ChapterPDF Available

Abstract

The supranational character of the European Union or supranationality itself represents a methodological basis for EU constitutionalization. This model of cooperation manifests the utilitarian and functionalist understanding of European integration, which emphasizes the efficiency of achieving the outlined goals of cooperation (Craig, The evolution of EU law. Oxford University Press, New York, 1999). This concept favours decision-making and the regulation of specific activities, which are confined to an independent administration, which unlike political representation, can more rapidly and effectively react to emerging problems, and to common desires of all involved entities.
123
S P R I N G E R BRIEFS IN L AW
OndrejHamuľák
National
Sovereignty in
the European
Union
View from the
Czech Perspective
Chapter 2
Constitutionalism Beyond the State
2.1 Supranationality as a Womb of Post-Westphalian
Deconstructions
The supranational character of the European Union or supranationality itself rep-
resents a methodological basis for EU constitutionalization. This model of coop-
eration manifests the utilitarian and functionalist understanding of European
integration, which emphasizes the efciency of achieving the outlined goals of
cooperation (Craig 1999). This concept favours decision-making and the regulation
of specic activities, which are conned to an independent administration, which
unlike political representation, can more rapidly and effectively react to emerging
problems, and to common desires of all involved entities. The formation of
supranational blocs not only helps to solve internal/mutual problems of the par-
ticipating states, but later it also becomes a consolation and means of confronting
the challenges of globalization (Holländer 2009).
The choice of the supranational method for the re-start of cooperation in
post-war Europe was based on the suppression of the logic of sovereign equality of
statesone of the basal principles of public international law.
1
Supranational
1
This principle was articulated by the Allies as a basis of post-war order of international relations
at the Moscow conference in October 1943, and after WW2 it was mentioned in the United
Nations Charter (article 2 paragraph 1). States are formally equal without prejudice to real power
relations and power distribution (military, economic and technical). Under sovereign equality,
nation states remain sovereign actors of the international community. There is no power that would
be superior to them, thus, no nation state can be forced to accept the binding effect of legal acts,
which the nation state did not participate on or did not agree with. We can observe a certain
paradox here. Even if we consider sovereign equality as just a different name for national
sovereignty, the establishment of international institutions and organizations makes its formulation
problematic, and its preservation threatens their existence. Hans Kelsen presented a contemporary
(and critical) analysis of the sovereign equality principle, where he highlighted the problem of
combining sovereign equality (which expected nation states to remain sovereign) with the actual
practice of international organizations jurisprudence (Kelsen 1944).
©The Author(s) 2016
O. Hamuľák, National Sovereignty in the European Union,
SpringerBriefs in Law, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-45351-4_2
7
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
cooperation negates this principle by several special features. Most visible is the
introduction of the qualied majority voting in the Council in connection with the
general binding force of decisions for all Member States. This could lead to a
situation when a Member State is bound by legal acts even if it did not vote in
favour of, or even it explicitly disagreed with, which violated the formal equality of
all voting countries. Furthermore, sovereign equality was affected by the estab-
lishment of an autonomous Court, which has obligatory jurisdiction in some
specied areas and which is authorized to review the compliance of Member States
behaviour with the demands of supranational law. Three basal instruments which
helps the Court of Justice to enforce EU law are: the judicial discourse, binding
judgements, and sanction-threats specied by article 260 of the Treaty on the
Functioning of the European Union (Panke 2010). Finally, the traditional position
of Member States is also affected by introduction of special responsibility regime
that helps to enforce obligations that stemmed from EU membership to the states
these were on one hand the doctrine of Member Statesduty to pay compensation to
individuals that suffered a loss due to the states violation of EU law (Aalto 2011) as
well as introduction of the special judicial procedure concerning the breaches of
EU law by the Member Statesinfringement procedure according to article 258
TFEUwhere Commission (as representative of supranational power) serves as the
main prosecutor.
As a result, the supranational organization competes with its forming blocsthe
national states. The EU is perceived as a mixed structure surpassing the denition of
a traditional international organization, and combining features of federation and
confederationit has jurisdiction and the power to legal regulation in certain areas
in all EU Member States; it uses the concept of divided competences of Member
States (units) and the EU (whole); it has the contractual foundations and holds the
subjectivity; and it has an autonomous set of own institutions (Wintr 2004).
European Communities and later European Union hold a sufcient autonomy and
space to comprehensively and without interference of Member States (or occa-
sionally even without their approval) manage affairs falling under its competences.
The supranational organizationa legal subject separate and independent of its
founding membersis positioned to certain extent aboveits Member States. This
superioritytowards Member States manifests itself in all stages of the law-making
process, and in the process of application of EU law. As a result, the law-making
institutions are independent, they have autonomous decision-making powers, they
independently execute individual decisions and accomplish objectives, which they
have dened, and nally EU law affects the legal status of individuals, who can be
awarded the rights or prescribed duties based on a supranational legal regulation
(Lenaerts and Van Nuffel 2005). The European Union is endowed with a com-
prehensive institutional, political and legal system, which likens it to a state and
represents a constitutional framework for its operation.
The supranational impetus associated with the creation of European
Communities and the evolution of the integration leads us to some theoretical
assumptions according to which international law in European region has entered
into post-Westphalian period (MacCormick 1999; Jakab 2006). This means the
8 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
necessity of rejection of the classical conception of the state sovereignty (indivis-
ible, exclusive, highest power) and acceptance of some supranational political and
legal will. I pay further attention to this phenomenon in the next chapters of this
volume.
European integration is something like planed and controlled deconstruction of
the content of the sovereignty of Member States. This phenomenon then logically
opens the debate about the nature of European Union itself. The central point of this
debate is the question whether the European Union is on the track to be a state-like
organization? I am not going to claim that European Union is a super-statewhich
replaced or is replacing the Member States. But on the other side one have to accept
that European Union is an autonomous entity, the original political structure which
has its own efcient construction of the internal organization and distinctive goals
and instruments leading to them.
2.2 The Complex Story of EU Constitutionalization
European integration transfers authority from Member States towards the supra-
national centre (Agnew 2009). This is the main building bloc of EUs own con-
stitutional story. Why do I speak about a story rather than a system? I believe that
the term storybetter describes the specics of the EU integration model, its
openness, constant changes, and doctrinal un-restrictiveness. EU constitutional-
ization and its constitutional matrix might be better understood as a narrative rather
than an exact formula. The story is a complex phenomenon. Here, the term com-
plexity manifests itself in both its linguistic meanings
2
; referring to its complicated
internal structure (involving many different related fragments), and to certain level
of incomprehensibility, which makes our understanding of this phenomenon more
intricate. The constitutionalization of the European project has certain quantitative
dimension (formal constitutional law)its structures, systems of operation, and
performed duties are constantly closer to the systems of the inner organization of
nation states (Forejtová2011). But it has also some qualitative dimension (material
constitutional law) while it is acquiring a constitutional character in terms of a
system of governance respecting rule of law, democratic principles and the invio-
lability of an individuals personal spheres. A large variety of texts examining EU
constitutionality almost unanimously assume that its basis lies in some autonomous,
internally organized structure of norms, relationships and principles without the
existence of a written constitution (Weiler 1999; Rosas and Armati 2010).
The unique characteristic of the Union gives rise to the notion of constitutional
movement which accompanies the European integration. Constitutionality,
Constitutional Law,Constitutional System’—all these terms currently exceeds
2
See the entry complexin the online version of Cambridge English Dictionary (http://dictionary.
cambridge.org/dictionary/british/).
2.1 Supranationality as a Womb of Post-Westphalian Deconstructions 9
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
beyond the borders of national states (De Búrca and Weiler 2012) and thus cannot
be regarded as sole objectives of the national law and jurisprudence. Certainly there
is no classical original pouvoir constituant behind the creation of the European
Union. But this claim does not contest the fact that the integration entities display
characteristics of a distinct constitutional system. The evidence of existence of such
system may be found in the specic structural elements that differentiates the
European Union from the traditional international organizations.
We may nd the social/institutional, normative and also material/meta-legal
arguments in favour of assertion that European Union has its own substantive
Constitution.
European Union has its own internal organization of relations between main partic-
ipating players (European Union and its Member States), between institutions of the
Union andbetween Union and the individuals/citizens of the Union. Here the assertionof
material constitutionality should sound like this: Where autonomous society exists, i.e.
some political and societal structure, there is a Constitution. The classic Latin maxim Ubi
societas ibi ius is transferred to the constitutionallevel here. This approach to the material
meaning of constitution is adhered to the theory of state of Georg Jellinek.
Another point is connected with the ability of the Union to manifest its own will
by the adoption of law (Forejtováand Tronecková2011) and making of admin-
istrative decisions. The Union has its own independent legal framework that lays
down rules of adoption of binding provisions. These provisions express the Union
powers in the outer world and they are internally applicable within the Member
States practice. The autonomous legal system give rise to the Kelsens argument
which should sound like this: Where a law is present, i.e. autonomous legal system
is working, there is a Constitution.
The last argument is connected with allegation according to which, where a rule
of law (i.e. democratic system based on the rule of law and protection of the fun-
damental rights) is respected there is a Constitution. Here, the role of mechanisms of
promotion and respecting the fundamental rights is crucial without any doubts.
The key role in determining the contours of the constitutionality of the European
Union was and still is played by the Court of Justice of the European Union. The
Court supported its quest for understanding the EU law as an autonomous con-
stitutional system also by some semantic turnovers. In judgment Les Verts
3
or
Opinion on the EEA Treaty
4
it expressly referred to the Treaty as constitutional
charter of the integration entities (Lenaerts 2010). It repeated this argument and the
crucial requirement which rises from it (that the [Union] is based on the rule of law,
inasmuch as neither its Member States nor its institutions can avoid review of the
conformity of their acts with the basic constitutional charter, the Treaty) also in
more recent constitutional hard casesKadi
5
and Opinion on Agreement on
3
Les Verts v Parliament, 294/83, ECLI:EU:C:1986:166.
4
Opinion on the EEA Treaty, 1/91, ECLI:EU:C:1991:490.
5
Kadi and Al Barakaat International Foundation v Council and Commission, C-402/05 P and
C-415/05 P, ECLI:EU:C:2008:461.
10 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
Accession to the ECHR.
6
The Court of Justice furthermore promoted independence
and some practical domination of European Union law as a prerequisite for the
functionality of the entire project of European integration. It served as the agent of
emancipation of supranational law and supranational entities.
7
And it was the Court
itself who played the pioneer role within the notion of respecting the fundamental
rights as general principles within the supranational legal and political structure (de
Witte 1999).
It is a fact that European Union lacks a written constitution. The attempt for its
documentary constitutionalisation
8
connected with the draft Treaty Establishing a
Constitution of Europe has failed.
9
Notwithstanding that the theory of EU law and
the Court of Justice does use the term constitution/constitutional Charterwithout
any doubts. EU is a sovereign polity with its own (even though not specically
designated) constitution, because it has its own system of legal rules, which regulate
its objectives, institutional competences, and individual rights, while establishing
the nature of the relationship between the centre, i.e. EU and its units, i.e. Member
States (Leczykiewicz 2009). Having in mind the complex sum of arguments
mentioned above the existence of the Constitutional system of the European Union
is a hardly contestable phenomenon. Of course it goes about the constitutionality in
the substantive sense of the word, the constitutionality based on principles, a
separation of powers and the human rights protection system, i.e. a respected
constitutionality and not one which was formally enacted or literally stated.
2.3 The Democratic Arrangement of the Internal
Functioning of the EU
The constitutional system and the constitutional law of the European Union predict
the existence of fundamental rules of organization of social structures. It indicates
that the Union may be foreseen as a legal community, an equivalent of the rule of
law-based state. It is a constitutional structure of a kind which acts, behaviours and
is regulated by the set of rules which have its own democratic ethos. The biggest
6
Opinion on the Agreement on Accession of the European Union to the European Convention for
the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, 2/13, ECLI:EU:C:2014:2454.
7
This is playing the role of Constitutional Court of the European Union.See Lenaerts and Van
Nuffel (2011, p. 22).
8
A term used to describe the process of drafting and adopting of the Treaty Establishing a
Constitution of Europe by Matej Avbelj and Jan Komárek (Avbelj and Komárek 2012).
9
Treaty Establishing a Constitution of Europe was prepared between February 2002 and July 2003.
It was signed by all Member States during an intergovernmental conference in June 2004. As well
known, the ratication process ended after it was rejected by a referendum in France and the
Netherlands (2005).
2.2 The Complex Story of EU Constitutionalization 11
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
shift towards democratic symbolism is connected with the Lisbon reform of primary
law. Restructuring the EU, or rather its internal unication and simplication,
represents the historically largest broadening of the EUs material competences.
