ArticlePDF AvailableLiterature Review

Mind-wandering as spontaneous thought: a dynamic framework

Authors:

Abstract

Most research on mind-wandering has characterized it as a mental state with contents that are task unrelated or stimulus independent. However, the dynamics of mind-wandering - how mental states change over time - have remained largely neglected. Here, we introduce a dynamic framework for understanding mind-wandering and its relationship to the recruitment of large-scale brain networks. We propose that mind-wandering is best understood as a member of a family of spontaneous-thought phenomena that also includes creative thought and dreaming. This dynamic framework can shed new light on mental disorders that are marked by alterations in spontaneous thought, including depression, anxiety and attention deficit hyperactivity disorder.
As we take … a general view of the wonderful stream of
our consciousness, what strikes us first is this different
pace of its parts. Like a bird’s life, it seems to be made
of an alternation of flights and perchings … The
resting-places … can be held before the mind for an
indefinite time … The places of flight … obtain between
the matters contemplated in the periods of comparative
rest. William James, Principles of Psychology, 1890.
The ‘flights’ and ‘perchings’ of our thought, so poeti-
cally described by William James1, are as mysterious to
us as they are intimately familiar. To James, a perching
represented a mental state including contents such as
imaginings, worries and inner speech, whereas a flight
represented the ‘movement’ from one mental state to
another. Although the forefather of psychology empha-
sized the spontaneous and dynamic nature of thoughts,
research in the century that followed left these topics
largely unexplored.
In the past 15years, mind-wandering and spontane-
ous thought have become prominent topics in cognitive
psychology and neuroscience2. However, most theories
of mind-wandering still overlook the dynamic nature
of thought that James viewed as central. By focusing on
these dynamics, in this Review, we formulate a novel
framework for understanding spontaneous thought
and mind-wandering. By introducing this framework,
we bring together a diverse range of relevant findings
from psychology, neuroscience and the clinicalarea.
Mind-wandering: the forgotten dynamics
Until the mid-1990s, cognitive psychology and the
emerging field of cognitive neuroscience were dom-
inated by a task-centric view of mental processes.
Experimental designs were carefully constructed to min-
imize the effects of task-unrelated thoughts that were gen-
erally viewed as experimental ‘noise. Indeed, cognitive
neuroscientists commonly used ‘rest’ (that is, a period
during which participants did not perform any experi-
mental tasks) as a baseline condition. This practice was
predicated on the assumption that any mental processes
that occur during periods of rest would essentially con-
stitute such noise. This assumption, however, was called
into question by observations that periods of rest con-
sistently recruit brain regions involved in memory3–5 and
complex reasoning6, and by an influential meta-analysis
by Shulman and colleagues7 showing that a specific set of
brain regions — that later became known as the default
network (DN)8 — are consistently more active during
baseline conditions than during experimentaltasks.
Although topics such as daydreaming, mind-wandering,
stimulus-independent thought and task-unrelated thought
had been studied for decades9–19, they had been rele-
gated to the backwaters of psychological research2. The
advent of the DN created a major shift in scientific atten-
tion: mind-wandering research came into prominence
within both mainstream psychology20,21 and cognitive
neuroscience22,23. However, this new research inherited
a historical legacy24 from previous task-centric views:
mind-wandering became predominantly defined as
the opposite of task-related and/or stimulus-related
thought. For example, a recent theoretical review25
defines mind-wandering as “a shift in the contents of
thought away from an ongoing task and/or from events
in the external environment. This prominent definition
regards mind-wandering as a type of thought charac-
terized by its contents (or, in William James’s terms, the
bird’s perchings rather than its flights).
1Department of Psychology,
University of British
Columbia, 2136 West Mall,
Vancouver, British Columbia,
V6T 1Z4, Canada.
2Centre for Brain Health,
University of British
Columbia, 2211 Wesbrook
Mall, Vancouver, British
Columbia, V6T 2B5, Canada.
3Departments of Philosophy
and Psychology, University of
California, Berkeley,
California 94720, USA.
4Laboratory of Brain and
Cognition, Department of
Human Development,
Cornell University.
5Human Neuroscience
Institute, Cornell University,
Ithaca, New York 14853,
USA.
6Institute of Cognitive Science,
University of Colorado
Boulder, UCB 594, Boulder,
Colorado 80309–0594, USA.
Correspondence to K.C.
kchristoff@psych.ubc.ca
doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.113
Published online 22 Sep 2016
Mind-wandering as spontaneous
thought: a dynamic framework
Kalina Christoff1,2, Zachary C.Irving3, Kieran C.R.Fox1, R.Nathan Spreng4,5
and Jessica R.Andrews-Hanna6
Abstract | Most research on mind-wandering has characterized it as a mental state with contents
that are task unrelated or stimulus independent. However, the dynamics of mind-wandering —
how mental states change over time — have remained largely neglected. Here, we introduce a
dynamic framework for understanding mind-wandering and its relationship to the recruitment of
large-scale brain networks. We propose that mind-wandering is best understood as a member of a
family of spontaneous-thought phenomena that also includes creative thought and dreaming. This
dynamic framework can shed new light on mental disorders that are marked by alterations in
spontaneous thought, including depression, anxiety and attention deficit hyperactivity disorder.
REVIEWS
718
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
VOLUME 17 www.nature.com/nrn
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
Nature Reviews | Neuroscience
Weak Strong
Weak
Strong
Automatic constraints
Deliberate constraints
Dreaming Mind-
wandering
Creative
thinking
Rumination and obsessive thought
Goal-directed
thought
Spontaneous thought
Thought
A mental state, or a sequence
of mental states, including the
transitions that lead to each
state.
Mental state
A transient cognitive or
emotional state of the organism
that can be described in terms
of its contents (what the state is
‘about’) and the relation that
the subject bears to the
contents (for example,
perceiving, believing, fearing,
imagining or remembering).
Task-unrelated thoughts
Thoughts with contents that
are unrelated to what the
person having those thoughts
is currently doing.
Daydreaming
Thinking that is
characteristically fanciful (that
is, divorced from physical or
social reality); it can either be
spontaneous, as in fanciful
mind-wandering, or
constrained, as during
deliberately fantasizing about
a topic.
This definition has been implicitly or explicitly
endorsed by most of the empirical investigations on
mind-wandering so far26. Although it has generated a
wealth of empirical findings about task-unrelated and
stimulus-independent thought, this content-based
definition fails to capture what is arguably the key fea-
ture of mind-wandering27,28, reflected in the term itself:
to wander means to “move hither and thither without
fixed course or certain aim(REF.29).
To say that one’s mental states are task unrelated or
stimulus independent tells us nothing about how such
states arise or change over time27. Only once we consider
the dynamics of thought are we able to make crucial dis-
tinctions between different types of thought. One such
distinction is between rumination and mind-wandering.
Rumination is sometimes viewed as negatively valenced
mind-wandering20 (or mind-wandering gone awry).
In one way, this makes sense: both mind-wandering
and rumination tend to be stimulus independent and
unrelated to the current task (that is, what the subject
is currently doing)21,30. However, when we consider the
dynamics of thought, mind-wandering and rumination
seem antithetical: although thoughts during mind-
wandering are free to ‘move hither and thither’, thoughts
during rumination tend to remain fixed on a single
theme or topic27. Furthermore, the content-based view of
mind-wandering relies on a relatively narrow definition
of the term ‘task’ as being confined to the goals of the
current experiment. However, if we define the term task
more broadly to also include one’s personal concerns (for
example, completing an essay by the end of the week),
then mind-wandering is often task related because spon-
taneously occurring thoughts often reflect personal goals
and concerns19,27,31,32.
Spontaneous thought: a definition
Here, we define spontaneous thought as a mental state,
or a sequence of mental states, that arises relatively freely
due to an absence of strong constraints on the contents
of each state and on the transitions from one mental state
to another. We propose that there are two general ways
in which the content of mental states, and the transitions
between them, can be constrained (FIG.1). One type of
constraint is flexible and deliberate26, and implemented
through cognitive control33,34. For example, we can deliber-
ately maintain our attention on a dry and boring lecture,
bringing our thoughts back to the lecture whenever they
begin to stray. Another type of constraint is automatic in
nature. Automatic constraints can be thought of as a fam-
ily of mechanisms that operate outside of cognitive con-
trol to hold attention on a restricted set of information27.
Affective salience35–37 and sensory salience38 can both act as
sources of automatic constraints. Despite our efforts, for
example, we may find ourselves unable to disengage our
attention from a fly buzzing in a quiet library or from a
preoccupying emotional concern.
Within our framework, mind-wandering can be
defined as a special case of spontaneous thought that
tends to be more-deliberately constrained than dream-
ing, but less-deliberately constrained than creative
thinking and goal-directed thought39 (BOX1; FIG.1). In
addition, mind-wandering can be clearly distinguished
from rumination and other types of thought that are
marked by a high degree of automatic constraints, such
as obsessive thought.
Recent advances have begun to reveal the neural
underpinnings of spontaneous thought and mind-
wandering. We review these advances through the lens
of our framework, which explains the contrast between
spontaneous and constrained thought in terms of the
dynamic interactions between large-scale brain net-
works. Using this framework, we also discuss a number
of clinical conditions that are marked by excessive varia-
bility or excessive stability of thought and the way mental
states change overtime.
Brain networks and their interactions
Among brain networks that are currently recognized
in cognitive neuroscience, the DN (FIG.2a) is most fre-
quently brought up in relation to mind-wandering and
spontaneous thought. The DN was originally identified7,8
as a set of regions that are consistently deactivated across
a range of externally oriented experimental tasks. This
network has been linked to spontaneously occurring,
internally oriented mental processes22,23,40. However, DN
recruitment is not specific to spontaneous cognition: it
is also consistently observed during internally oriented,
but deliberate, goal-directed tasks, including episodic
memory retrieval, autobiographical future thinking
and mentalizing41–44.
The DN is composed of several functionally distinct
subsystems45 (FIG.2a). The core DN subsystem (DNC ORE)
is characterized by its hub-like properties and its con-
tributions to internally oriented cognition45. The second
DN subsystem is centred around the medial temporal
lobe (MTL) and is known for its roles in memory and
Figure 1 | Conceptual space relating different types of thought. Deliberate and
automatic constraints serve to limit the contents of thought and how these contents
change over time. Deliberate constraints are implemented through cognitive control,
whereas automatic constraints can be considered as a family of mechanisms that operate
outside of cognitive control, including sensory or affective salience. Generally speaking,
deliberate constraints are minimal during dreaming, tend to increase somewhat during
mind-wandering, increase further during creative thinking and are strongest during
goal-directed thought39. There is a range of low-to-medium level of automatic
constraints that can occur during dreaming, mind-wandering and creative thinking, but
thought ceases to be spontaneous at the strongest levels of automatic constraint, such as
during rumination or obsessive thought.
REVIEWS
NATURE REVIEWS
|
NEUROSCIENCE VOLUME 17
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
719
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
Nature Reviews | Neuroscience
More active during REM sleep
More active during waking rest
More active during creative-idea generation
More active during creative-idea evaluation
a
b
LingG
LingG
PCC
rACC
PHC
PHC
HF
HF
rlPFC–dlPFC
OFC
IFG
FEF IPS–SPL
SPL
pIPL
MOG
MT+
LTC
TPC
IFG
AI
dlPFC
rlPFC
PCC–Prec
dACC
rmPFC
Stimulus-independent
thought
A thought with contents that
are unrelated to the current
external perceptual
environment.
Cognitive control
A deliberate guidance of
current thoughts, perceptions
or actions, which is imposed in
a goal-directed manner by
currently active top-down
executive processes.
constructive mental simulations43,44,46,47. Here, we refer to this
subsystem as DNMTL. The third DN subsystem seems to
be linked to a wide range of functions, including mental-
izing, conceptual processing and emotional processing47.
We refer to this subsystem using the generic designation
‘DNSUB3’ because its precise role in the DN has yet to be
clarified. The DNMTL and DNSUB3 are both closely con-
nected to the DNCORE, which serves as a major conduit
for information flow through the overall DN system45.
In contrast to the DN, which seems to be primarily
involved in internally oriented mental processes, the
dorsal attention network (DAN) (FIG.2b) becomes pref-
erentially recruited when we turn our attention towards
the external world48. The DAN is thought to support
selective attention to sensory features of the environment
and link this sensory information to motor responses48.
We hypothesize that the DAN increases the stability of
attention over time by constraining the spontaneous
movement of attention.
Attention and the focus of thoughts frequently shift
back and forth between the internal and external environ-
ment49,50, and there seem to be corresponding reciprocal
shifts between DN and DAN recruitment: when regions
of the DAN are active, there is often a simultaneous deac-
tivation of the DN in many different task paradigms7,51.
This antagonism has been observed in intrinsic fluctu-
ations in the functional MRI (fMRI) brain signal during
rest52 and in neuronal populations recorded using elec-
trocorticography in people with epilepsy53, although the
stability of this antagonism across different conditions has
not yet been systematically investigated.
One way in which thoughts can be triggered to shift
between an internal and an external focus is when some-
thing salient captures attention in an automatic or ‘bottom-
up’ manner. A right-lateralized ventral attention network
(VAN) (FIG.2c) may function to automatically direct (or
re-orient) attention towards salient perceptual stimuli48.
