducts, he explicitly addresses this problem two years
later in his lectures at the Collège de France On the Government of the Living, although from a
slightly different point of view.
Therefore, starting from What is Critique?, Foucault seems to replace the notion of
counter-conduct with the notion of critical attitude, which allows him to highlight the
voluntary aspect of resistance to governmental power relations. However, since the notion of
counter-conduct is conceptually wider than that of critical attitude, I suggest in conclusion that
it could be worth reactivating it as a “historical category which, in various forms and with
diverse objectives, runs through the whole of Western history.”
4
Conduct, counter-conduct, governmentality
The notion of counter-conduct, as the correlative of that of conduct, emerges in Foucault’s
work during the first months of 1978, when he begins analyzing the strategies, mechanisms,
and practices of governmentality. In this context, however, what Foucault considers
philosophically crucial is above all the notion of conduct, which remains at the center of his
interests until the end of his life.
5
Starting from 1978, in fact, Foucault never ceases to explore
the problem of government in its multiple dimensions. His most significant definition (or
redefinition) of the concept of government is probably to be found in his 1980 conferences
About the Beginning of the Hermeneutics of the Self, in which Foucault argues that government is
the contact point, where the way individuals are driven by others is tied to the way they
3
Michel Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, in Michel Foucault (auth.), Henri-Paul Fruchaud and Daniele
Lorenzini (eds.), Qu’est-ce que la critique? suivi de La culture de soi (Paris: Vrin, 2015), 33-70.
4
Michel Foucault, The Courage of Truth: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1983-1984, edited by Frédéric Gros,
translated by Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011), 174.
5
See for instance the third part of the Introduction to Michel Foucault, The Use of Pleasure: Volume 2 of The
History of Sexuality, translated by Robert Hurley (New York: Vintage Books, 1990).
Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 7-21.
9
conduct themselves.
6
The notion of counter-conduct is thus characterized from the beginning
by a certain “theoretical dependence” on the notion of conduct, and although Foucault
originally constructs it as a very interesting and rich philosophical concept,
7
he never credits it
with an autonomous conceptual status.
Foucault introduces the strictly complementary notions of conduct and counter-
conduct during the 1st March 1978 lecture of Security, Territory, Population. Thanks to these
notions, as Arnold Davidson has convincingly shown, it becomes possible to take into account
the essential link between ethics and politics,
8
and in particular to highlight the strategic role
played by the relationship of oneself to oneself within the framework of the government of
human beings as well as, a fortiori, in the possibility to resist it. Foucault defines the notion of
conduct as “one of the fundamental elements introduced into Western society by the Christian
pastorate,” and translates, by this word, what the Greek Fathers called “economy of souls
[oikonomia psuchōn], that is to say the set of techniques and procedures which characterize
pastorate as a specific art of governing human beings. The notion of conduct seems
particularly appropriate to Foucault because of its intrinsic ambiguity: conduct refers, indeed,
to “the activity of conducting [conduire], of conduction [la conduction],” but also and at the
same time to “the way in which one conducts oneself [se conduit], lets oneself be conducted [se
laisse conduire], is conducted [est conduit], and finally, in which one behaves [se comporter] as an
effect of a form of conduct [une conduite] as the action of conducting or of conduction
[conduction].
9
Hence, the concept of conduct has a threefold meaning: to conduct [conduire]
someone; to be conducted [être conduit] by someone, or better, to let oneself be conducted [se
laisser conduire]; to conduct oneself [se conduire]. As we can see, the notion of conduct covers
the entire field that goes from politics to ethics.
In his article The Subject and Power, originally published in English in 1982, Foucault
uses again the notion of conduct, but he does not apply it only to pastoral power; instead, he
presents it as a possible conceptual key to understand what “power” actually consists in:
[The exercise of power] is a set of actions brought to bear upon possible actions; it operates
on the field of possibilities in which the behavior of the acting subjects is inscribed: it incites,
it induces, it diverts, it makes easier or more difficult, it broadens or restricts, it makes more
or less probable; in the extreme it constrains or forbids absolutely; it is nevertheless always a
way of action upon an acting subject or acting subjects by virtue of their acting or being
capable of action. A set of actions upon other actions.
10
6
Michel Foucault, About the Beginning of the Hermeneutics of the Self: Lectures at Dartmouth College, 1980, edited
by Henri-Paul Fruchaud and Daniele Lorenzini (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2016), 25-26.
7
See Arnold I. Davidson, “In Praise of Counter-Conduct,” History of the Human Sciences, vol. 24, no. 4 (2011),
25-41.
8
Ibid., 26, 28.
9
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 192-193.
10
Michel Foucault, “The Subject and Power,” translated by Leslie Sawyer, Critical Inquiry, vol. 8, no. 4
(Summer 1982), 789; translation modified.
Lorenzini: From counter-conduct to critical attitude
10
Consequently, to exercise power means to try to conduct the conduct of another (or other)
human being(s), i.e. to try to govern him/her (or them), and the word “government” refers
here specifically to the way in which the conduct of individuals or of groups might be
directed,” or better, to the attempt to act upon the possibilities of action of other people,” to
structure the possible field of action of others.” This new definition of government, obtained
through a reflection on the concept of conduct and its “equivocal nature,” allows Foucault to
emphasize that freedom of individuals constitutes “the condition for the exercise of power,” or
better, of this specific form of power called “government”: government can only be exercised
on free subjects, and only as long as they remain free, that is to say as long as they are faced
with “a field of possibilities in which several ways of behaving [conduites], several reactions
and diverse comportments, may be realized.”
