ArticlePDF Available

A meditation on boredom: Re-appraising its value through introspective phenomenology

Taylor & Francis
Qualitative Research In Psychology
Authors:

Abstract

Boredom is almost universally regarded as a dysphoric mental state, characterised by features such as disengagement and low arousal. However, in certain quarters (e.g., Zen Buddhism), boredom is seen as potentially having great value and even importance. The current study sought to explore boredom through a case study involving introspective phenomenology. The author created conditions in which he would experience boredom for an hour, and recorded his experience in real-time using a variant of the Experiencing Sampling Method. The data were analysed using an adaptation of Interpretative Phenomenological Analysis. The results indicated that the state of boredom contained three main sources of value: (a) altered perception of time; (b) awakened curiosity about the environment; and (c) exploration of self. Consequently, the paper offers a re-appraisal of boredom, suggesting that rather than necessarily being a negative state, if engaged with, boredom has the potential to be a positive and rewarding experience.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
2
A meditation on boredom:
Re-appraising its value through introspective phenomenology
Dr. Tim Lomas,
University of East London,
School of Psychology,
t.lomas@uel.ac.uk
Note: This article may not exactly replicate the final version published in Psychology, Public Policy, and Law.
It is not the copy of record.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
3
Abstract
Boredom is almost universally regarded as a dysphoric mental state, characterised by features such as
disengagement and low arousal. However, in certain quarters (e.g., Zen Buddhism), boredom is seen
as potentially having great value and even importance. The current study sought to explore boredom
through a case study involving introspective phenomenology. The author created conditions in which
he would experience boredom for an hour, and recorded his experience in real-time using a variant of
the Experiencing Sampling Method. The data were analysed using an adaptation of Interpretative
Phenomenological Analysis. The results indicated that the state of boredom contained three main
sources of value: (a) altered perception of time; (b) awakened curiosity about the environment; and (c)
exploration of self. Consequently, the paper offers a re-appraisal of boredom, suggesting that rather
than necessarily being a negative state, if engaged with, boredom has the potential to be a positive and
rewarding experience.
Keywords: boredom; meditation; phenomenology; introspection; wellbeing.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
4
The problem of boredom
Boredom is almost universally regarded as a negative mental state. This disparaging appraisal is
reflected in Vogel-Walcutt et al.’s (2012, p.90) definition of it as temporary feelings of low-arousal
and unpleasant emotions induced by environmental factors,’ and in Fisherl’s (1993, p.396) depiction
as an ‘unpleasant, transient affective state, in which the individual feels a pervasive lack of interest.’
However, these sparse definitions do not really begin to capture the range of dysphoric feelings that
have historically been associated with the term ‘boredom’ (Toohey, 1988). Indeed, Toohey suggests
that boredom or non-English translative equivalents, since ‘boredom’ did not enter the English
language until 1852 with Charles Dickens’ (1853) Bleak House has been used throughout history to
depict states of malaise that involve some dispiriting combination of frustration, surfeit, depression,
disgust, indifference, apathy, and confinement. Moreover, each historical epoch has tended to
emphasise particular elements of this dysphoric state. One of the earliest literary works, the Sumerian
Epic of Gilgamesh (transcribed circa 2000 B.C.) describes the Mesopotamian King Uruk as being
‘oppressed by idleness’ (cited in Maier, 1997, p.314); this ennui is then the premise for Uruk
embarking on a quest to discover some sense of purpose and legacy. A somewhat more frustrated
state is depicted in Homer’s Iliad (circa 850 B.C.), in which a mood akin to boredom is cited when the
Achaeans are waiting restlessly to fight the Trojans, with the state taking on shades of vexation and
impatience (Toohey, 1988).
Later, in classical Greek and Roman philosophy, we find states comparable to boredom taking
on weighty existential overtones that verge on despair, emotional states that are arguably close to the
modern psychiatric diagnosis of depression (Szasz, 2002). For instance, the Stoic philosopher Seneca
(4 B.C. 65 A.D.) lamented the ubiquity of Taedium vitae (tiredness of life), which he describes
chillingly as ‘the tumult of a soul fixated on nothing’ (cited in Hecht, 2013, p.42); indeed, Taedium
vitae was recognised by Roman law as one of the few morally acceptable reasons for suicide (though
Seneca did not himself advocate this). In medieval times, boredom took on shades of spiritual
listlessness and melancholia in the form of acedia (Latin); this was often referred to by Christians as
the ‘demon of noontide,’ and was described by St. Thomas Aquinas (1273) as sorrow of the world,’
and the ‘enemy of spiritual joy’ (cited in Frevert, 2011, p.31). In more recent centuries, this existential
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
5
sense of anomie, and of the melancholia that would often accompany it, was recast and labelled in a
variety of ways, including as the ‘English disease’ in the 17th and 18th centuries, the ‘mal de siecle’ in
19th century Europe, and the ‘nausea’ of continental existentialists in the 20th century (Toohey, 1988).
Coming into the present day, contemporary psychological theory has sought to identify and
operationalise different forms of boredom. For instance, Toohey (2011) suggests that boredom can be
differentiated into: (a) existential boredom; (b) situational boredom; and (c) boredom of surfeit. The
first encapsulates many of the melancholic states depicted above, such as Taedium vitae. However, as
noted, this form of deep, existential boredom is perhaps more likely to be characterised in today’s
medicalised discourse as ‘depression,’ and in its extreme versions to be treated clinically as a
psychopathology (Szasz, 2002). In contrast, situational (or ‘situative’) boredom – referred to by the
novelist Flaubert (1856) as ‘common boredom’ – arises when a specific situation is judged to lack
interest or value. As Svendsen (2005) notes, this context-specific state can be distinguished from
existential boredom in numerous ways, not least their physiological manifestations; situational
boredom is revealed by signs of restlessness and/or tiredness, from fidgeting to yawning; in contrast,
existential boredom is not necessarily accompanied by any particular physical/behavioural patterns.
Finally, boredom of surfeit captures the kind of decadent overabundance where one encounters a lack
of constraining limits (e.g., as experienced by the very rich), but where one also lacks the ability or
passion to make any value distinctions, thereby finding all options to be equally uninteresting.
Another contemporary approach to boredom, driven by psychometric personality theory, has
been to differentiate between trait and state boredom, and to elucidate the differential factors
comprising these. Trait boredom, i.e., general tendencies towards experiencing boredom, has most
commonly been assessed using the ‘boredom proneness’ scale developed by Farmer and Sundberg
(1986). Although initially operationalised as a single factor, subsequent analyses (e.g., Vodanovich et
al., 2005) identified two main factors: lack of external stimulation (which pertains to one’s need for
variability and change); and lack of internal stimulation (which concerns an inability to produce
stimulation for oneself). Conversely, state boredom relates more to what Toohey (2011) refers to as
situational boredom, i.e., lack of interest in one’s current situation. In this respect, Fahlman et al.’s
(2013) Multidimensional State Boredom Scale comprises five main factors: disengagement, high
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
6
arousal, low arousal, inattentiveness, and (altered) time perception. In turn, both trait and state forms
of boredom have been associated with a host of negative outcomes. For instance, trait boredom has
been identified as a risk factor for anxiety and depression (LePera, 2011), negative social orientation,
such as alienation or paranoia (Leong & Schneller, 1993), impulsivity (Watt & Vodanovich, 1992),
and dysfunctional behaviours, e.g., pathological gambling (Blaszczynski et al., 1990). Similarly, state
boredom has been linked to multiple adverse outcomes; for example, in the context of work, boredom
has unsurprisingly been connected to greater dissatisfaction with most aspects of work, from work
itself, to pay and co-workers (Kass et al., 2001), as well as poorer performance as rated by managers
(Watt & Hargis, 2010). More broadly, adopting a phenomenological perspective, Bargdill (2000)
explored more extensive forms of boredom, analysing the experiences of six people who felt ‘bored
with their lives’ (p.188). His analysis revealed that this type of enduring malaise arose in part from an
assessment that endeavour and action were futile, leading to feelings of apathy and emptiness.
Re-evaluating boredom
So, boredom is generally considered to be a problematic or dysphoric state. While there are multiple
ways of conceptualising boredom, these all point to, in Klapp’s (1986, p.127) words, a ‘deficit in the
quality of life.’ However, alongside this dominant negative perspective, it is possible to discern a
subtly different strand of thought, one that is less obvious, but which actually finds some strange
value in boredom. In this line of thinking, the issue is not so much with boredom per se, but with
people’s inability to tolerate or engage with it. Indeed, many of the issues above, such as the
dysfunctional gambling behaviour associated with boredom proneness, can be viewed as the result of
a desperate fleeing from boredom; it is this common intolerance of boredom, and the resulting
troubles, that led to the existentialist philosopher Søren Kierkegaard (1843, p.281) arguing forcefully
that ‘Boredom is the root of all evil.’ In a less dramatic way, the anthropologist Genevieve Bell (2011)
suggests that recent technological innovations like the smartphone have created a world of constant
distraction that prevents people from ever having to be bored. On the surface, according to the
conventional negative appraisal of boredom outlined above, these technological developments are
surely a good thing, alleviating its ubiquitous and problematic burden. However, Bell argues that
actually this easy distraction is an issue, since allowing oneself to experience boredom can not only be
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
7
valuable, but important and vital. Indeed, she points to the emergence of trends such as ‘digital
detoxing’ (Morrison & Gomez, 2014) as indicators that people need the time and space to
occasionally be bored. Why might that be? What could boredom have to offer that might be of value?
