ArticlePDF Available

Literature as a defining trait of the human umwelt: From and beyond Heidegger

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

Writers and readers of literature are, among other things, biological entities that evolve under particular political (geographical/historical) conditions. A comparative study of certain texts by Martin Heidegger (1889-1976) can help us establish a fruitful interpretation of this threefold link between literary art, biology and politics. However, careful analysis reveals that Heidegger remains too rooted in an old-world, nationalistic and anthropocentric paradigm. We will attempt to rethink Heidegger's assumptions on the grounds that literature, a cultural practice, enables us to delineate our natural environment. By reformulating Heidegger's line of thought, we can more precisely address the plural structure of our biotic and political-literary experiences.
Content may be subject to copyright.
148 Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
Literature as a defining trait
of the human umwelt:
From and beyond Heidegger
Pierre-Louis Patoine
Sorbonne Nouvelle University
English Department
13 rue de Santeuil
75005 Paris, France
e-mail: pierre-louis.patoine@univ-paris3.fr
Jonathan Hope
Université du Québec à Montréal (Canada)
Literature Department
C.P. 8888 succ. Centre-ville
Montréal, QC H3C 3P8, Canada
e-mail: hope.jonathan@uqam.ca
Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
Abstract. Writers and readers of literature are, among other things, biological en tities
that evolve under particular political (geographical/historical) conditions. A comparative
study of certain texts by Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) can help us establish a fruitful
interpretation of this threefold link between literary art, biology and politics. However,
careful analysis reveals that Heidegger remains too rooted in an old-world, nationalistic
and anthropocentric paradigm. We will attempt to rethink Heidegger’s assumptions
on the grounds that literature, a cultural practice, enables us to delineate our natural
environment. By reformulating Heidegger’s line of thought, we can more precisely
address the plural structure of our biotic and political-literary experiences.
Keywords: literature body habitat Heidegger politics
Literature and habitat are entangled in complex configurations. What are the stakes
of such configurations? As the human habitat is confronted with successive social
and ecological crises, exploring this question becomes crucial, and we propose to do
so following the lead of Martin Heidegger. Indeed, not only does Heidegger reflect
on the fact that place, pervaded by time, is a defining trait of a meaningful existence,
he also states that the development of such an existence is shaped by specific literary
works. This is how we should understand his considerations on Friedrich Hölderlin,
the prominent 19th-century German philosopher-poet associated with Romanticism
Sign Systems Studies 44(1/2), 2016, 148–163
http://dx.doi.org/10.12697/SSS.2016.44.1-2.09
; ; ; ;
Literature as a de ning trait of the human umwelt 149
and Idealism. Heidegger claims that canonical literary works, such as Hölderlin’s,
should enable a culture to unite itself and express its national uniqueness, in
opposition to “others”. We will survey Heidegger’s thoughts on this matter, and then
propose an alternative model of the eco-cultural role of literature, inspired by, but
also critical of, the Heideggerean perspective.
Our paper is divided in three sections. First we will examine Heideggers under-
standing of the ontological difference between the worlds of animals and men.
Heidegger’s interpretation of animality is a valuable one in that it integrates biology,
and the crucial associated notion of lived surrounding, into the sphere of philosophy.
However, as we shall see, Heidegger’s openness to the animal is secondary to his
concern for Man; likewise, whatever openness he has for environmentalism is second
to his interest in nationalism. Thus, Heidegger’s subsequent ideas on dwelling,
rooted in a nostalgic feeling of lack, appear in need of a radical reinterpretation.
This will bring us to our second point: the examination of the manner in which
literary practices can be understood as one of Homo sapiens techniques of dwelling.
Literature appears as a species-specific technology through which humans relate
to their geo-historical context, and live together on a shared territory. Once again
Heidegger’s ideas on the topic will prove to be useful, but will need to be rethought,
in a third and final section, by actively integrating environmental concerns.
1. Animals, dwelling and lack
Martin Heidegger’s major work, his Being and Time, addresses the fundamental
question of the meaning of being” (Heidegger 1996[1927]: xxiv). To elaborate this
question, Heidegger basically recounts the adventures of an unfolding existence,
Dasein. This philosophical hero in becoming is Heidegger’s new definition of man,
critical of those definitions put forth by anthropologists, psychologists, theologians
and biologists. Daseins unique ability to use and recognize signs enables it to relate
to the world, to time, to others and to itself. Bound to the world, Dasein develops a
sense of locality that allows it to differentiate itself from neighbours, strangers and
other aliens. Bound to time, Dasein develops a sense of history through which it
promotes the uniqueness of its epoch. Thus Heidegger will examine the development
of our basic (individual) existential structures to the transcendental ontological
interrogations on the meaning of our (collective) historical and political experiences
1
.
Two years after the publication of Being and Time, in 1929–1930, Heidegger will
give a very dense seminar subsequently published under the title The Fundamental
Concepts of Metaphysics. World, Finitude, Solitude. As the title suggests, its goal is
1 For more on this see Hope 2014; 2015.
150 Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
nothing less than to interpret the underlying principles of philosophy, the most
autonomous of all activities of Dasein. In the first part of the seminar, Heidegger
claims that Daseins unique capacity for boredom, the oppression through time, is
a condition to the advent of philosophy/ontology. In the second part of the seminar,
and of particular interest to us here, Heidegger reflects on animality. Read in the
light of Being and Time, this seminar appears as Heidegger’s most accomplished
attempt to distinguish Man’s existence from the life of an animal. As if to insist on
the uniqueness of human existence, a principle already firmly established in Being
in Time, this seminar appears as a complementary text where Heidegger will drive
in his idea that Dasein is not an animal: ontology is not consubstantial with zoology.