11
Thus, the complex dynamics that structure the government of human beings can be
described as a permanent tension between the three dimensions cited above―to conduct
someone, to (let oneself) be conducted, to conduct oneself―where the linchpin role is of
course played by the “middle” element. Between the governmental mechanisms of power
trying to conduct the individual in a specific way, and the possibility the individual has to
conduct him/herself in a (relatively) autonomous way, the field of his/her freedom is defined
and structured by his/her acceptance or refusal to be conducted by this particular mechanism, to
let him/herself be conducted in this specific way. Therefore, according to Foucault, freedom is
not a metaphysical concept: on the contrary, the exercise of freedom is always punctual and
relative to a certain given configuration of power relations. However, or better, as a
consequence, freedom possesses a non-negligible force of insoumission:
The relationship between power and freedom’s refusal to submit [insoumission] cannot,
therefore, be separated. The crucial problem of power is not that of voluntary servitude
(how could we seek to be slaves?): at the very heart of the power relationship, and
constantly provoking it, are the recalcitrance [rétivité] of the will and the intransigence
[intransitivité] of freedom.
12
How should we term this rétivité of the will and this intransitivité of freedom? In other words,
how should we term the individual’s refusal to let him/herself be conducted in this or that
specific way? In Security, Territory, Population Foucault answers these questions by forging the
notion of counter-conduct,
13
and he gives it a first historical content through the analysis of
five counter-conducts that have been elaborated in reaction to Christian pastorate. It is worth
noting that Foucault is not interested here in the “great external blockages that the Catholic
and Christian pastorate came up against,” but rather in the “points of resistance,” in the
“forms of attack and counter-attack that appeared within the field of the pastorate.” In other
words, Foucault’s aim is to highlight a series of “specific revolts of conduct,” where the term
“specific” is crucial: these antipastoral struggles were not global revolts or revolutions, they
11
Ibid., 789-790; translation modified.
12
Ibid., 790.
13
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 201.
Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 7-21.
11
were not radical forms of refusal contesting the fact of government itself―the fact of being
governed tout court―but movements whose objective, within the field of pastorate, was “a
different form of conduct [une autre conduite]. These people wanted “to be conducted
differently [autrement], by other leaders [conducteurs] and other shepherds, towards other
objectives and other forms of salvation, and through other procedures and other methods.”
14
Foucault’s insistence on the otherness that characterizes these counter-conducts is not
accidental: resistance, in fact, never arises in a vacuum but is always relative to something or
someone―resistance always aims at changing, modifying, transforming a specific situation, in
order for the individual to be conducted (or to conduct him/herself) autrement. This is why, in
Security, Territory, Population, Foucault eventually decides to put aside the expression “revolt
of conduct,” which he considers “both too precise and too strong to designate much more
diffuse and subdued forms of resistance,” as well as the terms “disobedience” (although “the
problem of obedience is in fact at the center of all this”), “insubordination, and
“dissidence.”
15
Foucault chooses instead to speak of “counter-conduct,” since this term allows
him to emphasize the active sense of the word “conduct” and, at the same time, to avoid the
risk of “substantification” or sacralization:” the core of a counter-conduct, in fact, is the
struggle in order to claim and obtain an other conduct, in order for the individual to be
conducted (or to conduct him/herself) autrement. Therefore, a counter-conduct always implies,
on the one side, a governmental mechanism of power trying to impose on a group of
individuals a specific form of conduct (which is the target of resistance, of struggles) and, on
the other side, a refusal expressed by the individuals who can no longer accept being
conducted like that and want to conduct themselves differently.
Hence, it is clear that Foucault, in 1978, forges the concept of counter-conduct (also)
with the objective of giving the notion of resistance a “positive,” “productive” meaning, and
not at all a simply “negative” or “reactive” one, as some of his analyses of the first half of the
seventies seemed to suggest―although Foucault always tried to avoid every
misunderstanding on this point. In the fourth chapter of The Will to Know, for instance,
Foucault writes:
Where there is power, there is resistance, and yet, or rather consequently, this resistance is
never in a position of exteriority in relation to power. […] [The] existence [of power
relationships] depends on a multiplicity of points of resistance: these play the role of
adversary, target, support, or handle in power relations. These points of resistance are
present everywhere in the power network.
16
During the second half of the 1st March 1978 lecture at the Collège de France, Foucault
analyzes five main forms of counter-conductasceticism, communities, mysticism, the return
to Scripture, and eschatological beliefs―all of which tried to redistribute, reverse, nullify, and
14
Ibid., 194-195; translation modified.
15
Ibid., 200-201.
16
Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, Volume 1: An Introduction, translated by Robert Hurley (New
York, Pantheon Books, 1978), 95.
Lorenzini: From counter-conduct to critical attitude
12
partially or totally discredit pastoral power as well as its governmental strategies.
17
For present
purposes, it is particularly worth noting that these counter-conducts were not external to
Christianity: they were rather five border-elements, “which have been continually re-utilized,
re-implanted, and taken up again in one or another direction.” In brief, these tactical
elements” have been mobilized in favor or against pastoral government, which in turn has
repeatedly tried to “re-utilize them and re-insert them in its own system.”
18
Nevertheless, the
fundamental and common feature of the antipastoral use of these tactical elements consists in
fighting against the principle of obedience to a shepherd, in contesting the very fact of being
conducted through the modalities prescribed by the Catholic Church. And it would be easy to
show that all of these forms of counter-conduct aim at restructuring the relationship of oneself
to oneself, since the attempt to be conducted (or to conduct oneself) autrement necessarily
entails the refusal of the specific form of subjectivity that Christian spiritual direction (direction
de conscience) and, more generally, pastoral government constitute and impose on
individuals.