Apart from the signicant changes such as the unication of the Unions pillar
structure, gaining legal subjectivity to the EU and general simplication of the
integration entities by replacing the Community with a Union, the Treaty of Lisbon
introduced many changes and novelties, which aimed at further establishing the
supranational character of the EU, strengthening its legitimacy in the eyes of the
internal subjects, i.e. Member States and individuals, increasing the effectiveness of
the decision-making process, securing internal security of the Union, and increasing
its importance in the international arena (Craig 2010).
The arrangement of the EU after Lisbon further strengthens the supranational
elements of integration. The most systemic factors in this regard (which lead
towards central governance, politically unify the EU and support its federal ten-
dencies) are: the new system of division of competences (article 23 TFEU),
introduction of the so-called passerelle clause (article 48 paragraph 7 TEU) or the
extension of applicability in case of the exibility clause (article 352 TFEU).
Other features increase the democratic legitimacy and accountability of the EU
and strengthen the ties between EU and individuals. Treaty of Lisbon made binding
the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the EU (article 6 TEU), which comprises the
list of fundamental rights that the EU and its Member States must respect. The
Treaty anticipated the citizens initiative (article 11 paragraph 4 TEU). It
strengthened the role of national parliaments which started to serve as control points
within the so-called early warning system in respect to fullment of the principle of
subsidiarity (Kiiver 2012) and of the European Parliament, which became an equal
partner of the Council through the introduction of the ordinary legislative procedure
for secondary law adoption, article 288 TFEU. Besides that the simplication of the
rules for the access of individuals to justice (by widening the locus standi of
individuals in the connection with the action for annulment according to article 263
TFEU) broadened the competences (or control potential) of the Court of Justice
(Mazák2011).
There were also some ideological features of the shift towards more legitimate
and democratic Union. They are rst of all expressed in the denition of values that
the EUs activities should observe as specied in article 2 TEU: The Union is
founded on the values of respect for human dignity, freedom, democracy, equality,
the rule of law and respect for human rights, including the rights of persons
belonging to minorities. These values are common to the Member States in a
society in which pluralism, non-discrimination, tolerance, justice, solidarity and
equality between women and men prevail.
The demarcation of the democratic values of the EU completes the EUs value
basis. These democratic values are dened by Title II TEU and they include the
equality of EUs citizens, representative democracy, dialogue with civil society, and
a principle, which we could describe as decentralization of the decision-making
processes, which rests on the amplied role and wider competences of national
parliaments. The accentuation of values and principles underlines the state-like
12 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
character/ambitions of the EU. It is not surprising that EU is getting the label as
partially federal entity(Piris 2010).
It is often assumed that a serious effort to federalize supranational entities must
be accompanied with an adequate increase in their democratic legitimacy
(Habermas 2001). The authors of the last major reform of the primary law
(Constitutional treaty and its Lisbon clone) to a large extent satised these calls
and (according to Habermasian logic
10
) made another step towards federalizing the
EU. Even though there are some critical voices (Mac Amhlaigh 2011) it is clear that
Treaty of Lisbon certainly increases the democratic legitimacy of both input
democracy, i.e. shift towards parliamentarianism and output democracy, i.e.
respecting rights of individuals (Lenaerts and Cambien 2009). When we take into
account that identication of basic values, higher importance of Unions citizenship
(Forejtová2014) or the increased role of national parliaments (article 12 TEU)
enhanced the traditional supranational features (especially the triad: autonomous
competencesautonomous institutionsautonomous law), we must accept that the
EU has fortied the legitimacy of its existence and activities, and is headed towards
deeper federalization of Europeans, therefore it is in accordance to Jean Monnets
programming statement (presented in Washington, 30 April 1952): Nous ne
coalisons pas des États, nous unissons des hommes.
2.4 Coven of Lawyers and Its ChildEmancipated
and Dominant EU Law
2.4.1 New Legal System Shaped by Judges and Lawyers
The nature of European Community and today European Union law has been
essentially connected with the supranational nature of European integration.
Meeting the autonomous objectives of integration requires an autonomous, effective
and unied legal system. A new lawmaker other than a nation state unavoidably
emerged here. Ability to regulate the behaviour and conduct of society abandoned
the exclusive monopoly of state power and thus opened way for a pluralistic set-out
(Bárány 2007).
Yet, we have to note that the creation of European Communities had an inter-
national legal (contractual) basis and as such EC law was originally considered as a
part of the public international law. The authors of the Treaties did not try or did not
need to resolve the challenges of use and effects of EC law within the national legal
systems. Nor they shaped the relationship between EC and national law or estab-
lished the procedures for resolving the potential conict. They tacitly assumed that
these issues would be resolved by the constitutional law of the Member States
10
Jürgen Habermas belongs among the most powerful advocates of the need to increase the EUs
legitimacy (Habermas 2001).
2.3 The Democratic Arrangement of the Internal Functioning of the EU 13
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
(access to the international legal commitments, theories of dualism and monism, the
concept of national laws precedence over international law) or alternatively by the
concepts of public international law (the concept of a self-executing international
treaty).
Thus, the Treaties do not include any specic instructions on how to use the
EC/EU law in national practice and how its relationship to national law must be
settled.
11
The Court of Justice played an irreplaceable role here as it became to
serve as the engine of shaping the character of EU law and as pivotal authority
marking the line between supranational and national law. It is worth mentioning the
fact that the Court of Justice actually seized this position despite the weak and
unclear denition of its competences in the EU primary law which was referred as
fragile jurisdictional base(Stein 1981). Mainly thanks to the Court of Justice that
the process of EU law constitutionalization took place (Corrias 2011). JiříPřibáň
adds that the utopia of European (supranational) constitutionalization could mate-
rialize only owing to this specic group of lawyers working for the Court of Justice
and in the legal services of the other Community institutions (Přibáň2010). Eric
Stein described the importance of the lawyersestate for the deepening of European
integration with the following hyperbole (paraphrased in the title of this chapter):
Constitutionalisation of European integration is a story of a dark conspiracy and
outrageous collusion, engineered by a coven of judges and lawyers against
unsuspecting governments(Stein 2005).
2.4.2 Autonomous Legal System
The nature of the European Union law is necessarily interconnected with the
supranational character of the European integration. In order to achieve autonomous
objectives of the integration entities an autonomous, effective and uniform legal
order is required.
The Court of Justice gradually dened the EC/EU law as an autonomous legal
order valid within the territory of all Member States (Stein 1981) It has laid down
that this law is directly applicable without the need of its reception into the national
legal orders. Its internal effects are independent from principles of legal orders of
Member States; far from it the supranational law itself via its own application
principles denes its internal effects within the legal orders of Member States.
The fundamental characteristic of the European Union legal order is its inde-
pendence, sometimes recalled as sovereignty of EU law (Jacobs 2007). It means
that this legal order exists independently from the national law of Member States
and general public international law. It is a legal order different from both inter-
national and national law and it has an autonomous character dened by these
elementary features (Barents 2004).
11
The only exception was the explicit denition of direct effect as a source of secondary law.
14 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
Own constitutional basis laid down in founding Treaties, i.e. rules of law with a
constitutional character which concern only the European Union. The European
Economic Community is based on the rule of law, neither its Member States
nor its institutions can avoid a review of the question whether the measures
adopted by them are in conformity with the basic constitutional charter, the
Treaty(Les Verts
12
).
The existence of the Court of Justice as its own, autonomous court of last instance
that interprets the EU law. The Community law has the only one binding
interpretation and this interpretation is exclusively made by the Court of Justice
who has this exclusive competence (Krohn
13
). The same exclusive competence
applies considering the validity of rules of the European Union law. This com-
petence is conferred only upon the Court of Justice (Foto-Frost
14
). National
courts are in case of doubts about the validity of rules of the European Union law
entitled to bring a preliminary question to the Court of Justice. However, they
cannot decide whether the rule of EU law is valid or not themselves.
The completeness and self-sufciency of the European Union law required to
solve issues under the competences of the European Union (especially the
sphere of exclusive competences) reects that in order to achieve effects pre-
sumed by the EU law no law-making activity from the national institutions of
Member States is required.
Autonomous determination of the characteristics and the principles of applica-
tion of supranational law. These principles are based on the case law of the
Court of Justice which determines the conditions of their use. National legal
orders do not regulate these principles specically.
The Court of Justice pointed out in its case law that even though the
Communities were established by an international treaty and thus they derived from
the public international law, they cannot be regarded as typical international
organizations. Nor their legislation is a regional public international law, but a legal
order with specic characteristics. The Community constitutes a new legal order of
international law for the benet of which the states have limited their sovereign
rights, albeit within limited elds, and the subjects of which comprise not only
Member States but also their nationals(Van Gend en Loos
15
). In less than a year
and a half after the Van Gend en Loos case the Court of Justice make the supra-
national law absolutely independent from the international public law and dened
as a completely independent (autonomous) legal order. The EEC treaty has created
its own legal system which, on the entry into force of the treaty, became an integral
part of the legal systems of the Member States and which their courts are bound to
apply(Costa vs. ENEL
16
).
12
Les Verts v Parliament, 294/83, ECLI:EU:C:1986:166.
13
Krohn, 74/69, ECLI:EU:C:1970:58.
14
Foto-Frost, 314/85, ECLI:EU:C:1987:452.
15
Van Gend en Loos, 26/62, ECLI:EU:C:1963:1.
16
Costa vs. ENEL, 6/64, ECLI:EU:C:1964:66.
2.4 Coven of Lawyers and Its ChildEmancipated and Dominant EU Law 15
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
The autonomous character of the Union law is logically followed by a certain
self-enforceabilityof this law within the territory of the Member States. That
means that the Member States are not anymore supposed to make their own
decisions regarding the internal effects of the European Union law. The traditional
monist and dualist theory that denes the system of internal effects and applicability
of the international law rules within the national legal orders, does not apply here.
In contrast to that traditional view the European Union law denes its effects
autonomously; it prescribes the kind of EU monism (Forejtová2015). By making
the supranational law independent, the Court of Justice refuted the schematic
opinion that the EC law was just another form of international law and its subjects
could be only contractual parties (e.g. national states). The penetration of supra-
national law into the national legal systems disrupts the sovereignty idol’—the
traditional concept according to which a direct intervention of supranational
(international) norms into the legal system of a sovereign country is inadmissible
(Klokočka 2006). The tensions between revolutionary and traditional approach was
visible also during negotiatingthe landmark decision in Van Gend en Loos case,
where three of the opposing Member States (Germany, Belgium, and the
Netherlands) unsuccessfully contended against self-enforceability of supranational
law by argument that sovereignty had to be preserved.
The main effect is that European Union law prescribes the obligation (recalled as
duty to apply; see Prechal 2007) of national authorities to use its provisions
directly without any need to adopt implementing national rules = the principle of
the direct applicability. The European Union law is an independent legal order but
in a meantime it is an integral partof the legal order applicable in the territory of
each of the Member States (Simmenthal
17
).
According to the Court of Justice, the direct (immediate) applicability means that
the provisions of the European Union law shall be applied uniformly and fully from
the date of their entry into force for so long as they will be set aside. The Court of
Justice makes in this connection no differences between the Union law and the
national law regarding their application by the national courts and public authori-
ties. On the contrary, it recognizes the provisions of the European Union law as an
inseparable part of the legal orders of the Member States The direct applicability of
Community law means that its rules must be fully and uniformly applied in all the
Member States from the date of their entry into force and for so long as they
continue in force. Directly applicable provisions are a direct source of rights and
duties for all those affected thereby, whether Member States or individuals; this
consequence also concerns any national court whose task it is as an organ of a
Member State to protect the rights conferred upon individuals by community law
(Simmenthal).
The courts and even the administrative authorities (Constanzo
18
) of the Member
States are obliged to recognize the European Union law as a part of their national
17
Simmenthal, 106/77, ECLI:EU:C:1978:49.
18
Fratelli Constanzo, 103/88, ECLI:EU:C:1989:256.
16 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
legal order. The supranational law has become a part of the routine legal practice of
the national authorities (especially the courts). The courts of the Member States
were given a new power. The conferral of liability of application and enforcement
of the rules of supranational law upon national courts makes them a part of the
general judicial system of the Union. Wide responsibility of the national general
courts led to increase of their importance and fuels the changes in their relation to
the national Constitutional Court (Komárek 2014).
Direct (immediate) application of European Union law is a crucial element of its
autonomy. In essence it includes the command to national courts to acknowledge
the supranational law as the law of their own landand apply it in the forms in
which it was originally adopted by the supranational power, i.e. without the need to
transpose it into intrastate sources. The impact here is objective and abstract.