A more general salience network54 (FIG.2c) has been
Box 1 | Dreams and creativity as spontaneous thought
The similarities between waking spontaneous thought and dreaming while
asleep have been noted for decades183. Both waking thought and dreams
are instantiated mainly in the audiovisual modalities, centre on one’s
current goals and concerns, draw heavily on semantic and episodic
memory in constructing simulations and future plans, and are laden with
a wide range of affect184. Within our framework, dreaming is a type of
spontaneous thought that is highly unconstrained, hyperassociative and
highly immersive, and therefore it is predicted to be associated with very
low or absent deliberate constraints (although lucid dreaming is an
important exception). Dreaming should also be associated with a strong
influence from internal sources of variability, combined with low to
medium influence from automatic constraints. At the neural level,
dreaming should be accompanied by a strong recruitment of default
network (DN) medial temporal lobe (MTL)-centred subsystem (DNMTL)
regions, relatively weak to medium recruitment in regions of the core DN
subsystem (DNCORE) and strong deactivations in frontoparietal control
network (FPCN) regions. A recent meta-analysis184 of
studies of rapid-eye-movement (REM) sleep, the sleep
stage associated with, by far, the highest rate of dreaming,
reveals a pattern of activation that is consistent with these
predictions (see the figure, parta). Whereas regions of the
FPCN, including the rostrolateral prefrontal cortex
(rlPFC)–dorsolateral PFC (dlPFC), show deactivation
during REM sleep relative to waking rest (areas in blue),
regions within the DNMTL, including the hippocampal
formation (HF) and parahippocampal cortex (PHC), show
greater recruitment in REM sleep versus rest (areas in red).
By contrast, the DNCORE seems to be recruited to
a comparable degree by REM sleep and waking rest.
Creativity can also be seen as a form of spontaneous
thought. Creative thinking may be unique among other
spontaneous-thought processes because it may involve
dynamic shifts between the two ends of the spectrum of
constraints. The creative process tends to alternate
between the generation of new ideas, which would be
highly spontaneous, and the critical evaluation of these
ideas, which could be as constrained as goal-directed
thought in terms of deliberate constraints and is likely to
be associated with a higher degree of automatic
constraints than goal-directed thought because creative
individuals frequently use their emotional and visceral
reactions (colloquially often referred to as ‘gut’ reactions)
while evaluating their own creative ideas185. Consistent with our
framework, studies demonstrate186,187 that the DNMTL, including the HF and
PHC, is more active during creative-idea generation than during the
evaluation of these ideas (see the figure, partb; areas in red). By contrast,
regions within the FPCN and the DNCORE are more active during the
evaluation of creative ideas than during their generation (see the figure,
partb; areas in blue). The study from which the findings in partb come
from used functional MRI (fMRI) to examine brain activation in artists while
they were drawing visual art in the scanner using an fMRI-compatible
drawing tablet186.
AI, anterior insula; dACC, dorsal anterior cingulate cortex; FEF, frontal eye field;
IFG, inferior frontal gyrus; IPS, intraparietal sulcus; LingG, lingual gyrus; LTC,
lateral temporal cortex; MOG, medial occipital gyrus; MT+, middle temporal
motion complex; OFC, orbitofrontal cortex; PCC, posterior cingulate cortex;
pIPL, posterior inferior parietal lobule; Prec, precuneus; rACC, rostral ACC;
rmPFC, rostromedial PFC; SPL, superior parietal lobule; TPC, temporopolar
cortex. Partb is adapted with permission from REF.186, Elsevier.
REVIEWS
720
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
VOLUME 17 www.nature.com/nrn
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
Nature Reviews | Neuroscience
PCC
RSC
PHC HF vmPFC
amPFC
dmPFC
IFG TPC
LTC
IPL
pIPL
DAN
Salience
network
DNMTL FPCN
DNSUB3 COCN
DNCORE VAN
FEF IPS–SPL
MT+
ACC
IFG
vTPJ
AI
preSMA aIPL
dlPFC
rlPFC dAI ITG
dACC–msFC
a The DN and its subcomponents b The DAN
c The salience network and VAN d The FPCN and COCN
Affective salience
The emotional significance of
percepts, thoughts or other
elements of mental experience,
which can draw and sustain
attention through mechanisms
outside of cognitive control.
Sensory salience
Features of current perceptual
experience, such as high
perceptual contrast, which can
draw and sustain attention
through mechanisms outside of
cognitive control.
Mentalizing
The process of spontaneously
or deliberately inferring one’s
own or other agents’ mental
states.
proposed to detect both external and internal salient
events. Both the VAN and the general salience network
are involved in automatic bottom-up salience detection,
and there is substantial anatomical overlap between them,
especially within areas around the anterior insula. This
has led some scientists to view the VAN and the sali-
ence network as the same network55, although others
conceptualize them as distinct networks56,57.
Shifts in attention can also occur through deliber-
ate cognitive control. Such cognitive control34 is closely
linked to the frontoparietal control network (FPCN)58,59
(FIG.2d), which is involved in both internally and exter-
nally oriented goal-directed thought60,61. The FPCN can
couple (that is, display positive functional connectivity)
with the DN, to support internally focused deliberate
autobiographical planning, or with the DAN, to support
externally focused visuospatial planning60. We there-
fore hypothesize that the FPCN implements deliberate
constraints on thought. It also seems to mediate the
interactions between other networks57,60.
Finally, cognitive control can be implemented at dif-
ferent timescales62,63, which may distinguish between the
FPCN and another putative control network that has been
described in the literature, the cingulo-opercular control
network (COCN)64 (FIG.2d). Regions of the FPCN show
relatively transient activity that is associated with the ini-
tiation of cognitive control and short-term adjustments
of cognitive control as the demands of a task change from
one trial to another; by contrast, regions of the COCN
show more temporally sustained activity that may be
related to temporally extended cognitive-control pro-
cesses such as the maintenance of a task set over time62–64.
The rostrolateral prefrontal cortex (rlPFC) seems to
participate in both the FPCN58,65 and the COCN62,63.
This overview of large-scale brain networks rep-
resents only the current consensus about different
networks and their constituent regions. The precise ana-
tomical boundaries and the extent of functional separa-
tion66 between different networks remain active topics
of current investigation. There may be several conver-
gent brain zones where multiple networks intersect. For
example, the area centred around the temporoparietal
junction and inferior parietal lobule and the area centred
around the inferior frontal gyrus and opercular region
seem to act as such convergence zones. Nonetheless, the
evidence for functional specificity in the contributions
Figure 2 | Main large-scale brain networks with relevance to
spontaneous thought. a | The default network (DN) is centred on the
medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC), the medial parietal cortex and
the lateral parietal cortex, and extends into the temporal lobe and lateral
PFC. Three subcomponents within the DN have been identified. The first
of these subcomponents, the core DN subsystem (DNCORE), includes the
anterior mPFC (amPFC), posterior cingulate cortex (PCC) and posterior
inferior parietal lobule (pIPL). The second subcomponent, the DN
subsystem centred around the medial temporal lobe (MTL) (DNMTL),
includes the hippocampal formation (HF) and parahippocampal cortex
(PHC). The DNMTL also includes a number of MTL cortical projections, such
as the retrosplenial cortex (RSC), the ventral mPFC (vmPFC) and the pIPL.
The third subcomponent, DNSUB3, extends more dorsally and includes the
dorsomedial PFC (dmPFC), the lateral temporal cortex (LTC) extending
into the temporopolar cortex (TPC), and parts of the inferior frontal gyrus
(IFG). All three DN subsystems seem to include subsections of the IPL.
b | The dorsal attention network (DAN) comprises a distributed set of
regions centred around the intraparietal sulcus (IPS)–superior parietal
lobule (SPL), the dorsal frontal cortex along the precentral sulcus near, or
at, the frontal eye field (FEF) and the middle temporal motion complex
(MT+). c | The ventral attention network (VAN) comprises a ventral frontal
cluster of regions, including the inferior frontal gyrus (IFG), the anterior
insula (AI) and the adjacent frontal operculum (not shown); the VAN also
includes the ventral temporoparietal junction (vTPJ). Although the VAN is
predominantly right lateralized, a bilateral salience network has also
been defined. The most prominent regions of the salience network are
the AI and the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC). These regions are densely
connected with subcortical structures involved in interoception and
autonomic functions, which are also considered to be part of the salience
network. d | Two ‘control’ networks have been discussed in the literature.
The frontoparietal control network (FPCN) includes, most prominently,
the dorsolateral PFC (dlPFC) and the anterior IPL (aIPL). Under a broader
definition, the FPCN extends to regions including the rostrolateral PFC
(rlPFC), the region anterior to the supplementary motor area (preSMA)
and the inferior temporal gyrus (ITG). The cingulo-opercular control
network (COCN) includes the dorsal ACC (dACC)–medial superior
frontal cortex (msFC) and bilateral AI–frontal operculum. The rlPFC
contributes to both the FPCN and COCN. dAI, dorsal AI.
REVIEWS
NATURE REVIEWS
|
NEUROSCIENCE VOLUME 17
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
721
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
Constructive mental
simulations
Flexible combinations of
distinct elements of prior
experiences, constructed in the
process of imagining a novel
(often future-oriented) event.
Lucid dreaming
A type of dreaming during
which the dreamer is aware
that he or she is currently
dreaming and, in some cases,
can have deliberate control
over dream content and
progression.
Creativity
The ability to produce ideas
that are both novel (that is,
original and unique) and useful
(that is, appropriate and
meaningful).
Experience sampling
A method in which participants
are probed at random intervals
and asked to report on aspects
of their subjective experience
immediately before the probe.
Content-based dimensions
of thought
Different ways of categorizing a
thought based on its contents,
including stimulus dependence
(whether the thought is about
stimuli that one is currently
perceiving), task relatedness
(whether the thought is about
the current task), modality
(visual, auditory, and so on),
valence (whether the thought is
negative, neutral or positive) or
temporal orientation (whether
the thought is about the past,
present or future).
of different networks seems to be relatively robust. In the
following sections of this Review, we discuss the putative
relevance and functionality of different networks with
respect to spontaneous thought and its clinical disorders.
Content-based views of mind-wandering
Most empirical research to date has examined mind-
wandering from a content-based perspective by assessing
the contents of thoughts in terms of their relationship to
an ongoing task or activity. In this approach, researchers
use thought probes that ask, for example, “are you think-
ing about something other than what you are currently
doing?” (REF.21). Answering “yes” to this question would be
categorized as being in a state of mind-wandering. Using
this approach, research has suggested a striking prevalence
of task-unrelated thought in everyday life: it accounts for
as much as 30–50% of our waking cognition15,21,30.
As tasks get easier and external demands on attention
become lower, the frequency of task-unrelated thoughts
tends to increase10,12,17 and so does DN recruitment22.
Because of these parallels, early research into DN func-
tions hypothesized a link between this network and
task-unrelated thought3,7,8. Initial empirical support for
this link came from neuroimaging studies4,22,67,68 linking
the reported frequency of task-unrelated thoughts to DN
activation during conditions of low cognitive demand
and showing stronger DN activation during highly prac-
tised tasks compared with novel tasks in people with a
higher propensity for mind-wandering 22.
This initial empirical evidence for a link between
the DN and mind-wandering was tentative because it
relied on indirect retrospective reports about the overall
frequency of mind-wandering or on indirect inferences
about its frequency based on data from independent
studies. Furthermore, it did not distinguish between
task-unrelated and stimulus-independent thought, leav-
ing open the possibility that the DN might be involved
in task-unrelated but still stimulus-oriented thought69.
Subsequent research helped to address both of these issues
by using online experience sampling measures to capture
the moment-by-moment occurrence of specific instances
of mind-wandering23,70. This research demonstrated con-
clusively a consistent link between DN activation and both
task-unrelated and stimulus-independent thought.
However, the DN is not the only brain network that
is consistently involved in task-unrelated thought. The
FPCN, especially the lateral PFC, is also consistently
recruited71. Indeed, lateral PFC recruitment during
rest was one of the earliest observations in functional
neuroimaging, dating back to work by Ingvar72 in the
1970s. It continued to be reported in subsequent stud-
ies3,4,23,67,70,73–77 exploring rest, task-unrelated thought
and/or spontaneous thought.
The lateral PFC is closely linked to executive pro-
cessing78–81 and is consistently recruited during difficult
tasks involving deliberate task-directed thought6,79,81,82.
Its recruitment during task-unrelated thought and rest
therefore seems counterintuitive and requires an expla-
nation. One such explanation is the control failure hypo-
thesis83,84. According to this hypothesis, task-unrelated
thoughts occur because of a failure of executive control
to keep attention on the current task. Once this failure
and task-unrelated thoughts have occurred, executive
resources are recruited to suppress those thoughts and
redirect attention to the task athand.
Although this theory seems to be plausible, some of its
key predictions are at odds with empirical findings. For
example, the control failure hypothesis predicts that, when
executive resources are reduced, task-unrelated thoughts
should increase. However, individuals with higher
working-memory capacity (a major component of execu-
tive ability) show an increased frequency of task-unrelated
thoughts during easy tasks85 such as breath monitoring or
identifying a target among highly dissimilar distractors.
Another prediction of this theory is that, with advancing
age and associated declines in executive function-
ing86, the frequency of task-unrelated thoughts should
increase. Instead, research shows that task-unrelated
thought decreases in frequency with advancing age16,87.
At the neural level, stimulation of executive regions using
transcranial direct current stimulation increases task-
unrelated thought88, whereas the control failure hypo-
thesis would predict the opposite. Although it is possible
that executive resources can, in principle, be used to sup-
press task-unrelated thought, it seems unlikely that this
is the main role they play during task-unrelated thought.
An alternative explanation is that executive resources
are used to direct task-unrelated thoughts towards per-
sonal goals20. One development of this view, the decou-
pling hypothesis50,89, proposes that executive resources
suppress perceptual processing during task-unrelated
thought. This suppression serves to decouple attention
from the immediate external perceptual environment
and thus ‘insulates’ an internally oriented thought flow
against perceptual distractions. The decoupling hypo-
thesis is consistent with electroencephalography find-
ings of reduced cortical analysis of the external sensory
environment during task-unrelated thought90 and atten-
uated sensory responses in visual and auditory cortices
during task-unrelated compared with task-related mental
states91. It is also consistent with fMRI findings showing
that, during task-unrelated thought, activation in the
posterior cingulate cortex (a key region of the DNC ORE)
is inversely correlated with activation in the primary
sensorimotor and extrastriate visual cortices26.
However, the decoupling hypothesis equates task-
unrelated thought with internally oriented thought.