19
Thus, in the Medieval antipastoral use of these five tactical elements, within the
field of the Christian pastorate, we always find the same refusal to bend to the principle of
pure obedience, together with the attempt to construct an other form of subjectivity, to give the
relationship of oneself to oneself an other structure.
However, as we have seen, the notion of counter-conduct is explicitly constructed and
presented by Foucault as a conceptual tool whose field of application, both from a theoretical
and a historical point of view, is very broad, since it does not apply exclusively to the
antipastoral struggles of the Middle Ages.
Critical attitude and the will not to be governed like that
Why does Foucault abandon the notion of counter-conduct after having given it such a
detailed and philosophically rich description in Security, Territory, Population? Taking into
account the conference What is Critique?, delivered by Foucault on 27 May 1978 at the Société
française de Philosophie, I would like to suggest that Foucault (implicitly) replaces this notion
with that of critical attitude, realizing at the same time that it is crucial to emphasize the role
played by the will (to be or not to be governed like that) in resistance to governmental
mechanisms of power.
What is Critique? is the first great Foucauldian elaboration of the theme of critique as an
attitude which is “specific to modern civilization.”
20
But what Foucault calls, in this conference,
“critical attitude” is actually nothing else than one―or better the―form that counter-conduct
takes in modern societies.
21
According to him, critical attitude emerged in the fifteenth-
17
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 204.
18
Ibid., 214-215.
19
See on this point Daniele Lorenzini, Éthique et politique de soi: Foucault, Hadot, Cavell et les techniques de
l’ordinaire (Paris: Vrin, 2015), 66-68.
20
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, 34.
21
On the contrary, it is not possible to consider counter-conduct as a specific (Medieval) form taken by
critical attitude, because Foucault is very clear in tying the concept of critical attitude (and of critique tout
Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 7-21.
13
sixteenth centuries, when it is possible to observe a “veritable explosion of the art of governing
human beings.”
22
This art of governing, of course, had been elaborated over many centuries by
the Catholic Church in the form of pastoral power:
[E]ach individual, whatever his age or status, from the beginning to the end of his life and in
his every action [jusque dans le détail de ses actions], had to be governed and had to let himself
be governed, that is to say directed towards his salvation, by someone to whom he was
bound by a total, meticulous, detailed relationship of obedience.
23
Consequently, this art of governing human beings was, for a long time, connected to relatively
limited practices; but starting from the fifteenth century it came to be secularized, i.e.
displaced in relation to its (originally) religious center, thus beginning its great expansion in
civil society. At the same time, it proliferated into a variety of areas: the government of
children, of poor and beggars, the government of a family, of a house, of armies and cities, the
government of States, and also the government of one’s own body and mind. Multiplication of
the arts of governing and the institutions of government; “governmentalization of the res
publicaand emergence of the raison d’État.”
24
However, since the pastoral art of governing
was contested by a series of specific counter-conducts which exploited the possibility―always
(at least in theory) left open―to refuse to be conducted like that and to experiment with other
forms of conduct and self-conduct, we should analogously expect to find some forms of
counter-conduct reacting to the “secular” art of governing human beings.
Indeed, in What is Critique?, Foucault analyzes the emergence of a particular form of
counter-conduct trying to short circuit the modern arts of governing, and calls it “critical
attitude.” It is remarkable that the crucial feature of this critical attitude is exactly the same we
encountered at the heart of Medieval counter-conducts: not “how not to be governed at all,”
but “how not to be governed like that, by that, in the name of those principles, with such and
such an objective in mind and by means of such procedures.”
25
In the face of and as counterparty, or rather, as both partner and adversary to the arts of
governing, as an act of defiance, as a challenge, as a way of limiting these arts of governing
and sizing them up, transforming them, of finding a way to escape from them or, in any
case, a way to displace them, as an essential reticence, but also and by the same token as a
line of development of the arts of governing, there would have been something born in
Europe at that time, a kind of general cultural form, both a political and a moral attitude, a
way of thinking, etc., and which I would very simply call the art of not being governed, or
better, the art of not being governed like that and at that cost. I would therefore propose, as
court) to the “great process of [Western] society’s governmentalization,” thus explicitly excluding the Middle
Ages. See ibid., 41.
22
Ibid., 36.
23
Ibid., 35.
24
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 236-237.
25
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, 37. See Judith Butler, “Critique, Dissent, Disciplinarity,” Critical
Inquiry, vol. 35, no. 4 (2009), 791-792 and Daniele Lorenzini and Arnold I. Davidson, Introduction, in
Foucault, Qu’est-ce que la critique? suivi de La culture de soi, 17.
Lorenzini: From counter-conduct to critical attitude
14
a very first definition of critique, this general characterization: the art of not being governed
quite so much.
26
At the core of this art, Foucault explains, there is the will not to be governed thusly, like that,
by these people, at this cost
27
―but how should we interpret this will? It is worth noting that
it did not play any (explicit) role in Foucault’s analysis of pastoral counter-conducts.
During the 22 February 1978 lecture of Security, Territory, Population, within the
framework of his analysis of the Christian pastorate, Foucault closely examines the practice of
spiritual direction; he thus raises the problem of the disciple’s obedience and links it to the
question of the will. If the Greek citizen “basically does not let himself be directed, and is only
prepared to be directed by two things,” i.e. law and persuasion, and if―as a
consequence―“the general category of obedience does not exist in the Greeks,” in Christian
spiritual direction, on the contrary, we find what Foucault calls “the instance of pure
obedience,that is to say an obedient attitude which contains in itself its raison d’être, which is
an end in itself.
28
This “pure” obedience is characterized by three main features.