However, independence of EU law also embraces a subjective/personal
dimension. It directly addresses individuals through the so-called direct effect
principle. Direct effect means that the provisions of EU law are capable to create
rights and impose duties for the individual subjects of national law, i.e. natural and
legal persons. Direct effect makes EU law a direct source of inuencing the legal
status of legal subjects at a national level. Awarding the EU legal norms with direct
effect principle signicantly enhanced the rules of effective applicability of EU law
and boosted individualsstatus in the legal system.
The Court of Justices case law regarding direct effect and especially as far as the
secondary law was concerned was based on the need for efciency and utility of
supranational norms. The so-called leffet utillerequirement (Sehnálek 2009)
would have been signicantly undermined if the Member States failed to meet the
obligations imposed on them by the EU rules.
Effective functioning of the EU legal system requires Member States, as carriers
of specic duties to be continuously supervised. This supervision is primarily
executed by the Commission, which can take a Member State to court for failure to
comply with EU law (article 258 TFEU). Owing to the direct effect of EU norms,
individuals also have some power to monitor the state and claim a remedy before
national courts. In this respect, we talk about the so-called dual vigilance
(Weatherill 2010) or double control over the Member States. The acceptance of the
direct effect of EU law gave individuals more protection and simultaneously they
became protectors (guardians) of the EU law and its integrity (Weiler 1991). The
inclusion of individuals under umbrella of supranational law transformed the EU
law into an absolute, complete legal system. Wide direct effect changed our per-
ception of supranational law. EU law is built on the shoulders of individuals and
individuals became the spine of its development. The presence of individuals in the
EU legal order further improved our understanding of this legal system as state-like
structure.
2.4 Coven of Lawyers and Its ChildEmancipated and Dominant EU Law 17
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
2.4.3 Dominant Legal System
The Court of Justice gradually dened EC (EU) law as an independent legal system
valid on the territory of all Member States. It stated that this law in all its forms (e.g.
the Treaties formed by the Member States, international treaties adopted by the EU
itself and sources of secondary law formed by EU institutions) shall be directly
applicable without the need of transposition into national legal systems. Its internal
effects were not dependent on the existence of legal basis prescribed by the Member
Stateslegal systems.
National authorities hold a number of duties vis-á-vis EU law norms. They must
accept EU law as an integral part of their national legal system; they have to consider
the content of EU law and objectives of the EU when interpreting national norms;
and when they face the conict between EU law and national law norms, they are
under duty to give preference to the EU law norm and refuse to apply the national
one. The principles of the internal application of EU law in the Member states clearly
demonstrate that the notion of self-enforceabilityof EU law should be understood
in broad meaning. It is not only an ability to produce legal effect without the
transposition to national system but also general dominance over national law which
must be accepted here. The dominance of EU law over national law has three limbs
(a) it is capable to regulate legal situation directly despite the existence of
conicting national rule (principle of primacy);
(b) it inuences and changes the interpretation and understanding of national
norms (indirect effect);
(c) and it is connected with the threat of responsibility regime, i.e. risk of erase of
state liability for damages caused by the serious breaches of EU law
requirements by the national authorities.
If the wording or meaning of national law provisions collides with the EU law, it
is the supranational law which behaves as dominant legal system. It prevails over
national rules in two ways. It paralyses the applicability of conicting national rules
(Costa case impact) or narrows the possible ways of interpretation of national
norms to only those options which are in line with the EU law requirements (Von
Colson case impact).
19
2.4.3.1 The Cohabitation of Colliding Legal WorldsThe Principle
of Primacy of the European Union Law
The relationship between EU law and the law of the Member States is mostly
determined by the primacy of former over the later. The so-called primacy of EU
19
Von Colson and Kamann vs. Land Nordrhein-Westfalen, 14/83, ECLI:EU:C:1984:153.
18 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
law (sometimes known as supremacy
20
) belongs among the basic characteristics of
EU law, and is an indispensably interconnected with the direct applicability prin-
ciple.
21
A unitary application of supranational law demands that it is utilized despite
conicting national norms. TEU demarcates loyalty as a basic EU Member States
duty, according to which their activities cannot endanger EU objectives (article 4
TEU), but such vaguely dened commitment to their loyalty does not necessarily
affect the autonomy of the national decision-makers will. Formal preservation of the
autonomous position of the national decision-maker might be reected in the
existence of a legal norm that would collide with the EU law. The primacy principle
solves such situations.
The application of this principle in real life gives the national judge (or any other
authority applying the law such as administrative body, see Constanzo case) the
obligation to abstain in the procedure in question from the application of a national
norm, which contradicts the EU law and to apply the EU norm.
The establishments of the primacy principle resolves the conict between the EU
norm and the national one, because the national judge and every other national
institution must in such a situation apply the EU legal norm, and ignore the
conicting national norm notwithstanding its legal nature and authority.
The primacy of the European Union law is its fundamental element that denes
the relationship between this law and the national law of the Member States (Alter
2001). This principle causes that the national judge (or any other authority applying
law) is (in cases decided by him) subject to an obligation not to apply the national
legal rule inconsistent with the European legislation. European Union law thus
enjoys the ability to take priority over national legal norms in the sphere of the
judicial or administrative practice. It had to be pointed here, that primacy does not
mean absolute normative superiority. Introduction of this principle into the practice
20
The theoretical approach includes opinions which believe that primacy and supremacy should be
distinguished. These opinions generally refer to the crucial judgement of the Spanish constitutional
court on the compatibility of the Treaty Establishing a Constitution for Europe with the Spanish
Constitution of 13 December 2004. The Constitutional Court drew a line between primacy and
supremacy and accepted the former as an important characteristic of the EU law, and the latter as
inherent to the norms of the Spanish Constitution, because only the Constitution contained the
legal basis for Spains EU membership. Similarly, they referred to the England and Wales High
Court decision Thoburn v Sunderland City Council [2002] EWHC 195 (Admin), where supremacy
had been connected with the constitutional basis of the EU laws effect, and primacy with actual
dominance of EU law within such system (Avbelj 2011).
21
The theory of EU law discusses whether primacy and direct applicability/direct effect are
independent and separate principles of EU law, which are not necessarily related, or whether they
are related where primacy acts as a rule on a conict of norms in case when a directly applicable
norm of EU law collides with national law (Hinarejos 2008). I personally prefer the latter view.
The primacy principle was created to resolve conicts between national and European law. In
order for a conict to arise, the normative spheres (Bobek et al. 2011) of EU and national law must
overlap, which is possible only where there is a directly applicable EU norm. Primacy then serves
as an auxiliary principle, which should help to reach the full efcacy of EU law in cases when
directly applicable norm contradictsthe national law.
2.4 Coven of Lawyers and Its ChildEmancipated and Dominant EU Law 19
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
of application of law was not followed by the building of hierarchy pyramid
between the European Union law and national law of Member States.
The TEU denes only the fundamental obligation of states not to jeopardize the
attainment of the Unions objective = the principle of loyalty (article 4 paragraph 3
TEU). This generally dened obligation does not in principle impinge on the
autonomy of the will of the national legislator. The formal preservation of the
autonomous position of the national lawmaker may nd it is echo in the existence
of the national legislation inconsistent with the EU law. The principle of primacy
was established in order to solve the collision between the supranational law and the
national law. In case of this collision the national judge shall use the rule of EU law
and not apply the national provisions.
The principle of primacy does not emanate directly from any text of primary or
secondary law source.
22
Its basis, extent and effects were built from the case law of
the Court of Justice of the European Union.
The key-decision was the judgment of the Court of Justice in Costa case. The
Court of Justice laid down in this decision the basis of the doctrine of the primacy
of the Community (now EU) law over the national law. It dened the independence
of the supranational law, solved the issue of the relationship between the national
law of the Member States and the Community law and the division of powers
between the Union and the Member States. The Court of Justice considered the
conferral of powers upon the Community/Union as permanent and denitive and
recognized thus the independence of the supranational entity. According to the
Court of Justice: By creating a community of unlimited duration, having its own
institutions, its own personality, its own legal capacity and capacity of represen-
tation on the international plane and, more particularly, real powers stemming from
a limitation of sovereignty or a transfer of powers from the states to the community,
the Member States have limited their sovereign rights, albeit within limited elds,
and have thus created a body of law which binds both their nationals and
22
The rst attempt to stipulate this relationship occurred with the drawing up of the
Treaty establishing a Constitution for Europe, which for the rst time stated in article I-6 the legal
specications of the EU laws primacy. The failure of the constitutional process led to a post-
ponement of the legal denition of the EU law in the EUs primary law. The opportunity to solve
this problem opened again with the Treaty of Lisbon. It is well known that this document lacked
the formal constitutional ambitions of the Constitutional Treaty, thus, its text lacked provisions
with constitutional symbolism and did not carry any constitutional legal implications as had been
the case with article I-6 of the Constitutional Treaty. The authors of the Lisbon reform referred to
the principle of primacy only in the declarations attached to the Final Act of the Intergovernmental
Conference. Specically Declaration no. 17 recalls in a form of some softlaw(Craig and De
Búrca 2011) that the primacy principle is a stable principle of EU law and the failure to legally
dene it does not change the fact that it plays an important role when securing the effective
operation of EU legal regulation (The Declaration concerning primacy stipulates that: The
Conference recalls that, in accordance with well settled case law of the Court of Justice of the
European Union, the Treaties and the law adopted by the Union on the basis of the Treaties have
primacy over the law of Member States, under the conditions laid down by the said case law.).
The Declaration concerning primacy can be understood as a political consecrationof the Court of
Justices established case law (Niedobitek 2009).
20 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
themselves. [] the law stemming from the treaty, an independent source of law,
could not, because of its special and original nature, be overridden by domestic
legal provisions, however framed, without being deprived of its character as
community law and without the legal basis of the community itself being called into
question.
The primacy of the European Union law is a logical supplement to the principle
of the direct applicability. The uniform application of the supranational law requires
necessarily applying this law despite the collision with national provisions.
The principle of primacy of the EU law covers all sources of the European Union
law including the secondary legislation (Kreil
23
). According to the case law of the
Court of Justice, the supranational law has both retroactive effects (the application
of the already existing national legislation is ruled out) and future effects (the
application of the new national law is ruled out in the extent they will be incon-
sistent with the European norms Simmenthal). This effect of the primacy principle
derives from the requirement of an effective and uniform application of the
European Union law.
The formation of the primacy doctrine in Costa case represented the fundamental
basis within the framework of relationship between the Community (nowadays
Union) legal order and the national law of the Member States. In above-mentioned
case the Court of Justice did not express any limits of the primacy. Therefore, some
open questions remained. The most important and the most sensitive question was
whether this doctrine should apply also in connection with the cases of collision
between EU law and the highest rules of the national law = the Constitution and the
Constitutional law. The Court issued its opinion on this question in the judgment
Internationale Handelsgesellschaft.
24
There it dened the absolute weight of the
doctrine of primacy of the Union law. In case where the supranational law and the
national constitutional provisions regulate certain issues differently, the European
Union law shall prevail. National constitutional rules cant have the precedence
over the European Union law. Otherwise the autonomous character of the Union
and its legal order would be interfered as well as the effectiveness of achieving the
objectives of integration would be impinged. The next quoted passage from that
case became legendary: Recourse to the legal rules or concepts of national law in
order to judge the validity of measures adopted by the institutions of the community
would have an adverse effect on the uniformity and efcacy of community law. The
validity of such measures can only be judged in the light of community law. In fact,
the law stemming from the treaty, an independent source of law, cannot because of
its very nature be overridden by rules of national law, however framed, without
being deprived of its character as community law and without the legal basis of the
community itself being called in question. Therefore the validity of a community
measure or its effect within a Member State cannot be affected by allegations that it
23
Kreil, C-285/98, ECLI:EU:C:2000:2.
24
Internationale Handelsgesellschaft, 11/70, ECLI:EU:C:1970:114.
2.4 Coven of Lawyers and Its ChildEmancipated and Dominant EU Law 21
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
runs counter to either fundamental rights as formulated by the constitution of that
state or the principles of a national constitutional structure.
It is clear that Court of Justice understands primacy in absolute terms and does
not distinguishes between situations where obstacles to EU law have their roots in
general or constitutional law of Member state. This, however, does not change the
fact that primacy principle still has more or less procedural character and the Court
of Justice did not establish formal hierarchical relations between supranational and
national law. There is no hierarchy between these systems in terms of the validity of
norms, but there is some kind of structural relationship in terms of the applicability
of concrete legal rules to the facts in particular case. The primacy of EU law simply
establishes the obligations of national authorities to follow immediately the EU
norms, i.e. to abstain from applying a colliding national norm in a specic proce-
dure. A national court that hears the case cannot initiate any validity review; pro-
pose annulment or any other process of eliminating a national norm that contradicts
the EU legislation. The Court of Justice specically states that any provision of a
national legal system and any legislative, administrative or judicial practice which
might impair the effectiveness of Community law by withholding from the national
court having jurisdiction to apply such law the power to do everything necessary at
the moment of its application to set aside national legislative provisions which
might prevent, even temporarily, Community rules from having full force and effect
are incompatible with those requirements, which are the very essence of
Community law.