Although task-unrelated thought can sometimes be inter-
nally oriented, it can also be externally oriented towards
stimuli in the current perceptual environment. In princi-
ple, task relatedness, internal versus external orientation
and goal directedness are separable dimensions of thought
(BOX2). Nonetheless, most investigations so far have
used the terms ‘task-unrelated, ‘internally oriented,’ and
‘stimulus-independent’ interchangeably26. Furthermore,
mind-wandering has, so far, been defined25 largely based
on these content-based dimensions of thought. Although
mind-wandering is often task unrelated, internally ori-
ented and/or stimulus independent, none of these content-
based features captures the defining dynamic quality of
mind-wandering: the relatively free and spontaneous
arising of mental states as the mind wanders.
REVIEWS
722
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
VOLUME 17 www.nature.com/nrn
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
Mind-wandering as spontaneous thought
Although cognitive neuroscience research has not yet
directly investigated thought’s spontaneity using expe-
rience sampling probes, a growing body of related find-
ings hints at the potential neural basis of spontaneous
thought. Not all subnetworks within the DN seem to
be involved in spontaneous thought to the same extent
(FIG.3). Although the DNCORE and DNSUB3 are more
active during task-unrelated than task-related thought
and during internally oriented than externally oriented
thought, the DNMTL does not seem to be differentially
recruited along these dimensions23,70 (FIG.3a). Instead, the
DNMTL seems to be recruited when deliberate constraints
on thought are relatively weak. For example, the DNMTL
shows stronger recruitment when participants are una-
ware that they are having task-unrelated thoughts than
when they are aware of them23 (FIG.3b). This suggests
a link between the DNMTL and spontaneity because, in
the absence of meta-awareness (that is, awareness of
one’s ongoing mental state), deliberate constraints are
likely to be minimal.
Overall, a growing body of evidence suggests that the
generation of spontaneous thought may be closely linked
to the DNMTL and especially its central component, the
MTL itself. Converging evidence from humans and
rodents suggests that spontaneous memories and spon-
taneous mental simulations (both of which can be con-
sidered types of spontaneous thought), during periods
of awake rest, are initiated by the MTL and supported
by hippocampal–cortical interactions. Using single-cell
recordings in humans, one study92 found that the sponta-
neous recall of film clips following a film-viewing period
was preceded by an elevated firing rate in many of the
same medial temporal neurons that responded while first
viewing the film. The DNMTL also seems to be recruited
immediately before the spontaneous arising of thoughts,
as revealed by a recent fMRI study93 that used experienced
mindfulness practitioners to detect the precise onset of
spontaneous thoughts. In another fMRI study94, differ-
ences in resting-state connectivity within the DNMTL
predicted the propensity for spontaneous memories and
future thoughts during these periods of rest. Furthermore,
recent findings95 suggest that people with an increased
propensity to mind-wander in daily life (as measured with
a standard trait daydreaming questionnaire) exhibit more
variable (that is, more dynamic) functional connectivity
within the DNMTL in particular. In rodents, during peri-
ods of waking rest, hippocampal place cells demonstrate a
replay of previously encountered routes96–98 and a preplay
of future routes that are yet to be visited99101.
The hippocampus, which is a central part of the MTL,
has long been linked to episodic memory102,103. Recent
findings have also linked it to a broad range of constructive
mental processes such as imagining novel scenarios and
situations43,44,104106, constructing new spatial scenes107
and imagining potential future experiences108. Based
on these findings, it has been proposed that the hippo-
campus is involved in ‘episodic simulation’ — the imag-
inative construction of hypothetical events or scenarios
that might occur in one’s personal future109.
Of particular relevance to our dynamic framework
is the component process model110 of episodic memory.
According to this model, memory traces are encoded
in ensembles of neurons distributed throughout the
MTL and neocortex. Such ensembles are groups of
spatially distributed neurons capable of firing in a
coordinated manner. Hippocampal representations are
proposed to have an indexing function111, capable of
reactivating the ensembles that were active during the
original experience. During retrieval, cues rapidly and
unconsciously trigger the activation of hippo campal
representations, which then activate the ensembles that
they index112. This model also proposes that memory
becomes constrained and goal-directed only when
Box 2 | Varieties of task-unrelated thought
The terms ‘task-unrelated’, ‘stimulus-independent’ and ‘spontaneous’ are sometimes
used interchangeably in the cognitive and neuroimaging literature. This usage,
however, is problematic because these terms designate separable dimensions
of thought. To illustrate this independence, here, we list examples of task-unrelated
thought that is either stimulus independent or stimulus oriented. Within each of these
categories, we also list examples of task-unrelated thought that is highly constrained
(in a deliberate or automatic manner) or spontaneous.
In general, the term ‘stimulus’ is usually used to mean ‘external perceptual stimulus’. In
addition, ‘stimulus-independent thought’ is typically equated with ‘internally oriented
thought’, and ‘stimulus-dependent thought’ is typically equated with ‘externally
oriented thought’. Finally, the term ‘goal-directed thought’ refers to thought that is
deliberately directed by any goals, including personal goals that may be unrelated to the
task at hand. Although not included in the examples below, the contents of spontaneous
thought can also shift between being externally oriented (for example, a forest trail) and
being internally oriented (for example, reminiscence about one’s childhood).
Stimulus-independent (internally oriented)
Deliberately constrained (goal-directed)
While in the shower, a bobsledder deliberately and systematically visualizes each
turn they will take on an upcoming run.
While re-painting the walls of their room, a person plans their afternoon, figuring out
how to combine multiple errands into a single car ride.
Automatically constrained
While trying to fall asleep, a job candidate keeps imagining the terrors and triumphs
of tomorrow’s interview.
Despite their best attempts to write a research article, a professor keeps fixating on
a nasty teaching evaluation.
Spontaneous
While driving in their car, a writer suddenly thinks of a line for the book they are
writing, then remembers that they must pick up dog food on the way home, before
reminiscing about the winters of their childhood and fantasizing about the career
they might have had as a bobsledder.
Stimulus-oriented (externally oriented)
Deliberately constrained (goal-directed)
To entertain himself during a boring earnings report, a manager tries to estimate who
has the most expensive suit in the room.
While listening to harsh criticism by her teacher, a student starts counting the tiles on
the floor of the classroom as a means to stop herself from crying.
Automatically constrained
While studying in a quiet library, a student finds herself unable to ignore a buzzing fly.
A pedestrian loses the thread of his friend’s conversation when he cannot help but
gawk at a naked man walking down Main Street.
Spontaneous
While hiking on a forest trail, a woman’s thoughts move from the gravel on the path in
front of her to a slug crawling up a stump, and then to a leaf floating in a puddle.
REVIEWS
NATURE REVIEWS
|
NEUROSCIENCE VOLUME 17
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
723
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
Nature Reviews | Neuroscience
b Areas more active when unaware than when aware of task-unrelated thoughts
a Areas more active during task-unrelated than during task-related thoughts
c Neural mechanisms of contextual associative processing
DNCORE
DNCORE DNCORE
PHC (DNMTL)
PHC
mPFC
RSC
these hippocampal outputs are further processed by
slower and conscious control mechanisms mediated
by the neocortex103.
We propose that a similar sequence of processes may
operate during episodic retrieval, episodic simulation
and constructive mental processes in general. Within our
framework (FIG.4), the hippocampus acts as an internal
source of variability in thought by reactivating old or
activating novel (re-combined) hippocampal–neocortical
ensembles. A transition from the activation of one ensem-
ble to another would correspond to a transition between
mental states. In Jamesian terms, each activated ensem-
ble would be a perching, and the transition from one
activated ensemble to another would be aflight.
The DNMTL may also contribute to thought var-
iability by its involvement in contextual associative
processing113,114 (FIG.3c). The DNMTL may contribute to
conceptual variability in the contents of thought over
time when one activated ensemble cues the activation of
another because they partially overlap at the neural level.
This may lead to a stream of conceptually disconnected
(but contextually connected) mentalstates.
There may also be differences within the FPCN in
how it contributes to constraining thought through cog-
nitive control. In particular, the rlPFC and the dorso-
lateral PFC (dlPFC) may have a role in implementing
deliberate constraints at different timescales64 or levels
of abstraction115,116. The rlPFC is preferentially recruited
when thought is broadly constrained towards internal
mental events, such as when directing attention towards
one’s own thoughts and away from one’s perceptual
sensations117. The rlPFC is also preferentially recruited
when thought is guided towards highly abstract con-
cepts, such as during the solving of anagrams that are
known to subjects to have highly abstract nouns as
their solutions115. This suggests that the rlPFC may be
involved in an abstract ‘top-level management’ control,
constraining thought in a relatively general, nonspecific
manner: for example, when the goal of thinking is to
generate novel ideas for an essay topic, without limit-
ing the nature of ideas any further than their suitability
as an essay topic. This top-level control may implement
relatively weak- or medium-level deliberate constraints
on thought, thus allowing for some degree of spontane-
ous variability. By contrast, the dlPFC may be better con-
ceptualized as being involved in ‘mid-level management’
— carrying out adaptive online adjustments in cognitive
control based on relatively specific rules33,34 and in direct
response to specific feedback63,118. This mid-level control
may result in some of the strongest deliberate constraints
on thought.
We propose that automatic constraints on thought
can be exerted by multiple brain networks and structures,
such as the DNCORE, the salience networks (including the
VAN) and the DAN (FIG.4). The FPCN can exert deliber-
ate constraints on thought by flexibly coupling with the
DNCORE, the DAN or the salience networks, thus reinforc-
ing or reducing the automatic constraints being exerted
by the DNCORE, the DAN or the salience networks. The
level and type of constraints can change dynamically. For
example, thought may at first be spontaneous and there-
fore subject to relatively weak constraints, then it may shift
to become highly automatically constrained, and then it
may shift again to become highly deliberately constrained
(FIG.5). We propose that these fluctuations in the level and
type of constraints on thought correspond to changing
interactions between large-scale brain networks (FIG.5).
Whereas deliberate constraints are relatively well
characterized and specifically linked to executive func-
tions and control networks, automatic constraints are
much more diverse and therefore probably subserved by
diverse neural correlates. It is also likely that the neural
Figure 3 | Different patterns of recruitment in the DNCORE and DNMTL during
mind-wandering. a | Regions within the core default network (DN) subsystem (DNCORE)
are more active during task-unrelated thought than during task-related thought,
whereas regions within the DN subsystem centred around the medial temporal lobe
(MTL) (DNMTL) show similar levels of activity for task-unrelated and task-related thought.
The data are from a functional MRI study23 that used experience sampling during an
ongoing task, the sustained attention to response task (SART). b | Regions within the
DNMTL, including the parahippocampal cortex (PHC), are more active when participants
are unaware of their task-unrelated thoughts than when they are aware of them. Lack of
awareness is likely to be associated with minimal constraints on thought, suggesting
a specific link between DNMTL and spontaneity. By contrast, regions within the DNCORE
show similar levels of activity for unaware and aware task-unrelated thought. The data
are from the same study23 as in parta. c | The DNMTL may also contribute to spontaneous
thought by its involvement in contextual associative processing. A network for
contextual associative processing has been identified113,114 that closely resembles the
DNMTL and includes the PHC, the retrosplenial cortex (RSC) with its associated medial
parietal cortex, and the medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC). Areas within this network show
greater activation when people see pictures of objects that elicit relatively strong
contextual associations (for example, a traffic light) compared with pictures of objects
that are not unique to any particular context and are therefore not highly associative
(for example, a bag). Partc is adapted with permission from REF.114 , Elsevier.
REVIEWS
724
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
VOLUME 17 www.nature.com/nrn
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
Nature Reviews | Neuroscience
Sources of variability
Automatic constraints
Deliberate constraints
FPCN
DNCORE
DNMTL
DAN
Sensorimotor areas
Salience networks
basis of automatic constraints extends beyond the net-
works that we discuss here. For example, the basal ganglia
and their associated cortico–thalamic–striatal circuits are
known to be crucially involved in habit formation119 and
may exert habitual automatic constraints on thought (an
excess of which may be linked to obsessive–compulsive
disorder120). Therefore, an important goal for future
research is to improve our knowledge of different types
of automatic constraints and their neural basis. As we dis-
cuss next, dysfunctions in automatic constraints may be
a common factor across multiple mental health disorders.
Clinical implications
Spontaneous thought is altered in a wide range of clini-
cal conditions, including depression, anxiety, attention
deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD) and schizophre-
nia. We propose that clinically significant alterations in
spontaneous thought can be subdivided into two major
categories: those that are marked by excessive variability
of thought contents over time and those that are marked
by excessive stability.
Within our framework, thought becomes spontane-
ous and more variable when deliberate and automatic
constraints are relaxed. Whereas excessive constraints
may reduce the dynamic flow of thoughts, excessive vari-
ability may prevent thoughts from developing coherence
(that is, meaningful interconnectedness among succes-
sive mental states). Therefore, both excessive constraints
and excessive variability, especially when they become
chronic, might have detrimental effects on cognitive
functioning and emotional well-being.
Depression and rumination. Overall, depression seems
to be characterized by excessive stability in thought. It is
marked by increased elaboration of negative information
and by difficulties in disengaging from negative material
such as negative words or pictures121,122. One hallmark
of depression is rumination, which is defined as “repet-
itively and passively focusing on symptoms of distress”
and remaining “fixated” on one’s problems and one’s feel-
ings about them123. People with depression experience
thoughts that tend to be inflexible, perseverative124 and
characterized by excessively self-focused, mostly negative
content125,126. Rumination is largely involuntary: individ-
uals with depression may want to stop themselves from
ruminating but are often unable to do so, suggesting that
the constraints on thought in rumination are primarily
automatic.
When engaged in experimental tasks, individuals with
depression show several differences in neural recruitment
compared with healthy controls. The DN shows greater
activation in individuals with depression across a range of
tasks127,128. Moreover, people with depression show greater
activation of the salience network (specifically, the frontal
insula, dorsal anterior cingulate cortex and amygdala) but
lower activation of the FPCN (specifically, the dlPFC and
dorsal caudate) when they are presented with negative
stimuli129. There is also enhanced task-related coupling
between the DN and salience regions in individuals with
subclinical depression130. These results are consistent with
our hypothesis that depression involves a preponderance
of automatic affective constraints on thought.
