ArticlePDF Available

Citizens, Leaders and the Common Good in a world of Necessity and Scarcity: Machiavelli’s Lessons for Community-Based Natural Resource Management

Authors:

Abstract

In this article we investigate the value of and use Machialli's work for Community-Based Natural Resource Management (CBNRM). We made a selection of five topics derived from literature on NRM and CBNRM: 1. Law and Policy, 2. Justice, 3. Participation, 4. Transparency and Management and 5. Leadership and Management. We use Machiavelli's work to analyze these topics and embed the results in a narrative intended to lead into the final conclusions, where the overarching theme of natural resource management for the common good is considered. Machiavelli's focus on practical realities produces new, sometimes unsettling, insights. We conclude that this focus helps to understand the development and performance of management regimes and their consequences and that institutional design should be seen as an ongoing process, which requires a constant adaptation of these institutions.
This is a revised personal version of the article that is published in Ethics, Policy & Environment. Please cite as: Van
Assche, K., R. Beunen & M. Duineveld (2016) Citizens, leaders and the common good in a world of necessity and scarcity:
Machiavellis lessons for Community-Based Natural Resource Management. Ethics, Policy & Environment 19 (1): 19-36.
More papers can be found on the website governancetheory.com
Citizens, leaders and the common good in a world of necessity and scarcity:
Machiavellis lessons for Community-Based Natural Resource Management
Kristof Van Assche, Raoul Beunen, Martijn Duineveld
Kristof Van Assche is Associate Professor at the Faculty of Extensions, University of Alberta, Canada, Wageningen University, the Netherlands and Centre for
Development Research, Bonn University, Germany vanasch@ualberta.ca | Raoul Beunen is Assistant Professor at the Faculty of Management, Science &
Technology, Open University, and visiting researcher at Wageningen University, the Netherlands raoul.beunen@ou.nl| Martijn Duineveld is Assistant
Professor at the Cultural Geography Group at. P.O. Box 47, 6700 AA Wageningen, the Netherlands martijn.duineveld@wur.nl.
Abstract In this article we investigate the value of and use Machialli’s work for Community-Based
Natural Resource Management (CBNRM). We made a selection of five topics derived from literature
on NRM and CBNRM: 1. Law and Policy, 2. Justice, 3. Participation, 4. Transparency 5. Leadership
and Management. We use Machiavelli’s work to analyze these topics and embed the results in a
narrative intended to lead into the final conclusions, where the overarching theme of natural
resource management for the common good is considered. Machiavelli’s focus on practical realities
produces new, sometimes unsettling, insights. We conclude that this focus helps to understand the
development and performance of management regimes and their consequences and that
institutional design should be seen as an ongoing process, which requires a constant adaptation of
these institutions.
Key words: Community-Based Natural Resource Management, Machiavelli, Law, Policy, Justice,
Leadership
Introduction
Niccolo Machiavelli (1469-1527), the renaissance writer and self- professed founder of modern
political theory, drew upon his own observations as a Florentine diplomat and the insights of ancient
writers to investigate the ideal role of the citizen in governance. Machiavelli highlighted both the
necessity and risks of active citizen involvement in all aspects of governance. He has been
successively vilified and glorified, claimed by the political left (Gramsci, Althusser) and right (Strauss,
Mansfield). His ideas have been applied to a wide range of topics, from modern corporate leadership
(Mansfield, 1989) to democracy (McCormick, 2011), military tactics (von Clausewitz, 1976),
diplomacy (Berridge et al, 2001), the role of fortune (Mansfield, 1996), the nature of power
(Honohan, 2002) and human nature (Colish, 1971). In this article we investigate the value of his work
for Community-Based Natural Resource Management (CBNRM).
Community-Based Natural Resource Management (CBNRM) includes many different practices
like ‘social and community forestry, community wildlife management, cooperative or co-
management, buffer zone management, participatory multipurpose community projects, communal
area management for indigenous resources, and others’ (Kellert, Mehta, Ebbin, & Lichtenfeld, 2000).