Basically, Heidegger’s move is to reflect on the essence of animality in order to better
define, a contrario, the meaning of existence.
Heidegger’s thoughts on the animal – and its difference from Dasein – can reason-
ably be extended to all cellular life: eubacteria, archaebacteria, and the more complex
eukaryotes (domain under which are found, among others, protists, fungi, plants and
animals). Indeed, Heidegger (2008a[1929–1930]: 212) writes to this effect: “[w]e must
take up the task of defining the essence of the living being, of characterizing the essence
of life, if only with particular reference to the animal.” In a way, Heidegger seems to
consider the animal as a metonymy of life: what he says about the animal could be said
about any living system. Ultimately, we are to understand that Dasein is not a simple
living thing, bios is not a limiting condition of human existence. The crux of Heidegger’s
argument rests on a three-tiered model of ontological categories represented by stones,
animals and men. Stones or abiotic matter are worldless and know nothing; animals or
biotic matter are poor in world and have limited knowledge; and Man is world-forming
and is thus able to question his knowledge. (This is presented in the first sections of
Part II, §§ 39–48, to which we will limit our reading.)
Despite the fact that Heidegger came up with these ideas some 85 years ago and
that life sciences have flourished since then, his insights are still serviceable today.
Indeed, he demonstrates openness to the animal by integrating it in his ontology.
He questions the simplistic Modern divide between the rational Man and the non-
rational animal. Thus, in a barely allusive critique of Descartes (2000[1637]: 153)
who had claimed that philosophy enabled us to become “masters and possessors
of nature, Heidegger writes “man is at once both master and servant of the world.
(2008a[1929–1930]: 177). In a way, Heidegger seems to have foreseen some crucial
tenets of Postmodernity by discerning the uniqueness of other life-forms, and
the interrelatedness of all life through the lens of meaning. Indeed, Heidegger
(2008a[1929–1930]: 192) mentions that his tripartition “does not entail hierarchical
assessment”. Heidegger states to this effect that the pyramid-like model championed
in Max Scheler’s last essays on philosophical anthropology (a model that influenced
Literature as a de ning trait of the human umwelt 151
Heidegger) – where matter props plant/animal life, that in turn props human spirit–
is a “fundamental error” (Heidegger 2008a[1929–1930]: 192). Human spirit is not
the culmination of everything. Lower life forms such as amoebae or infusoria are not
any less perfect than higher ones such as apes or elephants. Heidegger (2008a[1929–
1930]: 194) writes: “Every animal and every species of animal as such is just as perfect
and complete as any other”.
It is also worth mentioning that Heidegger’s seminar on animality is not an exclu-
sively philosophical meditation, but is equally informed by the latest develop ments
in theoretical biology, critical of mechanistic, vitalist and Darwinist inter pretations
of life. Heidegger integrates into philosophy the works, among others, of Jakob von
Uexküll, Hans Driesch and Frederik Buytendijk, effectively federating allies whose
research demonstrates the corporeal and environmental completeness of the animal.
Heidegger is especially receptive to Uexküll’s monograph Umwelt und Innenwelt der
Tiere (1909) in which the Baltic German biologist convincingly argues in favour of
a species-specific correspondence between the exterior and the interior of a living
organism. Organisms generate their own umwelt (lived surroundings) through their
meaningful possibilities of action and perception, through the crystallization of
habits into habitat. (The time is right to remind readers of the objective of our paper
as it echoes Uexküll’s assumption: how can the specifically human literary practices
be integrated in the realm of organic activity, and recognized as a key element in the
extension of Mans umwelt?)
Notwithstanding Heidegger’s openness to Postmodernity and openness to the
animal, he remains relatively close to the typically Modern idea according to which
Man is the conductor of the vast orchestra of life. His conception of Nature, as
presided over by human existence, seems anchored in a Modern Weltanschauung,
and appears as an ontological continuation of 19th-century humanism. Indeed,
Heidegger (2008a[1929–1930]: 193) claims that non-human life possesses less
of what is accessible. That is to say, not only is the physical range of the animal
limited, even more importantly “the extent and manner in which an animal is able
to penetrate what ever is limited to it is also limited” (Heidegger 2008a[1929–1930]:
193). Thus, the world of the animal is quantitatively and qualitatively poorer than
that of Man – the world of the animal is in a state of poverty (Armut). On the other
hand, the world of Man, writes Heidegger (2008a[1929–1930]: 193):
is a rich one, greater in range, far more extensive in its penetrability, constantly
extendable not only in its range […] but also in respect to the manner in which
we can penetrate ever more deeply in this penetrability. Consequently we
can characterize the relation man possesses to the world by referring to the
extendability of everything that he relates to. This is why we speak of man as world-
forming.
152 Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
Heidegger gives a few telling examples. A bee is aware of blossoms, colours and
scents, but is clueless about stamens, leaves and roots, as stamens, leaves and roots
(that is to say as the organs of a plant responsible for, respectively: fertilization,
photosynthesis and transpiration, and hydration and nourishment). A lizard basking
in the sun on a rock knows nothing of the mineralogical constitution of the rock, and
it is in no way able to ponder on the astrophysical nature of the sun. For a scurrying
beetle, a blade of grass is a path, not a member of the Gramineae family, a dominant
vegetation of the world, nor a “part of the bundle of hay with which the peasant will
feed his cow” (Heidegger 2008a[1929–1930]: 198). Poor-in-world, the animal is in a
state of “being deprived [Entbehren]” (2008a[1929–1930]: 195).
