ArticlePublisher preview available
To read the full-text of this research, you can request a copy directly from the author.

Abstract

Peter Hanks and Scott Soames both defend pragmatic solutions to the problem of the unity of the proposition. According to them, what ties together Tim and baldness in the singular proposition expressed by ‘Tim is bald’ is an act of the speaker (or thinker) : the act of predicating baldness of Tim. But Soames construes that act as force neutral and noncommittal while, for Hanks, it is inherently assertive and committal. Hanks answers the Frege–Geach challenge by arguing that, in complex sentences, the force inherent in the content of an embedded sentence is cancelled. Indrek Reiland has recently objected to Hanks’s proposal that it faces a dilemma: either force cancellation dissolves the unity of the proposition secured by the cancelled act of assertion (and Hanks’s proposal does not work), or Hanks’s proposal reduces to Soames’s. In this paper, I respond to Reiland by offering an analysis of force cancellation which gets rid of the alleged dilemma. The proposal is based on a set of distinctions from speech act theory : between two senses of ’force’, two types of act, and two types of context. The role of simulation in force cancellation is emphasized, and connections drawn to broader issues such as the evolution of complex language.
Synthese (2019) 196:1403–1424
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1223-9
S.I.: UNITY OF STRUCTURED PROPOSITIONS
Force cancellation
François Recanati1
Received: 27 November 2015 / Accepted: 15 September 2016 / Published online: 7 October 2016
© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016
Abstract Peter Hanks and Scott Soames both defend pragmatic solutions to the prob-
lem of the unity of the proposition. According to them, what ties together Tim and
baldness in the singular proposition expressed by ‘Tim is bald’ is an act of the speaker
(or thinker) : the act of predicating baldness of Tim. But Soames construes that act
as force neutral and noncommittal while, for Hanks, it is inherently assertive and
committal. Hanks answers the Frege–Geach challenge by arguing that, in complex
sentences, the force inherent in the content of an embedded sentence is cancelled.
Indrek Reiland has recently objected to Hanks’s proposal that it faces a dilemma:
either force cancellation dissolves the unity of the proposition secured by the can-
celled act of assertion (and Hanks’s proposal does not work), or Hanks’s proposal
reduces to Soames’s. In this paper, I respond to Reiland by offering an analysis of
force cancellation which gets rid of the alleged dilemma. The proposal is based on
a set of distinctions from speech act theory : between two senses of ’force’, two
types of act, and two types of context. The role of simulation in force cancellation is
emphasized, and connections drawn to broader issues such as the evolution of complex
language.
Keywords Unity of the proposition ·Illocutionary force ·Locutionary act ·
Polyphony ·Echoic uses ·Cancellation ·Frege–Geach problem ·Embedding ·
Simulation ·Language and theory of mind
BFrançois Recanati
frecanati@gmail.com
1Institut Jean Nicod, Ecole Normale Supérieure, 29 rue d’Ulm, 75005 Paris, France
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
Article
Full-text available
To address the Frege-Geach objection, proponents of the ‘forceful’ version of the act-theoretic approach to propositions appeal to the idea of force cancellation. How is that idea to be understood? In this paper, three models of force cancellation are discussed (and their shortcomings pointed out): the mereological model, the Brentanian model, and the – intermediate – transmutation model. Extant versions of these models are meant to account for force cancellation in speech, but they do not easily extend to force cancellation in thought. To overcome that limitation, a psychologistic version of the transmutation model is put forward, based on ‘simulation theory’.
Article
The aim of this paper is to show that central problems arising in the current debate about the nature of inferring can be solved by means of a predicative account of inference, which is inspired by Peter Hanks’s (2007 Hanks, P. 2007. “The Content-Force Distinction.” Philosophical Studies 134: 141–164.[Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar], 2011 Hanks, P. 2011. “Structured Propositions as Types.” Mind; A Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy 120 (477): 11–52.[Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar], 2015 Hanks, P. 2015. Propositional Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.[Crossref] , [Google Scholar]) act-type theory of propositions. According to Hanks, the activity of judging is not the activity of assenting to an already structured content, but the activity of predicating a property of an object. The unity of the proposition is constituted by this very activity, and propositions are understood as types of predicative acts. I will argue that we are able to formulate a new account of the activity of inferring on the basis of Hanks’s account of judgement and proposition. We are able to take an inference itself to be a complex kind of predicative activity if we understand the premises and the conclusion of an argument as judgements in Hanks’s sense. A valid (or invalid) argument can then be described as a type of predicative act.
Article
Full-text available
Over the course of the past ten-plus years, Peter Hanks and Scott Soames have developed detailed versions of Act-Based views of propositions which operate with the notions of reference to objects, indicating properties, predication, and judgment (or entertaining). In this paper I discuss certain foundational aspects of the Act-Based approach having to do with the relations between these notions. In particular, I argue for the following three points. First, that the approach needs both an atomistically understood thin notion of reference, a bare act of thinking of o, as well as a more involved notion, something like making o a target of predication. Second, that the acts of thinking of o and indication of the property of being F are in no sense parts of the acts of predication of being F of o and judgment that o is F. Rather, the former are simply necessary preconditions for the performance of the latter. The acts of predication or judgment are emphatically not structured sequences of separate acts but unities in and of themselves. Finally, that we should understand the Act-Based theorists’ claim that to predicate is to judge as the claim that judgment can be reductively analyzed in terms of predication. Furthermore, while predication is metaphysically a multiple relation between a predicator, a target, and the property predicated, judgment is a monadic property, just one that has propositional content.