Individuals with depression also show altered pat-
terns of resting-state functional connectivity. A recent
meta-analysis131 found that, compared with healthy con-
trols, patients with depression show increased connec-
tivity within the DN and reduced connectivity within
the FPCN. Moreover, in cases of depression, the FPCN
shows increased coupling with the DN but decreased
coupling with the DAN, which may reflect depressive
biases towards internal thoughts at the cost of engaging
with the external world131. We hypothesize that an overly
connected DN allows the DNCORE to place greater auto-
matic constraints on the DNMTL, promoting an overly
constrained thought flow with an exaggerated internal
orientation. Consistent with this idea, recent findings132
suggest that patterns of resting-state connectivity in peo-
ple with depression tend to be less variable over time,
particularly between the medial PFC (within the DNCORE)
and the parahippocampus (within the DNMTL).
Anxiety disorders. Like depression, anxiety disorders are
characterized by repetitive negative thoughts124,133, often
accompanied by severe worry about events that might
happen in the future134. There are both commonalities
Figure 4 | Neural model of the interactions among
sources of variability, automatic constraints and
deliberate constraints. Arrows represent the influences
that large-scale networks have on the dynamics of thought:
networks can be sources of variability (in purple), sources of
automatic constraints (in blue) or sources of deliberate
constraints (in red). The default network (DN) subsystem
centred around the medial temporal lobe (MTL) (DNMTL) and
sensorimotor areas can act as sources of variability in
thought content over time. The salience networks, the
dorsal attention network (DAN) and the core DN
subsystem (DNCORE) can exert automatic constraints on the
output of the DNMTL and sensorimotor areas, thus limiting
the variability of thought and increasing its stability over
time. The frontoparietal control network (FPCN) can exert
deliberate constraints on thought by flexibly coupling with
the DNCORE, the DAN or the salience networks, thus
reinforcing or reducing the automatic constraints being
exerted by the DNCORE, the DAN or the salience networks.
The putative role of each network is meant to be illustrative
rather than exhaustive. The model includes only those
interactions that are relatively well understood given the
current state of research.
REVIEWS
NATURE REVIEWS
|
NEUROSCIENCE VOLUME 17
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
725
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
Sources of variability Automatic constraints Deliberate constraints
Spontaneous thought Automatically constrained
thought
Deliberately constrained
thought
While I walk to the grocery
store, I daydream about the
winter boots I’ve ordered
from an online store, recall
that blustery winter when
they shut down my elementary
school, then envision next
weekend’s ski trip to
Lake Tahoe...
As I cross the street, I begin
to worry about the story that
my newspaper editor wants
me to write before I leave for
Tahoe. Can I submit on time?
Will anyone read a piece on
trade unions? I picture my
scowling editor. Do I even
belong here?
While I step up the curb, I
realize that my thoughts are
making me miserable. I decide
to think about something else.
Where am I heading to?
Oh yes, groceries! I imagine
myself walking down each
grocery aisle... I should get
eggs, milk and lemonade from
the freezer, potatoes and
cauliflower from produce...
FPCN
DNCORE
DNMTL
Salience
networks
FPCN
DNCORE
DNMTL
Salience
networks
FPCN
DNCORE
DNMTL
Salience
networks
Nature Reviews | Neuroscience
and differences between anxiety and depression135. Like
depression, anxiety is associated with attentional biases to
consciously perceived stimuli121,136. However, patients with
anxiety show biased processing of subliminally presented
threat-related stimuli, whereas individuals with depres-
sion generally do not121,122. This suggests that anxiety
biases begin in relatively early, orienting stages of infor-
mation processing, before awareness of perceptual stim-
uli137, whereas depressive biases occur primarily at later
stages of processing involving the elaboration (that is, the
conceptual interpretation) of perceptual information122.
Within our framework, both anxiety and depres-
sion are marked by excessive automatic constraints on
thought. These constraints may differ, however, in terms
of the level of cognitive processing at which they begin.
Consistent with this idea, anxiety disorders, like depres-
sion, are marked by alterations in recruitment and func-
tional connectivity within the DN, FPCN and salience
network135,138,139. What seems to be more pronounced
in anxiety, however, are functional alterations in sub-
cortical structures and their interactions with the other
networks. For instance, generalized anxiety disorder is
associated with disrupted subregional functional connec-
tivity within the amygdala, which also shows enhanced
connectivity with the FPCN but reduced connectivity
with the salience network138. In addition, the amygdala
and the globus pallidus show increased activation across
studies when individuals with specific phobias are pre-
sented with phobic stimuli139. Finally, a recent study135
examined resting-state fMRI connectivity in individu-
als with anxiety disorder, depression, both anxiety and
depression (comorbid), or neither anxiety nor depres-
sion (control subjects). In this study, greater severity of
anxiety-specific symptoms was associated with stronger
functional connectivity between the ventral striatum and
subgenual anterior cingulate cortex, whereas people with
depression had reduced connectivity in the same circuit
compared with people without depression. Because here
we focus on large-scale cortical networks, our framework
does not currently highlight the specific contributions of
these subcortical structures and their possible role in
implementing automatic constraints. However, these top-
ics undoubtedly remain important directions for future
theoretical developments.
ADHD. Within our framework, ADHD is a disorder
marked by an excessive variability in thought movement.
Clinically, ADHD is characterized by a pattern of inatten-
tion and/or hyperactivity/impulsivity, which can occur
in both children and adults140. It is associated with broad
Figure 5 | Fluctuations in the level and type of constraints may correspond to dynamically changing interactions
between large-scale brain networks. In this example, an internally oriented stream of thought, described from a
person’s subjective perspective, transitions from spontaneous thought to automatically constrained thought, and then to
deliberately constrained thought. We propose that each transition corresponds to changing interactions among
large-scale brain networks. During spontaneous, internally oriented thought, the default network (DN) subsystem centred
around the medial temporal lobe (MTL) (DNMTL) exerts a relatively strong diversifying influence on the stream of thought, in
the context of relatively low deliberate and automatic constraints exerted by the frontoparietal control network (FPCN),
core DN subsystem (DNCORE) and salience networks. During automatically constrained, internally oriented thought, the
salience networks and the DNCORE exert relatively strong automatic constraints on thought, in the context of relatively
weak internal sources of variability from the DNMTL and relatively weak deliberate sources of constraint from the FPCN.
Finally, during deliberately constrained, internally oriented thought, the FPCN exerts strong deliberate constraints on
thought, in the context of relatively weak internal sources of variability from the DNMTL and relatively weak automatic
constraints by the DNCORE and salience networks. Arrows represent influences on the dynamics of thought: sources of
variability (in purple), automatic constraints (in blue) and deliberate constraints (in red). The thickness of an arrow
represents the hypothesized relative strength of these influences during the corresponding part in the stream of thought.
REVIEWS
726
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
VOLUME 17 www.nature.com/nrn
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
impairments in executive functions141,142, manifesting as
lapses in attention and heightened intra-individual (that
is, within-subject) variability in reaction time on cogni-
tive tasks143. Failures to sustain attention on a task goal
may relate to another characteristic of ADHD: excessive
task-unrelated thoughts144,145. Spontaneous thought in
ADHD has not yet been explored directly using expe-
rience sampling, but, based on our framework, we
would predict heightened variability of thought content
acrosstime.
Neural alterations associated with ADHD146148 are
consistent with it being a disorder marked by reduced
constraints on thought. Task-related fMRI studies indi-
cate that ADHD is associated with reduced activation
of the FPCN and DAN147,149, and failures to deactivate
regions within the DN150,151. In contrast to studies focus-
ing on depression, resting-state connectivity studies in
ADHD152157 generally report decreased within-network
functional connectivity in the DN and DAN, as well as
weaker anti-correlations between key regions of the DN
and control networks.
ADHD has a strong developmental component140,
and many of the neural alterations that are present in
adults with ADHD are also detectable in affected chil-
dren149,151,154. During typical development, regions within
large-scale brain networks, such as the DN, are initially
only sparsely connected and gradually mature into a
cohesive, interconnected network158. Children with
ADHD show a maturational delay, which is character-
ized by hypo-connectivity within the DN and weaker
anti-correlations between key regions of the DN and con-
trol networks154,156,159,160. Crucially, resting-state functional
connectivity in ADHD varies across DN subsystems: one
study161 found increased connectivity within the DNMTL
but decreased connectivity within the DNCORE, consist-
ent with an increased generation of spontaneous men-
tal content in ADHD (from the DNMTL) combined with
decreased automatic constraints on thought (from the
DNCORE). However, these results need to be interpreted
with caution because motion-induced fMRI artefacts
have been shown162,163 to have significant influence on
resting-state functional connectivity findings in ADHD,
especially in younger populations.
In summary, the patterns of neural alterations in
ADHD suggest a general reduction in both automatic
and deliberate constraints on thought, coupled with a
possible increase in DNMTL-derived sources of variabil-
ity. Our account extends the influential hypothesis164
that patients with ADHD are unable to suppress inter-
nally oriented cognition that is supported by the DN.
This hypothesis explains why ADHD is associated with
weaker anti-correlations between the DN and other
networks but not why the disorder is associated with
reduced connectivity within some DN subsystems. Our
model explains these results, as it suggests that ADHD
reflects a reduction in constraints from sources both
within and outside of theDN.
Psychotic disorders. Psychotic disorders, including schiz-
ophrenia, schizoaffective disorder and psychotic bipolar
disorder, are characterized by a profound disruption
of thought. The symptoms of such disorders include
thought disorganization, hallucinations and delusions140.
Psychotic disorders are also characterized by notable
impairments in executive functioning and processing
of semantic information165. Psychotic thought can be
marked by frequent and abrupt leaps from one topic to
another166 or by stereotyped thinking, including rigid,
repetitious or barren thought content167. Psychotic dis-
orders may therefore be associated with both excessive
variability and excessive stability of thought, which may
be present in different psychotic presentations across
individuals or may occur at different times within the
same individual.
At the neural level, schizophrenia is associated with
widespread structural and functional brain abnormal-
ities and with significant reductions in both grey and
white matter168. Progressive grey-matter reductions can
occur throughout the brain but are found most consist-
ently in salience network regions, the FPCN (especially
the dlPFC), and the DNMTL and DNCORE regions169171.
Whereas grey-matter alterations may be partially linked to
antipsychotic drug treatments169,172, white-matter abnor-
malities seem to precede treatment and may therefore be
linked most directly to the disease itself168.
Consistent with these findings, fMRI studies of psy-
chotic disorders reveal a pattern of global dysconnec-
tivity173,174. In both schizophrenia and bipolar disorder,
there is reduced global functional connectivity174. In
schizophrenia, the dlPFC shows reduced connectivity
with other lateral PFC regions but increased long-range
connectivity with non-FPCN regions175, suggesting an
impairment of FPCN integrity. Consistent with this
finding, functional connectivity within the FPCN is
reduced176. Within our framework, this disruption of
FPCN integrity suggests that deliberate constraints on
thought may still be present, but they may lack coherence
and logical structure.
Schizophrenia is also associated with disruptions
of connectivity within the DN127,177. There may be greater
connectivity within the DNCORE (REFS178,179) and weaker
anti-correlations between the DN and DAN during both
rest and working-memory tasks127. Finally, there seems
to be a failure of the salience network to appropriately
regulate the interactions between the DN and FPCN180.
We hypothesize that there is an overall dysregulation
of both deliberate and automatic constraints on thought
in psychotic disorders. There may also be a blurring
between external (visual, auditory and somatosensory)
and internal (DNMTL) sources of variability, which in
turn could be linked to a breakdown of the typical
network-based functional brain organization that
maintains a relative functional segregation between the
processing of internal and external information.
Summary and future directions
Mind-wandering has recently become a prominent topic
of research within cognitive neuroscience and psychol-
ogy. However, its dynamics have been all but forgot-
ten. Rather than emphasizing the spontaneous flow
of thought, most research has instead used the terms
‘mind-wandering’ and ‘spontaneous’ as loose synonyms
REVIEWS
NATURE REVIEWS
|
NEUROSCIENCE VOLUME 17
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
727
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
for ‘task-unrelated’ or ‘stimulus-independent’. Our
framework offers explicit definitions of spontaneous
thought and mind-wandering that capture those largely
ignored dynamics. In doing so, we lend conceptual clar-
ity to numerous issues. We draw conceptual distinctions
between the dimensions of spontaneity, task relatedness
and stimulus relatedness. Our framework can also tease
apart antithetical phenomena such as mind-wandering
and rumination, which seem to be indistinguishable if
we focus on the static contents of thoughts to the exclu-
sion of its dynamics. We argue that mind-wandering
is best understood as a member of a family of sponta-
neous-thought processes — a family that also includes
creative thought and dreaming. Finally, we also locate
spontaneous thought within a broader conceptual space
that allows its comparison to goal-directed thought, as
well as to clinical alterations that make thought exces-
sively constrained — such as in rumination and anxiety
— or excessively variable — such as inADHD.
Our conceptual framework is empirically grounded
and thus makes falsifiable predictions. Overall, it predicts
that fluctuations between spontaneous, automatically con-
strained and deliberately const rained thought correspond to
changes in the interactions between large-scale brain net-
works. Furthermore, divisions within these large-scale
networks are predicted to have different influences on the
dynamics of thought. Thus, we predict that the DNCORE
would show increased recruitment as automatic con-
straints on internally oriented thought increase, whereas
the DNMTL would show decreased recruitment as either
deliberate or automatic constraints on thought increase.
One future direction of development for our frame-
work is to enumerate the types of automatic constraints
and link them to their neural substrates. We have focused
here on constraints from affective salience, which are
implemented, in part, by the salience network and have
clear implications for disease. However, other forms
of automatic constraints, such as habits of attention
that depend on cortico–thalamic–striatal circuits or
neuromodulatory influences on thought by midbrain
mechanisms such as the locus coeruleus noradrenaline
system181, are also likely to be of theoretical and clinical
significance. Elucidating how automatic constraints are
implemented could improve our understanding of how to
de-automatize188 them when they become detrimental
to well-being, as in clinical conditions, or how to benefi-
cially harness already existing automatic constrains182, as
in the case of creative thinking. Future research will also
be needed to clarify the role of the DNSUB3 in the dynamics
of thought. Regions within the DNSUB3 have been linked
to the processing of social, semantic and emotional infor-
mation, but it remains unclear how they contribute to the
constraining and diversifying of thought.