The weak spot in Heidegger’s thesis – the reason why it appears out-dated – is
that it continues to define the world in an anthropocentric manner. The bee knows
nothing of botany; the lizard knows nothing of mineralogy and astrophysics; the
beetle knows nothing of botany and agriculture. That is to say: the poorness in world
of the animal is always determined in respect to the epistemic possibilities of Man,
while the limits of the human scales of knowing are never questioned. In a way,
Heidegger is not that far from the idea attributed to the ancient Protagoras, according
to which Man is the measure of all things.
2
The result is that from a Heideggerean
perspective the nature/culture divide is only partially weakened – in other words, it
still completely prevails.
To be fair, we must mention that Heidegger’s reflections on animality and on the
lived world evolve in the course of his seminar. Heidegger’s thoughts that we have
recalled in the preceding paragraphs are, at best, introductory and require in-depth
analysis. Heidegger (2008a[1929–1930]: 199) states to this effect: “we must attempt
once again to acquire further insight into the essence of the animal and its animality.
But we will no longer be able to proceed with the same naivety”. Then, he spends the
rest of the seminar explicating his ideas. That being said, in no way do Heidegger’s
subsequent thoughts contradict his early assumption, namely that the world and
the knowledge of stones, animals and men are essentially different – all Heidegger
does throughout the remainder of his seminar is detail this essential difference. The
animal is poor in world and it is incapable of grasping things as they are, as they
manifest themselves and “to reflect upon them as something thus grasped” (Heidegger
2008a[1929–1930]: 247). For the purposes of this paper, let us consider that what
Heidegger says in his introductory paragraphs represents his thoughts with sufficient
accuracy.
Following his 1929–30 seminar on animality, in the aftermath of the Second World
War, Heidegger gives a lecture entitled “Building dwelling thinking”. The context of this
2 For complementary interpretations of Heidegger’s debt to Protagoras, see Frings 1974 and
Casadebaig 2015.
Literature as a de ning trait of the human umwelt 153
paper is essential: at the end of the war there is a sense of grief and loss as women and
men, many of them Europeans, witness the destruction of their cities and homes. The
war and the subsequent threat of atomic annihilation have made them lose their sense
of direction and purpose. Gods have abandoned the world. Humans live, quite literally,
on a God-forsaken rock, and they subjugate it to their techno-empirical will. Humans
have forgotten how to dwell, to be, to cultivate and to care. Heidegger considers that
humans must learn anew the meaning of dwelling, they must rediscover a state of
peacefulness preserved from harm and danger, safeguarded. As Heidegger presents
it, poetic dwelling of existence is historical, political, theophanic. To dwell means to
reopen oneself to the fourfold (Geviert), an Aristotelian-like gathering of causes,
namely: the world, the heavens, the mortals and the Gods.3
Admittedly, environmental undertones could be discerned in these meditations.
Everything (the natural world, humans, culture, etc.) is at risk of destruction, we must
take care of our home, that in which we live. Yet even if an ecosystemic understanding
of dwelling may be hinted at by Heidegger’s lecture, that is not its main point. Heidegger
presents dwelling as a question of national urgency intended for the integrity of the
European, and specifically German Man, as we will see in our discussion of his use
of Hölderlin. This statement might appear surprising as Heidegger claims that the
problems relating to dwelling, building and thinking transcend any ontic differences
and touch the most general and authentic being of mankind. He writes:
However hard and bitter, however hampering and threatening the lack of
houses remains, the proper plight of dwelling does not lie merely in a lack of
houses. The proper plight of dwelling is indeed older than the world wars with
their destruction, older also than the increase of the earths population and the
condition of the industrial workers. The proper plight of dwelling lies in this, that
mortals ever search anew for the essence of dwelling, that they must ever learn to
dwell. (Heidegger 2008b[1951]: 363)
Even if Heidegger talks about mankind, his understanding of dwelling is nonetheless
grounded on some sort of anthropocentric, Euro-nationalist ideal, historically
situated and closely linked to the evolution of industrial Modernity. Why? Because
by framing the problem of building, dwelling and thinking within the parameters
of the fourfold, Heidegger loads the die, so to speak, as he considers it from an
essentially European perspective. In other words, Heidegger asks us to presume
that the European situation is unproblematically universal. This unjust presumption
3 It is interesting to note the change of tone in Heidegger’s thought. Whereas mankind’s
world-forming capacities in the 1930s denoted some kind of power in its duties towards
Nature, by the end of the war mankind’s technical capacities are perilous, to the point that all
men and women revert to being endangered mortals.
154 Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
explains why Heideggers statements at that time make little sense when applied to,
for example, North America, struggling with completely different problems, due to
the wide expanses of uninhabited territories, and coming up with context-specific
solutions, such as suburbs, skyscrapers and system homes.