It can be seen as the result of a transition within natural resource management (NRM) to more
participatory forms of governance (Clarke & Jupiter, 2010; Gruber, 2010; Gruber, 2011; Bixler &
Taylor, 2012; Dyer et al., 2014; Reida & Faulknerb, 2014; Wong, 2013). As Gruber argues: ‘CBNRM
has evolved during the last two decades in response to the limitations of previous top-down resource
management approaches, which were based primarily on a pure technical approach to natural
resource management’ (Gruber 2006). According to Armitage, quoted in Gruber (2006), CBNRM,
‘requires some degree of devolution of decision-making power and authority over natural resources
to communities and community-based organizations. [This approach] seeks to encourage better
resource management outcomes with the full participation of communities and resource users in
decision-making activities, and the incorporation of local institutions, customary practices, and
knowledge systems in management, regulatory, and enforcement processes’ (Armitage 2005). In
addition Keller, et al. (2000) state that CBNRM resulted from ‘a desire to link and reconcile the
objectives of socioeconomic development and environmental conservation and protection. A
tendency to defend and legitimize local and/or indigenous resource and property rights. A belief in
the desirability of including traditional values and ecological knowledge in modern resource
management’.
Scientific research on CBNRM and more in general on NRM has been approached from a
variety of theoretical perspectives. Many of these address the institutional arrangements that
communities develop in order to manage natural resources (Agrawal, 1999, Ostrom 1999, Quinn et
al., 2007, Leach, Mearns, & Scoones, 1999). This focus on institutional evolution and design entails
attention for the relations between people in and between different organizations (Sick, 2008;
Natcher, 2005). Partly in response to problems associated with more hierarchical forms of
management, pleas emerged for more participatory approaches (Parkins and Mitchell, 2005; Berkes,
2004; Fitzpack and Sinclair, 2003; Dyer et al., 2014). This shift has placed even more emphasis on the
political dimension of natural resource management and on issues such as institutional design,
leadership, transparency, knowledge/ power and justice (Thiele, 2003; Wootton, 1997; Manent,
1977).
Besides theoretical perspectives, the contemporary debates about CBNRM also encompass
many different and related topics, and different articles present different selections of ‘core’ topics.
Since what is recognized as a core topic within the CBNRM literature is arbitrary and not fixed once
and for all we made our own selection of five topics from both the thematically focused and the
theoretical work on CBNRM: 1. Law and Policy, 2. Justice, 3. Participation, 4. Transparency and
Management and 5. Leadership and Management. This list is neither exclusive nor definitive, other
concepts could be included. The reason to make this selection is that we believe these CBNRM
concepts could relatively easy be related to Machiavelli. Before we elaborate on each of these
concepts we will first explicit and contextualize our use of Machiavelli.
Machiavelli for CBNRM
While the ‘Machiavellian problem’, the notorious ambiguity associated with his rhetorical cunning
and relentless wit, will not dissolve any day soon, we argue that a Machiavellian perspective on
CBNRM has much to offer. Just as Machiavelli famously asserted that political communities have to
revisit and re- examine their roots on a regular basis to avoid decay (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): III,
8; 22), his own writings invite regular re- examination and have been yielding transformative insights
to generations of scholars and practitioners (See Pocock, 1975; Honohan, 2002; McCormick, 2011 for
overviews).
Because of his well- known neutral stance vis-a-vis different types of regimes (cf. Mansfield,
1996, p. 281), and his usually a- moral attitude, setting morality aside for the overriding purpose of
political and community survival (de Grazia, 1989), it is logically impossible to derive a single recipe
for perfect CBNRM. His insights, however can be useful for diverse players in the management game
(Mansfield, 1989), each deploying different perspectives, and they are useful in different institutional
settings (Berridge et al, 2001).