Indeed, the impetus for the current paper stems from a similarly curious and provocative
question by Robert Pirsig (1974) in his classic Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, in which
he discusses the value of meditation. A wealth of recent research has suggested that meditation (e.g.,
mindfulness) can be highly beneficial for wellbeing, from alleviating mental illness (Zindel et al.,
2002) to helping people function better at work (Shapiro et al., 2005). In his book though, Pirsig
makes a striking point in relation to the Zen practice of zazen (essentially a form of mindfulness):
Zen has something to say about boredom. Its main practice of “just sitting” has got to be the world’s
most boring activity… You don’t do anything much: not move, not think, not care. What could be
more boring? Yet in the very center of this boredom is the very thing Zen Buddhism seeks to teach.
What is it? What is it at the very center of boredom that you’re not seeing?’ (p317). This paper, then,
attempts to explore this question.
In exploring relevant literature in pursuit of possible answers, three main responses emerged:
(a) altered perceptions; (b) creativity; and (c) exploration of ‘the self.’ Regarding altered perceptions,
the most striking example is shifts in one’s experience of time. Indeed, Heidegger (1938), who wrote
extensively on the importance of becoming attuned to boredom, felt that it amounted to a physical
experience of time (and of our existence through time). More specifically, Heidegger argued that in
boredom which he referred to as an ‘existential orientation’ rather than a mood (Slaby, 2010)
subjective time tends to slow down, as if to a halt. In a similar vein, the dissident Soviet author and
Nobel laureate Joseph Brodsky (1997) argued that boredom ‘represents pure, undiluted time in all its
repetitive, redundant, monotonous splendour.’ Of course, this sense of time slowing is a familiar
feature of boredom; indeed, experiments in time perception suggest that high boredom prone people
do experience time as subjectively passing more slowly (although they can often still accurately judge
the objective passing of chronometric time) (Watt, 1991). However, what is striking about the position
of Heidegger and Brodsky is the great value of entering into this altered mode of time perception. For
instance, Brodsky described boredom as our ‘window on time’s infinity,’ the experience of which
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
8
could radically alter our sense of place in the cosmos. Similarly, for Heidegger, deep boredom creates
a clearing space in which one gains insights into the nature of reality, including the sense that one is
responsible for creating meaning in life, and moreover is free and empowered to do so (Slaby, 2010).
Such insights brings us to the second key value of boredom in the literature: creativity. One
can find many testimonials from geniuses attesting to the generative power of boredom. For instance,
Nietzsche (1882, p.108) wrote that great artists require a lot of boredom if their work is to succeed.
For thinkers and all sensitive spirits, boredom is that disagreeable ‘windless calm’ of the soul that
precedes a happy voyage and cheerful winds. They have to bear it and must wait for its effect on
them.’ Similarly, Kets de Vries (2014) argued that boredom played a crucial role in many great
artistic and scientific breakthroughs: Decartes allegedly ‘discovered’ the notions of x and y while
idling in bed watching a fly on the ceiling, while Einstein reportedly achieved his initial pivotal
insight into the nature of relativity while abstractly daydreaming. Thus, as Stern (1988) puts it, the
heavy-gaited time’ (p.5) of monotony and boredom serves as a gestational space, and finally as a
‘reluctant but nevertheless urgent passageway to creativity’ (p.11). Such anecdotes have been
corroborated by recent research. For instance, Gasper and Middlewood (2014) and Mann and Cadman
(2014) found that participants induced into a state of boredom performed far better on creativity tests
(e.g., thinking of novel uses for plastic cups) than people who were either elated, relaxed or distressed.
One explanation given was that boredom allowed attention to wander, and the mind to free-associate,
thus facilitating creativity. Indeed, from a neurophysiological perspective, boredom may activate the
default mode network (Raichle et al., 2001), which is thought to play a key role in creativity (e.g.,
stimulus independent thought) (Takeuchi et al., 2012).
Finally, and perhaps most dauntingly but also most transformatively, boredom can be a means
of self-exploration, of coming face-to-face with oneself. This brings us back to meditation, and to
Pirsig’s (1974) point that ‘in the very center of this boredom is the very thing Zen Buddhism seeks to
teach’ (p.317). Zen is generally regarded to have begun with the Indian monk Bodhidharma, who
brought Buddhism to China in 520 A.D. (Watts, 1957). According to semi-historical legend, upon
arrival in China, he failed to initially be well-received, and thereafter retreated to a cave and spent
nine years meditating facing its wall. Such was his subsequent influence that wall-facing became the
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
9
dominant form of meditation in Zen (Senauke, 2006). The contemporary teacher Osho (2015) freely
acknowledges that this activity is perhaps the very epitome of boredom. However, Eastern traditions
have an interesting explanation for this boredom: at its core, it is the result of psychological tension
that arises if people are uncomfortable being alone with themselves. As such, it is suggested that
many people seek company or distraction to avoid this type of uncomfortable self-encounter (Pezeu-
Massabuau, 2013). However, Buddhist theory holds that if one can tolerate and push on through this
boredom and discomfort, one is able to gain vital insights into one’s mind and self-identity (Biceaga,
2006). From a psychological growth perspective, such experiential insights can potentially be
liberating and transformative; as Osho puts it, ‘Watching the wall – slowly, slowly thoughts
disappear, thinking stops, mind evaporates and what is left is your authentic reality’ (p.486).
So, as can be seen, although boredom has tended to be conceptualised as a negative state,
there are valid reasons to suppose that it may potentially be of some value. The current study, then, is
an exploratory investigation of boredom, aimed at enquiring into its nature and understanding any
positive experiential elements. To do this, the study uses the relatively unconventional method of
phenomenological introspection. Introspection was a much valued methodology in the early years of
psychology, pioneered by phenomenological philosophers like Edmund Husserl (1931). Indeed,
William James (1890, p.185) wrote that ‘Introspective Observation is what we have to rely on first
and foremost and always.’ The technique fell out of favour due to numerous factors, from the
dominance of Skinner’s (1938) behaviourism in the first half of the 20th century, to the critique of
self-knowledge and agency provided by post-constructionist theories of identity in the latter half (e.g.,
Gergen, 1985). However, in recent years, the value of phenomenology has once again been
recognised, most prominently within consciousness studies with the emergence of Varela’s (1996)
neurophenomenology paradigm. As outlined in Varela and Shear’s (1999) edited book The View from
Within: First-Person Approaches to the Study of Consciousness, first-person reports of subjectivity
have an invaluable (and indeed irreplaceable) role in furthering our understanding of psychological
processes and experience. As such, this study brings the introspective phenomenological method to
bear on the experience of boredom, with the aim of enquiring whether boredom may contain value or
uses that are not readily apparent in conventional (i.e., negative) appraisals of this state.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
10
Method
Overview
Introspective phenomenology is a form of empiricism which involves observing and reporting on
one’s own subjectivity with as much accuracy as possible. As Sinnott-Armstrong (2008, p.85) puts it,
‘The method is simple: describe the phenomena. More precisely: introspect on your own experience
and then describe what it is like to have certain kinds of experience.’ The method can arguably be
situated within the broader emergent paradigm of auto-ethnography (Denzin, 2013), being
distinguished in particular by efforts to engage with one’s current subjective experience. For this
study, conditions were established in which I would experience boredom for an hour, specifically, in
the middle of a 13 hour airplane flight. (Given the nature of the project, the first person voice will be
used from here on in.) I recorded my experiences in real time using an adaption of Csikszentmihalyi
and Larson’s (1987) Experiencing Sampling Method. The recorded data were explored for thematic
content, and analysed using an adaptation of Smith’s (1996) Interpretative Phenomenological
Analysis.
Participant
Reflexivity is important in qualitative research, since the personal background and qualities of the
researcher impact upon the research at all stages of the process, including serving as the ‘filter of
salience through which data are sieved’ (Schreiber, 2001, p.60). As such, it is worth mentioning a few
salient details about myself here that are relevant to the study. (That said, I shall keep this brief, for
reasons given in the discussion.) I am a 36 year old lecturer in psychology. I was born in London into
to a very loving middle class family (although my parents, both teachers, have a working class
background), with one brother and sister. I did well academically at school, despite it being a rough
place, and spent much of my time playing music and football. Before university I taught English for
six months in China, and returned the following year to visit Tibet; it was there I became interested in
Buddhism, and have tried ever since (with varying success) to maintain a regular meditation practice.
I moved up to Edinburgh to study psychology, and stayed there for nine years. I spent five years in a
touring and recording band while also working as a psychiatric nursing assistant. I moved back to
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
11
London in 2008 to undertake a PhD, studying the impact of meditation on mental health, and took up
a position as a lecturer at a university in London in 2013.
Data collection
The intention was to gather real-time data on my own subjective experience of boredom. The data
collection method was an adaption of Csikszentmihalyi and Larson’s (1987) Experiencing Sampling
Method (ESM). Standard ESM protocol involves participants being contacted at various intervals
(e.g., via pager), at which point they are asked to self-rate current experience (e.g., in terms of affect).