To Heidegger, the world of humans is superior to the world of the animal in
terms of epistemic possibilities and in terms of its ultimate nationalist goal. As we
will see shortly, this bears on his understanding of the interlacement of dwelling and
literature, an interlacement we can begin to elucidate by unravelling the nostalgic
thread running through Heidegger’s rhetoric of dwelling. Indeed, such rhetoric
implies a positively valued earlier state, and a present lack: Gods have abandoned
our world, we have forgotten how to dwell. Abandonment and forgetfulness are
the modes through which such lack is experienced; and dwelling, cultivating and
caring appear as possible remedies to this lack. Let us momentarily reflect on these
remedies. From a simple physiological standpoint, building, dwelling, and cultivating
are gestures made necessary by various lacks: the absence of warmth forces us to
build and to dwell within an artificial structure; the absence of readily available
food forces us to cultivate the land. Such techniques as dwelling, building, and
cultivating thus emanate from an inherent lack at the core of our (organic) being,
a lack underlined by Heidegger in his seminar on animality when he states that a
human learns how to exist “solely to the extent that such a demand transpires from
out of an actual oppressiveness of Dasein as a whole.” (Heidegger 2008a[1929–1930]:
172) In other words, Dasein acquires knowledge through the feeling of oppression
(Bedrängnis, that Heidegger discovered in his first section on boredom), the feeling
that one’s being and one’s abilities are deficient, inadequate.
This idea of an essential deficit in the heart of existence, a dialectic between
absence and presence, is a recurring theme in different doctrines that share the stage
of Postmodern thinking – hermeneutics, phenomenology, psychoanalysis, semiotics
to name a few. But it is worth noting that this notion is also put into service in the life
sciences. A case in point is the American biological anthropologist Terrence Deacon
who uses similar terms in Incomplete Nature as he discusses the “abstential” essence
of life: “longing, desire, passion, appetite, mourning, loss, aspiration – all are based on
an analogous intrinsic incompleteness, an integral without-ness” (Deacon 2012: 2–3).
For Deacon, it is through such incompleteness that the organism develops a semiotic
and eventually linguistic understanding of the world. On this account, language, as a
symbolic technology admirably mastered by the human animal, is no different from
dwelling, building or cultivating. Indeed, many (if not most) uses of language are
rooted in absence or lack: we use hundreds of words every day to evoke things that
we cannot physically point to (things that are absent, impossible, false or fictitious),
things that we lack and things that we desire. We use language to fill with presence
Literature as a de ning trait of the human umwelt 155
the “integral without-ness” of human experience. It is the oppressiveness of Dasein
as a whole, the silence of the “God-forsaken rock” on which we live, which demands
the exchange of words. Relearning how to dwell, relearning how to connect Dasein
with the world and its elemental powers thus appears as a semiotic and, even more
precisely linguistic endeavour, in which literary practices have a key role to play – as
we shall now see.
2. Literary culture and collective dwelling
Indeed, literary culture, based on the tending and preserving of texts, can participate
in the development of a community and its connection (or reconnection) with
its place and time. This is exactly what Heidegger indicates in seminars and talks
given in the 1930s and 1940s, devoted to his compatriot Hölderlin. It is important
to remember that these studies on Hölderlin immediately follow Heidegger’s
unsatisfying mandate as rector of Freiburg University in 1933, one of his most explicit
political engagements, a debacle in which he subscribed to Nazism and, to a certain
extent, endorsed Hitler’s devastating project. Moreover, these seminars continue
straight into the Second World War, Europe’s most barbaric legacy to the 20th
century. This political and historical context is not an anecdotal bit of information,
but determines Heidegger’s conception of literature as a useful tool or activity around
which a people gathers, and consolidates its national heritage and destiny. Heidegger
saw (belatedly) that the raucous Hitler could not represent Germany’s essence; this
task could only be accomplished by Hölderlin, the subtler poet in tune with the
creativity of language and its intrinsic relation to philosophical interrogation. In his
essay “What are poets for?” devoted to the German-language poets Hölderlin and
Rilke, Heidegger (2001[1946]: 129) claims that the poet thinks “from the temple of
Being [fundamental ontology]” and is thus able to enhance, spur on (ethno)linguistic
creativity. Only by properly hearing Hölderlin – understanding, after a century
as did Rilke, his poetic composition– can we expect the return of the Gods, the
reestablishment of a connection between a people and its habitat. For Heidegger, the
homecoming of existence thus depends on our reception of Hölderlin.
This ethnolinguistic, nationalist interpretation of Heideggers poetic analysis may
appear surprising as Heidegger claims that Hölderlins poetry transcends any ontic diffe-
rences and fits squarely into the most general understanding of mankind. In his “Letter on
‘Humanism’ ”, Heidegger writes in reference to Hölderlin’s elegy Homecoming:
the word [homeland] is thought here in an essential sense, not patriotically or
nationalistically, but in terms of the history of being. The essence of the homeland
[…] is also mentioned with the intention of thinking the homelessness of
156 Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
contemporary human beings from the essence of beings history. […] [W]hen
Hölderlin composes “Homecoming” he is concerned that his countrymen find
their essence. He does not at all seek that essence in an egoism of his people. He
seeks it rather in the context of a belongingness to the destiny of the West. But
even the West is not thought regionally as the Occident in contrast to the Orient,
nor merely as Europe, but rather world-historically out of nearness to the source.
(Heidegger 1998[1946]: 257)
As was the case in his reflections on dwelling, Heidegger’s alleged global definition
of the homeland contrasts with his Western frame of reference. Heidegger is unable
or unwilling to see the variety of world cultures, erased under the postulated
universality of, for example, Hölderlin’s notion of “Homecoming”. We would not go
as far as Paul Cloke and Owain Jones (2001: 661) who admonish Heidegger for “the
sinister (nationalist) rustic romanticism which pervades [his] ideas”. Heidegger’s
appreciation of provincial life set forth in his essay “Why do I stay in the provinces”
(2010) indicates an acute understanding of regional differences and the threat
represented by the hegemony specific to urban life. Yet had Heidegger travelled
beyond his cherished Schwarzwald, maybe he would have identified more easily the
cultural situatedness of his perspective and of his frame of reference.