The impossibility of perfection is underlined by other ideas in his oeuvre: that the perfect
state does not exist, that perfect laws and institutions are perfectly adaptable institutions and that
people get tired of even the most efficient and just regimes (Viroli, 1998). With all the ambiguity and
suspicion of perfection, the insistence on pragmatism, adaptability and ‘effective truth’ (Machiavelli,
2005 (ca 1513): 15), Machiavelli’s writings on closer inspection (cf. Mansfield, Strauss, McCormick
and others) reveal principles and rules. What might look first as overly simplified and often
contradictory rules, then as pseudo- structure in associative collages, later appears to be patterned
more intricately and logically (Strauss, 1958; Mansfield, 1979, 1989, 1996; Fischer, 2000).
This paper draws upon an extensive reading of Machiavelli’s work. Machiavelli himself said
that The Prince (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513)) and The Discourses on the first decade of Livy
(Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515)) contained all he had to say. Yet, the later Florentine Histories
(Machiavelli, 1988A (1527)) and to a lesser extent the Art of War (Machiavelli, 2004 (1521)) and his
biography of Castruccio Castracani are rich and relevant enough to include them too. We consulted a
collection of his letters (Machiavelli, 1988b), but did not scrutinize his theatrical works (mostly
comedies) or the documents he produced as a civil servant.
The Prince, his most famous work, is a brief treatise instructing a prince or aspiring prince
(leader) how to gain and maintain power and territory. In The Prince Machiavelli seems to prefer an
authoritarian form of state, but the Discourses, probably written in about the same period (1513-17),
reveal a preference for a republican (proto- democratic) regime with strong citizen participation
(McCormick, 2011). In the Art of War (1521), a long dialogue, Machiavelli does not identify with one
interlocutor, so his position regarding the ideas brought forth by the characters is not always clear,
and it has to be distilled by analyzing the interplay of discourse within the Art of War and within his
whole oeuvre (Mansfield, 1996). The Florentine Histories dissect the history of his hometown in the
regional and international context, with lessons for many but no clear preference for one sort of rule.
In each work, the relation between the different narrative and rhetorical forms is different (cf.
Althusser, 2001; Strauss, 1958; De Grazia, 1989), but in each of them, the more general observations
have to be discovered amidst a wealth of stories and examples, and tested against a series of
apparent contradictions.
With regards to the secondary literature, we made a selection of Machiavelli scholarship that
represents the major lines of interpretation, i.e. a tradition that can be characterized as historicist,
emphasizing context and antecedent (Pocock, Viroli, de Grazia), and traditions that consider him part
of an ongoing conversation on enduring themes in society. Some of these can be categorized as left
(Althusser, Gramsci) or right (Strauss, Mansfield), but certainly not all of them. Comprehensiveness
could not be strived for, rather a mapping of the landscape of interpretations, topically focused on
concepts relevant to CBNRM.
Key topics and concepts
We will now present a series of analyses of five key topics related to CBNRM, to good governance
and active citizenship: 1. Law and Policy, 2. Justice, 3. Participation, 4. Transparency and 5.
Leadership and Management. From these analyses we derive insights we consider relevant for
present- day problems and discussions in CBNRM. Doing so, we intend to distinguish as carefully as
possible the various contexts Machiavelli had to consider in choosing rhetorical forms from the core
ideas he grappled with. We then interpret these ideas in the contemporary contexts of CBNRM. The
analyses are embedded in a narrative intended to lead into the final conclusions, where the
overarching theme of CBNRM for the common good is considered. Whether directly or indirectly
linked, many of these conclusions produce new, sometimes unsettling, insights.
