ArticlePDF Available

The Power of Ideas. The Teaching of Economics and its Image of Man

Authors:

Abstract

Economics as a science not only investigates what is (as a positive science) and what should be (as a normative science), but influences, through its fundamental ideas, what facts and norms are recognized as such in society. This holds especially true for economic education. My article explains this thesis and elaborates, in particular, how this form of education stipulates a particular vision of human beings worldwide. First, I show how economics actively seeks to influence the inscription of the commonplace image of the human through economics education. Second, I discuss economics as a textbook science in Thomas Kuhn’s sense: as a science incapable of giving the students any plural or critical understanding of their self and the world. In the third step, I identify the essential features of the human image lying at the base of the economic curriculum; an image (so I argue), which splits society into mere cogs in the machine of the economy on the one side and omnipotent social engineers on the other side.
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
Silja Graupe
The Power of Ideas.
The Teaching of Economics and its Image of Man
1
“I don't care who writes a nation's laws
− − or crafts its advanced treaties
if I can write its economics textbooks.”
(Paul Samuelson)
Economics as a science not only investigates what is (as a positive science)
and what should be (as a normative science), but influences, through its
fundamental ideas, what facts and norms are recognized as such in society.
This holds especially true for economic education. My article explains this
thesis and elaborates, in particular, how this form of education stipulates a
particular vision of human beings worldwide. First, I show how economics
actively seeks to influence the inscription of the commonplace image of the
human through economics education. Second, I discuss economics as a
textbook science in Thomas Kuhn’s sense: as a science incapable of giving
the students any plural or critical understanding of their self and the world.
In the third step, I identify the essential features of the human image lying
at the base of the economic curriculum; an image (so I argue), which splits
society into mere cogs in the machine of the economy on the one side and
omnipotent social engineers on the other side.
Keywords
Critique of Economics, economic education, textbook science, historical
amnesia, image of man, mechanistic worldview
1 Introduction
Why study economics? Paul Samuelson, the most famous economics
textbook writer of all time, answered this question with the following words
of John Maynard Keynes (1955, 12):
“The ideas of economists and political philosophers, both when they
are right and when they are wrong, are more powerful than is
commonly understood. Indeed the world is ruled by little else.
Practical men, who believe themselves to be quite exempt from any
intellectual influence, are usually the slaves of some defunct
economist. Madmen in authority, who hear voices in the air, are
distilling their frenzy from some academic scribbler of a few years
back. I
am sure the power of vested interests is vastly exaggerated
1 Translated from the German by Roger Gathman.
60
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
compared with the gradual encroachment of ideas.
This allows us to discover an important thesis about the function of
economics as a science: it not only investigates what is (as a positive
science) and what should be (as a normative science), but influences,
through its fundamental ideas, what facts and norms are recognized as
such in society. It forms something like the base of thought, from which we
think about the economy and society, without ever reflecting on it in turn. It
determines, tacitly, the assumptions of our scientific reason, without,
conversely, being interrogated by that reason. Thus, economics immobilizes
what can appear to us as the most interesting problems or relevant
questions in science. It forms what Ludwik Fleck (1980, 130) would call a
thought style: “It is readiness for both selective feeling and for
correspondingly directed action. ... It constrains the individual and
determines what cannot be thought in any other way.
In the following I want to explain this thesis and thus elaborate, in
particular, how economics is inscribed with a particular vision of human
beings. Doing this, I will start with the following idea: We cannot normally
foreground our image of man in order to observe it. Rather, it is inscribed
in how we see ourselves and others and the kind of explanations we seek
for our humanity. Fundamentally, our images of man are not images at all,
but ‘lenses’ or ‘filters’ through which we selectively observe our action in
the world: “Our image of the human is already, in our pre-scientific
reflection, an indissoluble component of our everyday activity” (Meinberg
1988, 10).
My essay is divided into three steps. In the first, I show how economics
actively seeks to influence the inscription of the commonplace image of the
human through economics education. Second, I attempt to present an
insight into the basic features of this form of education. Here, economics
will become visible as a textbook science in Thomas Kuhn’s sense: as a
science incapable of giving the students any plural or critical understanding
of self and the world. In the third step, I will identify the essential features
of the twofold human image that, I would argue, lies at the base of the
economic curriculum. On the basis of this image, students get trained to
understand themselves on the one hand as “pleasure machines,” “robots,”
or “laboratory guinea pigs.” On the other hand, they learn to identify
themselves as social engineers who observe other people as pleasure
machines, robots, or guinea pigs and to strive to manipulate the latter
according to their own ideas and interests.
61
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
2 The Influence of Economic Education
Globally, economics is booming as a discipline. In US colleges and
universities alone, 1.5 million students annually enroll in the introductory
economics course (Nasar 1995). “This introductory course is both the first
and the last brush that most educated Americans have with supply and
demand, marginal cost, comparative advantage and other first principles of
the dismal science” (ibid). One could make a similar observation about the
approximately 360,000 students of economics departments in German
universities who make up nearly seventeen percent of all students in
Germany (Statistisches Bundesamt 2010). They, too, in their beginning
micro- and macroeconomics classes are obliged to confront economics
thought. Even if in the past, most ambitious economists focused “on the
kind of esoteric research that might win them a Nobel Prize,” they are now
jumping at this chance “to mold the minds of the next generation of political
leaders, executives, image makers and other members of the … elite” (Nasar
1995). Here, we are not speaking simply about the power to shape individual
lectures or seminars; rather, the great names in the guild strive to write
textbooks powerful enough to dictate the canons of their discipline to
almost all universities around the world.
To begin with, it is a question of dominance within a giant market. In the
United States alone, the market for introductory economics textbooks
measures about fifty million dollars per year. Of the thirty to forty books that
compete for this revenue, a handful secures the lion’s share. Of these
blockbusters, as the New York Times, not without admiration, names them,
each sells annually about 50,000 books at a price of about fifty five dollars
each (Nasar 1995). The first fifteen editions of Paul Samuelson’s Economics
(from 1948-1995) sold approximately about four million copies, not
counting the more than forty translations (Skousen 1997). The careers of
other textbook authors are similarly steep. Take for example Gregory N.
Mankiw, who was chairman of the Council of Economic Advisers under
President George W. Bush. He was not only paid by Harcourt Publisher a
record advance of 1.4 million dollars for his textbook, Principles of
Economics, but also received a bonus of twenty two percent for each copy
sold with sales reaching well beyond the million. Here, too, we are not
counting the revenue garnered from over ten translations (Nasar 1995).
Yet the superstars of the intro economics textbooks business do not simply
seek money and wealth. By their own account, they are much more invested
in the struggle for the best minds in our society. “The top three or four
textbooks, even the top 10, are profitable, wildly profitable” admits, for
example, Mankiw. And he adds: “Besides, economists are proselytizers”
(quoted in Nasar 1995). Paul Samuelson formulates the point as follows: “My
interest was not so much in dollars as in influencing minds (quoted
Gottesman, Ramrattan, Szenberg 2005, 98, my emphasis). Here, as in the
fact that authors like Samuelson are, especially in the United States, often
treated as “high priests” and their books as “bibles” or “gospels,”
2
we find
2 Compare for instance the obituary notices in the Wall Street Journal (December 13, 2009) published on the occasion of Paul
Samuelson’s death, where Robert Hall, Professor at Stanford, for instance, writes: “His book, Foundations of Economic Analysis, was a
bible to my generation of economists, trained entirely in the then-new Samuelson mode.” Samuelson writes about himself: I was
besieged by groupies reminiscent of Talmudic students crowding around famous rabbis. The policeman at the door of the White House
whispers, ‘I am using your book at Georgetown n ight school.’ The chap w ho sells me a newspaper at Harvard Square confides that at
Northeastern he studied my book. . . . Wherever I go in Europe, Asia, or Latin America, strangers greet me as an old friend or old
62
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
that economists do not only desire to sell heaps of their standard intro
economics textbooks; they also want them to be read a million fold. They
wish their content to be actually learned and understood, pushed, if
necessary, by the constant pressure of grading and exams.
3
It all comes
down to consciously influencing the ideas, attitudes, and imaginations of
each new generation:
“It is hard to gauge the influence of Samuelson's textbook, or in
general the impact of introductory courses in economics, on U.S.
policymakers or corporate executives. Samuelson has been willing to
claim, with tongue only slightly in cheek, a considerable impact. He
has made a well-known comment: ‘I don't care who writes a nation's
laws or crafts its advanced treaties if I can write its economics
textbooks.’
He has also expressed hope that his textbook would be a reference
guide for former students. ‘When the election of 1984 rolls around,’
he wrote in 1967, ‘all the hours that the artists and editors and I have
spent in making the pages as informative and authentic as possible
will seem to me well spent if somewhere a voter turns to the old book
from which he learned economics for a rereasoning of the economic
principle involved” (Skousen 1997, 149-50).
Mankiw writes in his preface to the instructor (2001, vii): “Economists have a
unique way of viewing the world, much of which can be taught in one or two
semesters. My goal in this book is to transmit this way of thinking to the
widest possible audience and to convince readers that it illuminates much of
the world around them.” Critical economists like Steve Keen see in this
nothing less than a campaign of ideological persuasion: “What I had initially
thought was an education in economics was in fact little better than an
indoctrination” (Keen 2001, xiii).