The variation pioneered in the current study might be termed the ‘micro-experience auto-sampling
method’ (MEASM). It is micro because it covers a relatively short period of time (one hour in this
case). It is auto in two respects: (a) it is autonomous, in that the data was elicited and recorded by
myself, rather than at the prompting of an independent researcher; and (b) it is automatic, in that the
prompts were regulated by a set timer (in this case, setting my phone to alert me, via a vibration,
every 60 seconds).
The specific details of the data collection are as follows. A period of time was selected in
which I was likely to be bored. The occasion selected was a 13 hour flight (leaving Singapore at 7am,
bound for London). I selected the mid-point of the flight (i.e., after six hours) as the hour in which
data collection would occur. This was chosen as an ideal situation for boredom, given, (a) flights are
generally regarded as somewhat boring; (b) after six hours, I was already likely to be bored; (c)
limited opportunities for movement (none in fact occurred during the hour); (d) limited opportunities
for interaction (none in fact occurred during the hour); and (e) a relatively unchanging visual scene
(window blinds were purposefully kept closed, and my entertainment screen turned off). Moreover,
prior to the data collection hour, I specifically sought to ensure that I would already be in a state of
boredom. For the first four hours of the flight, I watched two films (The Usual Suspects, and
American Beauty), both of which I like but had seen at least twice before. I then spent two hours
doing nothing (i.e., not entertaining myself in any way, and also not specifically trying to meditate or
engage in interesting mental activities), to further foster a state of boredom. For the data collection
hour itself, I sat comfortably in my chair and set my phone to vibrate every 60 seconds. At each 60-
second prompting, I quickly wrote a note [a few words] on my laptop, simply recording what I was
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
12
thinking, feeling or experiencing at that particular moment. Immediately at the end of the hour, I then
expanded each note into a full sentence, drawing on my still-fresh memory to provide slightly more
detail and context to each note.
Data analysis
The data analysis method was a variation on Smith’s (1996) Interpretative Phenomenological
Analysis (IPA). Standard IPA protocol was developed for the analysis of one-to-one interviews of a
small group of participants who are ‘homogenous’ in some way. However, recent years have seen
adaptations to suit various methodological contexts, e.g., focus groups (Palmer et al., 2010). IPA
usually aims towards moving from the particular (i.e., one person’s experiences) to the shared (i.e.,
experiences people have in common). However, in the current study, the aim was to explore the
particular in some depth through a sustained exercise in introspection, thereby providing a case study
of boredom. In other respects, however, the protocol of IPA was followed, i.e., moving from the
descriptive to the interpretative via a process of close line-by-line coding followed by identification of
emergent themes.
The data analysis occurred immediately after the data collection hour. The raw data were the
60 notes I had made during the hour (one per minute). Thus, the first stage of the analysis was the
process of expanding these notes into whole sentences, as indicated above, which took about 10
minutes. I then moved into the initial coding stage, in which I sought to identify up to three themes for
each of the 60 entries (with an ‘entry’ consisting of the original note, plus the expanded sentence). In
doing so, since the experience was still fresh in my mind, I was able to move from description to
interpretation by drawing on memories and reflections of the hour itself, thereby substantiating and
fleshing out the recorded notes. This coding process generated 82 separate themes (some shared by
more than one entry). Next, I looked for emergent patterns of commonality by grouping the themes
into categories based on conceptual similarity, which generated 20 categories. The categories were
themselves then grouped into five meta-categories, again based on conceptual similarity: Time;
World; Subjectivity; Self/Identity; and Project.
Results
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
13
The data collection hour generated 60 separate initial notes (one per minute), as detailed below
verbatim in table 1. The expanded sentences based on the notes (written immediately after the hour)
are included in the third column.
Minute
Verbatim note
Expanded sentence
1
why do this, futile
Question futility of exercise
2
thinking of items! pressure
Wonder about pressure to write one item per minute
3
fast min
Surprised by speed of the previous minute
4
dirty screen
Notice computer screen needs cleaning
5
blank, fuzzy mind
No thoughts in mind head fuzzy
6
weird screen pattern
Notice unusual pattern in background to computer screen
7
sound stream wash over
Feel like I’m in a stream of sounds, washing over me
8
suites? etym.
Wonder about etymology of word ‘suites’
9
knot me, self?
Identify my ‘sense of self’ with a psychological ‘knot’
behind my forehead
10
quiet nice!
Pleasant moment of silence
11
lipread aisle man
Try to lipread conversation of man standing in the aisle
12
plastic - inventor?
Wonder about who invented plastic
13
sudden breath odd
Sharp intake of breath highlights the irregularity of my
breathing
14
shoulder old emo hurt?
Wonder whether tension in shoulder is an old emotional
wound
15
nice water, thanks
Gratefully accept a glass of water
16
tired, seeing nothing
Feel like I’ve exhausted my observational powers
17
child sound like bird
Think that child in front sounds like a bird when she talks
18
untie knot in mind
Return to psychological ‘knot,’ and try to untie it mentally
19
eyes dart look for interest
Feel my eyes darting around to find something of interest
in environment
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
14
20
eyes to window. free?
Head turns involuntarily towards window; wonder about
free will
21
time gone sad at time passing
A sudden sadness at 20 minutes of my life having
evaporated
22
blue light trance
Hypnotically drawn to blue light on cabin ceiling up
ahead
23
time waste
Condemn this whole project as a waste of time, and
unusable
24
words elusive
Finding that appropriate descriptive words are
increasingly elusive
25
emails! anxious, chest
A flutter of anxiety in chest about returning to work
emails
26
thoughts come from?
Wonder how thoughts are being formed, and by who
27
mind = ocean, looking for fish
Feel like I’m peering into the ocean, waiting for fish
(thoughts) to pop to the surface
28
want choc van ice
Craving for chocolate and vanilla ice cream
29
blinking = weird, nice
Think that blinking is an odd bodily activity, but pleasant
30
shins tingle
Tingling sensation in my shins
31
words like centipede chasing
Think that words on screen look like little centipedes
chasing each other
32
thick tongue want to poke
Tongue feels saturated an urge to poke it out
33
clearing, no thought
A clearing, without thoughts
34
feeling endurance, keep at it
A feeling of endurance, like I could stick at this
35
time quick, surprise
Surprised at the relative speed of the exercise
36
my bonnie
The tune ‘My bonnie’ darts into my mind
37
ossle ossle
Some of its lyrics morph into nonsense syllables (“ossle
ossle”)
38
sunshine field at home urge to run
Sudden urge to sprint across a field (behind my parents’
house) in the sunshine
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
15
39
nice fest, happy
A happy memory of being at a music festival
40
uniforms pretty
Admire ornate uniforms of cabin staff
41
bad election, annoyed
Bitterness at recent UK elections
42
red dungarees
Recall a pair of red corduroy dungarees I wore as a child
43
old and sad
Feel old, and a bit despondent
44
knot tight
Throbbing sensation in forehead the knot tightening?
45
eyes closing drowsy
Eyes close involuntarily; wave of drowsiness
46
time stopped
Feel that time hasn’t moved at all (despite clock changing)
47
crew at curtain clumsy magic
Flight attendant emerges suddenly from behind curtain,
like a clumsy magician
48
slow thoughts, all incomplete
Thoughts slowing down, and emerging half finished
49
knot again Nietz recur
A recurrence of the knot a sense of ‘eternal recurrence’
(Nietzsche)
50
Nietz like koan mystery
Think Nietzsche sounds like a Zen koan, and equally
mysterious
51
me a ball on hill
Feel like I’m a ball, bobbling haphazardly down a gentle,
bumpy, never-ending hill
52
vertigo, not just plane
A sudden vertigo, not related to being on a plane
53
silly task me too!
Find myself quite preposterous for doing this
54
no blame
Admitting stupidity seems to absolve me of responsibility
55
peace, happy
Feeling quite peaceful, happy even
56
I don’t matter – fine
My own insignificance strikes me as a relief
57
nearly done, free
Quite liberated at the thought of nearly finishing the hour
58
full? empty? strange
A strange sensation of being both fuller and emptier than
when the hour began
59
hopeful future mix of images
A sense of hopefulness about the future (arising from
relatively inconsequential images)
60
nice unusual hour
Grateful for spending the hour in this unusual way
Table 1: Results from the data collection hour.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
16
These entries were coded thematically, and grouped into categories and meta-categories. The themes,
categories and meta-categories are shown in table 2 below, together with the specific entries
associated with each theme.