25
The Court of Justice recalled the separated understanding of European and
national law also in decision Filipiak,
26
where it is restated that: Pursuant to the
principle of the primacy of Community law, a conict between a provision of
national law and a directly applicable provision of the Treaty is to be resolved by a
national court applying Community law, if necessary by refusing to apply the
conicting national provision, and not by a declaration that the national provision is
invalid, the powers of authorities, courts and tribunals in that regard being a matter
to be determined by each Member State (point 82)and further [] the incom-
patibility with Community law of a subsequently adopted rule of national law does
not have the effect of rendering that rule of national law non-existent. []
27
While it is true that the principle of the primacy of European Union law may
inuence in some way the decisions of the national legislature, the immediate
invalidation of the national law does not follow from this principle. The question of
validity or invalidity does not arise here as the two legal systemsEU law and the
national laware separate and autonomous legal orders.
28
No Treaty provision
25
Simmenthal, 106/77, ECLI:EU:C:1978:49, point 22.
26
Filipiak, C-314/08, ECLI:EU:C:2009:719.
27
Filipiak, C-314/08, ECLI:EU:C:2009:719, points 8283.
28
The only exception where setting aside (invalidation) of conicting national rules is necessary
(or better said required by EU law) arises in the situation when even the mere existence of the
national legal rule may endanger the application of the Union competences. Under those cir-
cumstances in order to strengthen the legal certainty and the position of individuals enjoying the
22 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
provides for a power to decide on the validity of national law with derogative
effects. Even condemnatory decision of the Court of Justice within the infringement
proceedings (article 260 TFEU) stating the failure to comply with EU legislation
caused by the existence of national legislation contradicting EU law does not bring
this consequences. Neither decision within preliminary ruling where the Court of
Justice indirectly (commenting on an EU law provision) identies a contradiction
between national and EU norms does not have this effects.
29
Introduction of principle of primacy and its absolute understanding vis-á-vis
national constitutional law serve as one of the main arguments in federalization
debate in Europe. The primacy (supremacy) of federal law over the law of the states
serves as the classical constitutional arrangement of modern federal states. It should
be recognized also as feature of formal constitutionalization of the EU (Schütze
2014). But it is the contested feature because this federal matrix is not explicitly
regulated in the main constituent documents (the Treaties) which content the
expressed will of foundersthe Member States. It is only the adjudicated principle
which is therefore open to (judicial) deliberations and contestations on the side of
national courts, which we will see on the Czech example in second part of this
volume.
2.4.3.2 Indirect Dominance of Supranational Rules. An EU-Consistent
Interpretation of National Law
The EU law is capable to affect the legal practice within the Member States even
much broader than by the normative inuence described above. The consequences
of Member States EU membership include also the commitment to solidarity or
loyalty (see article 4 paragraph 3 TEU) which stands as the building block of all
non-normative (i.e. different to direct applicability of EU norms) impacts of the EU
law. The most widely used non-normative impact is related to the so-called prin-
ciple of indirect effect. This principle implies the obligation of national authorities
to reect the aims of EU law and to follow the goals of EU norms when interpreting
national law. EU law stands here as a dominant matrix and forces the national
authorities to choose the pro-European options of given possible mods of national
law interpretation. Indirect effect of EU law is a exible principle. It produces
(Footnote 28 continued)
subjective rights steaming from EU law provisions, the Member States may be obliged to eliminate
(invalidate) the contradicting national rule (see Commission v. France, 167/73, ECLI:EU:
C:1974:35). But this consequence cannot be regarded as the impact of the primacy principle. The
extraordinary duty to set aside provision(s) of national law under above-mentioned circumstances
must be understood as impact of general principle (obligation) of loyalty (established by article 4
paragraph 3 TEU) according to which Member States he Member States hold a duty to take all
appropriate measure to ensure fullment of their obligations arising out of the Treaties or from the
acts of the institutions of the EU.
29
Attanasio Group, C-384/08, ECLI:EU:C:2010:133, point 16.
2.4 Coven of Lawyers and Its ChildEmancipated and Dominant EU Law 23
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
several consequences in national practice which are dependent on the wording and
strength of EU law norm (used as the model) and wording and scope of national
rule as well. EU law may be used as argument in different forms:
as conrmative argument to underline the relevance of the chosen decision,
which clearly ows from national law,
as mediatory argument where EU norm determines which of plausible paths of
interpretation of national law must be chosen.
as evolutive argument where EU law bent the traditional interpretation of
national norm and open it for new non-established meanings.
30
The foundations of the principle of the indirect effect of the European Union law,
i.e. the obligation to interpret the national law in conformity with the EU law
requirements were settled in Von Colson case. It represents another pillar of effective
impact of EU law in proceedings before national authorities. Basically it means that
the national judge (or another authority responsible for application of law) is obli-
gated to interpret the national law in the light of objectives and content of rules of EU
law. It was originally associated with the directives. According to the Court of
Justice: the Member Statesobligation arising from a directive to achieve the result
envisaged by the directive and their duty under article 5 of the Treaty to take all
appropriate measures, whether general or particular, to ensure the fullment of that
obligation, is binding on all the authorities of Member States including, for matters
within their jurisdiction, the courts. It follows that, in applying the national law and
in particular the provisions of a national law specically introduced in order to
implement directive [], national courts are required to interpret their national law
in the light of the wording and the purpose of the directive in order to achieve the
result referred to in the third paragraph of article 189. [] It is for the national court
to interpret and apply the legislation adopted for the implementation of the directive
in conformity with the requirements of community law, in so far as it is given
discretion to do so under national law.
31
The Court of Justice resolved here a
question whether the directive may have some legal effects even though its provi-
sions do not meet requirements laid down by Van Gend en Loos formula (are not
sufciently clear, precise and unconditional) and thus they cannot be directly
applicable. It replied this question in the afrmative because it stated an obligation of
national courts to interpret their law in line with the meaning of the directive. The
arguments for the imposition of such a new duty on national authorities were based
on the binding nature of directives and the principle of loyalty (article 4, paragraph 2,
third subparagraph 3 TEU) which impose to Member States the duty to take any
measures to full the obligations conferred upon them by Treaties.
30
Michal Bobek recalls these three options as weak, medium and strong indirect effect (Bobek
2014).
31
Von Colson and Kamann vs. Land Nordrhein-Westfalen, 14/83, ECLI:EU:C:1984:153, points
2728.
24 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
The subsequent case law of the Court of Justice brought the substantial devel-
opment of the principle of the indirect effect. The duty to interpret national law in
the light of EU norms evolved both qualitatively and quantitatively. At the very
beginning it covered only the duty to interpret national law adopted in order to
implement directives in the light of this particular directive. It was introduced as
some kind of alternative to the lacking direct effect (Betlem 2002) but developed to
the inuential impact of EU regulative power. The crucial expansions were brought
by the decision in Marleasing
32
case where Court of Justice brought a clarication
of some problematic aspects of this principle:
It extended the scope of national law that has to be interpreted in the light of
rules of EU law. One of the most problematic issues of the doctrine of indirect
effect was whether the duty of consistent interpretation covers only that part of
the national law that implemented a certain directive into the national legal
system of the Member State or whether it covers also other national laws whose
adoption was not related with the implementation. The Court of Justice stated
that duty of consistent interpretation has to be understood widely and
acknowledged that indirect effect covers all the national law even that which
was not adopted in the connection with the implementation of the directive and
no matter whether it was adopted before or after the adoption of the directive.
Basically the principle of indirect effect affects the national legal order as a
whole (including the national constitutions).
Another important issue is that Court of Justice acknowledged the impact of
indirect effect also in so-called horizontal relationships. National courts are
according to this wide view obliged to interpret the national law in a harmony
with EU requirements even in disputes between individuals, where indirect
effect served mainly as an alternative to the prohibition of horizontal direct effect
of directives.
The indirect effect stands as a robustEU law principle (Bobek 2014) and its
wide consequences seem to be more crucial for the national sovereignty and
national law autonomy discussions than the direct applicability and primacy. It is
because indirect effect is connected with all provisions of EU law and touches all
elds of national law and is capable to turn the established way of interpretation of
domestic norms (and therefore the adjudication processes). However, this wide
inuence is balanced by the fact that it is still national law, which is applied here. In
comparison with direct effect and primacy we do not face here the penetration of
norms produced by different public power and replacement of national norms. It is
also worth to say here, that direct effect is not limitless. Court of Justice expressed
several boundaries of EU-consistent interpretation of national law, which more or
less should act to protect its autonomy. It has formulated following rules in the
connection with the limits of obligation of national judges to interpret the national
law in the light of the European Union norms:
32
Marleasing vs. Comercial Internacional de Alimentación, C-106/89, ECLI:EU:C:1990:395.
2.4 Coven of Lawyers and Its ChildEmancipated and Dominant EU Law 25
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
The interpretation of the national law in the light of European Union law pro-
visions is limited by the scope of discretionary competences of the national
authority applying law and interpretation methods governed by the national law
(Von Colson).
The EU-consistent interpretation of the national law may not lead into con-
clusions denying the essence of the national legislation, i.e. to decisions contra
legem (Marleasing).
The position of an individual may not be aggravated in the meaning of the
establishment or the extension of the criminal responsibility (Kolpinghuis
33
).
In case of indirect effect of a directive the obligation of the harmonious inter-
pretation may be established only after the expiration of the period prescribed
for the implementation of a directive (Adeneler
34
).
2.4.3.3 The Price for the Non-conformityState Liability
for Damages Caused by Breaches of EU Law
The principle of state liability is usually perceived as remedy used to enforce the
individual right prescribed by the EU law (Aalto 2011). This principle completes
the aforementioned characteristics of the EU law as a complex and autonomous
legal order. The liability for damages is certain subsidiary consequence which
serves as a tool to protect individuals in case when State breaches its obligations
deriving from its commitments as a Member of the EU. From another point of view,
this remedy widens the notion of dominance of EU law and has a special relevance
for the sovereignty discussions. This special European remedy is an example of
interventionist approach(Dougan 2004) of the Court of Justice to the scale of
national remedies. Its wide evolution in the Courts case law touches upon the
autonomy of national (remedial) law but also interfere with the sensitive questions
like sovereignty of national legislators and independence of national courts. This
principle closes the circle of dominance by introduction of responsibility regime
connected with ignoranceof EU law rules by the Member States.
The pilot decision forming this doctrine was issued in case Francovich.
35
Form
and conditions were subsequently governed by following case law of the Court of
Justice. The Court of Justice understands the liability of the Member States for
damages as one of the key principles of EU law inherent to the system of the Treaty.
According to the Court of Justice the liability is a matter of principle because: It
should be borne in mind at the outset that the EEC Treaty has created its own legal
system, which is integrated into the legal systems of the Member States and which
their courts are bound to apply. The subjects of that legal system are not only the
Member States but also their nationals. Just as it imposes burdens on individuals,
33
Kolpinghuis Nijmegen, 80/86, ECLI:EU:C:1987:431.
34
Adeneler and others, C-212/04, ECLI:EU:C:2006:443.
35
Francovich and Bonifaci vs. Italy, C-6/90 and C-9/90, ECLI:EU:C:1991:428.
26 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
Community law is also intended to give rise to rights which become part of their
legal patrimony. Those rights arise not only where they are expressly granted by the
Treaty but also by virtue of obligations which the Treaty imposes in a clearly
dened manner both on individuals and on the Member States and the Community
institutions []. Furthermore, it has been consistently held that the national courts
whose task it is to apply the provisions of Community law in areas within their
jurisdiction must ensure that those rules take full effect and must protect the rights
which they confer on individuals []. The full effectiveness of Community rules
would be impaired and the protection of the rights which they grant would be
weakened if individuals were unable to obtain redress when their rights are
infringed by a breach of Community law for which a Member State can be held
responsible.
36
Court of Justice clearly recalled here to the notion of autonomy and
effectiveness of EU law. It repeated also the loyalty commitment of the Member
States. The style of the judgement and arguments used by the Court are very close
to the constitutionally landmark decisions (Costa, Van Gend, Simmenthal, actually
quoted by the Court) and puts this decision on the same level of importance.
Signicant development and clarication of problematic issues related to the
liability doctrine were brought by the Court of Justice in Brasserie du Pêcheur
case.