First of all, it does not take the form of a relationship of submission to a law or to a
rational principle (as it was the case in antiquity), but that of a “relationship of submission of
one individual to another”―a strictly individual relationship which covers every aspect and
detail of the disciple’s daily life, playing the role of the essential principle of Christian
obedience. The disciple has to show, during the entire course of his/her life, a complete and
permanent “subordination to someone because he is someone.”
29
Secondly, this relationship of submission to another, and to his will, is not finalized, or
better, it has its objective in itself: “One obeys in order to be obedient, in order to arrive at a
state of obedience. This is what Christians call humility, consisting―Foucault argues―in
“the definitive and complete renunciation of one’s own will.” The aim of obedience, for
Christians, “is the mortification of one’s will; it is to act so that one’s will, as one’s own will, is
dead, that is to say, so that there is no other will but not to have any will.” On the contrary, in
ancient Greece, the individual, at a given moment of his life, submitted to the will of someone
else always in order to arrive at a particular result (health, virtue, truth, happiness), and once
26
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?, 37. Unsurprisingly, Foucault argues that the first historical
“anchoring point” of the critical attitude is precisely one of the counter-conducts he already discussed in
Security, Territory, Population, namely the “return to Scripture” (ibid., 37-38). Moreover, during the debate,
Foucault claims that “the history of the critical attitude, as it unfolds specifically in the West and in the
modern Western world since the fifteenth-sixteenth centuries, must have its origin in the religious struggles
and spiritual attitudes prevalent during the second half of the Middle Ages” (ibid., 60), and he refers to
mysticism as “one of the first great forms of revolt in the West” (ibid., 65).
27
Ibid., 65.
28
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 173-174; translation modified. See also Michel Foucault, “Sexualité
et pouvoir” and Omnes et singulatim: vers une critique de la raison politique,” in Michel Foucault (auth.),
Daniel Defert and François Ewald (eds.), Dits et écrits II, 1976-1988 (Paris: Gallimard, 2001), 563-564 and 964-
965.
29
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 175.
Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 7-21.
15
such an objective realized, the relationship of submission ceased, since the individual had
already acquired a certain degree of self-mastery.
30
Finally, in the Christian structure of obedience, the master himself does not command
because he wants to do so (the good director, the good shepherd is humble and would prefer
not to play the role of the master):
31
he commands only because he has been ordered to
command, and since “his refusal would be the assertion of a particular will, he must gave up
his refusal; he must obey, and command.” Therefore, Christian spiritual direction is structured
as a “generalized field of obediencein which “even the points where there is mastery are still
effects of obedience.” And Foucault concludes that we can see here the emergence of a
fundamental problem, that of the self, because pastoral relationships of obedience imply “a
mode of individualization that not only does not take place by way of affirmation of the self,
but one that entails destruction of the self.
32
Two years later, during the 12 March 1980 lecture of On the Government of the Living,
Foucault analyzes again the problem of obedience in Christian spiritual direction, but in doing
so he introduces some new ideas that are crucial. On the one hand, he insists on the disciple’s
freedom, presenting it as a necessary condition for the practice of direction. In fact, the point of
application of pastoral power, of its techniques trying to govern the everyday life of human
beings in its meanest details, is precisely the field that is left free from both political constraint
and legal obligation:
[I]n direction an individual submits to and leaves to another a whole series of decisions of a
private kind in the sense that they normally, usually, and statutorily fall outside the
domains of political constraint and legal obligation. In the domain where political constraint
and legal obligation do not apply, direction requires one to rely on the will of the other.
Where one is free as an individual, one leaves the decision to another person.
33
On the other hand, Foucault argues that this submission of one’s own will to the will of the
other does not consist in a “transfer of sovereignty,” because in Christian spiritual direction
“there is no renunciation of will by the individual.”
34
Even if it was already implicit in Security,
Territory, Population that, in order “to act so that one’s will, as one’s own will, is dead, that is to
say so that there is no other will but not to have any will,”
35
the disciple must want to
“suppress” his/her own will, must want not to have any will, it is only in 1980 that Foucault
explicitly claims that Christian spiritual direction requires, as a sine qua non condition, the
positive exercise of the disciple’s will. Indeed, in order for the master to govern him/her, to
30
Ibid., 177-178.
31
See on this point Jacques Dalarun, Gouverner c’est servir: Essai de démocratie médiévale (Paris: Alma, 2012), 19-
32.
32
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 179-180. See also Foucault, Omnes et singulatim: vers une critique
de la raison politique,” 966.
33
Michel Foucault, On the Government of the Living: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1979-1980, edited by
Michel Senellart, translated by Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014), 229.
34
Ibid.
35
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 178.
Lorenzini: From counter-conduct to critical attitude
16
conduct his/her conduct, the disciple’s will must remain intact, since it is essential for the good
functioning of the relationship of direction that the disciple wants his/her will to be entirely
submitted to that of his/her master, who is supposed to tell him/her in every circumstance
what s/he must will:
I refer myself to the other’s will as the principle of my own will, but I must myself will this
other’s will. […] [In direction] there is someone who guides my will, who wants my will to
want this or that. And I do not cede my own will, I continue to will, I continue to will to the
end, but to will in every detail and at every moment what the other wants me to will.
36
Consequently, the two wills―the master’s and the disciple’s―coexist, they are always present
and intact, but the latter is completely submitted to the former and wants at every moment
what the other wants. The link which ties disciple and master is thus free and voluntary, and
the direction itself “will last, function, and unfold only insofar as the one directed still wants to
be directed,” because s/he is “always free to cease wanting to be directed.” This “game of full
freedom, in the acceptance of the bond of direction,” is crucial: Christian spiritual direction
does not rely fundamentally on constraint, threat or sanction.