Future research may particularly benefit from a
neuro phenomenological approach189 that combines
online experience sampling or first-person measures
of ongoing thought dynamics with measures of neural
activity. Such approaches may greatly benefit clinical
investigations, from which a wealth of information can be
gathered regarding the subjective experiences associated
with disruptions in thought dynamics. To do so, however,
reliable methods need to be develped for measuring the
extent to which individuals’ thoughts unfold in a sponta-
neous, automatically constrained or goal-directed man-
ner. The development of such methods, combined with
theoretical, empirical and neuroscientific advances such
as those that we have reviewed here, may one day unfurl
the mystery that captivated William James more than a
century ago: what do the ‘flights of the mind’ look like,
and can we ever observe them?
1. James,W. The Principles of Psychology (Henry Holt
and Company, 1890).
2. Callard,F., Smallwood,J., Golchert,J. &
Margulies,D.S. The era of the wandering mind?
Twenty-first century research on self-generated mental
activity. Front. Psychol. 4, 891 (2013).
3. Andreasen,N.C. etal. Remembering the past: two
facets of episodic memory explored with positron
emission tomography. Am. J.Psychiatry 152,
1576–1585 (1995).
4. Binder,J.R., Frost,J.A. & Hammeke,T.A. Conceptual
processing during the conscious resting state:
a functional MRI study. J.Cogn. Neurosci. 11 , 80–93
(1999).
5. Stark,C.E. & Squire,L.R. When zero is not zero: the
problem of ambiguous baseline conditions in fMRI.
Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 98, 12760–12766
(2001).
6. Christoff,K. & Gabrieli,J.D.E. The frontopolar cortex
and human cognition: evidence for a rostrocaudal
hierarchical organization within the human prefrontal
cortex. Psychobiology 28, 168–186 (2000).
7. Shulman,G.L. etal. Common blood flow changes
across visual tasks: II. Decreases cerebral cortex.
J.Cogn. Neurosci. 9, 648–663 (1997).
This meta-analysis provides convincing evidence
that a set of specific brain regions, which later
became known as the default mode network,
becomes consistently activated during rest.
8. Raichle,M.E. etal. A default mode of brain
function. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 98, 676–682
(2001).
This highly influential theoretical paper coined
the term ‘default mode’ to refer to cognitive and
neural processes that occur in the absence of
external task demands.
9. Singer,J.L. Daydreaming: An Introduction to the
Experimental Study of Inner Experience (Random
House, 1966).
10. Antrobus,J.S. Information theory and stimulus-
independent thought. Br. J.Psychol. 59, 423–430
(1968).
11. Antrobus,J.S., Singer,J.L., Goldstein,S. &
Fortgang,M. Mind wandering and cognitive structure.
Trans. NY Acad. Sci. 32, 242–252 (1970).
12. Filler,M.S. & Giambra,L.M. Daydreaming as a
function of cueing and task difficulty. Percept. Mot.
Skills 37, 503–509 (1973).
13. Giambra,L.M. Adult male daydreaming across the life
span: a replication, further analyses, and tentative
norms based upon retrospective reports. Int. J.Aging
Hum. Dev. 8, 197–228 (1977).
14. Giambra,L.M. Sex differences in daydreaming and
related mental activity from the late teens to the early
nineties. Int. J.Aging Hum. Dev. 10, 1–34 (1979).
15. Klinger,E. & Cox,W.M. Dimensions of thought flow in
everyday life. Imagin. Cogn. Pers. 7, 105–128 (1987).
This is probably the earliest experience sampling
study of mind-wandering in daily life, revealing that
adults spend approximately one-third of their
waking life engaged in undirected thinking.
16. Giambra,L.M. Task-unrelated-thought frequency as
a function of age: a laboratory study. Psychol. Aging
4, 136–143 (1989).
17. Teasdale,J.D., Proctor,L., Lloyd,C.A. & Baddeley,A.D.
Working memory and stimulus-independent thought:
effects of memory load and presentation rate. Eur.
J.Cogn. Psychol. 5, 417–433 (1993).
18. Giambra,L.M. A laboratory method for investigating
influences on switching attention to task-unrelated
imagery and thought. Conscious. Cogn. 4, 1–21
(1995).
19. Klinger,E. Structure and Functions of Fantasy (John
Wiley & Sons, 1971).
This pioneering book summarizes the early
empirical research on daydreaming and introduces
important theoretical hypotheses, including the
idea that task-unrelated thoughts are often about
‘current concerns’.
20. Smallwood,J. & Schooler,J.W. The restless mind.
Psychol. Bull. 132, 946–958 (2006).
This paper put mind-wandering in the forefront of
psychological research, advancing the influential
hypothesis that executive resources support
mind-wandering.
21. Killingsworth,M.A. & Gilbert,D.T. A wandering mind
is an unhappy mind. Science 330, 932 (2010).
22. Mason,M.F. etal. Wandering minds: the default
network and stimulus-independent thought. Science
315, 393–395 (2007).
This influential paper brought mind-wandering to
the forefront of neuroscientific research, arguing
for a link between DN recruitment and stimulus-
independent thought.
23. Christoff,K., Gordon,A.M., Smallwood,J., Smith,R.
& Schooler,J.W. Experience sampling during fMRI
reveals default network and executive system
contributions to mind wandering. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci.
USA 106, 8719–8724 (2009).
This paper is the first to use online experience
sampling to examine the neural correlates of
mind-wandering and the first to find joint activation
of the DN and executive network during this
phenomenon.
24. Callard,F., Smallwood,J. & Margulies,D.S. Default
positions: how neuroscience’s historical legacy has
hampered investigation of the resting mind. Front.
Psychol. 3, 321 (2012).
REVIEWS
728
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
VOLUME 17 www.nature.com/nrn
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
25. Smallwood,J. & Schooler,J.W. The science of mind
wandering: empirically navigating the stream of
consciousness. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 66, 487–518 (2015).
This comprehensive review synthesizes the recent
research characterizing mind-wandering as
task-unrelated and/or stimulus-independent
thought.
26. Christoff,K. Undirected thought: neural determinants
and correlates. Brain Res. 1428, 51–59 (2012).
This review disambiguates between different
definitions of spontaneous thought and
mind-wandering, and it argues that current
definitions do not capture the dynamics of thought.
27. Irving,Z.C. Mind-wandering is unguided attention:
accounting for the ‘purposeful’ wanderer. Philos. Stud.
173, 547–571 (2016).
This is one of the first philosophical theories of
mind-wandering; this paper defines
mind-wandering as unguided attention to explain
why its dynamics contrast with automatically and
deliberately guided forms of attention such as
rumination and goal-directed thinking.
28. Carruthers,P. The Centered Mind: What the Science of
Working Memory Shows Us About the Nature of
Human Thought (Oxford Univ. Press, 2015).
29. Simpson,J.A. The Oxford English Dictionary
(Clarendon Press, 1989).
30. Kane,M.J. etal. For whom the mind wanders, and
when: an experience-sampling study of working
memory and executive control in daily life. Psychol.
Sci. 18, 614–621 (2007).
This study of mind-wandering in everyday life is one
of the most important investigations into the
complex relationship between mind-wandering and
executive control.
31. Baird,B., Smallwood,J. & Schooler,J.W. Back to the
future: autobiographical planning and the functionality
of mind-wandering. Conscious. Cogn. 20, 1604–1611
(2011).
32. Morsella,E., Ben-Zeev,A., Lanska,M. & Bargh,J.A.
The spontaneous thoughts of the night: how future
tasks breed intrusive cognitions. Social Cogn. 28,
641–650 (2010).
33. Miller,E.K. & Cohen,J.D. An integrative theory of
prefrontal cortex function. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 24,
167–202 (2001).
34. Miller,E.K. The prefrontal cortex and cognitive
control. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 1, 59–65 (2000).
35. Markovic,J., Anderson,A.K. & Todd,R.M. Tuning to
the significant: neural and genetic processes underlying
affective enhancement of visual perception and
memory. Behav. Brain Res. 259, 229–241 (2014).
36. Todd,R.M., Cunningham,W.A., Anderson,A.K. &
Thompson,E. Affect-biased attention as emotion
regulation. Trends Cogn. Sci. 16, 365–372 (2012).
37. Pessoa,L. The Cognitive-Emotional Brain: From
Interactions to Integration (MIT Press, 2013).
38. Jonides,J. & Yantis,S. Uniqueness of abrupt visual
onset in capturing attention. Percept. Psychophys.
43, 346–354 (1988).
39. Christoff,K., Gordon,A.M. & Smith,R. in
Neuroscience of Decision Making (eds Vartanian,O. &
Mandel,D.R.) 259–284 (Psychology Press, 2011).
40. Stawarczyk,D., Majerus,S., Maj,M., Van der
Linden,M. & D’Argembeau,A. Mind-wandering:
phenomenology and function as assessed with a novel
experience sampling method. Acta Psychol. (Amst.)
136, 370–381 (2011).
41. Spreng,R.N., Mar,R.A. & Kim,A.S.N. The common
neural basis of autobiographical memory, prospection,
navigation, theory of mind, and the default mode:
a quantitative meta-analysis. J.Cogn. Neurosci. 21 ,
489–510 (2009).
This paper provides some of the first quantitative
evidence that the DN is associated with multiple
cognitive functions.
42. Andrews-Hanna,J.R. The brain’s default network and
its adaptive role in internal mentation. Neuroscientist
18, 251–270 (2012).
This recent review describes a large-scale functional
meta-analysis on the cognitive functions, functional
subdivisions and clinical dysfunction of the DN.
43. Buckner,R.L. & Carroll,D.C. Self-projection and the
brain. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11 , 49–57 (2007).
44. Buckner,R.L., Andrews-Hanna,J.R. & Schacter,D.L.
The brain’s default network: anatomy, function, and
relevance to disease. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 1124, 1–38
(2008).
This comprehensive review bridges across
neuroscience, psychology and clinical research, and
introduces a prominent hypothesis — the ‘internal
mentation hypothesis’ — that the DN has an
important role in spontaneous and directed forms
of internal mentation.
45. Andrews-Hanna,J.R., Reidler,J.S., Sepulcre,J.,
Poulin,R. & Buckner,R.L. Functional-anatomic
fractionation of the brain’s default network. Neuron
65, 550–562 (2010).
46. Schacter,D.L., Addis,D.R. & Buckner,R.L.
Remembering the past to imagine the future: the
prospective brain. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 8, 657–661
(2007).
47. Andrews-Hanna,J.R., Smallwood,J. & Spreng,R.N.
The default network and self-generated thought:
component processes, dynamic control, and clinical
relevance. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 1316, 29–52 (2014).
48. Corbetta,M., Patel,G. & Shulman,G.L. The
reorienting system of the human brain: from
environment to theory of mind. Neuron 58, 306–324
(2008).
This paper outlines an influential theoretical
framework that extends an earlier model by
Corbetta and Shulman that drew a crucial
distinction between the DAN and VAN.
49. Vanhaudenhuyse,A. etal. Two distinct neuronal
networks mediate the awareness of environment and
of self. J.Cogn. Neurosci. 23, 570–578 (2011).
50. Smallwood,J. Distinguishing how from why the mind
wanders: a process–occurrence framework for self-
generated mental activity. Psychol. Bull. 139,
519–535 (2013).
This theoretical paper presents an important
distinction between the events that determine
when an experience initially occurs from the
processes that sustain an experience over time.
51. Toro,R., Fox,P.T. & Paus,T. Functional coactivation
map of the human brain. Cereb. Cortex 18,
2553–2559 (2008).
52. Fox,M.D. etal. The human brain is intrinsically
organized into dynamic, anticorrelated functional
networks. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 102 ,
9673–9678 (2005).
This paper provides a unique insight into the
functional antagonism between the default and
dorsal attention systems.
53. Keller,C.J. etal. Neurophysiological investigation of
spontaneous correlated and anticorrelated
fluctuations of the BOLD signal. J.Neurosci. 33,
6333–6342 (2013).
54. Seeley,W.W. etal. Dissociable intrinsic connectivity
networks for salience processing and executive
control. J.Neurosci. 27, 2349–2356 (2007).
This paper is the first to name the salience
network and characterize its functional
neuroanatomy.
55. Kucyi,A., Hodaie,M. & Davis,K.D. Lateralization in
intrinsic functional connectivity of the
temporoparietal junction with salience- and
attention-related brain networks. J.Neurophysiol.
108, 3382–3392 (2012).
56. Power,J.D. etal. Functional network organization of
the human brain. Neuron 72, 665–678 (2011).
57. Cole,M.W. etal. Multi-task connectivity reveals
flexible hubs for adaptive task control. Nat.
Neurosci. 16, 1348–1355 (2013).
58. Vincent,J.L., Kahn,I., Snyder,A.Z., Raichle,M.E.
& Buckner,R.L. Evidence for a frontoparietal
control system revealed by intrinsic functional
connectivity. J.Neurophysiol. 10 0, 3328–3342
(2008).
59. Niendam,T.A. etal. Meta-analytic evidence for
a superordinate cognitive control network
subserving diverse executive functions. Cogn. Affect.
Behav. Neurosci. 12, 241–268 (2012).
60. Spreng,R.N., Stevens,W.D., Chamberlain,J.P.,
Gilmore,A.W. & Schacter,D.L. Default network
activity, coupled with the frontoparietal control
network, supports goal-directed cognition.
Neuroimage 53, 303–317 (2010).
This paper demonstrates how the DN couples
with the FPCN for personally salient,
goal-directed information processing.
61. Dixon,M.L., Fox,K.C.R. & Christoff,K.
A framework for understanding the relationship
between externally and internally directed cognition.