Meta-category
Category
Theme
Entry
Time
Perception
Shifting time perceptions
3, 35
Time quickening
3, 35, 52
Time slowing
46
Strangeness of passage of time
42, 46
Usage
Time well spent
57, 60
Time as a resource
60
Existential
Life passing quickly
21, 39, 43, 52
reflection
Preciousness of time
21
Make the most of time
21, 39
Nostalgia
39, 43
Sadness at time passing
43
World
Attentiveness
Noticing new features
4, 6, 22
Surprise at surroundings
4, 47
Perception/appreciation of detail
6, 24
Attention ‘ensnared/captured’
20, 40
Lack of attentiveness
16
Epistemic hunger
19
Altered
Aesthetic appreciation
6, 22, 40
relationship
Perceptual shifts
7, 31, 47, 51
Immersion in world
7
Transience/impermanence
7
Curiosity about phenomena
8, 11, 12, 50
De-familiarisation (see old as new)
8, 12, 17, 31
Engagement
Yearning for activity
38, 59
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
17
Yearning to explore world
38, 39, 57, 59
Sense of possibility
39, 52, 57
Intentions for future activities
4, 34
Probing the world
12, 19
Receiving goods
15
People
Attention to people
11, 15, 17, 40, 47
Care/regard for others
11
Broader
Reflection on events
41
concerns
Worry/concern about life
25, 41
Subjectivity
Embodiment
Somatisation of emotions
25
Unfamiliarity with body
13, 14, 30, 32
Involuntary nature of bodily processes
13, 32
Getting to know body
30
Sensations in head
5, 9
Vivid memory
28, 38, 39, 42
Mental
Slipperiness of mind
37
strangeness
De-familiarisation of internal world
29, 30, 32
Mind as sea of potentials
27
Content emerging unbidden
26, 27, 36, 41, 58, 60
Sudden (involuntary?) shifts in attention
13, 20, 22, 44
Strangeness of internal world
26, 29
Clearing
Internal space
10, 33,
Mental quietude
5, 10, 33
Calmness
10, 33,
Lightness
56
Creativity
Creative imagination
31, 37, 59
Free-associating (creativity/play)
8, 17, 36, 37, 47, 50, 60
Positivity
Happiness
55, 56
Freedom
56
Delight/pleasure
28
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
18
Pleasant sensation
29, 30
Gratitude
15
Desire
28
Negativity
Mind drowsy/sluggish
45, 48
Mental fuzziness
5
Bodily discomfort
14, 18, 49
Boredom
16
Negative cognitions
25
Self/identity
Awareness
Witnessing consciousness
27, 44, 58
Self-consciousness
53, 55
Insignificance of self
55, 56
Aspects of
Emptiness of self
58
self
Plenitude of self
58
Probing self/identity
9, 14, 18, 20, 26, 42, 44,
49
Lack of volitional control
36, 45, 51
Creation of
Linked to mental tension (knot)
9, 18, 44, 49
identity
Self-as-repetition
49
Sense of personal history/journey
14, 39, 42, 51
Project
Concerns
Doubt about value of project
1, 23, 53, 54
Doubts about own ability
2, 16, 23, 24, 53, 55
Exercise feels contrived
2
Difficulties
Ineffability of experience
23, 24, 48, 50
Exercise feels unfamiliar
1
Strangeness of activity
46
Positives
Appreciating activity
34, 57
Enjoying activity
34, 35, 54, 57
Flow
54, 55
Table 2: Themes, categories and meta-categories from the data collection hour.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
19
Analysis and Discussion
The results offer a revealing insight into the phenomenology of boredom, showing this to potentially
be a rich and dynamic state, full of value and possibility. Of course, there are the obvious caveats,
such as the impossibility of generalising from this one intensive observation by one person to all other
people and contexts, as discussed further below. Nevertheless, as a sustained introspective exercise,
the results offer a unique case study of the kaleidoscopic nuances of boredom; it can be seen, in this
case at least, that boredom is not necessarily the dull, valueless state that it is commonly taken to be,
but can facilitate a fascinating array of experiences and insights. The hour yielded positive or
intriguing moments relating to two of the three main sources of value outlined above altered
perception of time, and exploration of self with an additional boon not previously identified,
namely, curiosity regarding the external world. There were some experiences pertaining to the third
main strand above, namely creativity, such as the generation of novel mental data through free
association. In general though, there did not appear to be many moments of creativity per se.
However, this is not especially surprising: in the literature, boredom is often presented as a prelude to
creativity, a germinal state in which new associations are perhaps being made below the surface of
awareness, which then burst forth after the period of boredom (Mann & Cadman, 2014). Thus, the
three main sources of value were: (a) altered time perception; (b) environmental curiosity; and (c)
exploration of self. These shall be outlined below.
However, before discussing the phenomenology of boredom in this instance, it is worth re-
iterating one key point: I truly was bored! That is, as I began to engage with the exercise (i.e., at the
beginning of the hour), I was in the midst of an on-going state that I would have no hesitation in
describing as ‘boredom.’ Or more specifically, I was experiencing what could be called ‘situational’
(Toohey, 2011) or ‘state’ boredom (Fahlman et al., 2013), characterised by lack of interest in my
current environment, comprising elements like restlessness combined with tiredness, disengagement,
and inattentiveness, all of which are factors of Fahlman et al.’s (2013) Multidimensional State
Boredom Scale. However, following the advice of Brodsky (1997), rather than seeking to escape or
distract myself from the boredom as I and others might normally do I tried to enter deep into it, to
really probe and explore it. In doing so, the experience started to change; I might still have plausibly
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
20
and legitimately described the hour as ‘boring,’ yet at the same time it began to become vibrant and
interesting, full of mystery and depth. Whether it then still truly ‘counts’ as boredom is a fascinating
question, and one which highlights the limitations of language in capturing the ineffable nuances of
experience (Brockmeier, 2002). Indeed, this question actually highlights the shape-shifting nature of
emotional and experiential categories, showing that if an experience such as boredom is fully
embraced, it may no longer be boring per se. It is this same rationale that underpins mindfulness-
based interventions, which are based on the premise that if dysphoric states like anxiety are engaged
with in a particular spirit (e.g., open, curious, kind, and non-judgmental), then these states become
somehow transmuted into less noxious or threatening versions, and perhaps even dissipate entirely
(Kabat-Zinn, 2003).
The first emergent meta-theme was altered time perception. A slowing or lengthening of
subjective time is one of archetypal features of boredom, identified theoretically by philosophers such
as Heidegger (1938), and corroborated in empirical experiments (e.g., Watt, 1991). However, in the
current study, there was a strange sense of time both slowing and quickening: at points (e.g., min. 46)
time felt almost static, yet at other moments (e.g., mins. 3, 35, & 52) I was surprised by the swiftness
of the preceding minute, with a sensation of time slipping away through my fingers. Perhaps such
juxtapositions are not so unfamiliar; as Roeckelein (2008) elucidates, the elusive, paradoxical nature
of time has been recognised at least as far back as the Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea (circa 490-430
B.C.). It has been argued that eventful (i.e., interesting) experiences seem to pass quickly at the time,
but seem lengthy in retrospect (due to the formation of substantive and varied memories), while
uneventful (i.e., boring) experiences pass slowly, but seem short afterwards (due to a lack of discrete
memorable components) (Hammond, 2012). However, in the current study, sensations of time
quickening and slowing appeared to alternate and even co-exist; indeed, an overriding feeling was
simply of the strangeness of time, once observed up close.
Added to this strangeness was a strong, melancholic awareness of time as a precious resource
that was fast depleting, as capture in minute 21. This in turn evoked a range of emotions, from
nostalgia for time gone by, to an urgent wish to ‘make the most’ of future time. For instance, in
minute 42, I recalled a pair of red trousers I used to wear as a child (which are vivid to me still, as
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
21
there is a photo of me wearing them, in which I just look completely happy); this memory led
inexorably, in the next minute, to a sense of sadness at growing old. However, this melancholy train
of thought then seemed to dissipate, and by the closing of the hour (e.g., minute 59), I was feeling
rather more hopeful about life, and about the time that still lies ahead of me. Arguably these varied
reflections corroborate Heidegger’s point about the value of boredom as an embodied experience of
time itself, generating vital existential insights, such as the need to act and seize the day before it
passes (Slaby, 2010).
The second meta-theme was curiosity regarding my surroundings, both proximally (i.e., the
aircraft cabin) and more distally (the world ‘generally’). Usually, lack of interest in one’s environment
is a defining feature of boredom as conventionally understood (Fisherl, 1993). Indeed, I myself felt
disengaged and inattentive at the beginning of the introspective hour (having deliberately induced
boredom). However, as the hour proceeded, I noticed an unusual phenomenon. I had previously
judged my surroundings as devoid of interest, hence boring. Normally, this would be the cue to seek
alternative surroundings, or at least to distract myself. By removing these options though, I began to
find value in stimuli that I had previously judged as lacking. I found myself noticing new features of
my environment I had previously overlooked, and indeed appreciating these aesthetically (mins. 4, 6,
22, 40); moreover, stimuli I had become habituated to became ‘de-familiarised,’ i.e., seeming new and
strange. For instance, I became mesmerised at one point (minute 40) by the beautifully ornate patterns
on the uniforms of the cabin crew, which is certainly not something I have ever paused to appreciate
or even notice previously. These experiences reflect a passage in Pirsig (1974), in which he describes
people in the prairies noticing subtle phenomena that might be overlooked by people caught up in the
sensory overload of the city, quiet moments of beauty that ‘can be noticed because other things are
absent’ (p.24). In cognitive/epistemic terms, attention is often drawn to phenomena that are novel,
salient, or urgent (Posner & Petersen, 1990). Phenomena that lack these qualities are thus often judged
as lacking interest. But, if attention is compelled to stay with such phenomena, it is as if the mind
finds ways to make these novel or salient. An example of this is the ‘mindfulness of breathing,’ a
meditation practice focusing on the breath. Usually, one might take one’s breathing for granted, or see
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
22
it as lacking interest. However, practitioners report that, once engaged with, the breath can become a
source of great fascination, possessing subtle depths and nuances (Kapleau, 1965).