1. Law and policy
Law and policy and the manifold roles thereof are often explicitly and sometimes more subtly part of
CBNRM and NRM studies (Pollard & Cousins, 2014; Rahman, Hickey, & Sarker, 2012; Mulale et al.,
2014; Leach et al., 1999). As in much of the literature on policy and law, the possibilities and limits of
implementation, the role of formal and informal institutions (Beunen, Knaap, & Biesbroek, 2009; Van
Assche, Beunen, & Duineveld, 2014) and the successful and unsuccessful enforcements of policies
and laws are highlighted. An example within the CBNRM literature where many of these issues are
raised and illustrated is ‘Law, custom and community-based natural resource management in
Kubulau District’ (Clarke & Jupiter, 2010). According to Clarke & Jupiter the development,
implementation and enforcement of environmental legislation in the context of their study area ‘has
been constrained by a lack of financial, technical and human resources, professional training (…) and
public awareness of environmental laws. In practice, customary governance systems remain the
primary mechanism for regulating the use of terrestrial and marine resources in many contemporary
Pacific societies (…). Respect for customary law and institutions is an integral feature of most rural
communities, where the overwhelming majority of disputes are resolved by customary means (…). In
remote areas, daily life is almost entirely governed by custom and customary processes, and even
where state institutions exist at the local level, they co-exist with customary institutions, resulting in
‘legal pluralism’, or the existence of multiple legal systems within one geographic area’ (Clarke &
Jupiter, 2010).
For Machiavelli these observations would not come as a surprise, since for him policies and
law are neither naturally given nor fixed entities that can be imposed from above. He famously
omitted every reference to natural law or natural rights in his work (e.g. Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515):
I.2.15; Strauss, 1958; Mansfield, 1996; McCormick, 2011). He did not assume, like the Greeks, that a
natural order in society gave natural rights to each group (Thiele, 2003), and neither did he assume,
as in the later liberal- democratic tradition, that each individual was the bearer of a set of natural
rights that had to be guaranteed by a government (Held, 2006). For Machiavelli order has to be made
and remade in society (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.9.15-18), and maintaining a structured society,
where everyone can work and prosper, requires force. Force can come in the form of laws and arms
(Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 12), with arms as all the powers that can enforce laws or keep order by
means of the threat of violence (cf. Machiavelli, 1988b: nr 206). Laws, then, have to be remade
regularly, enforced by means of arms (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.24), and sometimes broken by
the leadership. Perfect laws are perfectly adapted laws, adapted to internal and external
environments, to the necessities of political and economic survival, and to the web of informal
institutions that can uphold laws more easily without resorting to force.
CBNRM in this perspective can never be perfectly regulated and requires an ongoing
adaptation (Quinn et al., 2007; Ostrom, 1999; Pollard & Cousins, 2014; Van Assche, Beunen, Smit, &
Verschraegen, 2015). The management can therefore never be reduced to the mere application of
laws and policies. For Machiavelli, laws do not maintain themselves, and laws governing resources
are bound to be undermined by shifting alliances between actors (Sick, 2008). The laws themselves
represent negotiated arrangements between stakeholders, and probably none of those stakeholders
entirely identifies with the outcome (cf. Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): III.5; D III.42).
For Machiavelli, both internal and external environments are continuously changing, by
design and because of Lady Fortune (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.37.5). Laws have to follow these
changes. A clear understanding of change and if possible looking forward and planning for
contingencies (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 25; D I.19.13), can make a big difference in the future of a
community. In CBNRM, a clear understanding of the needs of the community and a precise mapping
of resources can make a difference (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.1, Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): I.1).
Protection and wise use of resources might not be perfectly enforceable, but a continuous
communication on future needs and rights, a continuous reshuffling of plans (and associated
policies) stands a much better chance against Lady Fortune and against the always present dangers
of corruption (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.42; cf. Natcher et al, 2005).
When natural resources become scarcer, their increased value will feed corruption
(Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.6.30-36). The resources will make the community more vulnerable to
outside players and they are likely to create internal divisions, either directly, by means of emerging
patronage networks (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.5.20), or indirectly, by means of anticipated gains.