Neuropsychologia 62, 321–330 (2014).
62. Dosenbach,N.U.F. etal. A core system for the
implementation of task sets. Neuron 50, 799–812
(2006).
63. Dosenbach,N.U.F. etal. Distinct brain networks for
adaptive and stable task control in humans. Proc.
Natl Acad. Sci. USA 104, 11073–11078 (2007).
64. Dosenbach,N.U.F., Fair,D.A., Cohen,A.L.,
Schlaggar,B.L. & Petersen,S.E. A dual-networks
architecture of top-down control. Trends Cogn. Sci.
12, 99–105 (2008).
65. Yeo,B.T.T. etal. The organization of the human
cerebral cortex estimated by intrinsic functional
connectivity. J.Neurophysiol. 106 , 1125–1165
(2011).
This seminal paper uses resting-state functional
connectivity and clustering approaches in 1,000
individuals to parcellate the brain into seven
canonical large-scale networks.
66. Najafi,M., McMenamin,B.W., Simon,J.Z. &
Pessoa,L. Overlapping communities reveal rich
structure in large-scale brain networks during rest
and task conditions. Neuroimage 135, 92–106
(2016).
67. McGuire,P.K., Paulesu,E., Frackowiak,R.S. &
Frith,C.D. Brain activity during stimulus
independent thought. Neuroreport 7, 2095–2099
(1996).
68. McKiernan,K.A., D’Angelo,B.R., Kaufman,J.N. &
Binder,J.R. Interrupting the ‘stream of
consciousness’: an fMRI investigation. Neuroimage
29, 1185–1191 (2006).
69. Gilbert,S.J., Dumontheil,I., Simons,J.S.,
Frith,C.D. & Burgess,P.W. Comment on
‘wandering minds: the default network and
stimulus-independent thought’. Science 31 7, 43b
(2007).
70. Stawarczyk,D., Majerus,S., Maquet,P. &
D’Argembeau,A. Neural correlates of ongoing
conscious experience: both task-unrelatedness and
stimulus-independence are related to default
network activity. PLoS ONE 6, e16997 (2011).
71. Fox,K.C.R., Spreng,R.N., Ellamil,M., Andrews-
Hanna,J.R. & Christoff,K. The wandering brain:
meta-analysis of functional neuroimaging studies of
mind-wandering and related spontaneous thought
processes. Neuroimage 111 , 611–621 (2015).
This paper presents the first quantitative
meta-analysis of neuroimaging studies on
task-unrelated and/or stimulus-independent
thought, revealing the involvement of the DN and
other large-scale networks that were not
traditionally thought to play a part in
mind-wandering.
72. Ingvar,D.H. ‘Hyperfrontal’ distribution of the cerebral
grey matter flow in resting wakefulness; on the
functional anatomy of the conscious state. Acta
Neurol. Scand. 60, 12–25 (1979).
This paper by David Ingvar, a pioneer of human
neuroimaging, provides the original observations
that a resting brain is an active one and highlights
the finding that prefrontal executive regions are
active even at rest.
73. Christoff,K., Ream,J.M. & Gabrieli,J.D.E. Neural
basis of spontaneous thought processes. Cortex 40,
623–630 (2004).
74. D’Argembeau,A. etal. Self-referential reflective
activity and its relationship with rest: a PET study.
Neuroimage 25, 616–624 (2005).
75. Spiers,H.J. & Maguire,E.A. Spontaneous mentalizing
during an interactive real world task: an fMRI study.
Neuropsychologia 44, 1674–1682 (2006).
76. Wang,K. etal. Offline memory reprocessing:
involvement of the brain’s default network in
spontaneous thought processes. PLoS ONE 4, e4867
(2009).
77. Dumontheil,I., Gilbert,S.J., Frith,C.D. &
Burgess,P.W. Recruitment of lateral rostral
prefrontal cortex in spontaneous and task-related
thoughts. Q.J.Exp. Psychol. 63, 1740–1756
(2010).
78. Posner,M.I. & Rothbart,M.K. Attention, self-
regulation and consciousness. Phil. Trans. R.Soc.
Lond. B 353, 1915–1927 (1998).
79. Duncan,J. & Owen,A.M. Common regions of the
human frontal lobe recruited by diverse cognitive
demands. Trends Neurosci. 23, 475–483 (2000).
80. Botvinick,M.M., Braver,T.S., Barch,D.M.,
Carter,C.S. & Cohen,J.D. Conflict monitoring and
cognitive control. Psychol. Rev. 10 8, 624–652
(2001).
81. Banich,M.T. Executive function: the search for an
integrated account. Curr. Direct. Psychol. Sci. 18,
89–94 (2009).
82. Prado,J., Chadha,A. & Booth,J.R. The brain
network for deductive reasoning: a quantitative meta-
analysis of 28 neuroimaging studies. J.Cogn.
Neurosci. 23, 3483–3497 (2011).
REVIEWS
NATURE REVIEWS
|
NEUROSCIENCE VOLUME 17
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
729
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
83. McVay,J.C. & Kane,M.J. Does mind wandering
reflect executive function or executive failure?
Comment on Smallwood and Schooler (2006) and
Watkins (2008). Psychol. Bull. 136, 188–197 (2010).
This paper presents the theoretically influential
control failure hypothesis, which is opposed to the
thesis that executive function supports
mind-wandering.
84. Kane,M.J. & McVay,J.C. What mind wandering
reveals about executive-control abilities and failures.
Curr. Direct. Psychol. Sci. 21, 348–354 (2012).
85. Levinson,D.B., Smallwood,J. & Davidson,R.J. The
persistence of thought: evidence for a role of working
memory in the maintenance of task-unrelated
thinking. Psychol. Sci. 23, 375–380 (2012).
86. Salthouse,T.A., Fristoe,N., McGuthry,K.E. &
Hambrick,D.Z. Relation of task switching to speed,
age, and fluid intelligence. Psychol. Aging 13,
445–461 (1998).
87. Maillet,D. & Schacter,D.L. From mind wandering to
involuntary retrieval: age-related differences in
spontaneous cognitive processes. Neuropsychologia
80, 142–156 (2016).
88. Axelrod,V., Rees,G., Lavidor,M. & Bar,M. Increasing
propensity to mind-wander with transcranial direct
current stimulation. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 11 2 ,
3314–3319 (2015).
89. Schooler,J.W. etal. Meta-awareness, perceptual
decoupling and the wandering mind. Trends Cogn. Sci.
15, 319–326 (2011).
90. Smallwood,J., Beach,E. & Schooler,J.W. Going
AWOL in the brain: mind wandering reduces cortical
analysis of external events. J.Cogn. Neurosci. 20,
458–469 (2008).
91. Kam,J.W.Y. etal. Slow fluctuations in attentional
control of sensory cortex. J.Cogn. Neurosci. 23,
460–470 (2011).
92. Gelbard-Sagiv,H., Mukamel,R., Harel,M., Malach,R.
& Fried,I. Internally generated reactivation of single
neurons in human hippocampus during free recall.
Science 322, 96–101 (2008).
This pioneering study aimed to identify the neural
origins of spontaneously recalled memories, finding
strong evidence for the initial generation in the MTL.
93. Ellamil,M. etal. Dynamics of neural recruitment
surrounding the spontaneous arising of thoughts in
experienced mindfulness practitioners. Neuroimage
136, 186–196 (2016).
This study is the first to reveal a sequential
recruitment of the DNMTL, DNCORE, and FPCN
immediately before, during and subsequent to the
onset of spontaneous thoughts.
94. Andrews-Hanna,J.R., Reidler,J.S., Huang,C. &
Buckner,R.L. Evidence for the default network’s role
in spontaneous cognition. J.Neurophysiol. 104,
322–335 (2010).
95. Kucyi,A. & Davis,K.D. Dynamic functional
connectivity of the default mode network tracks
daydreaming. Neuroimage 10 0, 471–480 (2014).
96. Foster,D.J. & Wilson,M.A. Reverse replay of
behavioural sequences in hippocampal place cells
during the awake state. Nature 440, 680–683 (2006).
97. Karlsson,M.P. & Frank,L.M. Awake replay of remote
experiences in the hippocampus. Nat. Neurosci. 12,
913–918 (2009).
98. Carr,M.F., Jadhav,S.P. & Frank,L.M. Hippocampal
replay in the awake state: a potential substrate for
memory consolidation and retrieval. Nat. Neurosci.
14, 147–153 (2011).
99. Dragoi,G. & Tonegawa,S. Distinct preplay of multiple
novel spatial experiences in the rat. Proc. Natl Acad.
Sci. USA 110 , 9100–9105 (2013).
100. Dragoi,G. & Tonegawa,S. Preplay of future place cell
sequences by hippocampal cellular assemblies. Nature
469, 397–401 (2011).
101. Ólafsdóttir,H.F., Barry,C., Saleem,A.B. &
Hassabis,D. Hippocampal place cells construct
reward related sequences through unexplored space.
eLife 4, e06063 (2015).
102. Stark,C.E.L. & Clark,R.E. The medial temporal lobe.
Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 27, 279–306 (2004).
103. Moscovitch,M., Cabeza,R., Winocur,G. & Nadel,L.
Episodic memory and beyond: the hippocampus and
neocortex in transformation. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 67,
105–134 (2016).
104. Romero,K. & Moscovitch,M. Episodic memory and
event construction in aging and amnesia. J.Mem.
Lang. 67, 270–284 (2012).
105. Hassabis,D., Kumaran,D. & Maguire,E.A. Using
imagination to understand the neural basis of episodic
memory. J.Neurosci. 27, 14365–14374 (2007).
106. Buckner,R.L. The role of the hippocampus in
prediction and imagination. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 61 ,
27–48 (2010).
107. Hassabis,D. & Maguire,E.A. The construction system
of the brain. Phil. Trans. R.Soc. B 364, 1263–1271
(2009).
108. Schacter,D.L. etal. The future of memory:
remembering, imagining, and the brain. Neuron 76,
677–694 (2012).
109. Schacter,D.L., Addis,D.R. & Buckner,R.L. Episodic
simulation of future events: concepts, data, and
applications. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 1124, 39–60
(2008).
110 . Moscovitch,M. Memory and working-with-memory:
a component process model based on modules and
central systems. J.Cogn. Neurosci. 4, 257–267
(1992).
This paper introduces the influential component
process model of memory.
111. Teyler,T.J. & DiScenna,P. The hippocampal memory
indexing theory. Behav. Neurosci. 100, 147–154
(1986).
112 . Moscovitch,M. The hippocampus as a “stupid,”
domain-specific module: implications for theories of
recent and remote memory, and of imagination. Can.
J.Exp. Psychol. 62, 62–79 (2008).
113 . Bar,M., Aminoff,E., Mason,M. & Fenske,M. The
units of thought. Hippocampus 17, 420–428 (2007).
This paper introduces a novel hypothesis on the
associative processes underlying a train of
thoughts, originating in the MTL.
114 . Aminoff,E.M., Kveraga,K. & Bar,M. The role of the
parahippocampal cortex in cognition. Trends Cogn.
Sci. 17, 379–390 (2013).
115 . Christoff,K., Keramatian,K., Gordon,A.M.,
Smith,R. & Mädler,B. Prefrontal organization of
cognitive control according to levels of abstraction.
Brain Res. 1286, 94–105 (2009).
116 . Dixon,M.L., Fox,K.C.R. & Christoff,K. Evidence for
rostro-caudal functional organization in multiple
brain areas related to goal-directed behavior. Brain
Res. 1572, 26–39 (2014).
117 . McCaig,R.G., Dixon,M., Keramatian,K., Liu,I. &
Christoff,K. Improved modulation of rostrolateral
prefrontal cortex using real-time fMRI training and
meta-cognitive awareness. Neuroimage 55,
1298–1305 (2011).
118 . Dixon,M.L. & Christoff,K. The decision to engage
cognitive control is driven by expected reward-value:
neural and behavioral evidence. PLoS ONE 7,
e51637 (2012).
119 . Yin,H.H. & Knowlton,B.J. The role of the basal
ganglia in habit formation. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 7,
464–476 (2006).
120. Burguière,E., Monteiro,P., Mallet,L., Feng,G. &
Graybiel,A.M. Striatal circuits, habits, and
implications for obsessive–compulsive disorder. Curr.
Opin. Neurobiol. 30, 59–65 (2015).
121. Mathews,A. & MacLeod,C. Cognitive vulnerability to
emotional disorders. Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 1,
167–195 (2005).
122. Gotlib,I.H. & Joormann,J. Cognition and
depression: current status and future directions.
Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 6, 285–312 (2010).
123. Nolen-Hoeksema,S., Wisco,B.E. & Lyubomirsky,S.
Rethinking rumination. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 3,
400–424 (2008).
124. Watkins,E.R. Constructive and unconstructive
repetitive thought. Psychol. Bull. 134, 163–206
(2008).
This comprehensive review and theory article links
the psychological literature on task-unrelated or
stimulus-independent thought to the clinical
literature on rumination and other forms of
repetitive thought, proposing multiple factors that
govern whether repetitive thought is constructive
or unconstructive.
125. Giambra,L.M. & Traynor,T.D. Depression and
daydreaming; an analysis based on self-ratings.
J.Clin. Psychol. 34, 14–25 (1978).
126. Larsen,R.J. & Cowan,G.S. Internal focus of
attention and depression: a study of daily
experience. Motiv. Emot. 12, 237–249 (1988).
127. Whitfield-Gabrieli,S. & Ford,J.M. Default mode
network activity and connectivity in psychopathology.
Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 8, 49–76 (2012).
128. Anticevic,A. etal. The role of default network
deactivation in cognition and disease. Trends Cogn.
Sci. 16, 584–592 (2012).
129. Hamilton,J.P. etal. Functional neuroimaging of
major depressive disorder: a meta-analysis and new
integration of baseline activation and neural
response data. Am. J.Psychiatry 169, 693–703
(2012).
130. Kaiser,R.H. etal. Distracted and down: neural
mechanisms of affective interference in subclinical
depression. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 10,
654–663 (2015).