3 Economics as a Textbook Science
In order to be able to relate to Keen’s reproach, we first need to understand
how the self-conception of economics as a science has substantially changed
over the last seventy years or so. Originally, economics had defined itself by
means of its subject matter: it sought to explain the world of commerce
(see, for example, Becker 1990). In this way, what economists did was rather
well-defined. They were supposed to analyze what was commonly seen as
‘commercial’ or ‘economic’ matters.
4
This limitation in relation to the object
tormenter. I have never been to India, Russia, or China, but in my MIT office, I am asked to autograph copies of translations” (quoted in
Gottesman, Ramrattan, Szenberg 2005, 98).
3 Samuelson also invokes another form of pressure. He tells his students to consider the study of economics a factor absolutely
decisive to success or failure in the daily struggle for existence: “As we have come to realize, there is one overriding reason for learning
the basic lessons of economics: All your life from the cradle to grave and beyond – y ou will run up against the brutal truths of
economics. (…) Of course, studying economics cannot make you a genius. But without ec onomics, the dice of life are loaded against
you” (Samuelson, Nordhaus 2005, 3, my emphasis). In an earlier edition (1955, 3), Samuelson even writes: “Thus, even from the purely
egotistic standpoint of self interest [it is important to] find answers to ... the questions of modern economic life” (my emphasis).
4 This is to say that economics w as believed to simply analyze the production, distribution, and consumption of goods and services or ,
more specifically, the allocation of limited resources to the satisfaction of mutually exclusive ends. Common to these definitions is that
they refer to the objects of economic investigation, but do not prescribe the methods, with which one should investigate these objects.
63
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
of research stood in contrast to a great freedom with regard to the manner
of research. Each economist could freely control his methodological
approach, and thus how he was to conduct his research. In consequence the
self-understanding of the economic sciences was plural: it unified a number
of perspectives on ‘economic’ phenomena. Modern economics, however,
negates this pluralistic self-understanding and inverses the freedom of the
researcher into its exact opposite. Gary Becker, a leading figure of the
Chicago School of Economics and the Nobel Prize winner in economics for
1992, codified this turn-about as follows: “That which distinguishes
economics as a discipline
from other disciplines in the social sciences is not
its subject matter but its approach (1990, 5, my emphasis). Scientific
freedo
m
means, for Becker, that fundamentally all social subjects may be
analyzed by the economist: from “fertility, education and the uses of time,
crime, marriage, social interactions, and other ‘sociological,’ ‘legal,’ and
‘political problems” (ibid, 8). Nothing less than all human behavior gets
reduced to an object of economic research:
“Indeed, I have come to the position that the economic approach is a
comprehensive one that is applicable to all human behavior, be it
behavior involving money prices or imputed shadow prices, repeated
or infrequent decisions, large or minor decisions, emotional or
mechanical ends, rich or poor persons, men or women, adults or
children, brilliant or stupid persons patients or therapists,
businessmen or politicians, teachers or students” (ibid).
Under the flag of this economic imperialism,
5
modern economics claims
absolute freedom in the choice of its subject matter. Yet this is bought at the
price of a substantial limitation of the choice over one’s research methods.
The economist must (and should!) probe absolutely everything in the world.
But he has to approach it from a single angle of vision: that of modern
microeconomics or neoclassical theory. Only the “combined assumptions of
maximizing behavior, market equilibrium, and stable preferences, used
relentlessly and unflinchingly, form the heart of the economic approach”
(ibid, 5). While the economist may have become free to analyze everything in
the world, he has no choice regarding the rules of thought by which he
undertakes this analysis. In order to preserve the unity of economics as a
science, he must renounce the multiplicity of conceptual possibilities in
order to align himself with a single technique of thinking. In this way, a
monoculture of thought is established, that extends far over the borders of
what we usually understand to be ‘economic’ or ‘commercial.’
Often I hear colleagues reply that one can easily exaggerate the power of
this monoculture, if one ignores, on the one hand, the many directions that
are alternative to the economic mainstream, and on the other hand, refuses
to recognize the extent to which the mainstream itself continually works so
as to perfect and refine its approach. These objections might be justified, at
most, with respect to research. But in regard to the curriculum, they
certainly mistake the actual heart of things. Because in the lecture halls of
5 We are not using, here, some insult forged by critics, but the explicit self-understanding, in particular, of a science that has been
colored by the Chicago School of Economics. “I am an economic imperialist. I believe good techniques have a wide application” says, for
example, Gary Becker about himself (1993).
64
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
the world, the neoclassical refinements do not count; nor does their critique.
Both are not taught, or only taught in later semesters. It is much more likely
that the following prevails:
“Normal science can keep the student and practitioner on the straight
and narrow if there develops an interpretive tradition that makes it
unnecessary to consult the canonical texts with all their ambiguity,
passion, and contingency. The development of textbooks is a
hallmark of that interpretive tradition. Teachers of economics
sometimes complain that, pedagogical style apart, current economics
textbooks are almost all alike. (…) The existence of canonical
textbooks is a considerable part of what distinguishes economics
from other social sciences” (Pearce, Hoover 1995, 184).
A remark attributed to Paul Samuelson goes: “Economists are said to
disagree too much but in ways that are too much alike: If eight sleep in the
same bed, you can be sure that, like Eskimos, when they turn over, they’ll all
turn over together” (quoted in Weinstein 2009). This aptly hits on the
superstars of the intro economics textbooks, especially in regard to their
microeconomic insights. In this case, it even seems wholly appropriate to
say – to remain with Samuelson’s image – that all have slept in the same bed
for decades, but up to now none of them, either individually or together, has
turned over. Let us look at this more closely. Today’s economic doctrine is
commonly divided into the domains of micro and macro economics. To put
it a little simply, microeconomics is ascribed the task of explaining, mainly,
the individual behavior of economic actors. Here economists divide the
social world into two classes: the consumer and the producer. Then they
observe the behavior of a single individual of each class, in order to draw
conclusions about all consumers or producers. Thus, microeconomics gives
us a methodological individualism,
6
in which the behavior of groups can only
be explained from the aggregation of individual actions. On this basis there
arises the image of an ideal market. It is imagined that individual consumers
with already given preferences always meet individual suppliers with likewise
fixed ideas of profit on markets as though for the first time. Social
interaction is considered an end result in this view, but is not seen through
as the driving force behind individual utility and gain calculi. Modern
macroeconomics appropriates the principles of methodological individualism
unhesitatingly, in order to dedicate itself to the representation and shaping
of the mutual effects of different markets, for example those of
commodities, labor and capital. It is understood, in other words, to be micro
founded. Already from this rudimentary description we can see the fact that
microeconomics fundamentally shapes the human image which then
grounds all further economic descriptions of social interactions. And
precisely in regard to this subject area the following holds true: even if the
macroeconomic content of all standard textbooks already shows “a
surprising degree of consensus (Walstad, Watts, Bosshard 1998, 198-99),
microeconomics represents precisely that subject area where “the victory of
Samuelson's early pedagogy has been most complete and where the beliefs
of economists have changed least” (Skousen 1997, 138). Whether in Greek,
6 The concept of “methodological individualism” goes back to Joseph Schumpeter (1908).
65
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
German, Chinese, Japanese, Hebrew, Serbo-Croatian or Spanish, and under
whatsoever title: in regard to the basic understanding of humanity and
human action, all the important economics textbooks of our time establish a
single, unified lingo.
In order to trace this phenomenon more precisely, I suggest grasping
microeconomics as a textbook or normal science, as described by Thomas S.
Kuhn (1996, 17):
“In the early stages of the development of any science different men
confronting the same range of phenomena, but not usually all the
same particular phenomena, describe and interpret them in different
ways. What is surprising, and perhaps also unique in its degree to the
field we call science, is that such initial divergences should ever largely
disappear. For the do disappear to a very considerable extent and then
apparently once and for all.”
Actually, current economics textbooks, almost without exception, are based
on a single economic theory of human behavior that was already established
in the middle of the 19
th
century: the neo-classical. In this way, they prevent
the student in this science from meeting with the usual multiplicity of
perspectives, visions and ideas:
“More than a decade before I became an undergraduate, a major
theoretical battle had broken out over the validity of economic theory.
Yet none of this turned up in the standard undergraduate or honours
curriculum – unless it was raised by some dissident instructor. There
were also entire schools of thought which were antithetical to
conventional economics, which again were ignored unless there was a
dissident on staff” (Keen 2001, xiii).
The textbook science grounds a pedagogic concept that in essence rests on
forgetting history, or more precisely, on an almost complete forgetting of
economics ’own intellectual history and history of ideas:
“Textbooks, however, [are] pedagogic vehicles for the perpetuation of
normal science (…) Textbooks thus begin by truncating the scientist’s
sense of his discipline’s history and then proceed to supply a
substitute for what they have eliminated. Characteristically, textbooks
of science contain just a bit of history, either in an introductory
chapter or, more often, in scattered references to the great heroes of
an earlier age. From such references both students and professionals
come to feel like participants in a long-standing historical tradition.
Yet the textbook-derived tradition in which scientists come to sense
their participation is one that, in fact, never existed” (Kuhn 1996,
66
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
138).