This last point brings us to our final meta-theme, exploration of the self (comprising both
subjectivity and self/identity in the results table). Here we return to the idea that boredom brings us
face-to-face with ourselves. As Stern (1988, p.5) puts it, boredom is a ‘void [that] becomes a vital
capability, [one that] confronts the question of “Who am I?”.’ Indeed, in Zen, the rigours of wall
sitting meditation are designed to encourage/compel practitioners to ‘push through’ boredom and to
interrogate their identity (Watts, 1957). Essentially, the aim of Zen meditation is for people to realise
that their ‘ego’ (their conventional identity) is an ‘illusion(an on-going project of construction), and
instead to experience the liberation of not ‘having’ an ego per se (Kapleau, 1965). During my
introspection, I cannot claim to have had any such insights. However, I did certainly journey ‘into
myself, exploring unfamiliar aspects of my being, and becoming attentive to my mental dynamics.
For instance, there was a recurrent observation of a sensation of a ‘knot’ behind my forehead (minutes
9, 18, 44 and 49). This observation occurred in conjunction with a feeling that my sense of identity
was somehow bound up with this sensation, as if, were the sensation to dissipate, so might my sense
of self.
Similarly, I noticed the way that thoughts appeared to emerge unbidden (i.e., without me
volitionally ‘thinking’ them), as in minute 26. While such observations are common currency in
Buddhist theory indeed, the title of a prominent book on Buddhism and psychotherapy is Thoughts
without a Thinker (Epstein, 2004) it was interesting to notice this for myself. However, this does
raise the question as to whether my prior reading of Buddhism influenced my interpretation of minute
26 i.e., was I primed to feel as if thoughts were arising unbidden due to my exposure to a philosophy
that explicitly conceptualises thoughts thus?. More generally, I was intrigued by how slippery, elusive
and strange the mind was, a fleeting dance of vague ephemera; not for nothing did William James
(1890) famously refer to consciousness as a ‘stream. Indeed, I was particularly captivated by a meta-
image that occurred to me in minute 27 i.e., an image about the nature of mind itself, and about the
nature of the introspective activity I was engaged in. In particular, I felt that the process was much
like peering into an ocean, and waiting for fish (i.e., thoughts) to appear. In retrospect, this image does
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
23
indeed capture my feelings about the exercise, and the mind generally, quite effectively. I also found
that my sphere of subjectivity appeared to widen, encompassing more phenomenological ‘terrain.’ For
instance, I often tend to live ‘in my head,’ i.e., wrapped up in discursive thoughts, and am rather
inattentive to my embodied experience. However, here I enjoyed the sensation of exploring the
subjectivity of my body (e.g., minutes 29, 30 and 32), corroborating studies that have linked enhanced
body awareness to wellbeing (Brani et al., 2014). That said, it wasn’t an unmitigated enjoyment; both
minutes 29 and 32 felt ‘weird,’ in that I was acutely aware of the sheer fact of my physical being,
which evoked subsequent parallels in my mind with the sensation of ‘nausea’ described by Sartre
(1938).
So, in all, I encountered a range of absorbing experiences during the hour. As I will suggest
below, such empirical data have the potential to facilitate a re-appraisal of boredom, showing that it is
not necessarily the dysphoric state it is usually conceived as being, but has the potential to also be of
some psychological value. Before making this claim, however, I must introduce the inevitable caveat
regarding the generalisability of the data. Firstly, the design of the study, and in particular the decision
to elicit an observation every 60 seconds, inevitably influenced the nature of the data collected. In
practice, this period of time actually felt very brief, and therefore the prompts were experienced as
somewhat intrusive. Indeed, two of my first three observations (minutes 2 and 3) related specifically
to the pressure I felt relating to the need to note down observations so frequently. Moreover, this
design structure arguably impacted on the nature of the observations, in a number of ways. Firstly,
one might argue that the rapidity of the observation sequence impeded the chance for boredom to
truly ‘set in.’ There was roughly only 50 seconds between completing my note for a given minute and
being prompted for my note for the subsequent minute. Moreover, given that I knew in advance how
soon my next observation would be prompted, in the seconds leading up to the prompt I often found
myself already composing the notes I would write when prompted. This latter point was exacerbated
by my knowledge that I would seek to report and publish my observations, which perhaps created a
certain pressure to make them interesting or noteworthy. As such, it could be said that I was actually
task-focused for much of the time, rather than actually allowing myself to be bored. Given these
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
24
points, I have some suggestions below for how future research in this area might remedy these
limitations.
A second point regarding the generalisability of the data is the fact that this is just one
person’s experience of boredom on one occasion. Reflexivity demands that I acknowledge the data as
necessarily particular, determined by my own history and characteristics. To this extent, I have tried
to give some brief indications of how my personal history may have shaped the ‘filter of salience’
through which the data were sieved (Schreiber, 2001, p.60), such as my familiarity with meditation
(discussed further below), and my prior familiarity with Buddhist theory (mentioned above).
However, I am wary about focusing overly on my personal characteristics. This study is a
phenomenology of boredom, not of me, and there is a risk that excessive reflexivity turns into a form
of epistemological narcissism, in which researchers are more concerned with accounting for
themselves than their data (Cutcliffe, 2003). Moreover, there are limits to reflexivity: even the
lengthiest autobiographies fail to capture the near-infinity of stories and experiences that constitute a
person. Moreover, as psychoanalytic theory has recognised, there is so much about the person that is
hidden to themselves (Luft, 1969); thus, the idea that I can ever fully ‘account for’ myself, let alone
within the confines of a short academic paper, is something of an impossibility. In any case, the study
is not about ‘proving’ that boredom can be a valuable experience for everybody all of the time. No
doubt there are many people who experience severe boredom, such as isolated older adults (Gabriel &
Bowling, 2004), and need genuine assistance to find engaging activities and relationships to alleviate
its burden. Rather, this is simply a case study to suggest that boredom has the potential at least to not
be an entirely negative and unfulfilling state of mind.
That being said, it could also be argued that my ‘ability’ to engage with boredom, and to find
interest in it, was due to my experience as a practising meditator, as well as to the possibility that I
was motivated to make the experience interesting. Indeed, it could even be suggested that, during the
activity, I was actually meditating (i.e., trying to observe my internal world with non-judgemental
curiosity), rather than being bored. However, this latter reflection is precisely the point of this paper,
with its aim of ‘reappraising’ boredom. As Biceaga (2006) argues, perhaps meditation is boredom,
and boredom is meditation? The only difference between the two then is that boredom is
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
25
conventionally appraised as negative (and hence people tend to denigrate or devalue it), whereas
meditation is usually regarded as a worthwhile and beneficial mental activity (Kabat-Zinn, 2003).
Consequently, if people were able to regard their boredom as a meditative experience, it may no
longer be appraised as negative; indeed, it may no longer even be boring as I found during the hour,
the boredom became interesting!
These kinds of reappraisals have relevance for fields such as positive psychology (PP), which
are concerned with wellbeing and flourishing (Lomas et al., 2014). PP initially appeared to make a
distinction between mental states that were ‘positive’ (e.g., optimism) and those that were ‘negative’
(e.g., anxiety). It furthermore often implied that the former were necessarily good, and should be
sought, whereas the latter were intrinsically bad, and should be eschewed. However, in recent years, a
‘second wave’ of the field has been emerging (Held, 2004; Wong, 2011; Lomas & Ivtzan, 2015), in
which it is recognised that: (a) ostensibly positive states can be detrimental to wellbeing in certain
circumstances, e.g., ‘excessive optimism’ is linked to health risk behaviours (Weinstein, 1987); (b)
apparently negative states can sometimes be conducive to flourishing, e.g., anxiety can alert us to
potential threats, and encourage pro-active coping (Norem, 2001); and, (c) many desirable states (e.g.,
love) are actually ‘co-valenced,’ involving a complex dialectical blend of light and dark elements
(Lazarus, 2003). In this context, perhaps the current paper can contribute towards a re-appraisal of
boredom, challenging the conventional view that it is necessarily ‘negative’ and devoid of value, and
suggesting that it has the potential, if engaged with, to be a positive and rewarding experience.
However, this potential needs further corroboration through future research, given the
limitations of the current study, as outlined above. Based on these limitations, I would like to offer
various recommendations for any such research into this topic. Firstly, in terms of generalisability, it
will be helpful to recruit a broad range of participants, of varying age, gender, ethnicity, and
educational level. Efforts could also be made to compare people with and without meditation
experience, to explore the intriguing notion that meditators may have developed a particular ability or
capacity to appreciate boredom. Secondly, in terms of the session itself, a longer time period than 1
hour would ideally be allocated to allow boredom to truly manifest; indeed, researchers might try
experimenting with different durations to compare their impact (e.g., 2 hours versus 1 whole day).