Article
Full-text available
In the debate on the Frege Point, the ‘Spinoza thesis’ is often mentioned. But Leibniz is kept out. Yet, on this topic, Spinoza and Leibniz shared a fairly similar goal. They sought to root the assertive force in the conceptual activity of the subject. But Leibniz, unlike Spinoza, wanted also to build a coherent theory of propositions. Propositions are for him always provided with assertive force. But what is affirmed by the propositions of logic is only a possibility – the possibility of the conceptual link they express. Stronger assertions require something more: a mark of actuality, a modal symbol in logic or the use of notae or particulae which belong to natural languages. Leibniz does not modify his conception of propositions in his “ analysis particularum ”. He tries to understand what we do when we use them in various contexts. The Leibnizian proposition is neutral, but it is not forceless. Since it is not forceless, there is no need to appeal to an external act or to a judgment. Leibniz thinks, like most of the authors of the Aristotelian tradition, that the proposition contains the act of judging. Since it is neutral, there is no need to venture into the many difficulties raised by cancellation to account for the force/content relation in the conditional, disjunctive or fictional contexts.
Article
Several philosophers advance substantive theories of propositions to deal with several issues they raise in connection with a concern with a long pedigree in philosophy, the problem of the unity of propositions. The qualification ‘substantive’ is meant to contrast with ‘minimal’ or ‘deflationary’ – roughly, views that reject that propositions have a hidden nature, worth investigating. Substantive views appear to create spurious problems by characterizing propositions in ways that make them unfit to perform their theoretical jobs. I will present in this light some critical points against Hanks’ (2015 Hanks, Peter. 2015. Propositional Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.[Crossref] , [Google Scholar], 2019 Hanks, Peter. 2019. “On Cancellation.” Synthese 196: 1385–1402. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/ /s11229-016-1260-4.[Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar]) act-theoretic view, and Recanati’s [2019. “Force Cancellation.” Synthese 196: 1403–1424. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1223-9.] recent elaboration of Hanks’ notion of cancellation. Both Hanks and Recanati, I’ll argue, rely on problematic conceptions of fiction and pretense.
Article
Full-text available
Many philosophers believe in things, propositions, which are the things that we believe, assert etc., and which are the contents of sentences. The act‐type theory of propositions is an attempt to say what propositions are, to explain how we stand in relations to them, and to explain why they are true or false. The core idea of the act‐type theory is that propositions are types of acts of predication. The theory is developed in various ways to offer explanations of the important properties of propositions. I present the core idea of the theory, and some developments of it. I discuss the relationship between the theory and the content–force distinction. I also present an important type of objection that has been raised to the explanations offered by the act‐type theory.
Article
Full-text available
Building on their well-known act theory of propositions, Soames and Hanks have proposed a theory of what it is for sentences to express propositions, thereby answering a central question about the foundations of semantics. The basic idea is that for a sentence to express a proposition in a language is for speakers of the language to use the sentence to perform the act that is the proposition. I argue that this general account of expression fails to explain how incorrect usage is possible, how what sentences express differs from what they implicate, how unused sentences can express propositions, how compositional meanings are possible, and how to specify who the speakers of L are without circularity. I go on to show how these things can be explained within the structured cognitive proposition framework.
Article
Full-text available
Hanks (Propositional content, Oxford University Press, New York, NY, 2015) develops a theory of propositions as speech-act types. Because speech acts play a role in the contents themselves, the view overturns Frege’s force/content distinction, and as such, faces the challenge of explaining how propositions embed under logical operators like negation. The attempt to solve this problem has lead Hanks and his recent commentators to adopt theoretically exotic resources, none of which, we argue, is ultimately successful. The problem is that although there are three different ways of negating the sentence “Mary’s card is an ace”, current speech-act theories of propositions can only accommodate two of them. We distinguish between (1) “It is false that Mary’s card is an ace” (sentence negation), (2) “Mary’s card is a non-ace” (predicate negation), and (3) “Mary’s card is not an ace” (content negation) and show that Hanks and his commentators cannot explain content negation. We call this Hanks’ Negation Problem. The problem is significant because content negation is the negation required for logic. Fortunately, we think there is a natural way for Hanks to accommodate content negation (and all the other logical operators) as successive acts of predication. The view solves Hanks’ Negation Problem with only resources internal to Hanks’ own view.
Article
Full-text available
According to act theories, propositions are structured cognitive act‐types. Act theories appear to make propositions inherently representational and truth‐evaluable, and to provide solutions to familiar problems with alternative theories, including Frege’s and Russell’s problems, and the third‐realm and unity problems. Act theories have critical problems of their own, though: acts as opposed to their objects are not truth evaluable, not structured in the right way, not expressed by sentences, and not the objects of propositional attitudes. I show how identifying propositions with other cognitive event‐types, namely thoughts, has the perceived virtues of act theories without the defects.
Chapter
This essay sketches an approach to speech acts in which mood does not semantically determine illocutionary force. The conventional content of mood determines the semantic type of the clause in which it occurs, and, given the nature of discourse, that type most naturally lends itself to a particular type of speech act, i.e. one of the three basic types of language game moves'making an assertion (declarative), posing a question (interrogative), or proposing to one's addressee(s) the adoption of a goal (imperative). There is relative consensus about the semantics of two of these, the declarative and interrogative; and this consensus view is entirely compatible with the present proposal about the relationship between the semantics and pragmatics of grammatical mood. Hence, the proposal is illustrated with the more controversial imperative.