131. Kaiser,R.H., Andrews-Hanna,J.R., Wager,T.D. &
Pizzagalli,D.A. Large-scale network dysfunction in
major depressive disorder. JAMA Psychiatry 72,
603–637 (2015).
This meta-analysis of resting-state functional
connectivity studies in major depressive disorder
provides quantitative support for
functional-network imbalances, which reflect
heightened internally focused thought in this
disorder.
132. Kaiser,R.H. etal. Dynamic resting-state functional
connectivity in major depression.
Neuropsychopharmacology 41, 1822–1830
(2015).
133. Spinhoven,P., Drost,J., van Hemert,B. &
Penninx,B.W. Common rather than unique aspects
of repetitive negative thinking are related to
depressive and anxiety disorders and symptoms.
J.Anxiety Disord. 33, 45–52 (2015).
134. Borkovec,T.D., Ray,W.J. & Stober,J. Worry:
a cognitive phenomenon intimately linked to
affective, physiological, and interpersonal behavioral
processes. Cognit. Ther. Res. 22, 561–576 (1998).
135. Oathes,D.J., Patenaude,B., Schatzberg,A.F. &
Etkin,A. Neurobiological signatures of anxiety and
depression in resting-state functional magnetic
resonance imaging. Biol. Psychiatry 77, 385–393
(2015).
136. Bar-Haim,Y., Lamy,D., Pergamin,L., Bakermans-
Kranenburg,M.J. & van IJzendoorn,M.H. Threat-
related attentional bias in anxious and nonanxious
individuals: a meta-analytic study. Psychol. Bull. 133,
1–24 (2007).
137. Williams,J., Watts,F.N., MacLeod,C. & Mathews,A.
Cognitive Psychology and Emotional Disorders (John
Wiley & Sons, 1997).
138. Etkin,A., Prater,K.E., Schatzberg,A.F., Menon,V. &
Greicius,M.D. Disrupted amygdalar subregion
functional connectivity and evidence of
a compensatory network in generalized anxiety
disorder. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 66, 1361–1372
(2009).
139. Ipser,J.C., Singh,L. & Stein,D.J. Meta-analysis of
functional brain imaging in specific phobia. Psychiatry
Clin. Neurosci. 67, 311–322 (2013).
140. American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and
Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (American
Psychiatric Association, 2013).
141. Boonstra,A.M., Oosterlaan,J., Sergeant,J.A. &
Buitelaar,J.K. Executive functioning in adult ADHD:
a meta-analytic review. Psychol. Med. 35,
1097–1108 (2005).
142. Willcutt,E.G., Doyle,A.E., Nigg,J.T., Faraone,S.V. &
Pennington,B.F. Validity of the executive function
theory of attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder:
a meta-analytic review. Biol. Psychiatry 57,
1336–1346 (2005).
143. Kofler,M.J. etal. Reaction time variability in ADHD:
a meta-analytic review of 319 studies. Clin. Psychol.
Rev. 33, 795–811 (2013).
144. Shaw,G.A. & Giambra,L. Task unrelated thoughts of
college students diagnosed as hyperactive in
childhood. Dev. Neuropsychol. 9, 17–30 (1993).
145. Franklin,M.S. etal. Tracking distraction: the
relationship between mind-wandering, meta-
awareness, and ADHD symptomatology. J.Atten.
Disord. http://dx.doi.
org/10.1177/1087054714543494 (2014).
146. De La Fuente,A., Xia,S., Branch,C. & Li,X. A review
of attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder from the
perspective of brain networks. Front. Hum. Neurosci.
7, 192 (2013).
147. Castellanos,F.X. & Proal,E. Large-scale brain systems
in ADHD: beyond the prefrontal–striatal model.
Trends Cogn. Sci. 16, 17–26 (2012).
148. Hart,H., Radua,J., Mataix-Cols,D. & Rubia,K. Meta-
analysis of fMRI studies of timing in attention-deficit
hyperactivity disorder (ADHD). Neurosci. Biobehav.
Rev. 36, 2248–2256 (2012).
149. Hart,H., Radua,J., Nakao,T., Mataix-Cols,D. &
Rubia,K. Meta-analysis of functional magnetic
resonance imaging studies of inhibition and attention
in attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder. JAMA
Psychiatry 70, 185–198 (2013).
REVIEWS
730
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
VOLUME 17 www.nature.com/nrn
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
150. Fassbender,C. etal. A lack of default network
suppression is linked to increased distractibility in
ADHD. Brain Res. 1273, 114–128 (2009).
151. Cortese,S. etal. Toward systems neuroscience of
ADHD: a meta-analysis of 55 fMRI studies.
Am. J.Psychiatry 169, 1038–1055 (2012).
152. Castellanos,F.X. etal. Cingulate-precuneus
interactions: a new locus of dysfunction in adult
attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder.
Biol. Psychiatry 63, 332–337 (2008).
153. Uddin,L.Q. etal. Network homogeneity reveals
decreased integrity of default-mode network in
ADHD. J.Neurosci. Methods 169, 249–254 (2008).
154. Tomasi,D. & Volkow,N.D. Abnormal functional
connectivity in children with attention-deficit/hyperactivity
disorder. Biol. Psychiatry 71 , 443–450 (2012).
155. Mattfeld,A.T. etal. Brain differences between
persistent and remitted attention deficit hyperactivity
disorder. Brain 137, 2423–2428 (2014).
156. Sun,L. etal. Abnormal functional connectivity
between the anterior cingulate and the default mode
network in drug-naïve boys with attention deficit
hyperactivity disorder. Psychiatry Res. 201 , 120–127
(2012).
157. McCarthy,H. etal. Attention network
hypoconnectivity with default and affective network
hyperconnectivity in adults diagnosed with attention-
deficit/hyperactivity disorder in childhood. JAMA
Psychiatry 70, 1329–1337 (2013).
158. Fair,D.A. etal. The maturing architecture of the
brain’s default network. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA
105, 4028–4032 (2008).
159. Sripada,C. etal. Disrupted network architecture of
the resting brain in attention-deficit/hyperactivity
disorder. Hum. Brain Mapp. 35, 4693–4705 (2014).
By analysing data from more than 750 participants,
this paper links childhood ADHD to abnormal
resting-state functional connectivity involving the DN.
160. Fair,D.A. etal. Atypical default network connectivity
in youth with attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder.
Biol. Psychiatry 68, 1084–1091 (2010).
161. Anderson,A. etal. Non-negative matrix factorization
of multimodal MRI, fMRI and phenotypic data reveals
differential changes in default mode subnetworks in
ADHD. Neuroimage 102, 207–219 (2014).
162. Power,J.D., Barnes,K.A., Snyder,A.Z.,
Schlaggar,B.L. & Petersen,S.E. Spurious but
systematic correlations in functional connectivity MRI
networks arise from subject motion. Neuroimage 59,
2142–2154 (2012).
163. Van Dijk,K.R.A., Sabuncu,M.R. & Buckner,R.L.
The influence of head motion on intrinsic functional
connectivity MRI. Neuroimage 59, 431–438 (2012).
164. Sonuga-Barke,E.J.S. & Castellanos,F.X.
Spontaneous attentional fluctuations in impaired
states and pathological conditions: a neurobiological
hypothesis. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 31, 977–986
(2007).
165. Kerns,J.G. & Berenbaum,H. Cognitive impairments
associated with formal thought disorder in people with
schizophrenia. J.Abnorm. Psychol. 111, 211–224
(2002).
166. Videbeck,S.L. Psychiatric Mental Health Nursing
(Lippincott Williams & Wilkins, 2006).
167. Hales,R.E., Yudofsky,S.C. & Roberts,L.W. The
American Psychiatric Publishing Textbook of Psychiatry
6th edn (American Psychiatric Publishing, 2014).
168. Haijma,S.V. etal. Brain volumes in schizophrenia:
a meta-analysis in over 18 000 subjects. Schizophr.
Bull. 39, 1129–1138 (2013).
169. Glahn,D.C. etal. Meta-analysis of gray matter
anomalies in schizophrenia: application of anatomic
likelihood estimation and network analysis. Biol.
Psychiatry 64, 774–781 (2008).
170. Fornito,A., Yücel,M., Patti,J., Wood,S.J. &
Pantelis,C. Mapping grey matter reductions in
schizophrenia: an anatomical likelihood estimation
analysis of voxel-based morphometry studies.
Schizophr. Res. 10 8, 104–113 (2009).
171. Ellison-Wright,I. & Bullmore,E. Anatomy of bipolar
disorder and schizophrenia: a meta-analysis.
Schizophr. Res. 11 7 , 1–12 (2010).
172. Vita,A., De Peri,L., Deste,G., Barlati,S. &
Sacchetti,E. The effect of antipsychotic treatment on
cortical gray matter changes in schizophrenia: does
the class matter? A meta-analysis and meta-
regression of longitudinal magnetic resonance
imaging studies. Biol. Psychiatry 78, 403–412
(2015).
173. Cole,M.W., Anticevic,A., Repovs,G. & Barch,D.
Variable global dysconnectivity and individual
differences in schizophrenia. Biol. Psychiatry 70,
43–50 (2011).
174. Argyelan,M. etal. Resting-state fMRI connectivity
impairment in schizophrenia and bipolar disorder.
Schizophr. Bull. 40, 100–110 (2014).
175. Cole,M.W., Yarkoni,T., Repovs,G., Anticevic,A. &
Braver,T.S. Global connectivity of prefrontal cortex
predicts cognitive control and intelligence.
J.Neurosci. 32, 8988–8999 (2012).
176. Baker,J.T. etal. Disruption of cortical association
networks in schizophrenia and psychotic bipolar
disorder. JAMA Psychiatry 71, 109–110 (2014).
177. Karbasforoushan,H. & Woodward,N.D. Resting-
state networks in schizophrenia. Curr. Top. Med.
Chem. 12, 2404–2414 (2013).
178. Jafri,M.J., Pearlson,G.D., Stevens,M. &
Calhoun,V.D. A method for functional network
connectivity among spatially independent resting-
state components in schizophrenia. Neuroimage 39,
1666–1681 (2008).
179. Whitfield-Gabrieli,S. etal. Hyperactivity and
hyperconnectivity of the default network in
schizophrenia and in first-degree relatives of persons
with schizophrenia. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 10 6,
1279–1284 (2009).
180. Palaniyappan,L., Simmonite,M., White,T.P.,
Liddle,E.B. & Liddle,P.F. Neural primacy of the
salience processing system in schizophrenia. Neuron
79, 814–828 (2013).
181. Mittner,M., Hawkins,G.E., Boekel,W. &
Forstmann,B.U. A neural model of mind wandering.
Trends Cogn. Sci. 20, 570–578 (2016).
This paper convincingly argues for the introduction
of two important novel elements to the scientific
study of mind-wandering: employing cognitive
modelling and a consideration of neuromodulatory
influences on thought.
182. Fox,K.C.R. & Christoff,K. in The Cognitive
Neuroscience of Metacognition (eds Fleming,S.M. &
Frith,C.D.) 293–319 (Springer, 2014).
183. Foulkes,D. & Fleisher,S. Mental activity in relaxed
wakefulness. J.Abnorm. Psychol. 84, 66–75 (1975).
184. Fox,K.C.R., Nijeboer,S., Solomonova,E.,
Domhoff,G.W. & Christoff,K. Dreaming as mind
wandering: evidence from functional neuroimaging
and first-person content reports. Front. Hum.
Neurosci. 7, 412 (2013).
185. De Bono,E. Six Thinking Hats (Little Brown and
Company, 1985).
186. Ellamil,M., Dobson,C., Beeman,M. & Christoff,K.
Evaluative and generative modes of thought during the
creative process. Neuroimage 59, 1783–1794 (2012).
187. Beaty,R.E., Benedek,M., Kaufman,S.B. &
Silvia,P.J. Default and executive network coupling
supports creative idea production. Sci. Rep. 5, 10964
(2015).
188. Fox,K.C.R., Kang,Y., Lifshitz,M. & Christoff,K. in
Hypnosis and Meditation (eds Raz,A. & Lifshitz,M.)
191–210 (Oxford Univ. Press, 2016).
189. Fazelpour,S. & Thompson,E. The Kantian brain: brain
dynamics from a neurophenomenological perspective.
Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 31 , 223–229 (2015).
Acknowledgements
The authors are grateful to R. Buckner, P. Carruthers,
M. Cuddy-Keane, M. Dixon, S. Fazelpour, D. Stan,
E. Thompson, R. Todd and the anonymous reviewers for their
thoughtful feedback on earlier versions of this paper, and to
A.Herrera-Bennett for help with the figure preparation.
K.C. was supported by grants from the Natural Sciences and
Engineering Research Council (NSERC) (RGPIN 327317–11)
and the Canadian Institutes of Health Research (CIHR)
(MOP-115197). Z.C.I. was supported by a Social Sciences and
Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC) postdoctoral
fellowship, the Balzan Styles of Reasoning Project and
a Templeton Integrated Philosophy and Self Control grant.
K.C.R.F. was supported by a Vanier Canada Graduate
Scholarship. R.N.S. was supported by an Alzheimer’s
Association grant (NIRG-14-320049). J.R.A.-H. was supported
by a Templeton Science of Prospection grant.
Competing interests statement
The authors declare no competing interests.
REVIEWS
NATURE REVIEWS
|
NEUROSCIENCE VOLUME 17
|
NOVEMBER 2016
|
731
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
©
2016
Macmillan
Publishers
Limited,
part
of
Springer
Nature.
All
rights
reserved.
... Importantly, the question of "where" remains undetermined (Koutsoklenis & Honkasilta, 2023). In the past two decades, there has been a growing interest regarding the tendency to engage in internally generated content, i.e., MW (Bozhilova, 2018;Callard et al., 2013;Christoff et al., 2016;Mills et al., 2018;Murray & Kraisch, 2020). MW is a thought pattern rooted in a competition between self-relevant internal priorities and task-relevant external priorities, with the former manifesting a higher incentive value . ...