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
26
Thirdly, and similarly, it would be prudent to space the observation prompts further apart than 60
seconds. As discussed above, in practice, this interval felt too short, and indeed intrusive, making the
hour too ‘task-oriented.’ Gaps of 5 or even 10 minutes would be preferable in this regard. Moreover,
researchers might give thought to spacing these intervals with a degree of randomness, e.g., giving the
first prompt after 10 minutes, the second after 6 minutes, the third after 14 minutes, the fourth after 3
minutes, and so on. This would prevent participants anticipating or waiting for a prompt (e.g., trying
to guess when 5 minutes had lapsed, and preparing their observation in advance), as I did here.
Fourth, to alleviate task demands, it would be better for participants to be able to verbally report their
observations (via audio-recorder) rather than having to write these down.
Finally, in terms of recruiting participants, it may be worth developing a protocol where the
period of boredom appears to participants as merely accidental. This would help prevent participants
realising that it was a study about boredom, a realisation which would, (a) reduce the likelihood of
their participation in the first place, and (b) influence their responses. For instance, participants could
ostensibly be recruited to an experiment which seems appealing and interesting, such as a flight
simulation. Then, on arrival to the experiment, participants could simply be asked to sit alone in a
waiting room, with no distractions. Once there, they might be warned that there might be a ‘bit of a
wait, of up to two hours, say, before the experiment started. The researchers might then contrive
some reason to intermittently check on the participants and enquire what they are thinking about.
Obviously, this is just one suggestion, but arguably something akin to this might be needed to
generate an ecologically valid situation of genuine boredom. If this is managed, then we shall get a
better idea of whether boredom can indeed be a useful and valuable state, as this current paper has
suggested.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
27
References
Aquinas, St. T. (1273/1981). Summa Theologia (Fathers of the English Dominican Province, Trans.).
Westminster, MD: Christian Classics.
Bargdill, R. W. (2000). The study of life boredom. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 31(2),
188-219.
Bell, G. (2011). The value of boredom. Paper presented at the TEDxSydney Conference.
Biceaga, V. (2006). Temporality and boredom. Continental philosophy review, 39(2), 135-153.
Blaszczynski, A., McConaghy, N., & Frankova, A. (1990). Boredom proneness in pathological
gambling. Psychological Reports, 67(1), 35-42.
Brani, O., Hefferon, K., Lomas, T., Ivtzan, I., & Painter, J. (2014). The impact of body awareness on
subjective wellbeing: The role of mindfulness. International Journal of Body Psychotherapy,
13(1), 94-107.
Brockmeier, J. (2002). Ineffable experience. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9(9-10), 79-95.
Brodsky, J. (1997). On Grief and Reason: Essays. London: Macmillan.
Csikszentmihalyi, M., & Larson, R. (1987). Validity and reliability of the experience-sampling
method. The Journal of nervous and mental disease, 175(9), 526-536.
Cutcliffe, J. R. (2003). Reconsidering reflexivity: Introducing the case for intellectual
entrepreneurship. Qualitative Health Research, 13(1), 136-148.
Denzin, N. K. (2013). Interpretive autoethnography. London: Sage Publications.
Dickens, C. (1853). Bleak House. London: Bradbury and Evans.
Epstein, M. (2004). Thoughts Without a Thinker: Psychotherapy from a Buddhist Perspective. New
York: Basic Books.
Fahlman, S. A., Mercer-Lynn, K. B., Flora, D. B., & Eastwood, J. D. (2013). Development and
validation of the multidimensional state boredom scale. Assessment, 20(1), 68-85.
Farmer, R., & Sundberg, N. D. (1986). Boredom proneness: The development and correlates of a new
scale. Journal of Personality Assessment, 50(1), 4-17.
Fisherl, C. D. (1993). Boredom at work: A neglected concept. Human Relations, 46(3), 395-417.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
28
Flaubert, G. (1856/2009). Madame Bovary (R. N. MacKenzie, Trans.). London: Hackett Publishing.
Frevert, U. (2011). Emotions in History: Lost and Found. Paris: Central European University Press.
Gabriel, Z., & Bowling, A. (2004). Quality of life in old age from the perspectives of older people. In
A. Walker & C. H. Hennessey (Eds.), Growing older: Quality of life in old age (pp. 14-34).
Maidenhead: McGraw Hill.
Gasper, K., & Middlewood, B. L. (2014). Approaching novel thoughts: Understanding why elation
and boredom promote associative thought more than distress and relaxation. Journal of
Experimental Social Psychology, 52, 50-57.
Gergen, K. J. (1985). The social constructionist movement in modern psychology. American
Psychologist, 40(3), 266-275.
Hammond, C. (2012). Time Warped: Unlocking the Mysteries of Time Perception. London:
Canongate Books.
Hecht, J. M. (2013). Stay: A history of suicide and the philosophies against it. Bostons: Yale
University Press.
Heidegger, M. (1938/2001). The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude:
Indiana University Press.
Held, B. S. (2004). The negative side of positive psychology. Journal of Humanistic Psychology,
44(1), 9-46.
Husserl, E. (1931/1999). Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology (D. Cairns,
Trans.). London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
James, W. (1890/1981). The Principles of Psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kabat-Zinn, J. (2003). Mindfulness-based interventions in context: Past, present, and future. Clinical
Psychology: Science and Practice, 10(2), 144-156.
Kapleau, R. P. (1965). The Three Pillars of Zen. New York: Anchor.
Kass, S., Vodanovich, S., & Callender, A. (2001). State-trait boredom: Relationship to absenteeism,
tenure, and job satisfaction. Journal of Business and Psychology, 16(2), 317-327.
Kets de Vries, M. F. (2014). Doing nothing and nothing to do: The hidden value of empty time and
boredom. INSEAD: Faculty and Research Working Paper.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
29
Kierkegaard, S. (1843/1959). Either/Or (D. F. Swenson & L. M. Swenson, Trans.). New York:
Anchor Books.
Klapp, O. (1986). Overload and Boredom: Essays on the Quality of Life in the Information Society.
New York: Greenwood Place.
Lazarus, R. S. (2003). Does the positive psychology movement have legs? Psychological Inquiry,
14(2), 93-109.
Leong, F. T., & Schneller, G. R. (1993). Boredom proneness: Temperamental and cognitive
components. Personality and Individual Differences, 14(1), 233-239.
LePera, N. (2011). Relationships between boredom proneness, mindfulness, anxiety, depression, and
substance use. The New School Psychology Bulletin, 8(2), 15-25.
Lomas, T., Hefferon, K., & Ivtzan, I. (2014). Applied Positive Psychology: Integrated Positive
Practice. London: Sage.
Lomas, T., & Ivtzan, I. (2015). Second wave positive psychology: Exploring the positive-negative
dialectics of wellbeing. Journal of Happiness Studies. doi: 10.1007/s10902-015-9668-y
Luft, J. (1969). Of Human Interactions: The Johari Model. Palo Alto, CA: Mayfield.
Maier, J. R. (1997). Gilgamesh: A Reader. London: Bolchazy-Carducci Publishers.
Mann, S., & Cadman, R. (2014). Does being bored make us more creative? Creativity Research
Journal, 26(2), 165-173.
Morrison, S. L., & Gomez, R. (2014). Pushback: Expressions of resistance to the “evertime” of
constant online connectivity. First Monday, 19(8).
Nietzsche, F. (1882/1974). The Gay Science: With a Prelude in Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs
(W. Kaufman, Trans.). New York: Vintage Books.
Norem, J. K. (2001). The Positive Power of Negative Thinking. New York: Basic Books.
Osho. (2015). The Great Zen Master Ta Hui: Reflections on the Transformation of an Intellectual to
Enlightenment. New York: Osho Media International.
Palmer, M., Larkin, M., de Visser, R., & Fadden, G. (2010). Developing an interpretative
phenomenological approach to focus group data. Qualitative Research in Psychology, 7(2),
99-121.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
30
Pezeu-Massabuau, J. (2013). A Philosophy of Discomfort. London: Reaktion Books.
Pirsig, R. M. (1974). Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance. New York: Vintage.
Posner, M. I., & Petersen, S. E. (1990). The attention system of the human brain. Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 13(1), 25-42.
Raichle, M. E., MacLeod, A. M., Snyder, A. Z., Powers, W. J., Gusnard, D. A., & Shulman, G. L.
(2001). A default mode of brain function. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
98(2), 676-682.
Roeckelein, J. E. (2008). History of conceptions and accounts of time and early time perception
research. In S. Grondin (Ed.), Psychology of time (pp. 1-50). Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Sartre, J.-P. (1938/1964). Nausea (L. Alexander, Trans.). New York: New Directions.
Schreiber, R. S. (2001). The “how to” of grounded theory: Avoiding the pitfalls. In R. S. Schreiber &
P. N. Stern (Eds.), Using grounded theory in nursing (pp. 55-83). New York: Springer Publishing.
Senauke, H. A. (2006). A long and winding road: Soto Zen training in America. Teaching Theology &
Religion, 9(2), 127-132.
Shapiro, S. L., Astin, J. A., Bishop, S. R., & Cordova, M. (2005). Mindfulness-based stress reduction
for health care professionals: Results from a randomized trial. International Journal of Stress
Management, 12(2), 164-176.