37
One of the problems not covered by the Francovich case was the question
whether the Member States are liable for damages also in cases where they breach
the directly applicable rule of supranational law. The government of Member States
argued against the rise of liability in this situation and reasoned their position by the
plea that the direct effect is an adequate instrument to protect rights of individuals,
that there are sufcient national instruments for claiming the reparation and thus it is
not necessary to held the state responsible for the infringement also under the EU
law. The Court of Justice refused this argument and stated that the direct effect is
not a satisfactory instrument to ensure the effectivity of individualsremedy for
coverage of suffered harm. This principle entitles individuals to seek the EU law
directly in the proceedings before the national court but it does not guarantee the
reparation for damages and loss caused by the breach of States obligations. The
doctrine of the States liability for damages complements the principle of the direct
effect but it is an autonomous notion within the complex system of EU law. The
judgment also contributed signicantly to the development of conditions of
the State liability for damages. Court did not formulate the precise denition of the
liability but it lay down that the liability is conditional on many circumstances (such
as a precise denition of discretionary competences of the states authority, clarity
or non-clarity of the infringed norms, etc.). According to this decision the liability
conditions state as follows:
36
Francovich and Bonifaci vs. Italy, C-6/90 and C-9/90, ECLI:EU:C:1991:428, points 3135.
37
Brasserie du Pêcheur vs. Bundesrepublik Deutschland and The Queen/Secretary of State for
Transport, ex parte Factortame and others, C-46/93 and C-48/93, ECLI:EU:C:1996:79.
2.4 Coven of Lawyers and Its ChildEmancipated and Dominant EU Law 27
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
the infringed rules of EU law shall prescribe or at least presume the existence of
certain subjective rights of individual;
there must be a direct causal link between the breach of EU law and the loss or
damage caused;
the breach of EU law caused by the State authorities must be sufciently serious.
The denition of the seriousness of the breach depends on the clarity of the
Union rule infringed and further on the margin of a discretion left by the EU law
to the national authority
(1) Incase of a narrowmargin of discretion orno discretion, any infringement of the
MemberStateobligationissufcienttobedescribedastheseriousbreach.
(2) In case of a broad margin of a discretion of national authority it is further
necessary to prove the seriousness by subsidiary arguments, for instance a
fault, a conduct contrary to the settled case law, a contributory fault of an
individual, a certain margin of Union co-liability deriving from the unclear
denition of the state obligations, etc.
In Brasserie du Pêcheur, the Court of Justice also claried the question for the
conduct (or omission) of which national authorities the Member States should be
responsible. Here it stated that the States are liable regardless whether the breach of
EU law was caused by an authority representing legislative or executive power.
Further the Court of Justice broadened the sum of national authorities for whose acts
the State may be held responsible. The categories were widened to the local
authorities (Konle
38
;Haim
39
) and also to the national judiciary (Köbler
40
; Traghetti
del Mediterraneo
41
).
The liability of the State for the acting of the authorities representing the judicial
power is one of the most sensitive issues of the EU law (because of the judicial
independence, the wide discretion, etc.) and it is the subject to some additional
conditions (Breuer 2004). According to the Court of Justice the Member State
should be held responsible for the damage and loss caused by the breach of the
European Union law only under the circumstances that this damage was caused by
the decision of national court of the last instance and that infringement of the EU
law rule by the national court was sufciently manifest (arbitrary). However,
Member States cannot pose any special limitations or conditions for the claims of
individuals for compensation of damages caused by such manifest breach of EU
law. For example, restriction of the liability of Member State for the activity of the
judiciary only to the cases involving intentional fault or gross negligence of justices
is incompatible with the general principle of the liability of Member States for a
breach of EU law (Commission v Italy
42
).
38
Konle, C-302/97, ECLI:EU:C:1999:271.
39
Haim, C-424/97, ECLI:EU:C:2000:357.
40
Köbler, C-224/01, ECLI:EU:C:2003:513.
41
Traghetti del Mediterraneo, C-173/03, ECLI:EU:C:2006:391.
42
Commission vs. Italy, C-379/10, ECLI:EU:C:2011:775.
28 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
2.5 CerberusGuarding the Fundamental Rights
43
Nowadays, the key provisions which dene the Union as a constitutional com-
munity based on respect for human rights are included in the Treaty on European
Union. The most important are article 2 TEU (which denes the values of European
Union and presents the human rights as the fundamental core of the integration),
article 6 TEU (which denes or summarizes the sources and several instruments of
the human rights protection within the European Union) and article 7 (which
introduces the mechanism of control and sanctioning of the Member States in the
cases of grave violation of the fundamental rights by them).
The central provision is the second aforementioned provision (article 6 TEU) which
denes the three cornerstones of the protection of fundamental rights at the suprana-
tional level. These three totems seems to provide Union within the most complex
system of the promotion of fundamental rights which shall work as the one body of
tools with three different headslike the Cerberus guarding the mythic underworld.
Moreover, this strong impetus on the role of fundamental rights within the
supranational legal order serves as an indirect tool of defence of supranational
(Courts) view on the nature of the legal system of the Community and Union,
respectively (Craig 2010). The recognition of fundamental rights as immanent part
of supranational law and establishment of the complex system of their protection
rendered to the supranational legal system the nature of the constitutional order.
Therefore, it was suitable to be accepted by the national courts in their practice as
the law applicable in their judicial decision-making. The big lesson here was
learned in connection with the famous Solange sagaof German Federal
Constitutional Court (Frowein 1988). German court primarily rejected the possi-
bility of unlimited application of Community law within the national legal practice
by the argument that supranational law showed serious deciencies in the eld of
protection of individuals. It stated that as long as Community system will show the
deciencies (in comparison with German level) it will not accept its general internal
effects (case Solange I
44
). Once the Community system improved and the doctrine
of fundamental rights was introduced the Federal Constitutional Court changed its
opinion and accepted the application of Community rules (case Solange II
45
) but
once more with the objection that It will serve as the ultima ratio guardian of the
structural quality of this reached level. In case when serious structural discrepancies
will appear within the supranational system the German court reserves itself the
right not to accept the internal applicability of the certain rules of EU law within
43
This chapter is based on my previous work with title Idolatry of Rights and Freedoms
Reections on the Autopoietic Role of Fundamental Rights within Constitutionalization
of the European Union, which was published in volume Protecting Human Rights in the EU.
Controversies and Challenges of the Charter of Fundamental Rights (see Hamuľák2014).
44
Solange IInternationale Handelsgesellschaft von Einfuhrund Vorratsstelle für Getreide und
Futtermittel, decision of 29 May 1974, BVerfGE 37, 271.
45
Solange IIWünsche Handelsgesellschaft decision of 22 October 1986, BVerfGE 73, 339.
2.5 CerberusGuarding the Fundamental Rights 29
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
German system (Lebeck 2006). This raised nger is still valid (see its repetitions in
Maastricht-Urteil
46
as well as in Lissabon-Urteil
47
) and transmitted also to the
approach of other Member States courts (Czech Constitutional Court may serve as
one of the most inuenced examples, see cases Sugar Quotas
48
;European Arrest
Warrant,
49
Lisbon I
50
and Lisbon II
51
). And within this atmosphere of permanent
control from the national level the supranational approach to the protection of
fundamental rights has to develop perpetually in nowadays and also in the future.
Therefore, Union is bound by the sources and mechanisms and therefore it is still
willing to go furthermainly by the accession to the European Convention.
2.5.1 Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European
UnionInternal Pillar
Granting the legally binding force to the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the
European Union (Charter) via adoption of Treaty of Lisbon (by reference included in
the rst paragraph of the article 6 TEU) brought signicant changes within the EU
legal system as whole. Charter was adopted in December 2000 as mere political
declaration without legally binding nature. First attempt to make it legally binding
came in connection with the Treaty establishing Constitution for Europe. Here, the
Charter was included directly to the text of European Constitution. But because this
reform document was rejected by the French and Dutch people in referendums in
2005 the question of the binding force of the Charter was not resolved yet. Second
(successful) attempt was made in connection with the Treaty of Lisbon. This doc-
ument changed the wording of article 6 TEU and introduced the legalisationclause
according to which Charter got the same legal value as the Treaties. Starting by 1st
December, 2009 (when Treaty of Lisbon entered into the force) the Charter of
fundamental rights of the European Union became legally binding (Forejtová2013).
Thanks to the Charter the project of European integration entered a new stage
and got a new image. Union obtained an internal instrument of identication and
protection of human rights, which is the rst pillar of the whole system.
Breakthrough importance of adopting a legally binding catalogue of fundamental
rights has several aspects:
It can be viewed from the perspective of constitutional dogmatic where adoption
of own internal catalogue of rights and freedoms completes the constitutional
46
Maastricht-Urteil decision of 12 October 1993, BVerfGE 89, 155.
47
Lissabon-Urteil decision of 30 June 2009, 2 BvE 2/08.
48
Sugar Quotas III, Pl. ÚS 50/04, ECLI:CZ:US:2006:Pl.US.50.04.
49
European Arrest Warrant, Pl. ÚS 66/04, ECLI:CZ:US:2006:Pl.US.66.04.
50
Treaty of Lisbon I, Pl. ÚS 19/08, ECLI:CZ:US:2008:Pl.US.19.08.1.
51
Treaty of Lisbon II, Pl. ÚS 29/09, ECLI:CZ:US:2009:Pl.US.29.09.3.
30 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
system of the Union. Next to the more or less established formal/procedural
constitutional rules (relations of the Union and the Member States, the internal
rules of separation of powers between a several Union institutions, quasi-federal
rules on the application of Union law in the national practice, etc.) it brought
clear material constitutional rules dening the relationship between the indi-
vidual and public authorities into the to the supranational constitutional sys-
tem.
52
Charter itself legitimizes the EU public power in black letter
understanding. Its active use as the source of legality review by the Court of
Justice deepens this impact in real world (De Búrca 2013).
53
Moreover, this step can be evaluated from the perspective of some constitutional
symbolism where the existence of the human rights catalogue serves as
important legitimizing tool (Neacsu 2001) vis-á-vis ever-expanding and deep-
ening powers of the European Union or Member States acting on behalf of
Union. Lenaerts and Cambien speak about increasing of the output democracy
of the EU in this regard. Charter legitimizes EU with the same value as
increased role of principle of representation and parliamentarism in the EU (the
input democracy) (Lenaerts and Cambien 2009).
From another point of view Charter fullled the requirement of improvement of
legal certainty of the holders of fundamental rights by making these rights visible
and manifested. It conrmed the attitude of the Court of Justice towards the
fundamental rights from the previous decades. But it is true that great deal made
by the Court of Justice by introduction of the fundamental rights as General
Principles (see further) was always connected with the risk of uncertainty and
unpredictability. As AG Mazák rightly stressed in his Opinion in Palacios case:
[] in the nature of general principles of law, which are to be sought rather in
the Platonic heaven of law than in the law books, that both their existence and
their substantive content are marked by uncertainty.
54
Charter is the tool of
minimalizing of that uncertainty and this seems to be its crucial added value.
Additionally, the legally binding Charter serves as an important revolutionary
novelty in terms of theory and history of human rights. Charter by its wide
content revolutionizes the classic approach to human rights which used to be
52
Contours of material constitutionality of the European Union are dened primarily by the system
of protection of fundamental rights. The question of the role and place of fundamental rights within
the European Communities and the European Union has undergone major developments during
the history of integration (Šišková2008). But it is non-disputable that only by adoption of the
binding catalogue it reached the level of complexity and clarity.
53
As very visible example of the real impact of the Charter one may recall to the crucial decision of
the Court of Justice Digital Rights Ireland, C-293/12, ECLI:EU:C:2014:238, where Court used the
Charter as the main argument for the (surprising) invalidation of the so-called Data Retention
Directive (2002/58/EC) as whole. Another strong example is Opinion on the Agreement on
Accession of the European Union to the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights
and Fundamental Freedoms, 2/13, ECLI:EU:C:2014:2454, where Court of Justice found the
incompatibility between the proposed agreement and EU law including the Charter (stating the
doubts about sufcient protection of autonomy of Charter, see points 186190).
54
AG Opinion, Félix Palacios de la Villa, C-411/05, ECLI:EU:C:2007:106.
2.5 CerberusGuarding the Fundamental Rights 31
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
recognized by the separate documents in line with the theory of several human
rights generations. Charter abandons this traditional approach at least formally
and recognizes the civil and political rights as well as economic, social and
cultural rights as part of one general human rights record.
Last but not least, the Charter reaches also the spheres of the Member States as
they are included into the list of negativeaddressesthe entities obliged to
respect the Charter. We can see one more the federal impetus here. Charter as
the catalogue of the centrebinds the several parts of the Union and attributes
the one standard all over the entire community.