Certainly, Kuhn himself was making this statement simply in regard to the
natural sciences. Yet economics has attempted, since its origin in the 18th
century, to be a science, "which resembles the physico-mathematical
sciences in every respect" (Walras 1969, 71). And this ambition is mirrored in
a forgetting of history that takes shape in the way economics textbooks veil
the ancestry and dynamic history of their science and abbreviate it beyond
recognition, a process very similar to what Kuhn describes in the case of the
natural sciences. For instance, in the first edition of Samuelson’s Economics
we find just a single page dedicated to the history of economics (1955, 12-
13). This is presented by Samuelson as an “ancestral portrait gallery,” in
which he only mentions five economists: John Maynard Keynes and Adam
Smith, whom he praises, Karl Marx, whom he refers to as the “black sheep”
of the economic profession, as well as David Ricardo and John Stuart Mill.
7
In
the newer editions of his textbook, even these rudimentary descriptions
drop out; instead of which we find a few disparate references to “important
figures in economics(Samuelson, Nordhaus 2005, xx). If the student thus
will already find it almost impossible to clearly locate scholarly positions and
approaches within the original multiplicity of economics opinions and
perspectives, other textbooks drop out even these sporadic remarks
concerning the intellectual history of economics. Mankiw for instance
doesn’t spare a word for it (2001), and Varian does as little (2007).
“The depreciation of historical fact is deeply, and probably functionally,
ingrained in the ideology of the scientific profession” (Kuhn 1996, 138). Yet
with the loss of one’s proper intellectual history, an awareness of the
plurality of perspectives and methodological approaches that once was the
glory of the science vanishes as well. Commerce and society appear
differently depending on the perspective from which we envision them. Our
‘methodological lenses’ decide what aspects of the economy we will focus
on and how we do so. They also determine what problems remain essentially
hidden. Many of the central problems of present day commerce remain
completely in the dark as long as we only observe them from the angle of
the economic mainstream. Thus, for instance, Norbert Häring in his study,
Markt und Macht (“Power and Markets,” 2010), represents how textbook
economics systematically hinders taking into account the phenomenon of
market power. This can similarly be shown for creativity (Brodbeck 1996) or
the inherent dynamic of markets (Schumpeter 1942; Sraffa 1926; Keen
2010). In this way, a systematic blindness is spurred on, which already led
Joan Robinson (quoted in Hill, Myatt 2010, 1) to the following question:
“It is true that we cannot, in the time available, teach everything that
we would like. But why do we pick out for treatment just that
selection of topics that is least likely to raise any questions of
fundamental importance?”
7 About Adam Smith, Samuelson writes (1955, 12-13): “First comes Adam Smith, a Scotch bachelor with powdered wig like George
Washington, who gathered together the earlier wisdom of business pamphleteers and philosophic system builders in his Wealth of
Nations (1776). He recognized the virtues of free markets, and the times were ripe for his doctrines to become the bible of the rising
middle class. About Marx, Samuelson says: ‘And then our picture gallery comes upon the black sheep, who was beyond the pen of the
true classical tradition. Karl Marx, an e xile from Germany, worked away in the British Museum vowing that the Bourgeoisie would pay
for the suffering his boils cost hi m as he sat working out his theories of the inev itable collapse of capitalism’” (re-translated from the
German edition).
67
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
“The point is: The way we think changes things... The freedom of thought
depends on the fact that one can choose between different ways of thinking”
(Hedtke 2008, 5-6). As correct and important this insight is, as completely is
it ignored by a textbook economics for which ‘multiple perspectives’ is a
foreign term that is never even mentioned, once, as a possibility. “For every
critical economic issue there are competing concepts and theories that lead
to different conclusions. The problem is that when they are not missing from
textbooks altogether, these theories are almost always summarily
dismissed(Adler 2010, vx). “But if one is barred from all alternatives, one
does not even know that one could chose if one knew the different thought
concepts” (Hedtke 2008, 6).
The newer textbooks in particular drive such a method-monism to extremes,
in as much as they do not even make their own perspective clear as a means
of knowing. There exists a systematic difference between the observer and
the observed, or between the knower and the known, and it is the task of an
introductory chapter about the scope and methods of science to make the
reader aware, at least, of this difference. What commerce looks like to
economists, how it appears to them, is not simply equivalent to commercial
reality as such. Yet Varian, for instance, simply sweeps aside such reflections
as superfluous. He writes, explicitly, that “it is rather inappropriate to begin
the study of the economy with it” (2007, 1). Mankiw (2001, 3-17) takes this
kind of pedagogy even further. At the beginning of his textbook, he explains
his “10 principles of economics” so that they appear simply as facts, and not
a higher level, selective
description of facts. Take, for example, Mankiw’s
forth
principle “people respond to incentives” (2001, 7). This principle
essentially tells us to analyze individual behavior in the framework of a
stimulus-response model: we are to preconceive people as if they
automatically and unconsciously altered their behavior in response to
changes in market prices. As such, Mankiw essentially leads us to highlight
certain characteristics of human beings, i.e. the easily predictable, while
erasing others, i.e. the thoughtful, creative and essentially non-determinable
aspects of human activity. But Mankiw does not reveal this as a
methodological pre-adjustment. He rather pretends to speak about reality as
such. He simply tells us that all people factually respond to incentives. Thus
he misleads his students into taking a specific view of social reality
uncritically as the equivalent of or the substitute for this reality.
At least with Paul Samuelson one can perceive that such leveling is in no way
unintended, but is instead a conscious pedagogical program. Thus, he
confronts millions of students at the beginning of his textbook with the
following message (1955, 5-6):
We must “firstly develop the faculty in ourselves to see things without
partisanship or previous assumptions, that is, to see them as they
really are, and without reference to whether that is pleasant or
unpleasant to us. (…)We know that a doctor passionately interested in
stamping out disease must first train himself to observe things as
they are. (…) Similarly, there are elements of valid reality in a given
economic situation, however hard it may be to recognize and isolate
them. There is not one theory of economics for Republicans and one
68
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
theory for Democrats, one for workers and one for employers... On
many basic principles concerning prices and employment, most if
not all! economists are in fairly close agreement” (translated from
the German edition, emphasis in the German original).
These few references may satisfy us in order to show how textbook
economics narrows the student’s understanding systematically down to a
single perspective. Instead of making this limitation known, economics leads
the student to apply this perspective to ever more commercial as well as
social phenomena, and to describe the latter on this basis in continually
more refined detail. Students are thus hindered to develop their own
thought, if they are not completely blocked in regard to the following: They
are neither given the tools to critically reflect on the grounds of the
assumptions underlying their own thought, nor to transform them in any
respect. Again a similar point has been made by Kuhn with regard to the
natural sciences. The praxis of science “will seldom evoke overt
disagreement over fundamentals” (1996, 11). “Given a textbook, ...the
creative scientist can being his research where it leaves off and thus
concentrate exclusively on the subtlest and most esoteric aspects of the
natural phenomenon that concern his group” (ibid, 20). At the same time,
the student is isolated from all social problems that cannot be described
with the help of the conceptual instruments of economic textbook science.
He is, in other words, compelled to banish all of those problems that cannot
be adequately focused within the economic perspective to the realm of the
irrational and unscientific – even if they occur to him, as a human being, to
be obvious and pressing.
4 The Image of Man in Economic Textbook Science
Certainly, economic assumptions about humanity are an object of scientific
research. Here, advocates of mainstream economics openly acknowledge
that homo oeconomicus is simply a model, created for a particular, highly
specific purpose (see for instance Kirchgässner 1991). Likewise they repeat
Joan Robinson’s sentence: a model that didn’t dispense with the whole
variety of reality would be as useless as a map on the scale of one to one
(quoted in Felderer, Homburg 1999, 10). Every theory, the argument goes,
must emphasize certain aspects of reality as being ‘significant’ (positive
abstraction) while dismissing others as ‘meaningless’ or as ‘confusing
collateral circumstances’ (negative abstraction), so that it may serve its
specific end: the same thing should hold true with regard to the image of
man. But even though this statement from Robinson is frequently quoted in
economic textbooks, it is, with regard to the economics curriculum,
misleading in at least two senses. Firstly, they suggest that students are
continually made aware of abstractions as part of their own intellectual
69
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
activity, as their own instruments of thought. But with our contemporary
economics textbooks this is certainly not the case. And this concords with
our second sense, which is that textbook economics never makes its view of
economic man explicit as what it truly is: an image of man. Rather, homo
oeconomicus functions as a mere fundamental assumption, which is casually
introduced inside the framework of the greater theoretical structure. It is
hardly reflected upon but only applied to problem-solution. Thus, it is not
explained to students, why they are to observe just the properties of homo
oeconomicus as being ‘essential’ for humanity in commerce, nor do they
learn to reflect upon the conflicting human properties they are forced to
erase as mere disturbing matters. In other words, students are neither given
any explicit rules as to how they are supposed to think of humans nor why
they should do so. Yet this doesn’t mean that such rules do not exist.
Rather, what we see here is the binding force of tacit knowledge(Polanyi
1966). This is the kind of knowledge students assimilate in the course of
their learning process, without ever growing capable of articulating it
explicitly. In a sense, one can speak here of the development of a paradigm:
“Scientists work from models acquired through education and
through subsequent exposure to the literature often without quite
knowing or needing to know what characteristics have given these
models the status of community paradigms. (…) Paradigms may be
prior to, more binding, and more complete than any set of rules for
research that could be unequivocally abstracted from them (...) While
paradigms remain secure they can function without agreement
over rationalization or without any attempt of rationalization at all”
(Kuhn 1996, 46-49).