37
The structure of obedience
with its three featuressubditio (I want what the other wills), patientia (I want not to will
anything different from the other), and humilitas (I do not want to will)―constitutes of
course the condition, substratum, and effect of Christian spiritual direction,
38
but we should
not consider it as a perfectly oiled “subjugating machine.” Its force lies in the fact that it
constantly rests upon the individuals’ (free) will to be conducted; but this is also its weak spot,
because the “I want” which is essential for the good functioning of pastoral government (and
governmentality in general) can never be abolished. Therefore, it can always, at least in
principle, shift and become an “I do not want anymore.”
In other words, the art of governing human beings is neither all-powerful nor
constantly kept in check. Of course, it has been and still is extremely efficient, and its strength
derives precisely (and paradoxically) from the fact that it does not impose itself upon
individuals through constraint or threat. On the contrary, pastoral power―the matrix of
modern and contemporary governmental strategies―functions through “absolutely specific
modes of individualization, which entail a part of subjection [assujettissement], linked to
individuals’ obedience and to “a whole network of servitude that involves the general
servitude of everyone with regard to everyone and, at the same time, the exclusion of the self,
of the ego, and of egoism as the central, nuclear form of the individual, but also a part of
subjectivation. Pastoral power, in particular through the practice of spiritual direction, builds a
specific subject, i.e. a specific form of the relationship of oneself to oneself characterized by
“the production of an internal, secret, and hidden truth.”
39
36
Foucault, On the Government of the Living, 229-230; emphasis added.
37
Ibid., 230.
38
Ibid., 273.
39
Foucault, Security, Territory, Population, 184.
Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 7-21.
17
This truth is the central feature defining Christian subjectivity, and it constitutes the
lever on which governmental techniques rest in order to operate and be effective. Hence,
pastoral power is able to present to individuals the necessity of an integral direction of their
everyday life not as a dynamics aiming at subjection (although subjection is indeed one of its
effects), but as a process of subjectivation allowing one to discover his/her own secret truth
and to establish an adequate relationship to him/herself, thus carrying on the path towards
beatitude and eternal salvation. However, as we have seen, in this process subjectivation is
essentially linked to subjection―they are the two sides of the same coin―and such a dynamics
always implies that the freedom of the governed remains intact:
Basically, the formula of direction is this: I freely obey what you will for me, I freely obey
what you will that I will so that in this way I may establish a certain relationship to myself.
And as a result, if we call subjectivation the formation of a definite relationship of oneself to
oneself, then we can say that direction is a technique that consists in binding two wills in
such a way that they are always free in relation to each other, in binding them in such a way
that one wills what the other wills, for the purpose of subjectivation, that is to say access to a
certain relationship of oneself to oneself.
40
In brief, the pastoral art of governing human beings can function only thanks to the freedom
of individuals: it does not deprive them of their will, it rather incites them, pushes them to
enter into a process of subjectivation whose objective is to build subjects who are voluntarily
subjugated [assujettis]subjects who want what the other wills, who want not to will anything
different from the other, and who want not to will.
Counter-conduct as a trans-historical category
It is, at first, through the notions of critique and critical attitude that Foucault explicitly
highlights the crucial role played by the individual’s will within the framework of
governmental mechanisms of power. He abandons the concept of counter-conduct in order to
emphasize the importance, in every practice of resistance, of the exercise of a counter-will―in
this respect, unsurprisingly, the central notion he uses in his work of the eighties to redefine
resistance is “subjectivation.” In fact, in order to break the (governmental) relationship of
obedience, the individual must withdraw his/her consent to be conducted like that. To do so, as
we have seen, s/he has to contest and detach from the form of subjectivity that these specific
governmental techniques aim at constituting and imposing on him/her; in other words, s/he
has to work on the relationship of him/herself to him/herself, trying to transform it and to
cease willing what the other wants him/her to will, that is to say trying to build an other
subjectivity.
Thus, in What is Critique?, resistance is conceived as an attitude, both political and
moral,” and Foucault clearly states that “the core [foyer] of critique is basically made of the
bundle of relationships that tie one to the other, or one to the two others, power, truth, and the
subject. Indeed, if governmentalization is “this movement through which individuals are
40
Foucault, On the Government of the Living, 231-232; translation modified.
Lorenzini: From counter-conduct to critical attitude
18
subjugated [assujettis] in the reality of a social practice through mechanisms of power that
invoke a truth,” critique, symmetrically, “is the movement by which the subject gives himself
the right to question truth on its effects of power and to question power on its discourses of
truth.” Therefore, critique is “the art of voluntary insubordination, that of reflected
intractability [indocilité],” whose fundamental objective is “the desubjugation
[désassujettissement] in the context [jeu] of what we could call, in a word, the politics of truth.
41
This is why, in Foucault, ethics―defined as the constitution of a certain relationship of oneself
to oneself―takes on a crucial political value.
42
But contesting the form of subjectivity that is imposed on individuals in order to build
an other subjectivity is not an easy task. In fact, if the concrete functioning of governmental
mechanisms of power rests on the freedom of individuals, it is also essential to
governmentality to produce discourses that “neutralize” this freedom, thus giving them the
impression that there is no real choice to be made. If you want to be saved, you must will to be
conducted like that by your spiritual director;
43
if you want to take advantage of the fruits of
capitalism, you must will to submit your individual freedom to the freedom of the market;
44
and so on. The different forms of governmental power have indeed in common one crucial
feature: they can operate exclusively on the basis of an original consent (“I want”) which has
to be reiterated at every moment by individuals, but they constantly re-inscribe it within the
framework of a “You must” aiming at convincing them that this consent is the only choice
they have if they wish to achieve salvation, happiness, well-being, and freedom itself.