Notwithstanding Heidegger’s tendency to impose European modes of thinking
onto the world, his question remains intact: how can we understand the link between
literature as a creative linguistic practice and the collective inhabitation of a territory?
Again, Heidegger’s meditations on dwelling prove to be valuable. In “Building
dwelling thinking,” Heidegger (2008b[1951]: 351) writes: “To dwell, to be set at peace,
m eans to remain at peace within the free sphere that safeguards each thing in its
nature. The fundamental character of dwelling is this sparing and preserving”. In t ha t
it expresses the fourfold, dwelling spares mortals from the harshness and hostility
of the outer world; it preserves them, it enables them to conserve and to maintain
their existences. And mortals are spared and preserved, because, as they dwell in the
fourfold, they nurse and nurture “that with which [they] stay: in things” (Heidegger
2008b[1951]: 353). In other words, as they dwell, mortals learn to cultivate and
construct the meaningful things in their environment, “safeguard[ing] each thing
in its nature” (2008b[1951]: 351). There is a parallel here between Heidegger’s view
of Hölderlin’s work as a key to national homecoming and his definition of dwelling:
both are meant to safeguard existences and the things of their environment, the
things they relate to in their lived surroundings.
From a Heideggerean perspective, the collective inhabitation of a territory and
literature (a creative linguistic practice), appear as closely associated efforts. Relearning
how to dwell (in post-war Germany), and relearning the meaning of (Hölderlins)
literature are two ways to safeguard specific existences. Since literary practices are
fundamentally epistemic activities of sharing, knowing and feeling, they participate in
Literature as a de ning trait of the human umwelt 157
the extension of what Heidegger calls world-forming penetrability. Indeed, literary texts
produce the world we inhabit, they become key producers of umwelt when they are
shared among a community and create a common understanding of this community’s
lived surroundings. In this sense, the canonical text, the recognized, well-loved literary
work, is a form of settlement: like a physical building organizes a human milieu and
generates possibilities of acting, the canonical text organizes the semiosphere, it
organizes the environment and its possibilities of meaning. This conception of the text/
settlement can be developed through the vision of German-Canadian geographer Kraft
Eberhard von Maltzahn in his Nature as Landscape where he investigates the nature
of the human life-world and criticizes the alienating force of Modern positivism (in
other words, Mans techno-empirical transformation of the Earth into a “God-forsaken
rock”). Von Maltzahn (1994: 116) writes:
The built settlement as cultural form is the point of arrival, and it acts as a centre,
generating fields of forces that express themselves in the form of paths. These
directional paths subdivide the seemingly infinite extensions. The ordered space
that emerges admits particular patterns and rhythms of action.
Here, the built settlement, the dwelling place is not only a cultural technique of
preserving a community from an environment where warmth and food, for example,
may be lacking. Rather, it becomes, through this compensation of lack, a matrix of
possible actions, of ways of relating, penetrating and inhabiting an environment.
In a similar way, the canonical text, which according to Juri Lotman occupies the
centre of the semiosphere, generates paths for thought and experience, paths that are
shared by the community which inhabits these texts. These paths determine common
ways of seeing our milieu, common ways of speaking about and understanding our
immediate environment.
Thus the world-forming capacity of an organism to interact with its surroundings
gets externalized in technical artefacts (settlements, dwellings) and eventually
in habits, codes and symbolical systems such as verbal language and literature.
4
Of course, a symbolic system can only be a collective technology, and Heidegger’s
philosophical project reflects upon collective existence. This is a point that has
escaped many early commentators, who reduce Heideggers thought to an individual-
oriented existentialism marked by death and finitude. Watsuji Tetsurô, a Japanese
philosopher of the 1930s’ Kyoto School and interpreter of Heidegger’s work, purveys
this limited interpretation. In Fûdo, Watsuji claims to complete Heidegger’s project
by insisting on the being-toward-life of the collective where the interrelationship
4 See Leroi-Gourhan 1964 for an interpretation of hominization as a progressive externa-
lization of biological functions.
158 Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
between individuals survives the individual death; it is through the continual finitude
of the individual, through the unending chain of personal deaths, that the collective
being persists (Watsuji 2011: 50). Although Heidegger’s project does not call for
Watsuji’s amendment, in that collectivity was never so simply excluded from his
ontology, Watsuji does make an interesting point by insisting on the notion of milieu
or mediance, the geographical constitution of being. As Watsuji (2011: 44) explains,
our experience of locality, of local climate for instance, is always a shared, dialogical
socio-linguistic experience. For example, a snowstorm in Montreal or in Tartu is a
physical event experienced through language, through past and present enunciations.
These can be clichés used in daily dialogue, such as, “Oh no! Snow again!” or “What
beautiful snow!” Alternatively they can also be found in a shared literary heritage.
Through the exchange and circulation of these words, we discover ourselves, our
collective being, within the local climate and geography. Thus, as an especially
powerful form of language, literature gives shape to our collective experience of
climate, habitat, and territory.
For example, we can consider one of Quebec’s national poets, Émile Nelligan.
Associated with the emergence and persistence of francophone culture in the late
19th and early 20th centuries, when Canada was still completely controlled by the
British Empire, Nelligan would become an important figure of québécois culture.