But what composes the economics paradigm in regard to the understanding
of human beings? Let’s begin our search by tracing the “law of diminishing
marginal utility”. This law is taken as a central assumption about consumer
behavior by all standard microeconomics textbooks. “This law states, that
the amount of extra or marginal utility declines as a person consumes more
and more of a good” (Samuelson 2005, 85). What does this mean? “Marginal
utility
denotes the additional utility you get from consumption of an
additional unit of a commodity (ibid). Thus, this additional utility is
supposed to decline, the more units of the good are consumed altogether.
8
It is never thought, however, to become equal to or less than zero.
Samuelson mentions, correctly, that this law of economics was formulated
over a hundred years ago. Yet he suggests (2005, 85), that we can found
this law by means of observing our own proper world of experience:
“What is the reason for this law? Utility tends to increase as you
consume more of a good. However, according to the law of
diminishing marginal utility, as you consume more and more, your
total utility will grow at a slower and slower rate. Growth in total utility
slows because your marginal utility … diminishes as more of the good
8 Note that the concept of utility itself remains fairly obscure within some economic textbooks. Samuelson, for example, refers to it
either as “satisfaction,” “subjective pleasure,” or “usefulness that a person derives from consuming a good or se rvice” (2005, 84) And
yet he warns: “But you should definitely resist the idea that utility is a psychological function or feeling that can be observed or
measured”, advising the reader to think o f it just as a “scientific concept” (ibid). Mankiw, however, is less bothered by such sophistry.
He simply denotes utility as “a measure of happiness or satisfaction” (2001, 447).
70
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
is consumed. The diminishing marginal utility results from the fact that
your enjoyment of the good drops off as more and more of it its
consumed” (my emphasis).
Samuelson calls upon the experience of the students in order to explain a
major economic ‘law.’ At the same time, however, he instructs them to look
at this experience through lenses already colored by this very law itself. Very
clearly, this is an instance of circular logic, which in a careless manner mixes
together method and empiricism, experience and theory. A similar case can
be observed in regard to an even more important economic ‘law’ which
postulates in principle the limitlessness of human needs, a non-satiation, as
it is called by economists. In modern textbook economics this principle is
hidden in the abstract concept of indifference curves, which Samuelson, for
instance, introduces like this: “Start by assuming that you are a consumer
who buys different combinations of two commodities, say, food and
clothing, at a given set of prices. For each combination of these two goods,
assume that you prefer one to the other or are indifferent between the pair”
(Samuelson, Nordhaus 2005, 101). Again, the perception of the reader is
narrowed down from the outset with regard to his own possibilities of
action. And once again, this is not made explicit. A sort of perception filter is
installed, through which the world appears simply as an assembly of bundles
of goods, between which people predictably choose according to their own
utility: “If you offer the consumer two different bundles, he chooses the
bundle that best suits his tastes. If the two bundles suit his tastes equally
well, we say that the consumer is indifferent between the two bundles. (…)
An indifference curves show the bundles of consumption that make the
consumer equally happy” (Mankiw 2001, 466). Other bundles of goods are
taken to grant lower or higher levels of satisfaction. Thus, they are arranged
on higher or lower indifference curves respectively. In addition, the following
is taken for given: “Because the consumer prefers more of a good, points on
a higher indifference curve … are preferred to points on a lower indifference
curve” (ibid, 467). In this or a similar fashion all current economics
textbooks construct in a few paragraphs a simple “indifference map” in
which the total decision space of people is depicted as something like a
“utility mountain” (see figure 1; quoted from Stocker 2002, 143):
“This diagram is analogous to a geographic contour map. A person
who walks along the path indicated by a particular height contour on
such a map is neither climbing nor descending; similarly, the
consumer who moves from one position to another along a single
indifference curve enjoys neither increasing nor decreasing
satisfaction from the change in consumption. (…) Note that as we
increase both goods and thus move in a northeasterly direction across
this map, we are crossing successive indifference curves; hence, we are
reaching higher and higher levels of satisfaction (assuming that the
consumer gets greater satisfaction from receiving increased quantities
of both goods)” (Samuelson, Nordhaus 2005, 102-103).
Notice again that a highly crucial assumption about humans is introduced
here in a by the way fashion: microeconomic textbooks unanimously assume
71
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
that having more of a bundle of goods is always preferred to having less of it
(e.g. Varian 2007, 85). “Consumers usually prefer more of something to less
of it” (Mankiw 2001, 468). It appears as though people were, by internal
necessity, always driven to climb up the “utility mountain” to ever dizzier
heights, as if they were forced to continually chase after ever greater levels
consumption. There seems to exist something deep within them that causes
them to restlessly strive for ever greater bundles of goods. In other words,
their peculiar journey across the mountain of utility recognizes no climax. It
does not reference or account for any limitation of satisfaction.
This is the basic idea behind “indifference curves” and the “utility mountain”
(see again figure 1): utility (i.e. happiness or satisfaction) increases as more
of both goods are consumed. Indifference curves C’, D’ and E’ are conceived
analogous to height contours on a geographic contour map. Utility neither
increases nor decreases along these curves. But the level of utility is higher
along E’ than on D’, and higher on D than on C’. Note that textbooks
economics, in contrast to this graph, usually does not assume a “summit” of
the utility mountain to exist (point G). Rather, utility is thought to limitlessly
increase as consumption of both goods increases.
Figure 1
Samuelson explains this fundamental presupposition about human behavior
and why he takes it for granted as little as do his colleagues. Such lack of
explanation does not simply encumber the necessarily foreshortened forms
of presentation normal to a textbook. Instead, it is deeply anchored in the
72
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
tradition of economics research as such. A reference to one of the actual
originators of the ‘laws’ of diminishing marginal utility and of non-satiation,
the Prussian political economist Hermann Heinrich Gossen (1810-1858), can
illustrate this: “Man arranges his actions so that the sum of his life
enjoyments will be of the greatest amount,” so Gossen already postulated in
1854 (4-5). We already know this from our economic textbooks. Yet the
manner in which Gossen justifies this postulate is very illuminative:
“Not only is this maximization viewed by all men without exception as
life’s ultimate purpose, but it is undoubtedly the real purpose of man’s
life, willed by his Creator. We can explain the ineradicable and
unceasing human desire to reach this objective only by the same
procedure by which we seek to explain all other phenomena in nature,
namely by assuming that the creator created in men a power whose
effect intervenes as this wish in his existence, as we also all other
phenomena in nature through the assumption of effective forces
corresponding to certain specific laws. ... Its purpose, and thus the
purpose of the creator by his creation, can thus not be anything other
than willing this effect, that he wanted man to follow its promptings.
Hence it would frustrate totally or in part the purpose of the Creator
were we to attempt to neutralize this force in total or in part, as is the
intention of some moral codes promulgated by so many men. But how
can a creation be more presumptuous than to want to frustrate the
purpose of his creator in whole or in part!” (ibid, 2-3).
Here we see: Gossen does not truly ground the law of decreasing marginal
utility. Rather, it intervenes at a point where reflection stops, beyond which
we are told that any further explanation is superfluous, and even appears to
be vicious: “For its genuineness or truth, this revelation needs no human
testimony; it confirms itself in such an indubitable manner that any other
proof seems superfluous” (ibid, 4). This kind of dead end is not an anomaly
in the history of economics. It is the norm. It is already found for instance in
Adam Smith, the originator of economics as a science. For he claimed the
workings of his famous “invisible hand” to be located beyond the purlieus of
all scientific explanation (see Ulrich 1991). These workings, according to the
Scottish moral philosopher, were like the creative power of a watchmaker,
owing themselves “in reality to the wisdom of God” and thus not being
rationally explainable by human mortals. Like the cogs of the clockwork, the
latter must believe in this working, but not seek to ground it in a strictly
scientific sense (1759, II.II.19). But the standard economics textbooks don’t
say a word to draw the student’s attention to the problematic of such
fragmentary foundations. They only require that the existence of social
regularities be taken as given, as if they ever had been correctly founded.
They mislead, in other words, students to unconsciously put themselves on
the shoulders of long dead economists without ensuring the credibility of
these foundations, not to speak of seeking alternative standpoints.
Let’s go a step further. Textbook economics does not only confront the
students with the alleged laws of decreasing marginal utility and of non-
satiation. It also introduces them to the supposedly hard reality of scarcity:
“Let us give the consumer a fixed income. He has, say, $6 per day to
spend, and he is confronted with fixed prices for each food and clothing unit
73
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
$1.50 for food, $1.00 for clothing” (Samuelson, Nordhaus 2005, 103).
People, so it is suggested, always prefer to select bigger bundles of goods;
yet this can only happen in the framework of their command over a given
income, and thus over money. The actual wandering in the mountains of
utility can only unfold along an income gradient, as if every human decision
were like a ball slotted into a specific track (see figure 2; quoted from
Stocker 2002, 159): left of this gradient, bundles of goods are not preferred
because they grant too low levels of satisfaction; on the right, they cannot
be reached, because of the lack of income to back them. Thus, there
remains only one choice: “The consumer chooses the point of his budget
constraint that lies on the highest indifference curve” (Mankiw 2001, 471).
This is what economists call the principle of utility maximization. Here is
where we see: first, textbook economics offers the students only a single
‘map’ for orientation in the economy.
9
Closer inspection reveals, second,
that this map in truth is not even analogous to a terrain map as long as we
think of the latter as an aid to real orientation. Its purpose is, rather, to
describe a seemingly inexorable program of action, which inevitably limits
human freedom of choice to a single point in a pregiven commodity space.