Charter is very complex and quite ambitious document. It includes the tens of
human rights from all generations (classical division of human rights to the three
generations of rights: civil and political; economic, social and cultural; the modern =
solidarity rights). It has its own special structure which does not follow the classical
division of human rights to types or generations. The body of Charterincludes 50
material and 4 horizontal provisions (+explanations which are attached to the cata-
logue). It is internally structured into the seven titles
First title called dignity(articles 15) is inspired by Kantianideal concepts,
i.e. human dignity at the rst place. It includes the hard core rights as rights to
life, protection of personal integrity, prohibition of torture, etc.
Second title entitled freedoms(articles 619) deals with the various examples
of personal liberties like personal freedom, protection of private spheres, free-
dom of thought and expression, freedom of association and assembly, etc.).
Third title called equality(articles 2026) stresses the fact that
anti-discrimination policy is one of the most important elds of activity of the
Union. There is big variety of equality general anti-discrimination clause, equality
between men and women, special protection of vulnerable groupschildren,
elderly and people with disabilities, etc.
Fourth title marked solidarity(articles 2738) includes mainly the economic
and social rights, e.g. collective bargaining and action, fair and just working
conditions, access to health care, etc.
Fifth title called Citizens rights(articles 3946) is inspired by the Treaty
provisions on Unions citizenship. It repeats the classical group of rights of
Unions citizens (electorate rights, free movement, political rights and diplomatic
protection) and adds quite detail provision on the righto good administration.
Sixth title is identied as Justice(articles 4750) and includes the procedural
safeguards as right to fair trial, presumption of innocence, legality and pro-
portionality of criminal justice, ne bis in idem principle).
Seventh title includes so-called horizontal provision which determines the
general rules of application and interpretation of Charter and presents the
sources of inspiration for the adoption of this document (articles 5154).
Very important provision which has to be mentioned in this introductory elab-
oration of the Charter is article 51 paragraph 1. It denes the addresses of obligation
32 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
to respect the rights included in the Charter. There are two categories of addresses
which have obligation to respect of the Charter:
Institutions, bodies, ofces and agencies of the Unionhere the Charter serve as
the tool of strengthening of rule of law and democratic legitimacy of the
supranational governance. It is the goal of long path on which Communities and
Union were nding the ideal tool for the protection of fundamental rights.
Institutions of the EU are responsible to respect rights protected by the Charter
generally in all activities which could touch upon individualsrights.
Member Stateshere Charter brings the federalisation question on the scene.
The question of existence of common (central) standard of fundamental rights
protection binding upon all Member States (peripheries) is clearly interconnected
with the above-mentioned emancipation and dominance of EU law. And it
deepens the scope of protection of individuals within the whole system of
application of EU law. But it is worth to mention here that not all Member States
conducts fall under Charter conformity test. It is clear from the wording of article
51 paragraph 1 that Charter is applicable vis-á-vis Member States only when
they are implementing Union law. The Charter (unlike for example the
European Convention on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms) is not
universally applicable. Its applicability occurs where the conduct of a Member
State has some EU dimension. The question is not whether Member states must
full the Charter but to what extent they have to do that. By resolving this
problem we will answer the question of intensity of federal impacts of the Charter
itself. This important query is covered by the next section of this chapter.
The widening of effects of Charter to the conducts of Member States is not a
novelty or systemic revolution in EU law. Even before the adoption of the Charter,
the Court of Justice recognized the applicability of EU fundamental rights standards
(as unwritten general principles of law) on the selected activities of Member States
and recognized that national courts must follow these principles in their decisions.
EU law recognized certain situations where Member States held the duty to respect
supranational standards of fundamental rights protection:
(a) The basic form, i.e. the explicit situations where some EU legislation directly
introduces a specic obligation to protect the fundamental right (typically in
the area of anti-discrimination law or general duty to ensure judicial remedies
to protect individual rights steaming from EU law, e.g. Johnston
55
or
Defrenne
56
cases).
(b) The agentsituations, i.e. the situations where Member States were imple-
menting or applying a Union law. This so-called Wachauf situation
57
is
55
Johnston vs. Chief Constable of the Royal Ulster Constabulary, 222/84, ECLI:EU:C:1986:206.
56
Defrenne vs. SABENA, 43/75, ECLI:EU:C:1976:56.
57
Wachauf, 5/88 ECLI:EU:C:1989:321. See also Bosphorus vs. Minister for Transport, Energy
and Communications and Others, C-84/95, ECLI:EU:C:1996:312.
2.5 CerberusGuarding the Fundamental Rights 33
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
interconnected with phenomenon of decentralized governance when state
authorities act essentially as an extended arm of the European Union. Weiler
points out that in the background of this argument there is a need to use a
single standard of European Union law in all states (Weiler 1999).
(c) And a derogation model, i.e. the cases where Member States (within their
scope of discretion) derogate from the Internal Market rules (uses permitted
exemptions from the prohibition of restrictions on freedom of movement). This
so-called ERT situation
58
differs to both former types. Here Member States
apply their own law and do not behave as implementers of EU decisions. But
still even when applying their national law, they do so thanks to permission of
the EU rules and for the purpose to deviate from EU rules. So they appear in
the area outlined by EU law (Weiler 1999). The arguments here, similar to
previous situations, are based on the general need for a uniform standard of the
application of EU law in all states.
It is thus clear that the application of the Charter by the Member States is limited
only to a certain segment of their activities somehow connected with the effects of
EU law. The question is, what this segment covers, which actions of the Member
States fall under the umbrella of the Charter (and therefore under control and
interpretative jurisdiction of the Court of Justice)?
This question was among the most discussed issues in relation to the negotiation
of the Charter (Schönlau 2005) and brought a signicant case law of the Court of
Justice in recent where Court of Justice upheld above-mentioned broad interpre-
tation of article 51 paragraph 1 is the judgment in Fransson case.
59
In this case the
Court of Justice answered a preliminary question from the Swedish court, which
concerned criminal proceedings against H.Å. Fransson for serious tax evasion. H.Å.
Fransson was charged for stating false information in tax returns and for failing to
declare employerscontributions for the certain accounting periods. The problem
was that two years before Swedish tax authorities ordered him to pay some tax
surcharge for the same tax misconducts. National court therefore faced the problem
whether previous administrative sanction and new criminal prosecution fall under
prohibition of double jeopardy. And since the Charter conrms principle of ne bis
in idem in article 50 it was confronted with the potential conict of national rules
with the EU human rights catalogue. Therefore, it decided to stay proceedings and
turned to the Court of Justice with the preliminary question. The circumstances of
the case opened the initial question whether tax penalties and related criminal
proceedings represent the implementation of EU law within the meaning of article
51 paragraph 1 of the Charter? Part of the Member States
60
European Commission
and the Advocate General (Cruz Villalón) reected this question negatively and
rejected the applicability of the Charter and therefore the Courts jurisdiction to
decide the case.
58
ERT, C-260/89, ECLI:EU:C:1991:254. See also Familiapress, C-368/95, ECLI:EU:C:1997:325.
59
Åkerberg Fransson, C-617/10, ECLI:EU:C:2013:105.
60
Sweden, Czech Republic, Denmark, Ireland and Netherlands.
34 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
However, the Court of Justice took the opposite view and recognized the
applicability of the Charter despite the fact that it was neither a classic case of the
implementation of EU law (Wachauf situation), nor the case of derogation from EU
rules (ERT situation). It extended the scope of application of the Charter vis-á-vis
Member States also to other (much more broad) situations. According the Court:
Since the fundamental rights guaranteed by the Charter must therefore be complied
with where national legislation falls within the scope of European Union law,
situations cannot exist which are covered in that way by European Union law
without those fundamental rights being applicable. The applicability of European
Union law entails applicability of the fundamental rights guaranteed by the
Charter.
61
The wide understanding of the Court of Justice lies in fact that term
applicabilityin its view does not mean a concrete situation of application of EU
rules in specic case, but basically just a sort of their factual abstract existence. It is
not important whether EU law was used (directly or indirectly) in concrete case.
The key feature for applicability of the Charter is that circumstance of the case falls
within the scope of EU law. To meet this test even partial or indirect connection to
Union law is sufcient (Hancox 2013). This requirement was met in the case of
H.Å. Fransson. His tax offenses were partly related to the area of value added tax,
which forms an area harmonized by EU law. Moreover, part of the revenue from
VAT constitutes one of the own resources of the Union budget. According to the
Court of Justice these facts were satisfactory enough to build a bridge between
prosecution at the national level and EU law. The matter therefore dropped within
the scope of application of Union law and criminal prosecution of tax evasion here
was considered as the implementation of EU law within the meaning of article 51
paragraph 1 of the Charter. Judgment in Fransson case brought an extremely broad
interpretation of the Chartersimpact on the conduct of Member States. The Charter
became a shadow of European Union law (Lenaerts and Gutiérrez-Fons 2014) and
its applicability became somewhat unpredictable. Its not surprising that interpre-
tation offered by the Court of Justice opened the discussion about the very sensitive
questions related to the problem whether there is any autonomous space for
Member States conduct which should be free of testing by the Charterand what
are the denitive frontiers of the scope of the Charter (Fontanelli 2014).
The subsequent case law of the Court of Justice partially corrected the excessive
abstractness of Fransson ruling and conrmed that there are still some autonomous
domains of the Member States. Court of Justice brought some light to the unclear
Fransson ndings and offered (a bit complicated but still applicable) criteria of
testing whether there is some connection between national law applied in the case
and EU law (Pirker 2014). In case Siragusa Court of Justice stated that: In order to
determine whether national legislation involves the implementation of EU law for
the purposes of article 51 of the Charter, some of the points to be determined are
whether that legislation is intended to implement a provision of EU law; the nature of
that legislation and whether it pursues objectives other than those covered by EU
61
Åkerberg Fransson, C-617/10, ECLI:EU:C:2013:105, point 21.
2.5 CerberusGuarding the Fundamental Rights 35
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
law, even if it is capable of indirectly affecting EU law; and also whether there are
specic rules of EU law on the matter or capable of affecting it [].
62
This point
brought a certain explanation to the conceptacting within the scope EU lawgiven
by the Fransson judgment. The applicability of the Charter still requires that certain
matter falls within the scope of EU law. But to make this conclusion one needs to
nd a specic interconnection between national law (decision) and concrete provi-
sions of EU law. The Court concluded that applicability of the Charter to the acts of
Member States necessarily presupposes the existence of a certain degree of con-
nection between the EU law and relevant national law measures that goes beyond the
mere similarity of areas concerned or indirect impact of one area to another. As the
Court stated in the Hernández case: the mere fact that a national measure comes
within an area in which the European Union has powers cannot bring it within the
scope of EU law, and, therefore, cannot render the Charter applicable [].
63
From the case law (before and after Lisbon reform) follows a fairly wide range
of understanding the concept of implementingof EU law by Member States,
which creates the potential for wide impact of the Charter on the national practice.
But the important nding is that Charter cannot be used as the vehicle to widen the
EU competences alone without any further relation to the existing scope of EU law.
As the Court of Justice stated repeatedly
64
the Charter alone is not capable to
establish its own competence. To sum up the notion of implementation of EU law
covers both the direct application of EU rules and the application and interpretation
of national rules that serves as transposition of EU sources, moreover, it regulates
the application of national rules which could lead to derogation of EU-based
entitlements (most in the internal market) and nally it covers the
application/interpretation of national rules that relate to specic areas of Union
competence settled by concrete EU law provisions.
2.5.2 European Convention for the Protection of Human
Rights and Fundamental FreedomsExternal Pillar
The second paragraph of article 6 TEU includes the commitment of the Union to
accede to the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and
Fundamental Freedoms (ECHR). This provision is a reection of established
62
Siragusa, C-206/13, ECLI:EU:C:2014:126, point 25.
63
Julian Hernández and Others, C-198/13, ECLI:EU:C:2014:2055, point 36.
64
Torralbo Marcos, ECLI:EU:C:2014:187, C-265/13, point 30; Sociedade Agrícola e Imobiliária
da Quinta de S. Paio, C-258/13, EU:C:2013:810, point 20; Dutka and Sajtos C-614/12 and
C-10/13, ECLI:EU:C:2014:30, point 15; Weigl, C-332/13, ECLI:EU:C:2014:31, point 14;
Cholakova, C-14/13, ECLI:EU:C:2013:374, point 30; Nagy and Others, C-488/12, ECLI:EU:
C:2013:703, point 17.
36 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
practice, when the Court of Justice in its case law
65
commonly refers to the ECHR
as the source of its inspiration (Douglas-Scott 2006).