A number of his poems would be taught in schools, and today anyone living in
Quebec is expected to know such lines as “Ah! comme la neige a neigé! / Ma vitre
est un jardin de givre” (“Ah! how the snow has snowed! / My window is a garden of
frost”) (Nelligan 2007[1902]: 215). Because they are so largely shared, these words
have provided a way of experiencing the climatic and habitational event of frosted
windows to an entire culture, allowing this culture to dwell together through this
specific experience.
The same could be said of the canonical Christmas songs with which the winter
season is launched in North America. From a strict Heideggerean perspective, we
could hardly associate the poetry of Hölderlin or Nelligan in all their authenticity
(admittedly, a dubious Heideggerean concept) to popular songs. Popular songs
code our experience of the Christmas/winter holidays because they occupy the
conventional core of the semiosphere. Played repeatedly on radios, in shopping malls
and restaurants, they are obvious signs of capitalism’s firm grip on our communities,
of the industrialization and the commodification of our cultural relationship with
seasonal changes. Contrary to the predictable and repetitive productions of pop
culture, the Romantic poets would elevate their expressions and sentiments towards
more noble goals. Notwithstanding the disdain towards mainstream culture that
permeates Heideggerean philosophy, Christmas songs still generate a shared mode
of dwelling. Like the words of Hölderlin or Nelligan, these songs mediate our
Literature as a de ning trait of the human umwelt 159
relationship to our living environment, filling the negative, silent space between the
collective subject and its environment with meaning – however commodified it may
be. When poetry reflects territory, it fills the silence – the site of the Heideggerean
abandonment of the Gods –, and reminds us the forgotten art of dwelling, caring and
tending. Thus, through singular uses of language, of rhetoric devices, of poetic and
narrative forms, literature produces new modes of co-existing within a territory.
This buttresses Heidegger’s point: the “homecoming of existence, the consoli-
dation of a national heritage and destiny, are intrinsically linked to a literary culture
and its creators. In other words, the literary institution, by definition a collective
effort, participates in the association of a people and its territory. By communicating
with itself through canonical texts – what Lotman (1990: 33) refers to as auto-
communication – a culture codes itself. Like a grammar, the canonical text occupies
the centre of the semiosphere, allowing self-preservation and structuration of a
culture through time. It becomes a code through which meaning is organized
and communicated, a model used to discriminate the meaningful from the un-
meaningful. As such, the text is a site of productivity, to use the terms of another
semiotician, Roland Barthes (2002: 448; our translation, P.-L. P., J. H.):
a text is a productivity. […] Even written (fixed) it never ceases to work, to
maintain a process of production. What does a text fashion? Language [La
langue]. It deconstructs the language of communication, of representation, or
expression […] and reconstructs another full language, with neither substance
nor surface.
Literary works that attain the status of masterpieces serve to redefine our language,
our cultural codes and habits, our possibilities of meaning and, among these
possibilities, the representation through which we relate to our cultural and bio-
physical territory. The reintroduction of the bios here is not random. Indeed,
canonical literary texts determine the destiny of language, and language is a
structuring factor of our biosemiotic habitat. In the words of Jesper Hoffmeyer (1996:
112), language is a “common dwelling place […] one large common Umwelt”). As
such, canonical texts produce an environment of meaning, habits and codes that are
interwoven with our organic mode of existence. The linguistic productivity of these
texts enlarges and enlivens the horizon of meaning, truly bringing forth a community
where perceptual and interpretative possibilities are never purely individual. Meaning
is thus always co-meaning, shared within a community.
160 Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
3. Communities, territories, and texts:
New configurations
But this raises a legitimate question: which community? And which habitat for this
community? From a Heideggerean perspective, the answer is rather straightforward:
a literary masterpiece such as Hölderlin’s allows for a nostalgic homecoming to a
quintessentially European (Greek-German) historical-destinal being. Considering
the fact that Heidegger was thinking of, and elaborating upon an early-20th-century
vision of international geopolitics and cultural dynamics dominated by the nation-
state, his answer is unsurprising. Indeed, the structure of modern languages, themselves
shaped by their literary canons, is closely associated with the boundary-drawing
Modern nation-states in which habitat and linguistic space are superimposed. This
fact is evident in Modern colonialism. Although Germany did not engage in colonial
expansion, the 19th century European nations that did, used their literary masterpieces
as cultural and linguistic tools to enforce their hegemony; for example, Shakespeare
was deliberately used by the British to propagate their values across their Empire.
5
In
the second half of the 20th century, as most European empires collapsed, emerging
nations reclaimed the strategy to reconstruct a national identity that would correspond
to their newly freed territory. Local languages or dialects, such as québécois, would play
an important role in the emancipation of these postcolonial nations that organized
themselves around new literary texts.
6
In the 1960s, Quebec was undergoing its own
postcolonial awakening, an intense period of social, cultural and political changes. The
Quiet Revolution was marked by secularization, the creation of a welfare state and the
construction of a new national identity. In this context, québécois poets such as Anne
Hébert, Claude Gauvreau, and Gaston Miron will promote a dialectal French to the
status of national language, a source of pride and a vector of collective destiny. By
productively fashioning language (as Barthes would say) the poems penned by Hébert,
Gauvreau and Miron rapidly accessed and transformed the core of the literary canon.