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Is moral phenomenology unified? Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences, 7(1), 85-97.
Skinner, B. F. (1938). The Behavior of Organisms: An Experimental Analysis. Oxford: Appleton-
Century.
Slaby, J. (2010). The other side of existence: Heidegger on boredom. In S. Flach, D. Margulies & J.
Söffner (Eds.), Habitus in Habitat II: Other Sides of Cognition. Bern: Peter Lang (pp. 101-
120).
Smith, J. A. (1996). Beyond the divide between cognition and discourse: Using interpretative
phenomenological analysis in health psychology. Psychology and Health, 11(2), 261-271.
Stern, E. M. (1988). An awakening and complexity. The Psychotherapy Patient, 3(3-4), 5-16.
Svendsen, L. (2005). A Philosophy of Boredom. London: Reaktion books.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
31
Szasz, T. S. (2002). Fatal Freedom: The Ethics and Politics of Suicide. New York: Syracuse
University Press.
Takeuchi, H., Taki, Y., Hashizume, H., Sassa, Y., Nagase, T., Nouchi, R., & Kawashima, R. (2012).
The association between resting functional connectivity and creativity. Cerebral Cortex,
22(12), 2921-2929.
Toohey, P. (1988). Some ancient notions of boredom. Illinois Classical Studies, 13(1), 151-164.
Toohey, P. (2011). Boredom: A Lively History. Boston: Yale University Press.
Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal
of Consciousness Studies, 3(4), 330-349.
Varela, F. J., & Shear, J. (Eds.). (1999). The View from Within: First-Person Approaches to the Study
of Consciousness. Thorverton, UK: Imprint Academic.
Vodanovich, S. J., Wallace, J. C., & Kass, S. J. (2005). A confirmatory approach to the factor
structure of the boredom proneness scale: Evidence for a two-factor short fsorm. Journal of
Personality Assessment, 85(3), 295-303.
Vogel-Walcutt, J. J., Fiorella, L., Carper, T., & Schatz, S. (2012). The definition, assessment, and
mitigation of state boredom within educational settings: A comprehensive review.
Educational Psychology Review, 24(1), 89-111.
Watt, J., & Hargis, M. (2010). Boredom proneness: Its relationship with subjective underemployment,
perceived organizational support, and job performance. Journal of Business and Psychology,
25(1), 163-174.
Watt, J. D. (1991). Effect of boredom proneness on time perception. Psychological Reports, 69(1),
323-327.
Watt, J. D., & Vodanovich, S. J. (1992). Relationship between boredom proneness and impulsivity.
Psychological Reports, 70(3), 688-690.
Watts, A. W. (1957). The Way of Zen. London: Penguin Books.
Weinstein, N. (1987). Unrealistic optimism about susceptibility to health problems: Conclusions from
a community-wide sample. Journal of Behavioral Medicine, 10(5), 481-500.
Running head: A MEDITATION ON BOREDOM
32
Wong, P. T. P. (2011). Positive psychology 2.0: Towards a balanced interactive model of the good
life. Canadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 52(2), 69-81.
Zindel, V., Segal, J., Williams, M. G., & Teasdale, J. D. (2002). Mindfulness-Based Cognitive
Therapy for Depression: A New Approach to Preventing Relapse. New York: Guilford.
... For example, 'weariness' has been defined as "the state of being bored with something because you have experienced too much of it" (Cambridge Dictionary, n.d). Also, 'tedium vitae' (a synonym for ToL found in our systematic review) has been described as a form of existential boredom (Lomas, 2017). Lastly, in the qualitative study into CL, one constituent of the phenomenon -'multidimensional tiredness'includes experiences of being bored with life (van Wijngaarden et al., 2015). ...
... A similar rate has been found in adolescents (Bould et al., 2013; but see Lamers et al., 2013). With regard to boredom, some authors state that existential boredom might currently be (mis)classified as depression (Barnett, 2012;Lomas, 2017). Relatedly, (habitual) boredom over time might develop into depression (Bargdill, 2014), or cooccur with it (Martin et al., 2006). ...
Article
A phenomenon referred to as ‘tiredness of life’ or ‘weariness of life’ appears in current discussions on the legitimacy of euthanasia for relatively healthy older adults as well as in research on suicidality more broadly. However, a consensus conceptualization of the phenomenon is lacking. In the current paper, we offer such a conceptualization by reviewing and integrating knowledge from terminology, available descriptions, and first qualitative findings. Boredom with life, aversion towards life, meaninglessness, and fatigue are identified as central components of the phenomenon. Per component, we describe how the component was identified, our definition of the component and its foundation in descriptions in the literature, and empirical studies on how the component relates to euthanasia requests and suicidality. Moreover, hypotheses on the structure of the phenomenon are outlined, such as on interactions among and the importance of the different components.
... (1889/1998, p. 6), reflects not a narrow criticism of the hedonistic, utilitarian worldview with which PP agrees but rather a much deeper observation regarding slave morality, that is, people's need for absolute truth that minimizes suffering by providing a spiritual shelter in the form of conventional norms they see as eternal and universal (the pursuit of happiness) and therefore as something that must guide them through practical conduct to achieve it (e.g., embracing the dark side). Lomas (2017) used Nietzsche as a theoretical basis that can "contribute towards a re-appraisal of boredom, challenging the conventional view that it is necessarily 'negative' and devoid of value, and suggesting that it has the potential, if engaged with, to be a positive and rewarding experience" (p. 17). ...
Article
Full-text available
This article provides a constructive critique of positive psychology, focusing on its second wave, which attempts to offer a more developed position than the first but still lacks a philosophical foundation anchored in an understanding of the inherent tensions between dialectical processes of authentic self-development and meaningful happiness or flourishing. Much criticism has been leveled against the so-called “tyranny of positive thinking,” and many agree that one of positive psychology’s most significant flaws is its consistent refusal to participate in any deep philosophical discussion. I argue that both the criticism of positive psychology and the approach it criticizes lack in-depth dialogue regarding human nature, freedom, and purpose in modern thought. Although the second wave tends to rely on Hegel’s dialectical worldview, I know of no reference in the positive psychology literature, even in works by its critics, to the fact that, from Hegel’s perspective, the ideal of happiness should be rejected. The lack of attention to the significance of this rejection, which profoundly influenced perceptions of individualism among nineteenth-century thinkers and significantly impacted the field of humanistic psychology in the twentieth century, points to significant failures that must be addressed if positive psychology is to preserve its relevance.
... A number of positive qualities of boredom have been unearthed in recent years (for a review, see Elpidorou, 2014). Researchers found that boredom may inspire (Hunter et al., 2016), elevate prosocial tendencies (Van Tilburg & Igou, 2017b), and provoke self-reflection (Lomas, 2017). It serves a regulatory function by informing people that they are not optimally engaged (Danckert et al., 2018;Eastwood & Gorelik, 2019;Tam et al., 2021b), and motivates them to search for more meaningful (Van Tilburg et al., 2013;Van Tilburg & Igou, 2017b) and novel experiences (Bench & Lench, 2019). ...
Article
Full-text available
Boredom is a ubiquitous emotion that has strong behavioral and mental health impacts. Research suggests that how people experience and regulate emotions is influenced by their beliefs about them. What lay beliefs about boredom do people have? The present research sought to answer this question using a mixed-methods approach. In Study 1, we conducted a series of individual and focus-group interviews (N = 29) to explore how people evaluate boredom. In Study 2, we developed and validated a 15-item self-report measure, the Boredom Beliefs Scale (BBS), in Hong Kong Chinese (N = 231) and American (N = 498) samples. In Study 3, we examined the scale’s convergent, discriminant, and incremental validity in a British sample (N = 296). We identified three lay boredom beliefs—the extent to which people recognize the functions of boredom (boredom functionality), affectively dislike this emotion (boredom dislike), and believe its experience to be normal (boredom normalcy). The three-factor BBS was demonstrated to be a reliable and valid scale that showed meaningful relationships with measures of emotion beliefs, boredom, and well-being. Our findings enrich the current literature by introducing a new construct, boredom belief, which has both theoretical and applied significance.
... Lin and Westgate, 2022), it motivates some animals to experiment with new sources of food, play with new materials, change territories, learn new skills -"those who had to fight boredom ended up knowing more about their environment and having more skills than those who were satisfied with simple tasks" (Davies and Fortney, 2012, p. 139), therefore, it has promoted self-regulation processes, which might increase adaptability to a changing environment (Elpidorou, 2017a). In other words, "boredom 'punishes' behavior lacking in meaning or optimal attentional engagement, encouraging people to disengage from those behaviors in the present, and making such behavior less likely in the future" (Lin and Westgate, 2022, p. 13); (3) it has deepened one's perception (Lomas, 2017;Raposa, 1999) and enabled quick switches of attention between events, increasing the chances for locating both the sources of nourishment and danger (Mann, 2016); (4) it has been a mild form of disgust (Miller, 1997) and analogically "[i]f disgust protects humans from infection, boredom may protect them from 'infectious' social situations: those that are confined, predictable, too samey for one's sanity" (Toohey, 2011, p. 17; see more in Finkielsztein, 2016). ...