Even though accession negotiations had been commenced right at the beginning
of 2010 and after intensive work (Králová2011) they led to the nal proposal of the
Agreement on the Accession of the European Union to the Convention in April 2013
(Gragl 2013) EU still is not a party to the ECHR. The draft Agreement on Accession
was evaluated by the Court of Justice according to article 218 paragraph 11 TFEU
and this procedure led to the well-known negative Opinion 2/13
66
from 18th
December 2014. In this opinion, Court of Justice refused the draft of the agreement
for its incompatibility with the EU law. The Court gave uncompromising opinion
according to which: The agreement on the accession of the European Union to the
European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental
Freedoms is not compatible with Article 6(2) TEU or with Protocol (No 8) relating to
Article 6(2) of the Treaty on European Union on the accession of the Union to the
European Convention on the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental
Freedoms. The main reasons for this negative opinion were the risk for the
autonomous character of the EU law, risk to the mutual trust between Member
States, insufcient reection of the specics of the Common foreign and security
policy of the EU and decit in preservation of the special position of the Court of
Justice by the efcient prior involvement mechanism. The Opinion of the Court was
evaluated and criticized from many angles. It is not the aim of this volume to analyse
the opinion and therefore I just refer to the signicant literature on the topic.
67
Actually, we are facing the deadlock situation in the accession process.
Notwithstanding that, the accession is still the vivid matter as it was introduced as the
constitutional duty of the Union by the adamant formulation in the article 6 para-
graph 2 TEU (Grabenwarter and Pabel 2013). The accession is important goal of the
Union but it is to some extent rather a symbolic act. By the accession to the ECHR
Union will show the determination and readiness to be subject to the same control
mechanism as its Member (and other European) countries. It is clear even from the
statement of the Committee preparing the accession which says that As a result of
the accession, the acts, measures and omissions of the EU, like every other High
Contracting Party, will be subject to the external control exercised by the Court in the
light of the rights guaranteed under the Convention. This is all the more important
since the EU member States have transferred substantial powers to the EU.
68
On the
other hand, it is worth to say, that importance of ECHR as the external pillar of
65
Nold v Commission, 4/73, ECLI: EU:C:1974:51; Rutili vs. Ministre de lintérieur, 36/75, ECLI:
EU:C:1975:137; Hauer vs. Land Rheinland-Pfalz 44/79, ECLI:EU:C:1979:290; ERT, C-260/89,
ECLI: EU:C:1991:254; Kadi and Al Barakaat International Foundation v Council and
Commission, C-402/05 P and C-415/05 P, ECLI: EU:C:2008:461 etc.
66
Opinion on the Agreement on Accession of the European Union to the European Convention for
the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, 2/13, ECLI:EU:C:2014:2454.
67
De Witte and Imamovic (2015); Nanopoulos (2015), Spaventa (2015) and many others.
68
cParagraph 5 of the DRAFT Explanatory report to the Agreement on the Accession of the
European Union to the Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms.
2.5 CerberusGuarding the Fundamental Rights 37
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
human rights protection in the EU will be preserved even without the accession.
Above I wrote about stabile position of the ECHR as the source of inspiration for the
Court of Justice when deciding the fundamental rights cases. This role of ECHR was
underlined also in the third paragraph of the article 6 TEU
69
which referrers to this
international treaty as one of the sources of the fundamental rights as the general
principles of EU law. This provision drags the ECHR indirectly to the system of EU
law even without formal accession. The importance of the ECHR is emphasized also
by the article 52 paragraph 3
70
of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights. This
provision known as the de minimise clause preserves the reached level of protection
of fundamental rights and introduces the hierarchy of a kind between Charter and
ECHR. Finally, the action of the Union could be reviewed by the European Court for
Human Rights indirectly via prosecutingthe Member States acting as the EU
agents. According to the Bospohus
71
decision of European Court for Human Rights
the complaints against Member States for the actions determined by the EU are
acceptable if there is a lack of equivalent protection by the Union in comparison to
the level of protection guaranteed by the ECHR. Taking into account all
above-mentioned reections of the ECHR it is right to conclude that EU has the
external pillar of protection of fundamental rightsthe European Convention for
Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedomseven without building of
formal bonds to this document.
2.5.3 Unwritten General PrinciplesEternal Pillar
The third paragraph of article 6 TEU then identies the last (but historically oldest)
pillar of human rights protection on supranational levelthe unwritten rules con-
tained in the general principles of law. Even Union has it written catalogue
(Charter) now, the importance of general principles is still high. First of all even
when the Fathers of the treaty decided to state down explicitly the list of protected
rights there is always a risk of deciencies and incompleteness. There is also the
phenomenon which may be determined by the phrase society overtake the law
which means that legal regulation is always somehow behind the evolutional
69
Article 6 paragraph 3 TEU states: Fundamental rights, as guaranteed by the European
Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms and as they result
from the constitutional traditions common to the Member States, shall constitute general principles
of the Unions law.
70
Article 52 paragraph 3 of the Charter states: In so far as this Charter contains rights which
correspond to rights guaranteed by the Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and
Fundamental Freedoms, the meaning and scope of those rights shall be the same as those laid
down by the said Convention. This provision shall not prevent Union law providing more
extensive protection.
71
Judgement of the European Court for Human Rights (Grand Chamber) of 30 June 2005,
Bosphorus Hava YollarıTurizm ve Ticaret Anonim Şirketi v. Ireland, Application no. 45036/98.
38 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
features in technology and society which bring the new unknown problems. And
the open categoryas the principles areis the best instrument for the exible
reaction and protection of individualsrights in these circumstances. The devel-
opment of the doctrine of fundamental rights as part of the general principles of law
played a crucial role in building of the constitutionality of supranational entities.
Contours of material constitutionality of the European Union (remember that our
third claim is where a rule of law is secured there is a constitution) are dened
primarily by the system of protection of fundamental rights. The question of the role
and place of fundamental rights within the European Communities and the
European Union has undergone major developments during the history of
integration.
The original text of founding documents did not pay any attention to this issue.
Also the Court of Justice was originally very strict and by using of precise formal
approach rejected the possibility of protection of fundamental rights within the
Community legal system. The Court of Justice believed that then sources of
Community law contained no (nor explicit nor implicit) basis for the protection of
fundamental rights (see Geitling case
72
). The most quoted reasons for this initial
resistance where:
the dominant focus on the economic integration,
the existence of the Council of Europe (another European organization which
was established primarily for the protection and promotion of democracy, rule
of law and fundamental freedoms),
fundamental rights as a traditional domain of national constitutional law,
absence of legal competence of the Community in the eld of fundamental
rights.
The silence of the Treaties and reluctance of the Court of Justice to possibility of
fundamental rights protection had a negative impact in several aspects. It led to the
reduction in quality of protection of individuals, tension between Community law
and national law and decrease of legitimacy and democratic nature of European
Communities. Therefore, this undesirable situation (with its negative consequences)
was not sustainable for the long time. And it was the Court of Justice who brought
the revolution and caused the end of dark erain the approach to the fundamental
rights.
In the seminal Stauder
73
Court of Justice turned its approach from strictly formal
and positive to the material and stated that fundamental rights form the part of
general principles of law on which the Community id based and prescribed itself the
assignment to be their guardian. Courts doctrine of fundamental rights as part of
the general principles of law laid the foundations of inner (supranational) prism to
human rights protection. The importance of Stauder ruling is that Court of Justice
72
Präsident Ruhrkohlen-Verkaufsgesellschaft and others vs. ECSC High Authority, 36/59, ECLI:
EU:C:1960:36.
73
Stauder vs. Stadt Ulm, 29/69, ECLI:EU:C:1969:57.
2.5 CerberusGuarding the Fundamental Rights 39
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
found the way how to safeguard the rule of law in cases of alleged violation of
fundamental rights by actions of Community authorities. The court denied its own
initial assertion that Community law does not contain any (no explicit nor implicit)
rules providing for protection of fundamental rights.
In the next period of the evolution of this doctrine, the Court of Justice primarily
pointed out particular sources of inspiration
74
which lled and precise the
unspecied category of general principles of law. These sources of inspirations
were constitutional traditions common to the Member States
75
and international
treaties on human rights on which the Member States participate or are their sig-
natories and in particular the European Convention for the Protection of Human
Rights and Fundamental Freedoms.
76
Fundamental rights encoded in the unwritten general principles of law become
the only source of protection for long decades of existence of supranational entities.
Recognition of human rights was important not only in terms of individuals and
their protection. As I mentioned above, the doctrine of fundamental rights as a
general principles served also as certain self-reference, the autonomous claim for
the constitutionality of European integration entities which supported their
accountability and legitimacy of their actions.
2.5.4 Autopoietic Role of Fundamental Rights
The recognition of human rights and the introduction of a system that monitors their
observance are not important only for individual citizens and their protection as
some universal pan-european superstructure (Klíma 2011). The doctrine of the
general legal principles, the adoption of its own catalogue of human rights, and the
will to surrender to an external (Strasbourg based) control mechanism, represent
certain autopoiesis of the EUs constitutionalism (Torres Pérez 2009). It is clear that
a constitution without fundamental rights is not a constitution (Holländer 2009).
Only the recognition of the possibility to protect fundamental rights, only their
74
It is important to stress the notion of inspirationhere. Even though the Court of Justice was
and still is open to draw inspiration from the national constitutional traditions and international
sources it does not mean that all acknowledged rights are transposed to the supranational level
automatically. Court of Justice understands the fundamental rights autonomously as the original
part of supranational legal order and also offers an autonomous interpretation of the content of the
fundamental rights. We may call it a Community/Union viewwith regard to the objectives of the
Community/Union, which in some way limits the scope of protection afforded to fundamental
rights (see Nold, 4/73, ECLI:EU:C:1974:51 or Hauer vs. Land Rheinland-Pfalz 44/79, ECLI:EU:
C:1979:290, where fundamental right to property was to some extent suppressed by the
Community economic and market interests).
75
Internationale Handelsgesellschaft, 11/70, ECLI:EU:C:1970:114; Nold, 4/73, ECLI:EU:
C:1974:51.
76
Rutili vs. Ministre de lintérieur, 36/75, ECLI:EU:C:1975:137; Hauer vs. Land Rheinland-Pfalz
44/79, ECLI:EU:C:1979:290.
40 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
recognition as an immanent component of the supranational legal system, gave this
system the nature of a legal system. First and foremost, the case law of the Court of
Justice and the subsequent adoption of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights drew
human rights into the system of EU law and they became the criterion of EU
institutionslegitimacy.
77
The introduction of human rights protection also serves as a strong unication
tool, because shared values bond the European integration project (Dutheil de la
Rochère and Pernice 2003). The failure to test the conformity of supranational law
with fundamental individual rights would result in low legitimacy of this legal
system and could jeopardize its emancipation and domination. Historical devel-
opment conrms this because actual and potential human-legal decits of the
European Communities became key arguments against the obligation to accept
supremacy of supranational law over national law. Standard-bearer of this approach
was the German Federal Constitutional Court (Kirchhof 1999), which in a doctrine
formed by its decisions in the so-called Solange saga
78
referred to the human-legal
decit of the Communities and its position became a catalyst for progress in this
area on the supranational level. The Courts support of general legal principles not
only resolved the human rightsprotection decit, but its doctrine served also as an
indirect defence of its view regarding the nature of the EU legal system.
References
Aalto, P. (2011). Public liability in EU law. Brasserie, Bergaderm and beyond. Oxford: Hart
Publishing.
Agnew, J. (2009). Globalization and sovereignty. Lanham: Rowman & Littleeld Publishers.
Alter, K. (2001). Establishing the supremacy of European law. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Avbelj, M. (2011). Supremacy or primacy of EU law(Why) does it matter? European Law
Journal, 17(6), 744763.
Avbelj, M., & Komárek, J. (Eds.). (2012). Constitutional pluralism in the European union and
beyond. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Bárány, E. (2007). Pojmy dobrého práva [The notion of goof law]. Bratislava: Eurokódex.
Barents, R. (2004). The autonomy of community law. Hague: Kluwer Law International.
Betlem, G. (2002). The doctrine of consistent interpretationManaging legal uncertainty. Oxford
Journal of Legal Studies, 22(3), 397418.
Bobek, M. (2014). The effects of EU law in the national legal systems. In C. Barnard & S. Peers
(Eds.), European union law (pp. 140173). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
77
For examples of ECJ judgements where it established a conict between community acts with
fundamental rights, see Oyowe and Traore v. Commission, 100/88, ECLI:EU:C:1989:638 or Prais
v. Council, 130/75, ECLI:EU:C:1976:142.
78
Federal Constitutional Court judgement of 29 May 1974, BVerfGE 37, 271 (Solange I)
Internationale Handelsgesellschaft mbH. v. Einfuhrund Vorratstelle für Getreide und
Futtermittel and Federal Constitutional Court judgement of 22 October 1986, BVerfGE 73, 339
(Solange II) Re Wünsche Handelsgesellschaft.
2.5 CerberusGuarding the Fundamental Rights 41
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
Bobek, M., Bříza, P., & Komárek, J. (2011). Vnitrostátníaplikace práva Evropskéunie [Domestic
application of EU law]. Praha: C. H. Beck.