They opened paths for thought and experience, they indicated potential ways of living
together on a shared territory.7
But which territory? By the 21st century, in the face of global capitalism, new
dynamics of conflict, unpredictably shifting populations, and the pervasive environ-
5 See Viswanathan 1989 for a thorough analysis of the Indian case.
6 Incidentally, Heidegger will insist on a similar point in a series of later texts on Alemannic
lyric poetry: thinking and expressing ourselves through language, with the poet who poetizes
in our particular dialect, enables us to come home, installs us at home, helps us, mortals, to
dwell in the fourfold. For a sympathetic and detailed analysis of this moment in Heidegger’s
thought, see Mugerauer 2008.
7 For more on the unique manner in which literature and nationalism were played out in
Quebec, see Popovic 1992.
Literature as a de ning trait of the human umwelt 161
mental challenges, the dominance of the nation-state model in world organisation
appears jeopardized. The question remains open as to how the human animal’s
linguistic abilities, literary exploits, lived surroundings, territorial dwellings and
identity-forming processes interact to create new world structures. Indeed, in our
global ecological context, it is crucial to create shared horizons of meaning large enough
to embrace the whole biosphere, where local specificities and identities are articulated
with international co-habitation. We cannot limit ourselves to national existences. This
impos sibility has appeared clearly in the past decades, notably with the paradigm-
changing pictures of the Earth taken from space, such as the famous Earthrise taken by
astronaut William Anders in 1968 during the Apollo 8 mission (Fig. 1).
Figure 1. Earthrise. Picture taken by William Anders, 1968. (Courtesy of NASA; public
domain).8
8 e image has been retrieved from http://www.hq.nasa.gov/o ce/pao/History/alsj/a410/
AS8-14-2383HR.jpg.
162 Pierre-Louis Patoine, Jonathan Hope
Such pictures have shown the Earth, not national territories, as our real, and perhaps
definitive, habitat. Thus, as thought-provoking as they are, Heidegger’s ideas on
animal worlds, and on Man’s capacity to dwell through literature, must be enlarged.
“Homecoming” can no longer be defined by national (ethnic-linguistic) boundaries,
those unsurpassable ontic conditions that find their way into Heideggers ontological
understanding of dwelling and poetry. The oppressiveness of Dasein is shared by
billions of humans and trillions of other living organisms coexisting on our small Earth.
Reconnecting our existences with such a habitat, relearning how to dwell responsibly
together will be done by the institution of a common semiosphere as large as our
common biosphere. How can literature serve such a project? How can we preserve the
wealth of local cultures and languages in such a context? Is it possible to establish a
fair global literary canon that would give equal opportunity to every culture? These are
questions that we as citizens of the 21st century will definitely need to ponder.
References
Barthes, Roland 2002[1973]. Texte (théorie du). In: Œuvres completes IV. Paris: Seuil, 443–459.
Casadebaig, Philippe 2015. Heidegger et Protagoras. Revue de métaphysique et morale 85:
3–42.
Cloke, Paul; Jones, Owain 2001. Dwelling, place, and landscape: An orchard in Somerset.
Environment and Planning A 33: 649–666.
Deacon, Terrence 2012. Incomplete Nature. How Mind Emerged from Matter. New York: W. W.
Norton & Co.
Descartes, René 2000[1637]. Discours de la méthode. Pour bien conduire sa raison et chercher la
vérité dans les sciences. Paris: Librairie générale française.
Frings, Manfred 1974. Protagoras re-discovered: Heidegger’s explication of Protagoras’ frag-
ment. The Journal of Value Inquiry 8(2): 112–123.
Heidegger, Martin 1996[1927]. Being and Time. (Stambaugh, Joan, trans.) Albany: State
University of New York Press.
1998[1946]. Letter on “Humanism. In: Pathmarks. (McNeil, William; Capuzzi, Frank,
trans.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 239–276.
2001[1946]. What are poets for? In: Poetry, Language, Thought. (Hofstadter, Albert, trans.)
New York: Harper Perennial, 87–140.
2008a[1929–1930]. The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics. World, Finitude, Solitude.
(McNeill, William; Walker, Nicholas, trans.) Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
2008b[1951]. Building dwelling thinking. In: Basic Writings. (Krell, David Farrell, trans.)
New York: Harper Perennial, 343–363.
2010[1934]. Why do I stay in the provinces?. In: Heidegger. The Man and the Thinker.
(Sheehan, Thomas, trans.) New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 27–30.
Hoffmeyer, Jesper 1996[1993]. Signs of Meaning in the Universe. (Haveland, Barbara, trans.)
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Hope, Jonathan 2014. The sign in Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit. Semiotica 202: 259–271.
2015. Heidegger and the signs of history. Semiotica 207: 567–581.
Literature as a de ning trait of the human umwelt 163
Leroi-Gourhan, André 1964. Le geste et la parole. (2 vols.) Paris: Albin Michel.
Lotman, Juri 1990. Universe of the Mind: A Semiotic Theory of Culture. (Shukman, Ann, trans.;
Eco, Umberto, intr.) Bloomington, Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Maltzahn, Kraft Eberhard von 1994. Nature as Landscape: Dwelling and Understanding. Mont-
real: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Mugerauer, Robert 2008. Learning to become at home in saying. In: Heidegger and Home-
coming. The Leitmotif in the Later Writings. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 370–445.
Nelligan, Émile 2007[1902]. Œuvres complètes I. Poésies complètes 1896–1941. Montréal:
Bibliothèque québécoise, 262.
Popovic, Pierre 1992. La contradiction du poème. Poésie et discours social au Québec de 1948 à
1953. Repentigny: Éditeur Balzac.
Tetsurô, Watsuji 2011[1935]. Fûdo. Le milieu humain. (Berque, Augustin, trans.) Paris: Centre
National de la Recherche Scientifique – Éditions.