... Others formulate MW as internally generated thought (Schooler et al., 2011) or task-unrelated thoughts , meaning that it is defined by its lack of relationship to the ongoing task at hand. These theoretical terminologies and operative definitions have been claimed to be vague and even paradoxical since they consider contradicting structures of thought such as wandering versus fixating, scattered versus coherent, reminiscing versus fantasizingas the same mental activity (Christoff et al., 2016;Irving, 2016;Irving & Thompson, 2018;Mills et al., 2018). It has also been criticized as contributing to a theoretical fog in the MW research field (Christoff et al., 2018). ...
Article
Maladaptive daydreaming (MD) is an impairing condition characterized by addiction to narrative, emotional fantasizing, involving dissociative absorption. By compulsively withdrawing towards vivid imaginative scenarios, MD hinders attentional functioning and replaces social interactions. Previous Interview-based research showed clinical importance in differentiating MD from Attention-Deficit/Hyperactivity Disorder (ADHD) and the associated construct of mind-wandering. We aimed to create a self-report tool asking directly about the content and structure of distracting thoughts. Two samples, namely, 346 undergraduate students and 381 adults from the general community, completed a novel measure, the Daydreaming Characteristics Questionnaire (DCQ), along with validated measures for ADHD, mind-wandering, MD, dissociation, and general distress. Exploratory Factor Analyses on the DCQ, replicated across both samples, yielded two distinct factors (immersive daydreaming, and daydream functionality) uniquely associated with MD. The DCQ represents characteristics of immersive daydreaming much more than general attentional deficiency and is thus useful in differentiating MD from ADHD/mind-wandering distractions.
... These response options were chosen to minimize assumptions about what the actual partition of mental states might be. For example, debates about what can be classified as MW 40 refer to whether MW is a coherent cluster of events 1,41 and how it is separated from awareness and processing of environmental stimuli 40,42 . We believe that our division respects the literature on internal/external thought-orientation brain networks 3,43,44 while introducing minimum assumptions as to the actual content of each state. ...
Article
Full-text available
Mind blanking (MB) is the inability to report mental events during unconstraint thinking. Previous work shows that MB is linked to decreased levels of cortical arousal, indicating dominance of cerebral mechanisms when reporting mental states. What remains inconclusive is whether MB can also ensue from autonomic arousal manipulations, pointing to the implication of peripheral physiology to mental events. Using experience sampling, neural, and physiological measurements in 26 participants, we first show that MB was reported more frequently in low arousal conditions, elicited by sleep deprivation. Also, there was partial evidence for a higher occurence of MB reports in high arousal conditions, elicited by intense physical exercise. Transition probabilities revealed that, after sleep deprivation, mind wandering was more likely to be followed by MB and less likely to be followed by more mind wandering reports. Using classification schemes, we found higher performance of a balanced random forest classifier trained on both neural and physiological markers in comparison to performance when solely neural or physiological were used. Collectively, we show that both cortical and autonomic arousal affect MB report occurrences. Our results establish that MB is supported by combined brain-body configurations, and, by linking mental and physiological states, they pave the way for novel embodied accounts of spontaneous thinking. ‘The stage 1 protocol for this Registered Report was accepted in principle on 02/01/23. The protocol, as accepted by the journal, can be found at: 10.17605/OSF.IO/SH2YE’ Techniques: Life sciences techniques, Biophysical methods [Electrocardiography - EKG]; Life sciences techniques, Biophysical methods [Electroencephalography - EEG]; CTS received date: 27.11.2024.
... These are task-unrelated, stimulus-independent thoughts that spontaneously arise over the course of daily life, and can occupy up to 60% of an individual's waking hours 2 . A defining feature of mind-wandering is that thoughts flow freely between topics without staying on any one concept for too long 3 . In contrast, when thought patterns become repetitively focused on content of self-referential negative valence, individuals may be said to be ruminating or worrying, generally known as repetitive negative thinking (RNT) 4 . ...
Article
Full-text available
The nature and frequency of spontaneous thoughts play a critical role in cognitive processes like perception, decision-making, attention, and memory. Deficits in these processes are also greatly associated with the development and maintenance of psychopathology. However, the underlying cognitive dynamics of free and stuck spontaneous thought remain unclear, as these often occur in the absence of measurable behaviors. Here, we analyze free word-association data using attractor-state dynamic modeling, which conceptualizes stuck spontaneous thought as navigating a multidimensional semantic space while in the presence of strong attractor locations. Word-association data was collected from an exploratory sample (N1 = 65), a first replication sample (N2 = 79), and, following pre-registration, a second replication sample (N3 = 222). After the data was embedded into a 3-dimensional semantic space and fit by our dynamic model, unsupervised learning consistently grouped data into four clusters across all independent samples. These clusters were characterized by two distinct patterns of stuck negative thinking, a pattern of protective positive thinking, and a pattern of flexible mind-wandering. Our results support a method for modeling spontaneous thought and isolate distinct sub-types that may not be accessible using retrospective self-report methods. We discuss implications for clinical and cognitive science.
... This differs from unguided thoughts that race from topic to topic without a particular course or aim, characterizing ADHD (Irving & Thompson, 2018;Theodor-Katz et al., 2022. Fantasizing is a free and spontaneous mental activity, more controlled than nocturnal dreaming but with fewer constraints and control than goal-directed thought (Christoff et al., 2016). ...
... This suggests offsetting between the two networks. One interpretation of this pattern is that these two networks support different yet complementary aspects of cognitive control, with the MDN important early in the trial when focusing on taskrelevant perceptual information, encoding trial rules, and deploying task-based processing, and the MAIN being activated when coordinating and regulating introspective processes such as those engaged during elaboration (Dixon et al., 2018;Christoff, Irving, Fox, Spreng, & Andrews-Hanna, 2016). The MAIN included rostrolateral prefrontal cortex, which has been associated previously with the construction of complex internal representations, particularly when reasoning processes are required to flexibly integrate novel details together (Roberts, Schacter, & Addis, 2018;Roberts et al., 2017;Christoff et al., 2001). ...
Article
Full-text available
fMRI studies typically explore changes in the BOLD signal underlying discrete cognitive processes that occur over milliseconds to a few seconds. However, autobiographical cognition is a protracted process and requires fMRI tasks with longer trials to capture the temporal dynamics of the underlying brain networks. In the current study, we provided an updated analysis of the fMRI data obtained from a published autobiographical event simulation study, with a slow event-related design (34-sec trials), that involved participants recalling past, imagining past, and imagining future autobiographical events, as well as completing a semantic association control task. Our updated analysis using Constrained Principal Component Analysis for fMRI retrieved two networks reported in the original study: (1) the default mode network, which activated during the autobiographical event simulation conditions but deactivated during the control condition, and (2) the multiple demand network, which activated early in all conditions during the construction of the required representations (i.e., autobiographical events or semantic associates). Two novel networks also emerged: (1) the Response Network, which activated during the scale-rating phase, and (2) the Maintaining Internal Attention Network, which, while active in all conditions during the elaboration of details associated with the simulated events, was more strongly engaged during the imagination and semantic association control conditions. Our findings suggest that the default mode network does not support autobiographical simulation alone, but it co-activates with the multiple demand network and Maintaining Internal Attention Network, with the timing of activations depending on evolving task demands during the simulation process.
... According to some studies, the DMN is composed of different subsystems (Andrews-Hanna et al. 2010, Christoff et al. 2016. A 'core' DMN subsystem is thought to be anchored on the vmPFC and the posteromedial cortex, while a 'dorsal medial subsystem' includes the dmPFC. ...
Article
Full-text available
Social comparisons are a core feature of human life. Theories posit that social comparisons play a critical role in depression and social anxiety triggering negative evaluations about the self, as well as negative emotions. We investigated the neural basis of social comparisons in participants with major depression and/or social anxiety (MD-SA, n = 56) and healthy controls (n = 47) using functional magnetic resonance imaging. While being scanned participants performed a social comparison task, during which they received feedback about their performance and the performance of a coplayer. Upward social comparisons (being worse than the coplayer) elicited high levels of negative emotions (shame, guilt, and nervousness) across participants, with this effect being enhanced in the MD-SA group. Notably, during upward comparison the MD-SA group showed greater activation than the control group in regions of the default mode network (DMN). Specifically, for upward comparison MD-SA participants demonstrated increased activation in the dorsomedial prefrontal cortex and reduced deactivation in the posteromedial cortex, regions linked to self-referential processing, inferences about other people’s thoughts, and rumination. Findings suggest that people with depression and social anxiety react to upward comparisons with a more negative emotional response, which may be linked to introspective processes related to the DMN.
Article
During wakefulness, the stream of thought is occasionally interrupted by moments when we cannot report any content, termed ‘mind-blanking’ (MB). As MB is a relatively unexplored mental state, we here examine how it relates to spontaneous thinking, namely, thought content and thought dynamics. By reviewing empirical studies on the neural correlates of MB, we first indicate that MB reports are mediated by variations in cortical and physiological arousal levels. In terms of thought content, we propose to view MB on a dimensional space representing content types, where MB is unrelated to any type of content. In terms of thought dynamics, we suggest conceptualizing MB as a moment during content transitioning or as a failure to transition across contents. Taken together, we suggest that MB has a unique place in the study of spontaneous thinking, and its inclusion can facilitate the isolation of the neural correlates of ongoing cognition.
Article
Full-text available
A neglected question regarding cognitive control is how control processes might detect situations calling for their involvement. The authors propose here that the demand for control may be evaluated in part by monitoring for conflicts in information processing. This hypothesis is supported by data concerning the anterior cingulate cortex, a brain area involved in cognitive control, which also appears to respond to the occurrence of conflict. The present article reports two computational modeling studies, serving to articulate the conflict monitoring hypothesis and examine its implications. The first study tests the sufficiency of the hypothesis to account for brain activation data, applying a measure of conflict to existing models of tasks shown to engage the anterior cingulate. The second study implements a feedback loop connecting conflict monitoring to cognitive control, using this to simulate a number of important behavioral phenomena.
Book
A study that goes beyond the debate over functional specialization to describe the ways that emotion and cognition interact and are integrated in the brain. The idea that a specific brain circuit constitutes the emotional brain (and its corollary, that cognition resides elsewhere) shaped thinking about emotion and the brain for many years. Recent behavioral, neuropsychological, neuroanatomy, and neuroimaging research, however, suggests that emotion interacts with cognition in the brain. In this book, Luiz Pessoa moves beyond the debate over functional specialization, describing the many ways that emotion and cognition interact and are integrated in the brain. The amygdala is often viewed as the quintessential emotional region of the brain, but Pessoa reviews findings revealing that many of its functions contribute to attention and decision making, critical components of cognitive functions. He counters the idea of a subcortical pathway to the amygdala for affective visual stimuli with an alternate framework, the multiple waves model. Citing research on reward and motivation, Pessoa also proposes the dual competition model, which explains emotional and motivational processing in terms of their influence on competition processes at both perceptual and executive function levels. He considers the broader issue of structure-function mappings, and examines anatomical features of several regions often associated with emotional processing, highlighting their connectivity properties. As new theoretical frameworks of distributed processing evolve, Pessoa concludes, a truly dynamic network view of the brain will emerge, in which "emotion" and "cognition" may be used as labels in the context of certain behaviors, but will not map cleanly into compartmentalized pieces of the brain.
Article
The role of the default-mode network (DMN) in the emergence of mind wandering and task-unrelated thought has been studied extensively. In parallel work, mind wandering has been associated with neuromodulation via the locus coeruleus (LC) norepinephrine (LC-NE) system. Here we propose a neural model that links the two systems in an integrative framework. The model attempts to explain how dynamic changes in brain systems give rise to the subjective experience of mind wandering. The model implies a neural and conceptual distinction between an off-focus state and an active mind-wandering state and provides a potential neural grounding for well-known cognitive theories of mind wandering. Finally, the proposed neural model of mind wandering generates precise, testable predictions at neural and behavioral levels.
Article
Large-scale analysis of functional MRI data has revealed that brain regions can be grouped into stable "networks" or communities. In many instances, the communities are characterized as relatively disjoint. Although recent work indicates that brain regions may participate in multiple communities (for example, hub regions), the extent of community overlap is poorly understood. To address these issues, here we investigated large-scale brain networks based on "rest" and task human functional MRI data by employing a mixed-membership Bayesian model that allows each brain region to belong to all communities simultaneously with varying membership strengths. The approach allowed us to 1) compare the structure of disjoint and overlapping communities; 2) determine the relationship between functional diversity (how diverse is a region's functional activation repertoire) and membership diversity (how diverse is a region's affiliation to communities); 3) characterize overlapping community structure; 4) characterize the degree of non-modularity in brain networks; 5) study the distribution of "bridges", including bottleneck and hub bridges. Our findings revealed the existence of dense community overlap that was not limited to "special" hubs. Furthermore, the findings revealed important differences between community organization during rest and during specific task states. Overall, we suggest that dense overlapping communities are well suited to capture the flexible and task dependent mapping between brain regions and their functions.
Article
Thoughts arise spontaneously in our minds with remarkable frequency, but tracking the brain systems associated with the early inception of a thought has proved challenging. Here we addressed this issue by taking advantage of the heightened introspective ability of experienced mindfulness practitioners to detect the onset of their spontaneously arising thoughts. We observed subtle differences in timing among the many regions typically recruited by spontaneous thought. Only in some of these regions did neural activation peak prior to the spontaneous arising of a thought - most notably in the medial temporal lobe and inferior parietal lobule. In contrast, activation in the medial prefrontal, temporopolar, mid-insular, lateral prefrontal, and dorsal anterior cingulate cortices peaked together with or immediately following the arising of spontaneous thought. We propose that brain regions that show antecedent recruitment may be preferentially involved in the initial inception of spontaneous thoughts, while those that show later recruitment may be preferentially involved in the subsequent elaboration and metacognitive processing of spontaneous thoughts. Our findings highlight the temporal dynamics of neural recruitment surrounding the emergence of spontaneous thoughts and may help account for some of spontaneous thought's peculiar qualities, including its wild diversity of content and its links to memory and attention.