Therefore, a typically Kantian schema is at work here: the only will which is actually
free is the one that takes the form of the law, thus wanting universally everything it wants. Far
from being the sine qua non condition of the exercise of the will, freedom is its result, since we
are truly free if and only if our will takes the (universal) form of the law. But there could also
be applied a Freudian schema: you do not know what you really want, it is me and only me
(your therapist) who can help you to discover it, thus giving you the chance to be free and
happy.
Question: Should we not distinguish between conscious will and unconscious will? I may
choose to submit, to accept a power: can one speak of domination in that case? One may
also say to me: “Even if you do not choose, it is good for you, you want it in fact, and I
know it.” In such a case can one speak of domination?
Michel Foucault: Well, I do not know what an unconscious will is. The subject of will wants
what it wants, and as soon as you introduce a split that consists in saying: “You do not
41
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?,39.
42
See Daniele Lorenzini, “Ethics as Politics: Foucault, Hadot, Cavell and the Critique of Our Present,” in
Sophie Fuggle, Yari Lanci, and Martina Tazzioli (eds.), Foucault and the History of Our Present (Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2015), 223-235.
43
Foucault, “Sexualité et pouvoir,” 562-563.
44
Michel Foucault, The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978-1979, edited by Michel
Senellart, translated by Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), 63-64.
Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 7-21.
19
know what you want. I am going to tell you what you want,” it is clear that this is one of the
fundamental means for exercising power.
45
As a consequence, the possibility to say “I do not want” (to be governed, directed, conducted
like that), in other words the possibility to withdraw one’s own consent to be governed in this
specific way, is “masked” from the beginning or presented as inaccessible. This is why, in What
is Critique?, opposing the Kant of What is Enlightenment? to the Kant of the Critiques,
46
and
insisting on a notion of resistance to governmental strategies which does not take the form of a
“fundamental anarchism,” but consists instead in “the will not to be governed thusly, like that,
by these people, at this cost,”
47
Foucault’s objective is clearly to unmask this governmental
“trap,” thus giving us the chance to see it and to exercise a counter-will―that is to say, a
practice of freedom.
Besides, we should not interpret this “will” not to be governed thusly in the light of a
traditional philosophical conception of the will, just like we should not give the word
“freedom” its current meaning. Will and freedom are not, in Foucault, metaphysical or
juridical concepts, but rather tactical concepts. The will not to be governed like that has nothing
to do with the exercise of a specific human faculty, linked to a certain idea of law,
rationality, and autonomy of the individual.
48
And the freedom to withdraw one’s own
consent to be governed like that is not a fundamental human right nor the empty dream of a
place without power relations. Hence, instead of “will,” we should perhaps speak of decision,
courage or effort,
49
and instead of “freedom,” as Foucault himself suggests, we should rather
speak of practices of freedom, because it is always the singularity and specificity of a given
situation, of a certain actual configuration of power relations, which confers a singular and
specific form to the effort and the practices of freedom aiming at giving rise to an other conduct.
The “passage” from counter-conduct to critical attitude is thus only the first step
Foucault takes into a far wider project which consists in rethinking resistance as an ethico-
political task essentially centered on the effort by the individual to practice and experiment
with different modes of subjectivation. However, to conclude, it should be noted that, within
such a framework, both the concept of counter-conduct and that of critical attitude can still
45
Michel Foucault, “Interview with Michel Foucault,” in Foucault, About the Beginning of the Hermeneutics of
the Self, 134.
46
See Lorenzini and Davidson, “Introduction, 13-15.
47
Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?,” 65.
48
During the debate following his conference at the Société française de Philosophie, Foucault claims that,
“since this problem of will is a problem that Western philosophy has always treated with infinite precaution
and difficulties,” he has himself “tried to avoid it as much as possible,” but eventually admits that it is
crucial for his purposes. However, in order to carry on this “work in progress,” it is clear that Foucault’s
objective is to detach himself from the traditional (metaphysical, naturalistic, juridical) concept of the will
(ibid., 66).
49
“[I]t is no longer a matter of saying: given the bond tying me voluntarily to the truth, what can I say about
power? But: given my will, decision, and effort to break the bond that binds me to power, what then is the
situation with regard to the subject of knowledge and the truth?” (Foucault, On the Government of the Living,
77; translation modified, emphasis added).
Lorenzini: From counter-conduct to critical attitude
20
play a fundamental role. As we have seen, these are not exactly interchangeable: on the
contrary, they give rise to two different historical and philosophical enterprises.
On the one side, critical attitude, which emerged for the first time in the fifteenth-
sixteenth centuries as a specific form of resistance to governmental mechanisms of power,
gives rise to a genealogical analysis which, nevertheless, should not simply refer to Medieval
antipastoral struggles (as Foucault seems to suggest in 1978), but has to be pushed far back
into the past. Foucault’s analysis of parrēsia in Greco-Roman antiquity is indeed one piece of
such a genealogy. During the last lecture of The Government of Self and Others, Foucault
explicitly argues that “Kant’s text on the Aufklärung is a certain way for philosophy […] to
become aware of problems which were traditionally problems of parrēsia in antiquity;
50
and a
few months later, at the University of California, Berkeley, he claims even more clearly that,
“in analyzing this notion of parrhesia,” his aim is to “outline the genealogy of what we could
call the critical attitude in our society.”
51
On the other side, the concept of counter-conduct could give rise to an enterprise that
Foucault never undertook systematically, but which it is possible to recognize in many
“fragments” of his work―from his study of the Cynics’ scandalous behavior
52
to the attention
he draws on the great episodes of convulsions in the body of the possessed during the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries,
53
from his interest in the insurrection of the hysterics”
against psychiatric power in the nineteenth century
54
to his appreciation of the feminist and
gay movements in the eighties.