The profits will foster corruption, undermining the regulatory framework and trust in government,
and they render the definition of a common good more complicated, as the factions (new or old)
perceive great gains if a common good is not considered (Ledeneva, 2005). As soon as factions (in the
form of clans, parties, networks, or ‘big men’ and followers) arise, envisioning the common good
becomes more difficult and factions are necessarily fostered by money flows (Machiavelli, 1988A
(1527): II. 42; McLean, 2007; Collins, 2006). Hidden flows are more dangerous, since it is not clear
how the money is affecting formal institutions (Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): II.41; Machiavelli, 2004
(1521): III; cf. Boix 2003; Bowles et al 2008). Laws are then more likely to be broken and new laws are
more likely to be benefiting interest groups. For Machiavelli, it is therefore better to ‘keep the state
rich and the citizens poor’ (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.37). Economic development is to be
stimulated, because expansion, prosperity and stability are positively valued (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca
1515): II.2.44), but the fruits are to be kept close to the state, a state which in turn should be kept
close to the citizens. Furthermore, ‘poverty’ (the absence of great wealth) motivates human activity,
cooperation and therefore economic development (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.3.6)
Natural resources are more difficult to manage than other ‘products’, since their necessity
can create harsh competition and since they are more visible, inviting more direct corruption and
leading more directly to the de- stabilization of society (Easterly, 2006). If things go wrong, and after
a while they will, ‘extraordinary measures’ will be necessary, measures few are willing to take
(Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): 1.17.13). Under these circumstances, that will appear cyclically
(Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.2; Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): V.1), strong
leadership will need to be able to selectively use and ignore law and morality, as a precondition for
the re- establishment of order (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 5; Machiavelli, 1988A (1527);
Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): IV.1). Such order cannot be a blind authoritarian regime, as that would
quickly collapse under popular resentment, and require too much effort to enforce its laws. A
distribution and management of natural resources has to appear as just to the people, if compliance
with the laws is expected (cf. Wilson, 2005; Verdery, 2003; Anderson, 1999).
2. Participation
Based on an analysis of 23 research themes Gruber (2010) identified 12 organizational principles of
CBNRM initiatives. The first and ‘one of the most essential for successful CBNRM programs’ principle
according to him is public participation and mobilization. According to Gruber, a ‘paradigm shift [is]
required (…) to move from ‘‘getting people on your side’’ or selling them on your ideas (the lowest
rung) to including local people in a substantive and meaningful manner, such as sharing decision-
making authority (the higher rungs). (…) Public participation needs to occur at all stages of CBNRM
initiative development and implementation including information gathering, consultation, decision
making, initiating action, and evaluation (… ). This ‘‘true public participation’’ includes stakeholders
with programmatic, operational, scientific, and legal expertise through involvement that is open,
inclusive, and fair (…). Effective public participation will empower citizens and involve all affected
parties, including marginalized communities (…)’ (Gruber, 2010, see e.g. Natcher, Davis, & Hickey,
2005 for a more critical account).
Machiavelli, can in part be used to argue in favor of public participation, but his view would
have been different and contradict much of the optimism on participation, public involvement or
public mobilization. For him the people are capable of recognizing truth, even where the leaders
don’t recognize it (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.4.10). Even in The Prince, Machiavelli asserts that
republics (democracies) are the hardest to subject for a prince, since the freedom enjoyed in
republics is most in tune with human nature and the memory of freedom will always render
subjugation to someone else’s rules more difficult (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 9). In the Discourses
and elsewhere, he intimates that the perfect prince is almost certainly a group, since the qualities
that are supposed to be combined in one person are almost certainly too much to ask (Machiavelli,
1997 (ca 1515): I.20). He also argues that a prince who was successful under certain conditions, will
probably repeat his recipe for success even when conditions are changed, and both vanity and the
increasing rigidity of aging will cause a disaster for the community (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515):
III.9.11). Certain characters of leaders are also more suitable for certain conditions.
In other words, a republic, a democracy, is likely to be more sustainable, more stable, if it is
more resilient to changing circumstances (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): III.46.8). This is the case
simply because there are more different observations available to the leadership (Machiavelli, 1988A
(1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): II 25). Both the laws and other ruling strategies can then be
adjusted on a regular basis, and if the people remain vigilant, non- adaptation of the ruling group can
bring a different group to power (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): III.12.8; Machiavelli, 1988A (1527);
Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): II 27; Machiavelli, 2003 (1520)).