Economic textbooks certainly qualify students to calculate this program in
all of its details. They also instruct them to make it the foundation for all
further questions concerning economic theory and politics. But at the same
time they systematically disempower students, or even force them to retreat
from, becoming conscious of the image of man lying at the foundation of
this program.
It escapes them, for instance, that textbook economics implicitly supposes
that man can only chose between given goods whose price is dictated by the
market. Man cannot create for himself his choices, neither can he create his
own area of action, but must always chose between given things within a
pre-fixed commodity space. This is the equivalent of saying: the actor does
not have the choice when it comes down to the question of the rules that
govern his choice” (Baurmann 1996, 325). Moreover, money is always
preconceived as the entry ticket into the realm of satisfaction. One must
possess it, if one wants to act at all, and one must always possess more of it,
if one wants to experience an increase in one’s happiness or satisfaction.
Also, the reverse has to hold true: as soon as one controls more money,
one’s own utility must unhesitatingly mount: Every
increase in income
invariably
shifts the budget line, i.e. the path through the utility mountain,
outward, i.e. in such a way, that not only higher regions of utility mountains
can be climbed, but also must be climbed.
This is the economic idea about “optimal choice:” Given the basic textbooks
assumptions about individual behavior, individual choice must, by necessity,
seek the highest possible indifference curve attainable within the pregiven
boundaries of a fixed income. Invariably, it comes to rest at point E (see
again figure 2).
Figure 2
9 One might hold the idea that at least the action of the entrepreneur or firm is represented by textbook economics in a different
manner. But this is systematically not the case, in as much as its theory of supply feeds back to the same way of representing human
action as its demand theory. It only replaces “indifference curves” with “isoquants” and the “budget constraints” with “isocost lines” as a
foundation for its theory of profit maximization. For the particularly abstruse assumptions that result from these presuppositions, see
Mirowski 1989.
74
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
We have yet to name a further assumption. Man must not only calculate all
the action possibilities open to him individually. He also has to be able to
compare them one to the other. Let us denominate three bundles of goods
A, B, and C, as economic textbooks usually do. When A is preferred to B, and
B to C, so the economic mainstream teaches, one must inevitably prefer A to
C, too. Otherwise one’s behavior is considered “kinky,” “irrational” or
“inconsistent,” and thus unworthy of further analysis. “What is usually
assumed is that consumers are reasonably consistent in their tastes and
actions that they do not flail around in unpredictable ways and do not
make themselves miserable by persistent error” (Samuelson,
Nordhaus 2005,
89). What is praised here as “reasonable” shows itself, upon closer
inspection, as clearly incompatible with fundamental human capacities.
Microeconomics does not simply claim to map and calculate actions in the
present moment, but pretends that it can prognosticate them. In order to do
so, it must, at least implicitly, preclude erratic changes” in choosing
behavior over an, in principle, endless span of time. Whoever prefers A to B
today, and B to C, must also prefer A to C in the future. In other words, the
indifference curves and thus the whole of the utility mountain are presumed
to be stable in time and space. Man is not supposed to ever alter his
preferences from one moment to another (see for instance Becker 1990).
Yet, an essential human property is thus negated and damned to
meaninglessness: the capacity to reflect on one’s own needs and
tastes and
from this background to rethink old decisions and to develop new
predilections. Any idea of the human potential to change oneself is missing
here, because this potential would shake the utility mountain as if an
earthquake occurred from within. It would shove aside and bend the
indifference curves, thus simply making any microeconomic calculations and
prognoses of human action null and void – precisely those calculations and
prognoses which are presumed in the textbooks without question (see
Graupe 2007, 59-68). Also, the inventions of new goods and thus the
development of new tastes and desires are completely cast into the dark.
But what actually allows textbook economics to ground its statements about
human beings? And what consequences result on this basis for the image of
75
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
man? Let us look again into the history of economics, about which the
textbooks of economics are so abstinently silent. Beyond the religious
grounding of the ‘laws’ of economics, as we have found with Smith and
Gossen, we find this: “The full truth is that the teaching of political
economics in the manner in which it is professionally practiced today, is in
the strict sense a mechanistic science, like none other than classical physics”
(Georgescu-Roegen 1971, 1). “One must study the laws of social cooperation
in exactly the same way as the physicist studies the laws of mechanics”
(Mises 1940, 2). Since the second half of the 19
th
century, mainstream
economics has literally taken up this demand. Back then, economists like
Irving Fisher, Léon Walras and W. Stanley Jevons began to transpose the
formulas of mechanics, especially in regard to its notion of energy and the
differential calculus, to the social world (see Mirowski 1989). In the course of
this process, they more or less consciously pasted the previously named
rigid assumptions about human beings in order to justify their own claims
and standards of scientificity. They began to think in terms of utility
mountains only to be able to describe human actions with the same
formulas with which physicists calculate the motion of particles. In order to
correspond to their own ideal of science, they simply translated the central
concepts of mechanics into economic concepts. “Utility“, as for instance
Irving Fisher made clear, was equated with “energy,” “marginal utility” with
“force,” the “commodity space” with (physical) “space,” and “negative utility”
with (physical) “labor” (1925, 85). Neo-classical theory and thus the current
crop of economics textbooks blindly absorbed this mechanistic frame of
concepts, without ever thinking about its presuppositions.
10
This also holds
true for the concepts of utility and profit maximization, with which
economists invariably describe all human activity, as though it were self
evident (see for instance Becker 1990). These concepts have also nothing to
do with a faithful observation of the social world, but instead with the
imperative to manufacture a social physics:
“‘Mecanique Sociale’ may one day take her place along with
‘Mecanique Celeste,’ throned upon the double-sided height of one
maximum principle, the supreme pinnacle of moral as of physical
science. As the movements of each particle, constrained or loose, in a
material cosmos are continually subordinated to one maximum sum-
total of accumulated energy, so the movements of each soul whether
selfishly isolated or linked sympathetically, may continually realising
the maximum energy of pleasure. (...) The invisible energy of
electricity is grasped by the marvelous methods of Lagrange, the
invisible
energy of pleasure may admit of a similar handling”
(Edgeworth 1881, 9-13).
For the image of man, it follows that men are to be pictured as machines,
because otherwise the economist would be incapable of carrying out his
calculations:
“The conception of Man as a pleasure machine may justify and
10 Clearly this accords with the fact that the early neo-classicals rarely were completely clear about the consequences of their theory for
the image of man (see Mirowski 1989).
76
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
facilitate the employment of mechanical terms and Mathematical
reasoning in social science” (ibid, 15, emphasis in the original).
We can see, here, that the economists’ image of man is simply not the result
of a long search for truth or description of human action as realistic as
possible, but just the by-product of a specific, if also mostly unconscious
ideal of science. It exists only because it suits the economist and his
scientific pretenses. According to Milton Friedman (1953, 14-15), who was a
Nobel Prize winner for economics, such an instrumental understanding is
basic to economic theory:
“Really important and significant hypotheses will be found to have
‘assumptions’ that are wildly inaccurate descriptive representations of
reality, and in general, the more significant the theory, the more
unrealistic the assumption (in this sense). (…) To be important,
therefore, a hypothesis must be descriptively false in its assumptions
(…) To put this point less paradoxically, the relevant question to ask
about the ‘assumptions’ of a theory is not whether they are
descriptively ‘realistic,’ for they never are, but whether they are
sufficiently good approximations for the purpose in hand (my
emphasis).
Walter Bagehot’s perspective on the image of human beings is even more
revealing (1885, 5):
“Of course we know that this is not so, that men are not like this; but
we assume it for simplicity's, sake, as a hypothesis. And this deceives
many excellent people, for from deficient education they have very
indistinct ideas what an abstract science is. More competent persons,
indeed, have understood that English Political Economists are not
speaking of real men, but of imaginary ones: not of men as we see
them, but of men as it is convenient to us to suppose they are” (my
emphasis).
Certainly, every scientific process of abstraction pursues a certain goal and,
in this sense, can be seen as interested. The textbooks all agree here, either
implicitly or explicitly: “the level of abstraction from reality depends on the
purpose for which the model is built” (Koutsoyiannis 1975, 1). Yet the actual
problem lies elsewhere. For the economic textbooks neither reflect the
implications of this simple scientific-theoretical insight, nor do they reveal
the purpose of their own highly specific abstractions. “Economic theory is a
method to understand human behavior,” said, for example, Robert Lucas,
the 1995 Nobel Prize winner in Economics, “in which we investigate
artificial, fictional people
imitations of robots, one might saythat are
constructed in order to
analyze the functionality of artificial economic orders
that are constituted from these actors” (quoted in Brodbeck 2009, 97, my
emphasis). Yet students do not learn to actively go through this imaginative
procedure, but are instead pushed to merely accept the results of these
procedures as seemingly irresistible ‘facts.’ They are not given the
77
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
possibility of explaining the extent to which they are misled to imagine
human beings as utility machines or robots; they simply learn to apply these
images tacitly in their first or second semesters. Their further study then
offers hardly any occasion to touch on this paradigmatic understanding ever
again. Rather, this understanding’s field of application is continuously
extended. What students learn to consider as ‘normal’ behavior for instance
in the regard to the choice between clothing and food, is, in higher courses,
uncritically transferred to all the situations of life: “we can”, it is taught,
“never
have enough of everything
,
and so must accept tradeoffs among the
different things we value including life, love, and the most trivial
pleasures
(Friedman 1996, 33, my emphasis). In brief, textbook economics
introduces students first to a highly selective picture of human beings, and
then persuades them to blindly apply this picture to all human behavior. Said
differently, it trains them into the already mentioned tradition of economic
imperialism, of which Gary Becker says (1993): “The horizons of economics
need to be expanded. Economists can talk not only about the demand for
cars, but also about matters such as the family, discrimination, and religion,
and about prejudice, guilt, and love.”