55
Taking inspiration from his idea of a “trans-historical
Cynicism,” we shall define this enterprise in terms of an analysis of counter-conduct as a
“historical category which, in various forms and with diverse objectives, runs through the
whole of Western society.”
56
It is precisely in its capacity to open the conceptual space for such
an analysis that lies the essential philosophical, ethical, and political value of the notion of
counter-conduct today.
Daniele Lorenzini
EA 4395 “Lettres, Idées, Savoirs”
Université Paris-Est Créteil
61 avenue du Général de Gaulle
50
Michel Foucault, The Government of Self and Others: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1982-1983, edited by
Frédéric Gros, translated by Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), 350.
51
Michel Foucault, Discours et vérité précédé de La parrêsia, edited by Henri-Paul Fruchaud and Daniele
Lorenzini (Paris: Vrin, 2016), 103.
52
See Foucault, The Courage of Truth, 254-255 and passim.
53
See Michel Foucault, Abnormal: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1974-1975, edited by Valerio Marchetti and
Antonella Salomoni, translated by Graham Burchell (London-New York: Verso, 2003), 201-227. See on this
point Mark D. Jordan, Convulsing Bodies: Religion and Resistance in Foucault (Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2014).
54
See Michel Foucault, Psychiatric Power: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1973-1974, edited by Jacques
Lagrange, translated by Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006), 253-254 and passim.
55
See Davidson, “In Praise of Counter-Conduct,” 32-34.
56
Foucault, The Courage of Truth, 174.
Foucault Studies, No. 21, pp. 7-21.
21
94010 Créteil cedex (France)
d.lorenzini@email.com
... These points of resistance are present everywhere in the power network. (Foucault, 1978, p. 95) Foucault, as emphasized in Lorenzini (2016), argues that forms of counter-conduct may "restructure the relationship of oneself to oneself, since the attempt to be conducted (or to conduct oneself) necessarily entails the refusal of the specific form of subjectivity that, generally, pastoral government constitutes and imposes on individuals" (Lorenzini, 2016, p. 12). Subjects are not simply constructed by power. ...
... Through the demonstration, Life Matters, as counter-conduct (Lorenzini, 2016), the protesters may have experienced the ability to restructure "the relation of oneself to oneself " refusing the subjectivity that pastoral government constitutes and imposes on them (Foucault, 1978). People with learning disabilities may have been able to modify themselves through these practices of self in the campaign, artful reconstructing social reality (Friedman 2021, Duncombe 2016. ...
Chapter
Full-text available
This chapter addresses how people with learning disabilities in the city of Trondheim, Norway, spoke up regarding the precarity of their living conditions through the demonstration, Life Matters, in 2019. I approach this performance of protest through the lens of performativity and the civil right of freedom of assembly. The research question is: How may the power of assembly strengthen citizen practice and citizen status for people with learning disabilities? Through an illustrative case methodology, I argue that the embodied character of the demonstration created a plural form of agency. The power people have, when coming together, is itself an important political prerequisite, which may also strengthen the position of people with learning disabilities as political subjects and citizens.
... O artigo tem como fio condutor uma ressignificação da questão (Parrott, 2017), fora do eixo de saber "uspeano" (Silva, Bernardino & Gomes, 2017). E segue a constituição base epistemológica, construção crítica como linha da condução (Colley, 2014;Lorenzini, 2016;Silva et al., 2017). ...
Article
Full-text available
RESUMO Discussões acerca dos crescentes desgastes do meio ambiente e sua capacidade de resiliência imputam em dívida das sociedades e das células sociais. O uso das Ciências Contábeis na tratativa de divulgar os demonstrativos econômico-financeiros podem ser evocados como forma de evidenciar as ações contributivas das células sociais junto ao meio ambiente. Dessa forma, a pesquisa buscou as evidências ambientais de manutenção do entorno patrimonial em relatórios e demonstrativos econômico-financeiros, com o uso da função socialidade, provinda da teoria das funções sistemáticas do patrimônio aziendal. Sob a perspectiva metodológica, a pesquisa foi classificada, quanto aos objetivos e abordagem, como exploratória, descritiva, qualitativa e dedutiva. No que se refere aos procedimentos e técnicas, utilizou-se pesquisa bibliográfica, documental, análise de conteúdo e estudo de casos múltiplos em células sociais com alto impacto ambiental. Os dados foram tratados por meio de planilhas no software Excel. Os resultados apontaram que a maioria das ações ambientais evidenciadas permaneceu nas células sociais e na sociedade, enquanto o meio ambiente recebeu apenas algumas ações voltadas para a manutenção do entorno patrimonial, caracterizadas como não operacionais e de longo prazo. Como contribuição científica, a pesquisa enfatizou, de maneira holística, as interações entre as células sociais e o meio ambiente. Palavras-chave: Meio ambiente. Sustentabilidade. Contabilidade ambiental. Editado em português e inglês. Versão original em português.
... are integral parts (Lessem et al., 2016), whether as individuals or as part of a socio-environmental network to which we are inextricably connected Vázquez et al., 2020). This article is guided by a re-signification of the question (Parrott, 2017), moving beyond the traditional "USP-centric" epistemological axis (Silva, Bernardino & Gomes, 2017), and follows a critical epistemological foundation as the guiding line of inquiry (Colley, 2014;Lorenzini, 2016;Silva et al., 2017). ...