Uexküll, Jakob von 1909. Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere. Berlin: Julius Springer.
Viswanathan, Gauri 1989. Masks of Conquest: Literary Study and British Rule in India. New
York: Colombia University Press.
Литература как определяющая черта человеческого умвельта:
Начиная с Хайдеггера и далее
Писатели и читатели литературы являются, помимо всего прочего, биологическими
существами, которые развиваются при определенных политических (географических
и исторических) условиях. Сравнительное изучение некоторых текстов Мартина Хай-
деггера может помочь нам плодотворно интерпретировать тройственную связь между
литературой, биологией и политикой. Однако тщательный анализ показывает, что
Хайдеггер излишне укоренен в националистической и антропоцентрической пара-
дигме старого мира. Мы попытаемся заново пересмотреть предпосылки Хайдег гера,
основываясь на идее, что литература как культурная практика позволяет очертить
нашу окружающую среду. Переформулируя ход мыслей Хайдеггера, мы можем точнее
обрисовать множественную структуру наших биотических и политико-литературных
опытов.
Kirjandus kui inimese omailma määratlev tunnusjoon:
Heideggeri ideedest lähtudes ja neid avardades
Lisaks muule on kirjanikud ja lugejad ka bioloogilised olendid, kes kujunevad välja teatavates
poliitilistes (geograafilistes ning ajaloolistes) tingimustes. Martin Heideggeri (1889–1976)
mõnede tekstide võrdlev uurimine võib meil aidata viljakalt interpreteerida kolmiksidet
kirjanduskunsti, bioloogia ja poliitika vahel. Nende tekstide hoolikas analüüs näitab paraku,
et Heidegger takerdub liigselt Vana Maailma rahvuskesksesse ja antropotsentristlikku para-
digmasse. Me püüame Heideggeri eeldused uuesti üle vaadata, võttes lähtekohaks, et kirjan-
dus kultuuripraktikana võimaldab visandada meie loomulikku keskkonda. Heideggeri mõtte-
käiku ümber sõnastades suudame täpsemalt käsitleda elusloodust puudutavate poliitilis-
kirjanduslike kogemuste mitmikstruktuuri.
Article
Full-text available
The article gives a brief overview of the publication of the journal Sign Systems Studies. Throughout its publication period that started in 1964 the journal has been edited by a group of Tartu semioticians; the publisher has been the University of Tartu Press. While the first 25 volumes mainly contained articles in Russian, the next 25 volumes have predominantly been given out in English. We provide a list of thematic issues and a complete bibliography of the articles that have appeared in the journal during its entire publication period from 1964 to 2022.
Chapter
Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere, Originaltext von 1921
Book
Martin Heidegger's philosophical works devoted themselves to challenging previously held ontological notions of what constitutes "being," and much of his work focused on how beings interact within particular spatial locations. Frequently, Heidegger used the motifs of homelessness and homecoming in order to express such spatial interactions, and despite early and continued recognition of the importance of homelessness and homecoming, this is the first sustained study of these motifs in his later works. Utilizing both literary and philosophical analysis, Heidegger and Homecoming reveals the deep figural unity of the German philosopher's writings, by exploring not only these homecoming and homelessness motifs, but also the six distinctive voices that structure the apparent disorder of his works. In this illuminating and comprehensive study, Robert Mugerauer argues that these motifs and Heidegger's many voices are required to overcome and replace conventional and linear methods of logic and representation. Making use of material that has been both neglected and yet to be translated into English, Heidegger and Homecoming explains the elaborate means with which Heidegger proposed that humans are able to open themselves to others, while at the same time preserve their self-identity.
Article
Sign studies are traditionally divided into two major traditions: Peircean and Saussurean. However, other thinkers theorized the sign in radically unique terms. The German philosopher Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) is one of these parallel thinkers. Rather than considering the sign in exclusively logical or linguistic terms, Heidegger claimed that the sign grounded existence itself. The sign was at the very heart of being. Strangely, Heidegger's contribution to sign studies is, on the whole, disregarded. With this paper I will explain Heidegger's conception of the sign, in hope that this will broaden our field's theoretical encyclopaedia.
Article
Heidegger's conception of the sign formulated in Sein und Zeit (1996 [1927]) may shed some light on his disastrous, philosophical and political experience with Nazism. In order to show this, I propose to assess how Heidegger establishes the relationship between signs and history in his magnum opus. Then, relying on the fact-central to Heidegger's thinking, and to sign studies in general-that ideas are linked to the world, I will proceed to examine how Heidegger's philosophical meditations stand up to his real-life engagements. My final remarks, more interrogative than declarative, will raise the question as to how Heidegger was lured into believing that Nazism represented a moment of truth.
Article
The starting point of this paper is a supposed kinship between the “man-measure” of Protagoras and Heidegger’s concept of “Dasein”, since, according to him, there is no other truth but commensurate with the Dasein (“daseinsmässig”). One finds indeed, following Heidegger’s interpretation of the sophist, that Protagoras’sentence is for him “the highest principle of any philosophy”. Many objections can be opposed to this interpretation, but one must recognize that his way of reading the texts, as well as the doctrine about presence which it implies, cannot but escape any attempt of refutation in the proper dialectical meaning of this word. However, it is finally suggested that the “deconstruction” of Protagoras thesis in Plato’s Thaetetus, which is firmly denied and rejected by Heidegger’s own commentary upon it, could be returned against him, in order to question his thought as a modern kind of sophistry.