Thus, a democracy, and certainly the form of participatory democracy Machiavelli seems to
encourage in many places, involves all possible forms of active citizenship (McCormick, 2011; cf
Putnam, 1993; Goodin, 2008). It enhances the adaptability and thus sustainability of the political
community. It also enables a community to shift its definitions of the common good and of justifiable
needs and distributions. It makes it easier to enforce laws, since the collective is more strongly
represented in the leadership, and since chances are that laws passed in such systems will represent
beliefs already held. In other words, participatory democracy tends to improve the fit between
formal and informal institutions (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): II.19.9; Easterly, 2006; Young, 2006;
Wilson, 2005).
It also tends to favor a distribution of resources that is perceived as fair and just, because the
rules governing that distribution are the product of open deliberations incorporating already
accepted beliefs and habits (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.58.30; Guinier, 1995). Such perception of
fairness again increases the stability of the state by diminishing the causes of resentment and
division (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 21). Also here, legality is not an overriding goal but a tool to
serve different purposes. The law can stabilize a distribution deemed fair, but if the overriding goal of
the leadership is political stability, it can also be forced to break the law or change it (Machiavelli,
1997 (ca 1515): II.13.8; Collins, 2006).
Participation for Machiavelli is not advisable in every form and he believes it cannot be full
and complete. A democracy has to include forms of representation, for reasons of limited time and
expertise on the part of the populace (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515) III.28.14), but also because there
needs to be a curtain between rulers and ruled, even if that curtain can be drawn every moment
(Mansfield, 1996). As said, the necessities of governing demand a space for deceit (Kluxen, 1949;
Rebhorn, 1988), for dissimulation, vice and unlawfulness (Langton, 1987), but that space cannot be
visible to all. People often do not know what it takes to keep things going (Mansfield, 1989) and
often they do not want to know, being wed to overly optimistic images of individual and community
(Gerber, 1999). Citizens therefore, are required to remain vigilant and active, but the leadership is
required to maintain a distance (Strauss, 1958). This tension, in Machiavelli’s perspective, is
productive, as it gives a space for the necessities of governing while creating a counter- pressure that
can minimize the chance that this space becomes a hotbed for corruption and authoritarianism
(Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): IV.9).
All these remarks apply to CBNRM. Machiavelli does not prescribe the exact role of
corporations, individuals and state in this, but would argue that whatever arrangement is chosen,
one has to take care that the needs of the community are met and that it does not foster corruption
undermining the institutions (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.58.33). Participatory resource
governance or co-management, as advocated by many these days (Van Assche, 2011b; Berkes, 2009;
Berghöfer, 2008; Carlsson and Berkes, 2005; Mitchell, 2005; Plummer and FitzGibbon, 2004), would
be subjected to the same considerations. Some form of participation seems to be a requirement in a
Machiavellian perspective, as decision- making entirely by corporations or bureaucrats will
eventually produce a situation where resource distribution is perceived as unfair, as disregarding a
common good (cf. Jensen-Lee, 2009; Jentoft, 2000). Participatory approaches can also reduce the
need to break the law out of necessity for small actors, and they can improve the implementation of
resource law because of a tightening fit between formal and informal institutions (cf. Rose-
Ackerman, 1999; Ledeneva, 2005). Simultaneously, a raison d’etat still exists and not all participants
are either capable or willing to discern certain threats to the community and to adopt certain
strategies to address them (Goodwin, 1998). Participatory forms of management for Machiavelli
could not replace indirect government entirely, since they rely too much on a set of identifications
with factions (and not the community) and since they create their own political arena, that over time
will be marked by the same strategies and ‘conspiracies’ as the institutions of representative
democracy (Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): IV.15; c.f. Goodwin, 1998; Gerber,
1999).