Article
Full-text available
Discussions regarding the increasing degradation of the environment and its resilience capacity result in a debt incurred by societies and their social units. The use of Accounting Sciences to disclose economic and financial statements may serve as a means of evidencing the contributory actions of social units in relation to the environment. Accordingly, this study sought to identify environmental evidence of surrounding asset preservation in reports and economic-financial statements, through the application of the sociality function derived from the theory of systematic functions of aziendal assets. From a methodological perspective, the research was classified, in terms of objectives and approach, as exploratory, descriptive, qualitative, and deductive. As for procedures and techniques, it employed bibliographic and documentary research, content analysis, and multiple case studies involving social units with high environmental impact. Data were processed using spreadsheets in Microsoft Excel. The results indicated that most of the environmental actions disclosed remained within the social units and society, while the environment itself received only a few actions aimed at preserving surrounding assets, which were characterized as non-operational and long-term. As a scientific contribution, the study holistically emphasized the interactions between social units and the environment.
... O artigo tem como fio condutor uma ressignificação da questão (Parrott, 2017), fora do eixo de saber "uspeano" (Silva, Bernardino & Gomes, 2017). E segue a constituição base epistemológica, construção crítica como linha da condução (Colley, 2014;Lorenzini, 2016;Silva et al., 2017). ...
Article
Full-text available
Discussões acerca dos crescentes desgastes do meio ambiente e sua capacidade de resiliência imputam em dívida das sociedades e das células sociais. O uso das Ciências Contábeis na tratativa de divulgar os demonstrativos econômico-financeiros podem ser evocados como forma de evidenciar as ações contributivas das células sociais junto ao meio ambiente. Dessa forma, a pesquisa buscou as evidências ambientais de manutenção do entorno patrimonial em relatórios e demonstrativos econômico-financeiros, com o uso da função socialidade, provinda da teoria das funções sistemáticas do patrimônio aziendal. Sob a perspectiva metodológica, a pesquisa foi classificada, quanto aos objetivos e abordagem, como exploratória, descritiva, qualitativa e dedutiva. No que se refere aos procedimentos e técnicas, utilizou-se pesquisa bibliográfica, documental, análise de conteúdo e estudo de casos múltiplos em células sociais com alto impacto ambiental. Os dados foram tratados por meio de planilhas no software Excel. Os resultados apontaram que a maioria das ações ambientais evidenciadas permaneceu nas células sociais e na sociedade, enquanto o meio ambiente recebeu apenas algumas ações voltadas para a manutenção do entorno patrimonial, caracterizadas como não operacionais e de longo prazo. Como contribuição científica, a pesquisa enfatizou, de maneira holística, as interações entre as células sociais e o meio ambiente.
... For example, rather than outright rejecting the new PFM system, the political and bureaucratic counter-conduct observed in IFMIS reforms involved calling for a system that accommodates "political exigencies" and cultural tenets of Ghana's public bureaucracy. In this sense, resistance is indirect, covert and subtle; in other words, counter-conduct is hidden, invisible and invoking new practices that escape normalised practices of conduct (Lorenzini, 2016). ...
Article
Purpose-The World Bank-sponsored public financial management reforms attempt to instil fiscal discipline through techno-managerial packages. Taking Ghana's integrated financial management information system (IFMIS) as a case, this paper explores how and why local actors engaged in counter-conduct against these reforms. Design/methodology/approach-Interviews, observations and documentary analyses on the operationalisation of IFMIS constitute this paper's empirical basis. Theoretically, the paper draws on Foucauldian notions of governmentality and counter-conduct. Findings-Empirics demonstrate how and why politicians and bureaucrats enacted ways of escaping, evading and subverting IFMIS's disciplinary regime. Politicians found the new accounting regime too constraining to their electoral and patronage politics and, therefore, enacted counter-conduct around the notion of political exigencies, creating expansionary fiscal conditions which the World Bank tried to mitigate through IFMIS. Perceiving the new regime as subverting their bureaucratic identity and influence, bureaucrats counter-conducted reforms through questioning, critiquing and rhetorical venting. Notably, the patronage politics of appropriating wealth and power underpins both these political and bureaucratic counter-conducts. Originality/value-This study contributes to the critical accounting understanding of global public financial management reform failures by offering new empirical and theoretical insights as to how and why politicians and bureaucrats who are supposed to own and implement them nullify the global governmentality intentions of fiscal disciplining through subdued forms of resistance.
... 12 Foucault perspektifinde karşı-tutum ve sınır-tutum için ayrıca bkz. (Lorenzini, 2016) ve "Michel Foucault's Collège De France Lectures: 13 Years at the Collège, 13 Seminars at Columbia". "bir varoluş estetiği" arayışı olarak "kendilik pratikleri" biçimine geri dönmüştür. ...
Chapter
In a couple of previous articles I have tried to show why it is possible, interesting and philosophically crucial to tie together the perspectives on ethics and politics developed by Pierre Hadot, Stanley Cavell and Michel Foucault (Lorenzini, 2010a; 2010b). These three thinkers have indeed in common the effort to consider ethics as a non-teleological and non-deontological field (Cavell, 1990: 46), and they allow us to explore the link between ethical subjectivation and a politics of resistance — which is, in my opinion, one of the most urgent challenges for contemporary philosophy as well as one of the most important stakes of our global present. More specifically, in this chapter I will argue that Foucault’s, Hadot’s and Cavell’s perspectives on ethics and politics — or better, on ethics as politics — provide us with fundamental tools to conceive and practice philosophy as a ‘critical attitude’ (Foucault, 2007).1
Sexualité et pouvoir
  • Foucault
Foucault, "Sexualité et pouvoir," 562-563.
The Courage of Truth, 254-255 and passim
  • See Foucault
See Foucault, The Courage of Truth, 254-255 and passim.
Psychiatric Power: Lectures at the Collège de France
  • See Michel Foucault
See Michel Foucault, Psychiatric Power: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1973-1974, edited by Jacques Lagrange, translated by Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006), 253-254 and passim.