It is in this way that economic textbooks lead to gradually imagining every
individual social domain as a market in the sense of an aggregation of
individual utility machines. Whether we are dealing with marriage, church
attendance, or the working environment: the theory of the “perfect market”
always awakens the impression as if the multiplicity of these machines could
be organized in a giant clockwork with hardly any friction. The consumers’
individual utility maximizing behaviors lead to aggregate economic demand,
and the profit maximizing behaviors of individual firms to aggregate
economic supply. But what moves both in common is not the will of any
individual, but only and uniquely the “unconscious, automatic price
mechanism (Samuelson 1955, 39). “Who does the rationing? A planning
board? Congress? The president? No. The marketplace” (Samuelson,
Nordhaus 2005, 59). Students learn to imagine the whole world as if nothing
else mattered but “the rationing of the purse.”
“The power of the purse dictates the distribution of income and
consumption. Those with higher incomes end up with larger houses,
more clothing, and longer vacations. When backed up by cash
,
the
most urgently needs get fulfilled through the demand curve” (ibid,
60, my emphasis).
Thus, economic textbook science makes students to blindly accept an unjust
distribution of income as the starting point of all scientific reflection As
such, it encourages them to systematically as well as uncritically deal with
social inequality as an unquestionable fact. Yet this is not enough still. It
also cements, below the radar of awareness, a further form of fundamental
inequality. This form can be sussed out by asking one simple question: does
the economist actually
understand
himself
as a utility machine? Does he
consider
himself
a
homo oeconomicus
or does he only utilize this concept in
order to speak about other human beings? Actually, students learn to
perceive free market competition – the “rationing of the purse” – not from an
internal but from a kind of
external perspective
only. As though it were self-
78
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
explanatory, from the very first semester they learn to look upon the
economy with the help of graphs and formulas, as though they could,
through some curious process, place themselves outside of it. It seems as if
they were able to gain a ‘God’s eye’ perspective on people and markets.
Certainly, Adam Smith already (1759, IV.I.11) prizes this kind of observation:
“The perfection of police, the extension of trade and manufactures,
are noble and magnificent objects. The contemplation of them
pleases us, and we are interested in whatever can tend to advance
them. They make part of the great system of government, and the
wheels of the political machine seem to move with more harmony and
ease by means of them.”
At least, Smith still remarks that this distant observation is fundamentally
nothing other than an illusion. Explicitly he names it a “deception of nature”
impeding the true knowledge of commercial reality. For him, ultimate
knowledge is gained out of immediate experience, out of a sympathetic
position within human society, not from an outside observer’s standpoint.
(cp. ibid, IV.I). Yet ultimately Smith dubs this deception good, in as much as
it promises to satisfy a goal: “And it is well that nature imposes upon us in
this manner. It is this deception which rouses and keeps in continual motion
the industry of mankind” (ibid). Only in the position of distant observation
can the human spirit be formed into an instrument of unlimited striving for
growth, and because of this Smith tells us to approve this speculative
position. Economics textbooks blindly follow this command, without making
this underlying instrumental understanding explicit or even critically
thinking it through. Thus, the students are apprenticed, silently and without
being presented any alternative, in a pitiless positioning outside of economic
affairs. At the same time, they are trained to negate any kind of source of
knowledge that may spring from conscious participation in these affairs. It is
a matter of what Alfred Schütz (quoted in Brodbeck 2009, 102) observes
without intending any critical undertone:
The social scientist “is not involved in the observed situation, which
interests him not practically, but only cognitively. It is not the theater
of his activities, but only the object of his contemplation. He does not
operate in it and has no vital interest in the outcome of his actions;
no hope and fear are bound together with the consequences of his
acts. He looks at the social world with the same cool equilibrium with
which the natural scientist follows the events in his laboratory.”
This is the background that allows us to explain why, for instance,
Samuelson (1966, 64) conceives people simply as the “guinea-pigs” of his
analysis. Yet in one essential point, Schütz’s remark still falls short. For his
proper position outside of society does not simply serve the economist as a
place of contemplation. Rather, his science offers him the opportunity to
actively intervene in the sphere of economic affairs as if coming from the
outside. Already, Adam Smith praises this in the direct continuation of the
above cited passage (1759, IV.I.11):
79
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
“We take pleasure in beholding the perfection of so beautiful and
grand a system, and we are uneasy till we remove any obstruction
that can in the least disturb or encumber the regularity of its
motions” (my emphasis).
“The purpose of theoretical science is to control the real world” (Menger
1883, 33). Even Mankiw (2006, 29) understands the economist, in truth, not
as a disinterested researcher, but as a social engineer, who should guide the
destiny of the economic machine:
“Economists like to strike the pose of a scientist. I know this, because I
often do it myself. When I teach undergraduates, I very consciously
describe the field of economics as a science, so no student would
start the course thinking he was embarking on some squishy
academic endeavor. (…) Having recently spent two years in
Washington as an economic adviser [of Georg W. BushS.G] at a time
when the U.S. economy was struggling to pull out of a recession, I am
reminded that the subfield of macroeconomics was born not as a
science but more as a type of engineering
.
God put macroeconomists
on earth not to propose and test elegant theories
but to solve
practical problems
(my emphasis).
“Cool heads at the service of warm hearts”
(Samuelson, Nordhaus 2005, 7):
Students are not only guided to the “dispassionate development and testing
of theories” (Mankiw 2001, 20-21) but also attuned to the role of
experimenters
,
who can manipulate other human beings, markets or even
whole nations according to their own will. “The economy is a system without
a steering wheel,” Samuelson claims (1948, 255). And the textbooks leave
no doubt as to the fact that the economically educated elite not only have to
put the steering wheel in place, but have to firmly grip it:
“However, with understanding usually
comes the ability to predict and
to control
,
and this has been the case in microeconomics. The
concepts and relationships economists have developed
provide the
basis for the design of policies by governments wishing to influence
the outcome of this process
,
or alternatively for the critique of the
actions governments may take” (Gravelle, Rees 1981, 1, my
emphasis).
To put this in terms of another economics metaphor: if we think of
commerce as a game or play, whose rules are inalterably given to the actors
(see for instance Friedman 1971), then it is merely a step to get to this
conclusion: “The economists determine the rules of the play” (Kyrer 2005, 7).
This shows the problematic of a twofold, and one could even say split image
of man that the standard economics textbooks propagate, but do not reflect
upon: on the one side most humans are considered utility machines, robots
or guinea pigs. On the other side, a few other human beings exist, who, as
80
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
part
of the elite, can steer and control those utility machines, robots, and
guinea pigs. The question of whether such elite can, at least, be entrusted
with the common good may appear in any case as a subsequent question
only. But basically, this question is posed as rarely in the framework of
standard economics research as the question of whether the systematic
difference between game strategies and game rules, players and referees
makes any sense in the first place (see Graupe 2011). In contrast to pure
textbook economics, a researcher like Patrick Gunning nevertheless puts
into explicit words the basic logic of the science’s two-fold image of man
(1988, 168):
Homo economicus must always maximize his financial wealth in
situations specified by the economist. The a priori being can create
his own situations. He can even become an economist. To put this
still differently, Homo economicus is a puppet or robot that is
programmed by the economist. The a priori being is his own
controller. It is the a priori being who encompasses the humanness in
the human being. Economic models must be peopled by individuals
who are programmed by the modelbuilder. They cannot be peopled
by a priori beings. The usefulness of models lies in the fact that they
enable the modelbuilder to contrast (1) what he can, through
reflection, come to know about the nature of the a priori being with
(2) the puppet or robot that he employs in his model. In this way, he
can isolate the inventive, creative, programming, controlling, alert
aspects of human nature.”
5 A Prospective View
The economics curriculum, under the surface of awareness, shapes an image
of man, which splits society into mere cogs in the ‘machine’ of the economy
on the one side and omnipotent social engineers on the other side. The
latter are portrayed as if they could steer this machine from the outside
according to their own precepts. Thus, the curriculum gives the impression
as if homo oeconomicus inexorable striving for utility and gain
maximization could always be held within bounds by sensible managerial
precepts. In generating this combination, it completely obscures one
essential question: what kind of game is being played when the elite learns
to recognize itself in the idea of striving for gain and personal utility, on the
one side, while at the same time learning tacitly to locate themselves outside
of the competitive order so as to perform as its judge and leader in the
name of their own goals? An idea of such omnipotence contrasts with the
danger that young people will only silently identify with homo oeconomicus
and thus learn to count themselves among the impotent part of society only,
who find delight merely in consumption, but have no ability to actively shape
the world around them as well as their selves. It is possible, that the image
of man of the economics curriculum misleads students into constantly
wavering between these positions of omnipotence and impotence; unable to
find a middle way between these extremes. It has been my concern to show
81
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
and outline this fundamental problem, how it arose and against what
background it stands.