Breuer, M. (2004). State liability for judicial wrongs and community law: The case of Gerhard
Köbler v. Austria. European Law Review, 29(1), 243254.
Corrias, L. (2011). The passivity of law. Competence and constitution in the European court of
justice. Dordrecht: Springer.
Craig, P. (1999). The nature of the community: Integration, democracy and legitimacy. In P. Craig &
G. De Búrca (Eds.), The evolution of EU law (pp. 154). New York: Oxford University Press.
Craig, P. (2010). The lisbon treaty. Law, politics and treaty reform. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Craig, P., & De Búrca, G. (2011). EU lawText, cases and materials (5th ed.). Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
De Búrca, G. (2013). After the EU charter of fundamental rights: The court of justice as a human
rights adjudicator? Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law, 20(2), 168184.
De Búrca, G., & Weiler, J. H. H. (Eds.). (2012). The worlds of European constitucionalism.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
De Witte, B., & Imamović,Š. (2015). Opinion 2/13 on accession to the ECHR: Defending the EU
legal order against a foreign human rights court. European Law Review, 40(5), 683705.
Dougan, M. (2004). National remedies before the Court of Justice. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Douglas-Scott, S. (2006). A tale of two courts: Luxembourg, strasbourg and the growing European
human rights acquis. Common Market Law Review, 43(3), 629665.
Dutheil de la Rochère, J., & Pernice, I. (2003). European Union law and national constitutions.
In M. Andenas & J. Usher (Eds.), The treaty of nice and beyond. Enlargement and
constitutional reform (pp. 47105). Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Fontanelli, F. (2014). Implementation of EU Law through domestic measures after Fransson: The
Court of Justice Buys Time and non-preclusionTroubles Loom Large. European Law
Review, 39(5), 782800.
Forejtová, M. (2011). Evropskáunie jako subjekt mezinárodního práva veřejného [The European
Union as a subject of international law]. In Evropsképrávo [European Law]. Plzeň: Aleš
Čeněk.
Forejtová, M. (2013). Diskriminace jako referenčníkritérium v judikatuře evropských soudů
[Discrimination as a reference in the case law of the European courts]. Plzeň: Aleš Čeněk.
Forejtová, M. (2014). Občanstvív judikatuře Soudního dvora Evropskéunie v Evropském roce
aktivního občanství[Citizenship by the Court of Justice of the European Union, the European
Year of Active Citizenship]. Acta Universitatis Carolinae - Iuridica, 60(2), 4555.
Forejtová, M. (2015). Recognition and enforcement of judgements within the EUOr is it really
so easy to achieve them? The Lawyer Quarterly, 5(1), 5972.
Forejtová, M., & Tronečková, M. (2011). Evropsképrávo v praxi [European law in practice].
Plzeň: Aleš Čeněk.
Frowein, J. (1988). Solange II, (BVerfGE 73, 339) constitutional complaint Firma W. Common
Market Law Review, 25(1), 201206.
Grabenwarter, Ch., & Pabel, K. (2013). Commentary on article 6 TEU. In H.-J. Blanke &
S. Mamgiameli (Eds.), The treaty on European union. A commentary (pp. 287348).
Heidelberg: Springer.
Gragl, P. (2013). The accession of the European Union to the European Convention on human
rights. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Habermas, J. (2001). The postnational constellation. Political essays. (M. Pensky, trans.).
Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.
Hamuľák, O. (2014). Idolatry of rights and freedomsReections on the autopoietic role of
fundamental rights within constitutionalization of the European Union. In T. Kerikmäe (Ed.),
Protecting human rights in the EU. Controversies and challenges of the charter of fundamental
rights (pp. 187198). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.
Hancox, E. (2013). The meaning of implementingEU law under Article 51(1) of the charter:
Åkerberg Fransson. Common Market Law Review, 50(5), 14111431.
42 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
Hinarejos, A. (2008). On the legal effects of framework decisions and decisions: Directly
applicable, directly effective, self-executing, supreme? European Law Journal, 14(5),
620634.
Holländer, P. (2009). Základy všeobecnéstátovědy [The essentials of the general theory of state].
Plzeň: Aleš Čeněk.
Jacobs, F. G. (2007). The sovereignty of law: The European way. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Jakab, A. (2006). Neutralizing the sovereignty question; compromise strategies in constitutional
argumentations before European integration and since. European Constitutional Law Review,
2(3), 375397.
Kelsen, H. (1944). The principle of sovereign equality of states as a basis for international
organization. The Yale Law Journal, 53(2), 207220.
Kiiver, P. (2012). The early warning system for the principle of subsidiarity. New York:
Routledge.
Kirchhof, P. (1999). The balance of powers between national and european institutions. European
Law Journal, 5(3), 225242.
Klokočka, V. (2006). Ústavnísystémy evropských států[Constitutional systems of the European
states]. Praha: Linde.
Komárek, J. (2014). Why national constitutional courts should not embrace EU fundamental
rights. London School of Economics. https://www.lse.ac.uk/collections/law/wps/WPS2014
23_Komarek.pdf. Accessed May 20, 2016.
Králová, J. (2011). Comments on the draft agreement on the accession of the European union to
the convention for the protection of human rights and fundamental freedoms. Czech Yearbook
of Public & Private International Law, 2(1), 127142.
Lebeck, C. (2006). National constitutionalism, openness to international law and pragmatic limits
of European integrationEuropean Law in the German Constitutional Court from the EEC to
PJCC. German Law Journal, 7(11), 907945.
Leczykiewicz, D. (2009). Constitutionalising the third pillar. Centre for European Legal Studies.
http://www.cels.law.cam.ac.uk/events/Leczykiewicz.pdf. Accessed November 21, 2015.
Lenaerts, K., & Cambien, N. (2009). The democratic legitimacy of the EU after the treaty of
lisbon. In J. Wouters (Ed.), European constitutionalism beyond Lisbon (pp. 185207).
Antverps: Intersentia.
Lenaerts, K., & Gutiérrez-Fons, J. A. (2014). The place of the charter in the EU constitutional
edice. In S. Peers & T. Hervey, T. (Eds.), The EU charter of fundamental rights.
A commentary (pp. 16001637). Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Lenaerts, K., & Van Nuffel, P. (2005). Constitutional law of the European Union. London: Sweet
& Maxwell.
Lenaerts, K., & Van Nuffel, P. (2011). European Union Law (3rd ed.). London: Sweet and
Maxwell.
Mac Amhlaigh, C. (2011). The European Unions constitutional mosaic: Big Cor small c, Is
that a question? In N. Walker, J. Shaw, & S. Tierney (Eds.), Europes constitutional mosaic
(pp. 2147). Oxford: Hart Publishing.
MacCormick, N. (1999). Questioning sovereignty. Law, state, and nation in the European
Commonwealth. New York: Oxford University Press.
Mazák, J. (2011). Locus standi v konanío neplatnosť: od Plaumannovho testu k regulačným
aktom [Locus Standi in the legality reviewFrom the Plaumann test towards regulatory acts),
Právník, 150(3), 209231.
Nanopoulos, E. (2015). Killing two birds with one stone? The Court of Justices Opinion on the
EUs Accession to the ECHR. The Cambridge Law Journal, 74(2), 185188.
Neacsu, E. D. (2001). The Draft of the EU charter of fundamental rights: A step in the process of
legitimizing EU as a political entity, and economic-social rights as fundamental human rights.
Columbia Journal of European Law, 1(1), 141146.
Niedobitek, M. (2009). Přednost práva EU a Lisabonskásmlouva [Primacy of EU law and the
treaty of Lisbon]. Jurisprudence, 18(1), 1217.
References 43
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
Panke, D. (2010). The effectiveness of the European Court of Justice. Why reluctant states comply
(329 p). Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Piris, J.-C. (2010). The Lisbon Treaty. A legal and political analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Pirker, B. (2014). Case C-206/13 Siragusa: A Further Piece for the Åkerberg Fransson Jigsaw
Puzzle. European law blog http://europeanlawblog.eu/?p=2253. Accessed May 14, 2016.
Prechal, S. (2007). Direct effect, indirect effect, supremacy and the evolving constitution of the
European Union. In C. Barnard (Ed.), The fundamentals of EU Law revisited. Assessing the
impact of the constitutional debate (pp. 3569). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Přibáň, J. (2010). Multiple sovereignty: On Europes self-constitutionalization and legal
self-reference. Ratio Juris, 23(1), 4164.
Schönlau, J. (2005). Drafting the EU CharterRights, legitimacy and process. London: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Schütze, R. (2014). Constitutionalism and the European Union. In C. Barnard & S. Peers (Eds.),
European Union law (pp. 7196). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sehnálek, D. (2009). Effet utille a jeho projevy při interpretaci komunitárního práva [Effet utile and
its expressions within the implementation of community law]. Právník, 148(8), 785808.
Šišková, N. (2008). The process of constitutionalisation of the EU and related issues. Groningen:
Europa Law Publishing.
Spaventa, E. (2015). A very fearful court? The protection of fundamental rights in the European
Union after opinion 2/13. Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law., 22(1),
3556.
Stein, E. (1981). Lawyers, judges, and the making of a transnational constitution. The American
Journal of International Law, 75(1), 127.
Stein, E. (2005). The magic of the C-Word. EUSA Review, 18(3), 15.
Torres Pérez, A. (2009). Conict of rights in the European Union. A theory of supranational
adjudication. New York: Oxford University Press.
Weatherill, S. (2010). Cases and materials on EU Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Weiler, J. H. H. (1991). The transformation of Europe. The Yale Law Journal, 100(8), 24012483.
Weiler, J. H. H. (1999). The constitution of Europe. Do the new clothes have an Emperor?and
other essays on European integration. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wintr, J. (2004). Právně-politickámetoda evropskéintegrace a návrh evropské ústavy [Legal and
political method of European integration and proposal of constitution for Europe]. Česképrávo
na prahu Evropskéunie (pp. 3143). Karolinum: Praha.
Witte, B. (1999). The past and future of the European court of justice in the protection of human
rights. In P. Alston (Ed.), The EU and human rights (pp. 859897). Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
44 2 Constitutionalism Beyond the State
ondrej.hamulak@upol.cz
ResearchGate has not been able to resolve any citations for this publication.
Chapter
For all its achievements in integrating Europe, the EU lacks a human rights policy which is coherent, balanced and professionally administered. Whether in relation to access to Community justice, sex equality, race and disability discrimination, or policing, or in its external policies from Kosovo to China, the Union needs new principles, procedures and institutions to design and implement an effective set of human rights policies. The introduction of a single currency, the problems of racism and xenophobia, the need for a humane refugee policy, the growing powers of the EU in many fields, and the Unions imminent eastward expansion, all make it urgent to adopt such policies. In this volume the leading experts in the field, including individuals from every EU country, provide an insightful critique of current policies and detailed recommendations for the future. The volume includes comprehensive analyses of: the competencies of the EU in human rights, access to justice, the Third Pillar.
Chapter
This chapter examines how EU law interacts with national legal systems. It first explains the default rules for the national application of EU law. It then focuses on three key principles: direct effect, indirect effect, and primacy. It considers requirements formulated with respect to procedures for the national enforcement of EU law and state liability for breaches of EU law. The chapter concludes with a case study, which illustrates the interplay between the rules and principles introduced in this chapter.
Book
All books in this flagship series contain carefully selected substantial extracts from key cases, legislation, and academic debate, providing students with a stand-alone resource. The seventh edition of EU Law: Text, Cases, and Materials provides clear analysis of all aspects of European law in the post Lisbon era. This edition looks in detail at the way in which the provisions of the Lisbon Treaty have worked since the Treaty became operational, especially innovations such as the hierarchy of norms, the different types of competence, and the legally binding Charter of Rights. The coming into effect of the new Treaty was overshadowed by the financial crisis, which has occupied a considerable part of the EU’s time since 2009. The EU has also had to cope with the refugee crisis, the pandemic crisis, the rule of law crisis and the Brexit crisis. There has nonetheless been considerable legislative activity in other areas, and the EU courts have given important decisions across the spectrum of EU law. The seventh edition has incorporated the changes in all these areas. The book covers all topics relating to the institutional and constitutional dimensions of the EU. In relation to EU substantive law there is detailed treatment of the four freedoms, the single market, competition, equal treatment, citizenship, state aid, and the area of freedom, security and justice. Brexit is the rationale for the decision to have a separate UK version of the book. There is no difference in the chapters between the two versions, insofar as the explication of the EU law is concerned. The difference resides in the fact that in the UK version there is an extra short section at the end of each chapter explaining how, for example, direct effect, supremacy or free movement are relevant in post-Brexit UK. Law students in the UK need to know this, law students in the EU and elsewhere do not.