Article
Full-text available
This article aims at providing concise but thorough presentation of the state of art in the emerging field of boredom studies evidencing the significance of boredom. The premise of the significance of boredom is to be expounded by documenting its widespread, social consequences, functions and positive outcomes. Boredom has been found prevalent irrespectively of age, gender, culture or social class. It affects all main spheres of human life-work, leisure, education, romantic relationships, and even religious life. It has also been evidenced that boredom has many significant consequences. It has been associated with, among others, risk-taking behaviours, overeating, impulse shopping, or (self-)destructive and violent behaviours. Yet, boredom may serve numerous significant functions as well. As an emotion, it is important for cognition, motivation and communication and has had evolutionary meaning for human beings. In society nowadays, it serves as a defensive mechanism against overload of stimuli, but somehow to the contrary is also found to be a basic mechanism animating current consumerism. Boredom is also conceived to be a catalyst for reflection, self-cognition, creativity, and as a consequence a rudimentary element of culture production and its advances.
... The perception of meaninglessness or task unimportance is an independent determinant of state boredom (Fahlman et al., 2009;Anusic et al., 2016;Van Tilburg and Igou, 2017b;Chan et al., 2018;Westgate and Wilson, 2018). State boredom may affect individual preference and behavior through stimulation seeking (Van Tilburg and Igou, 2012), awakening curiosity about the environment (Lomas, 2017), or reflecting the self-regulation function of state boredom (Miao and Xie, 2019). Individuals with a high-level state of boredom have been associated with increased hostility (Van Tilburg and Igou, 2012), riskier decisions (Matthies et al., 2012), and poor sustained attention (Westgate, 2020). ...
Article
Full-text available
Gender plays an important role in various aspects of second language acquisition, including lexicon learning. Many studies have suggested that compared to males, females are less likely to experience boredom, one of the frequently experienced deactivating negative emotions that may impair language learning. However, the contribution of boredom to gender-related differences in lexicon learning remains unclear. To address this question, here we conducted two experiments with a large sample of over 1,000 college students to explore the relationships between gender differences in boredom and lexicon learning. In Experiment 1, a cohort of 527 participants (238 males) completed the trait and state boredom scales as well as a novel lexicon learning task without awareness of the testing process. In Experiment 2, an independent cohort of 506 participants (228 males) completed the same novel lexicon learning task with prior knowledge of the testing procedure. Results from both experiments consistently showed significant differences between female and male participants in the rate of forgetting words and the state boredom scores, with female participants performing better than male participants. Furthermore, differences in state boredom scores partially explained differences in the rate of forgetting words between female and male participants. These findings demonstrate a novel contribution of state boredom to gender differences in lexicon learning, which provides new insights into better language-learning ability in females.
Article
Full-text available
In an era where entertainment is effortlessly at our fingertips, one would assume that people are less bored than ever. Yet, reports of boredom are higher now than compared to the past. This rising trend is concerning because chronic boredom can undermine well-being, learning, and behaviour. Understanding why this is happening is crucial to prevent further negative impacts. In this Perspective, we explore one possible reason—digital media use makes people more bored. We propose that digital media increases boredom through dividing attention, elevating desired level of engagement, reducing sense of meaning, heightening opportunity costs, and serving as an ineffective boredom coping strategy.
Article
Not all of the stimuli that we encounter are unequivocal; some of them may be ambiguous. In a series of two experiments, we investigated how people perceive and assess the emotionality of the words ambiguous on three emotional spaces: valence (dimensions of positivity and negativity), origin (automaticity and reflectiveness), and activation (arousal and subjective significance). Using two types of measurement - behavioural and webcam-based eye tracking - we compared words of moderate and high ambiguity on each of those spaces with control (uniequivocal) words. The behavioural measurements indicated that reaction times were significantly longer for the control words than for all the ambiguous words; the emotionality of words of ambiguous valence and origin was rated as significantly lower than the control words and words of ambiguous activation. The eye-tracking measurements indicated that words of ambiguous valence and origin caused significantly more and longer eye fixations than control words and words of ambiguous activation. The results showed the visible distinctiveness of the ambiguous words compared with the control words; they also showed differences between words of various ambiguities, verifying the proposed new model for the emotional ambiguity and presenting the behavioral and eye tracking correlates for each of the three ambiguities.
Chapter
Applying digital technologies to preserve cultural heritage is hardly a new concept. In 1990s, with the launch of the Memory of the World project by UNESCO, scholars all over the world began to pay attention to the digital protection of cultural heritage, both tangible and intangible [1]. Through the Memory of the World research network that could be forged globally, UNESCO aims for concerted efforts in mediating, safeguarding, and even promoting cultural heritage by new means of information communicating technologies [2]. Nonetheless the efforts, although commendable, have been more focused on the digital documentation instead of promotion of cultural heritage. Concurrently, as China attaches great importance to “entrepreneurship and entrepreneurship” education, college students’ innovation and entrepreneurship education has become an important field of research in China. This study defines intangible cultural heritage, explains digitization of intangible cultural heritage, points out the limitations of the efforts on digital preservation, overviews entrepreneurship education for college students in China, and proposes a pedagogical model targeted at new media art in higher education which seeks to propagate the efforts to digitally preserve and promote intangible cultural heritage under the values of innovation and entrepreneurship.
Chapter
Much of the research on digital wellbeing (DWB) in HCI focuses on increasing happiness, reducing distraction, or achieving goals. Distinct from this is a conceptualization of DWB sensitive to another commonly observed type of interaction with technology: the interstitial, the mundane, or the “meaningless.” We examine DWB with a mixed methods approach – a series of three separate but related Experience Sampling Method studies (ESM) paired with user interviews and diary studies. Through both quantitative and interpretive analyses, we clarify the distinction between what is identifiable – in terms of what is observable, measurable, or significant – and what is, from a human perspective, important. Extending from our analysis, we define and operationalize meaningless interactions with technology, highlighting how those interactions can contribute to self-empathy and contentment. Ultimately, we suggest a framing for DWB sensitive to these observations to support design for people in their lived experiences.
Article
Full-text available
Discusses the social constructionist movement in modern psychology, noting that social constructionism views discourse about the world not as a reflection or map of the world but as an artifact of communal interchange. Both as an orientation to knowledge and to the character of psychological constructs, constructionism presents a significant challenge to conventional understanding. Although the roots of constructionist thought may be traced to long-standing debates between empiricist and rationalist schools of thought, constructionism moves beyond the dualism of these traditions and places knowledge within the process of social interchange. Although the role of psychological explanation is problematic, a fully developed constructionism could furnish a means for understanding the process of science and invites the development of alternative criteria for the evaluation of psychological inquiry. (100 ref) (PsycINFO Database Record (c) 2012 APA, all rights reserved)
Article
Full-text available
Positive psychology has tended to be defined in terms of a concern with ‘positive’ psychological qualities and states. However, critics of the field have highlighted various problems inherent in classifying phenomena as either ‘positive’ or ‘negative.’ For instance, ostensibly positive qualities (e.g., optimism) can sometimes be detrimental to wellbeing, whereas apparently negative processes (like anxiety) may at times be conducive to it. As such, over recent years, a more nuanced ‘second wave’ of positive psychology has been germinating, which explores the philosophical and conceptual complexities of the very idea of the ‘positive.’ The current paper introduces this emergent second wave by examining the ways in which the field is developing a more subtle understanding of the ‘dialectical’ nature of flourishing (i.e., involving a complex and dynamic interplay of positive and negative experiences). The paper does so by problematizing the notions of positive and negative through seven case studies, including five salient dichotomies (such as optimism versus pessimism) and two complex processes (posttraumatic growth and love). These case studies serve to highlight the type of critical, dialectical thinking that characterises this second wave, thereby outlining the contours of the evolving field.
Article
Coming to terms with emotions and how they influence human behaviour, seems to be of the utmost importance to societies that are obsessed with everything "neuro." On the other hand, emotions have become an object of constant individual and social manipulation since "emotional intelligence" emerged as a buzzword of our times. Reflecting on this burgeoning interest in human emotions makes one think of how this interest developed and what fuelled it. From a historian's point of view, it can be traced back to classical antiquity. But it has undergone shifts and changes which can in turn shed light on social concepts of the self and its relation to other human beings (and nature). The volume focuses on the historicity of emotions and explores the processes that brought them to the fore of public interest and debate.
Article
Worldwide, more people die by suicide than by murder, and many more are left behind to grieve. Despite distressing statistics that show suicide rates rising, the subject, long a taboo, is infrequently talked about. In this sweeping intellectual and cultural history, poet and historian Jennifer Michael Hecht channels her grief for two friends lost to suicide into a search for history's most persuasive arguments against the irretrievable act, arguments she hopes to bring back into public consciousness. From the Stoics and the Bible to Dante, Shakespeare, Wittgenstein, and such twentieth-century writers as John Berryman, Hecht recasts the narrative of our "secular age" in new terms. She shows how religious prohibitions against self-killing were replaced by the Enlightenment's insistence on the rights of the individual, even when those rights had troubling applications. This transition, she movingly argues, resulted in a profound cultural and moral loss: the loss of shared, secular, logical arguments against suicide. By examining how people in other times have found powerful reasons to stay alive when suicide seems a tempting choice, she makes a persuasive intellectual and moral case against suicide.