As for viable alternatives, I must leave this question
open at this point. Yet let us go at least this far: a first step, in my own
experience of teaching, consists in encouraging students to become
conscious of the many ways in which the economic “missionaries” and their
“bibles” can be disputed. A critical course through the history of economic
ideas empowers them to be able to find their own actual point of view and
the reasons for it. “The difficulty lies, not in the new ideas, but in escaping
from the old ones, which ramify, for those brought up as most of us have
been, into every corner of our minds” (Keynes cited in Keen 2010, xii). Yet
this escape is only possible for those ideas that one really is aware of. At
least we should (re)introduce the discipline’s intellectual history, as much as
the explicit reflection on the economics image of man, into economics
teaching. This could serve as a first step in order that young generations are
no longer brought up as the slaves of dead economists and – lets add to the
often cited image from Keynes – dead or living textbook authors.
References
Adler, Moshe. 2010. Economics for the Rest of Us. Debunking the Science
that Makes Life Dismal. New York.
Bagehot, Walter. 1885. Postulates of English Political Economy. New York,
London.
Baurman, Martin. 1996. Der Markt der Tugend. Tübingen.
Becker, Gary S. 1990. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago.
Becker, Gary S. 1993. Economic Imperialism. In: Religion & Liberty, Vol. 3,
No. 2. (http://www.acton.org/de/pub/religion-liberty/volume-3-number-
2/economic-imperialism) accessed May 28, 2012.
Brodbeck, Karl-Heinz. 1996. Erfolgsfaktor Kreativität. Die Zukunft unserer
Marktwirtschaft. Darmstadt.
Brodbeck, Karl-Heinz. 2009. Die Herrschaft des Geldes. Geschichte und
Systematik. Darmstadt.
Edgeworth, Francis Y. 1881. Mathematical Psychics. An Essay on the
Application of Mathematics to the Moral Sciences. London.
Felderer, Bernhard; Homburg, Stefan. 1999. Makroökonomik und neue
Makroökonomik. Berlin.
Fisher, Irving. 1925. Mathematical Investigations into the Theory of Value
and Prices. New Haven.
Fleck, Ludwig. 1980. Die Entstehung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache.
Frankfurt/Main.
Friedman, David. 1999. Der ökonomische Code. Wie wirtschaftliches
Denken unser Handeln bestimmt. Frankfurt/Main.
Friedman, Milton. 1953. Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago.
Friedman, Milton. 1971. Kapitalismus und Freiheit. Stuttgart.
82
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas. 1971. The Entropy Law and the Economic
Process. Cambridge, London.
Gossen, Herrmann Heinrich. 1854. Die Entwicklung der Gesetze des
menschlichen Verkehrs und der daraus fließenden Regeln für menschliches
Handeln. Braunschweig.
Gottesman, Aron; Ramrattan, Lall; Szenberg, Michael. 2005. Samuelson’s
Economics: The Continuing Legacy. In: The Quarterly Journal of Austrian
Economics, Vol. 8, No. 2, 95-105.
Graupe, Silja. 2007. The Basho of Economics. An Intercultural Analysis of
the Process of Economics. Heusenstamm.
Graupe, Silja. 2011. Standing on Mount Lu. How Economics Has Come to
Dominate Our View of Culture and Sustainability – and Why It Shouldn’t. In:
Banse, Gerhard; Nelson, Gordon;GrauGra Parodi, Oliver, eds. Sustainable
Development. The Cultural Perspective. Berlin, 251-77.
Gravelle, Hugh; Ress, Ray. 1981. Microeconomics. London, NewYork.
Gunning, Patrick J. 1988. Professor Caldwell on Ludwig von Mises'
Methodology. In: The Review of Austrian Economics, Vol. 3, 163-176.
Häring, Norbert. 2010. Markt und Macht. Was Sie schon immer über die
Wirtschaft wissen wollten, aber bisher nicht erfahren sollten. Stuttgart.
Hedtke, Reinhold. 2008. Ökonomische Denkweisen. Eine Einführung.
Schwalbach/Ts.
Hill, Rod; Myatt, Tony. 2010. The Economics Anti-Textbook. London, New
York.
Kirchgässner, Gebhard. 1991. Homo Oeconomicus. Das ökonomische
Modell individuellen Verhaltens und seine Anwendungen in den Wirtschafts-
und Sozialwissenschaften. Tübingen.
Keen, Steve. 2010. Debunking Economics. The Naked Emperor of the Social
Sciences. London, New York.
Koutsoyiannis, Anna. 1975. Modern Microeconomics. London, Basingstoke.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1996. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago.
London.
Kyrer, Alfred. 2005. Neue politische Ökonomie. München.
Mankiw, N. Gregory. 2005. Principles of Economics. Orlando.
Mankiw, N. Gregory. 2006. The Macroeconomist as Scientist and Engineer.
In: Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 20, No. 4, 29-46.
Meinberg, Eckhard. 1980. Das Menschenbild der modernen
Erziehungswissenschaft. Darmstadt.
Menger, Carl. 1883. Untersuchungen über die Methode der
Socialwissenschaften und der Politischen Oekonomie insbesondere. Leipzig.
Mirowski, Philip. 1989. More Heat than Light. Economics as Social Physics,
Physics as Nature’s Economics. Cambridge.
Mises, Ludwig von. 1940. Nationalökonomie. Theorie des Handelns und des
83
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
Wirtschaftens. Genf.
Nasar, Sylvia. 14. März 1995. A Hard Act to Follow? In: The New York
Times. (http://www.nytimes.com/1995/03/14/business/a-hard-act-to-
follow-here-goes.html?src=pm) accessed July 4, 2011.
Pearce, Kerry A.; Hoover, Kevin D. 1995. After the Revolution. Paul
Samuelson and the Textbook Keynesian Model. In: History of Political
Economy, Vol. 27, Supplement, 183-216.
Polanyi, Michael. 1966. The Tacit Dimension. New York.
Samuelson, Paul. 1966. Consumption Theory in Terms of Revealed
Preference. In: Stiglitz, Joseph E., ed. The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul
A. Samuelson, Vol. I. Cambridge (Mass.), 64-74.
Samuelson, Paul. 1948. Economics. 1. Edition. Boston et al.
Samuelson, Paul. 1955. Volkswirtschaftslehre. Eine Einführung. Second
Edition. Köln.
Samuelson, Paul; Nordhaus, William D. 2005. Economics. Eighteenth
Edition. Boston et
al.
Schumpeter, Joseph. 1908. Das Wesen und der Hauptinhalt der
theoretischen Nationalökonomie. Leipzig.
Schumpeter, Joseph. 1942. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy. New
York.
Scousen, Mark. 1997. The Perseverance of Paul Samuelson’s Economics. In:
Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 11, No. 2, 137-152.
Smith, Adam. 1759. Theory of Moral Sentiments. London.
Sraffa, Piero. 1926. The Law of Returns under Competitive Conditions. In:
Economic Journal, Vol. 40, 538-550.
Statistisches Bundesamt. 2010. Technical Report “Studierende an
Hochschulen – FS 11 R. 4.1.” Wiesbaden.
Stocker, Florian. 2002. Spaß mit Mikro. Einführung in die Mikroökonomik.
Stuttgart.
Ulrich, Peter. 1991. Der kritische Adam Smith – im Spannungsfeld zwischen
sittlichem Gefühl und ethischer Vernunft. In: Meyer-Faje, Arnold; Ulrich;
Peter, eds. Der andere Adam Smith. Beiträge zur Neubestimmung von
Ökonomie als politischer Ökonomie. Bern-Stuttgart, 145-190.
Varian, Hal R. 2007. Grundzüge der Mikroökonomie. München, Wien.
Wall Street Journal. 13. Dezember 2009. Remembering Paul Samuelson.
(http://blogs.wsj.com/economics/2009/12/13/remembering-paul-
samuelson/) accessed July 28, 2011.
Walras, Léon. 1969. Elements of Pure Economics. New York.
Walstad, William B.; Watts, Michael; Bosshardt, William. 1998. The Principles
of Economics Textbook. History, Content, and Use. In: Walstad, William B.;
Saunders, Phillip, eds. Teaching Undergraduate Economics. A Handbook for
Instructors. Boston.
84
Volume 11, Number 2, © JSSE 2012 ISSN 1618-5293
Weinstein, Michael. December 13, 2009. Paul A. Samuelson, Economist,
Dies at 94. In: The New York Times.
(
http://www.nytimes.com/2009/12/14/business/economy/14samuelson.ht
ml?pagewanted=1
)
accessed July 28, 2011.
85
... Economics education has long been dominated by a neoliberal and positivist paradigm that impedes sustainable development goals by promoting a narrow, decontextualized, and hyperrational understanding of human behavior and economic activity guided by individual utility and profit motives [1,2]. This ontological foundation has shaped the way in which economics is taught and has influenced policies that derive from economic knowledge imparted in the classroom, devoid of social considerations and ecological concerns [3][4][5][6][7]. ...
... This is due to a prevailing positivist epistemological approach that seeks 'objective' knowledge and hermetically separates positive and normative positions in favor of the former, resulting in a methodological monism characterized by an absence of ethical and social considerations [1,2,19,20]. Given the proclaimed 'value-free' economics approach (see, e.g., [21]), the pursuit of logical positivism implies a subjective view of value, an (over-)emphasis on demand-side analyses, and a mathematically driven and anti-metaphysical mechanization of economics towards utility through self-interest [1]. ...
... In contrast, logical positivism degenerated utility as a tool for analyzing choice behavior into a description of consumer preferences devoid of ethical considerations [23,24]. This methodological stance, coupled with an epistemological approach of abstract mathematical deduction, reflects key aspects of current economic orthodoxy [1,2,25]. Value judgments are excluded, and interpersonal comparisons of utility are reduced to the Pareto principle, which hampers debates about (global) social justice, since material improvements for one person are only recognized as such if no other person is made worse off [26,27]. ...
Article
Full-text available
This conceptual paper proposes a posthumanist practice approach as an alternative onto-epistemological framework for economics education. It applies a critical literature review to examine the positivist and neoliberal foundations of mainstream economics education. We find that the prevailing economics education promotes a decontextualized and hyperrational perspective on economic phenomena and human behavior, which impedes sustainable development goals by pushing pressing socio-ecological challenges to the periphery. In response, we propose a posthumanist practice approach grounded in social practice theory, which aims to provide a more holistic, contextualized, nature-immanent, and materially mediated understanding of human behavior and economic realities. By emphasizing practical learning through knowledgeable doing, relational entanglement, and multisensory interactions, the posthumanist practice approach recognizes economic knowledge to be situated, pluralistic, and shaped by interdependent human/nonhuman relations. This opens up a more ethical and relational way of understanding, learning, and acting that helps to reconnect the social with the natural and to align economics education with the goals of sustainable development. In order to apply a posthumanist onto-epistemological foundation for economics education, we provide guidance by outlining appropriate pedagogical methods, such as diversifying learning environments, embracing community and nature engagement as well as service learning, and revising the role of educators.
... While Edward Lazear is not representative for all orthodox economists, one can say that orthodoxy is on the level of theory a monist enterprise as it is above all defined by its very method ( Dow 2004Dow , Mäki 2009). While this methodological monism must not hold true for the whole discourse ( Davis 2006, Hands 2013), it seems to fit the way economics is taught to young scholars ( Graupe 2012). The lack of historical awareness and awareness of alternative perspectives often leads to a degeneration of young scholars into dogmatists, if they do not take voluntary extra courses ( Hodgson 2001, Ötsch & Kapellar 2010, Graupe 2012). ...
... While this methodological monism must not hold true for the whole discourse ( Davis 2006, Hands 2013), it seems to fit the way economics is taught to young scholars ( Graupe 2012). The lack of historical awareness and awareness of alternative perspectives often leads to a degeneration of young scholars into dogmatists, if they do not take voluntary extra courses ( Hodgson 2001, Ötsch & Kapellar 2010, Graupe 2012). Among heterodox economists who question the dominance of neoclassical economics, nearly all combinations exist. ...
Working Paper
Full-text available
... While the concept of a self-interested and rationally optimizing homo economicus still seems to dominate standard economics textbooks and curricula (e.g., Bäuerle, 2021;Bäuerle, Pühringer, & Ö tsch, 2020;Graupe, 2012Graupe, , 2020, most other social sciences dealing with human behavior have long recognized that humans are not only egoistic and competitive but also altruistic, prosocial, and highly cooperative beings (e.g., Atkins, Wilson, & Hayes, 2019;Batson & Powell, 2003;Bregman, Manton, Moore, & Trans, 2020;Hare & Woods, 2020;Schlaile, Klein, & Böck, 2018;Schlaile, Mueller, Schramm, & Pyka, 2018). Yet, this fact alone is obviously not enough to explain why some people have been more prone than others to engage in behaviors that can help to keep COVID-19 at bay. ...
Article
During the COVID-19 pandemic, contact tracing apps such as the German Corona-Warning-App (CWA) were introduced to facilitate contact tracing of infected individuals with the aim of breaking chains of infection. Therefore, using a contact tracing app is beneficial to society as a whole. Even though this is a good cause, the rather reluctant use of the CWA in the beginning indicated that the pains (e.g., privacy concerns) obviously outweighed the gains (helping others) at the level of the individual user. Thus, in order to identify what lies behind the gain of this app and how it can be promoted, we were interested in the individual's moral perspective (helping others) on the app. We expected a positive relation between CWA download and moral intensity derived from (i) the magnitude or seriousness of consequences, (ii) social norms about app use, (iii) the individual proximity to COVID-19 cases, and (iv) the probability of the app's positive effect. Using a heterogeneous German sample of N = 1,454, we found a strong influence of moral intensity on app download. Furthermore, a manipulation of moral intensity among non-users led to a higher number of downloads in a follow-up study (N = 662) as compared to the population. Our results show possibilities to enhance the adoption of contact tracing apps and potentially other apps for the common good in the population.
... Orthodox Economics of the 20th century put a particular emphasis on methodological uniformity and unification (Graupe, 2012;Mäki, 2009a). In the singular of 'the economic approach' or introductory chapters like 'how to think like an economist' this orthodoxy still echoes in some publications and in most economics textbooks (Lazear, 2000;Samuelson and Nordhaus, 2009;Mankiw, 2014;Lazear, 2015). ...
... As a consequence, economics adapted a very specific scientific attitude towards society starting from the end of the 18 th century (Graupe, 2007;Don Ross, 2010). It has come to define itself by virtue of its method (Mäki, 2009a;Graupe, 2012) and thereby conforms with a mechanistic explanatory model (Hempel-Oppenheim, 1948), that is widely contested for the domain of social science (Hedström et al., 2010). The aspiration is to isolate mechanisms through positive analysis that are the basis for normative judgements of political interventions. 2 A successful isolated mechanism seems to make methodological reflection obsolete: The moment we had a working description of gravity, we had a "true picture" of it. ...
... Eine besondere Rolle im Prozess der Standardisierung und damit einer weitreichenden Margi- nalisierung der Heterodoxie nehmen in dieser Beziehung die ökonomische Lehre und dabei ins- besondere international vereinheitlichte Lehrbücher ein (vgl. etwa Bäuerle 2017;Graupe 2012a;Peukert 2018aPeukert , 2018bvan Treeck/Urban 2016;Decker et al. 2018). ...
Book
Full-text available
This is the first qualitative examination of student’s perception of undergraduate economics curricula in the German-speaking area. Based on the Documentary Method we conducted and analyzed group discussions at five of the most important economics departments in Germany and Austria. In doing so we reconstructed four basic orientations that can be labelled ‘typical’ for a student’s handling of an undergraduate economics study program. Contrary to a mainly theoretical discourse around the Status quo of academic economic education (monism vs. pluralism of schools, theories, methods and disciplines), our results suggest to further take into account the institutional and structural contexts of economic education (Bologna reform). Furthermore we urge for an intensified debate on the current state of methods of performance assessment and the curricular organization. The dominance of mathematical methods as well as a lack of real world orientation are topics already discussed within the literature and are being empirically backed by our results.
Article
The article investigates the contentious relationship between economics and social studies and considers the extent to which the dominant narratives and methodological approaches in economics are compatible with ambitious views of equity in civics education. Tensions between social studies and economics are described. These include differing views on the role of government, democracy, and equality, as well as economics’ “imperious mindset” (Heilbroner, 1991, p. 463). After identifying these tensions, the article devotes significant space to recent scholarship that can bridge the civics-economics divide and introduce the kind of equity work being called for in social studies education.
Chapter
Was lernen Studierende im Unterricht über die Wirtschaft? Wie setzen Studierende der Ökonomie ihr Studium um? Wie geht es Ihnen dabei? Was erleben sie? Was macht das Studium mit ihnen? Welche Wirkungen werden damit erzielt? Wie stehen ihre Erfahrungen und die Inhalte ihres Studiums im Verhältnis zu ihren Motivationen Ökonomie zu studieren?
Article
This article outlines core tenets of feminist economics and contrasts these tenets with traditional neoclassical economic assumptions about human nature, value, markets, inequality, and power. Further, it challenges the Voluntary National Content Standards in Economics and the C3 Framework for their exclusion of any perspective beyond the neoclassical paradigm while exposing the deleterious consequences of this paradigm, including its promotion of neoliberal policies; its opposition to democratic ideals; its exclusion of topics related to race, class, and gender; and its problematic assertions about human welfare. The article concludes with alternative ways of thinking about economics that might encourage teachers to question the prevailing neoclassical dominant narrative with a feminist counter narrative.
Article
This article examines the theoretical assumptions underlying K-12 economic curriculum and the consequences of this curriculum for citizenship education and democracy. Specifically, the article discusses scholarship related to the critique of neoclassic economic theory’s role in influencing the Voluntary National Content Standards in Economics and the trickle-down effects into state standards and textbooks. From the literature, the author uncovers two main critiques of neoclassicism: that neoclassic theory is unrealistic and impersonal. Neoclassic theory has enormous consequences for the civic mission of social studies. The author investigates the extent to which neoclassical theory makes for good citizenship and is desirable for a democratic society.
Book
In the parlance of modern Japanese philosophy, the term Basho denotes a field of experience underlying all conceptions of reality, while remaining itself conceptually ungraspable. The Basho of Economics, then, refers to the economy's hidden experiential ground, which has never been explicitly scrutinized, as such, by mainstream economics. We uncover this ground by discerning the tacit presuppositions of classical and neo-classical theories from the perspective of modern Japanese philosophy. In particular, we draw attention to the traditional atomist assumptions implicit in their equilibrium-centered models. By breaking through these assumptions, we reconstruct the economy as a functional and relational world of habitual and creative activity outside of the scope of mechanical laws.
Article