The finite and necessary character of natural resources adds complexity to the participation
issue in a Machiavellian perspective. We argue that, once scarcity of a necessary resource reaches a
threshold, for Machiavelli it would have to be either taken over by the state, or regulated in such a
way that the survival of the community is safeguarded. Property rights are shifting use arrangements
(Jacobs, 1998; Verdery, 2003) and individuals and corporations for Machiavelli cannot be allowed to
undermine the institutions or jeopardize the community by means of property, since it was the
community that granted these rights in the first place (Ellickson, 1991; Jacobs, 1998). The threshold
for action, for Machiavelli, could either be a sufficient threat as perceived by the people (since not
recognizing that would create internal tumult) or as perceived by the leadership (more objective
according to Machiavelli). Scarcity capable of destabilizing the economy (and hence the political
institutions) and the fear of such scarcity are politically equivalent and should be met with the same
extraordinary measures. Just as the beginning of a new order requires unorthodox measures
(Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 5), the irrational fear of collapse can require these measures, including
the taking of property and identification of scapegoats.
3. Justice
Ideas and concepts of justice are core of the CBNRM literature and perhaps one could argue, the
concept CBNRM by definition contains the notion of justice (cf. Brosius, Tsing, & Zerner, 1998), since
it’s the product of the normative assumption of inclusion. No surprise that the second of the 12
organizational principles of CBNRM initiatives, identified by Gruber (2010) is that of resources and
equity, in other words: the question of justice. He argues that ‘For community-based environmental
programs to be effective, there must be clear linkages between natural resource protection and
conservation and the recognition of local social and economic needs and livelihoods of the
community members (…). This linkage should take into consideration equity, local needs, and
sustainability (…). To promote equity, CBNRM initiatives should seek the fair distribution of benefits
as well as the sharing of hardships for those who may be subject to limited access to resources and
sanctions (…)’ (Gruber, 2010).
If we describe natural resources as natural goods, as goods that have a value for many, then
the issues of ownership and distributive justice loom large. If natural resources are part of the
necessities of life for a community, then that necessity can, for Machiavelli, override all other
concerns (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): III.12; Machiavelli, 2004 (1521): I). That includes dissolving
property rights (see e.g. his discussion of a contested mine, Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli,
1988A (1527): VII. 29) and it includes the possibility of spectacular deterrents and punishments for
those who go against the community.
While Aristotle, the model for most Renaissance political and legal thinkers, disconnected
distributive justice from political and criminal justice (Mansfield, 1996, p. 299), for Machiavelli, the
different forms of justice were manifestations of one and the same justice, a justice that is seen as
primarily a feature of a well- ordered society (Viroli, 1998; Strauss, 1958). If necessity requires to
break laws or to take away privileges from some, that is excusable. Neither criminal justice nor
distributive justice can be derived from natural law, and they can both be manipulated in the pursuit
of the common good (Mansfield, 1989).
Since natural resources are naturally limited, their value is bound to increase with the growth
of economies and populations. For Machiavelli that implies immediately that the question of
ownership will become more politically fraught (cf. Verdery 2003; Jacobs, 1998). It means that
acquiring some form of property rights will become a necessity for more communities, factions and
individuals (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): II.2.46) and that a wide range of strategies will be deployed
to obtain them (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): III.19.12; Ishihura & Pascual, 2009; Radin, 1996). These
strategies will include legal, illegal and pseudo- legal ones, and morality will not play a role in the
calculations of many actors. Machiavelli’s tenet that one cannot discount what is for what ought to
be (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 15) comes into play, and any actor who takes the order of formal
institutions for granted will perish ‘when surrounded by so many who are not virtuous’ (Machiavelli,
2005 (ca 1513): 15). Scarcity, then, forces realism, acuity and pragmatism, as it requires flexibility,
since many players under pressure will act more quickly, less overtly, and less bound by laws
(Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.3.6; I.7.7).
Justice, then, will look different in times of scarcity, and upholding the law will be more
difficult and sometimes less appropriate. Justice, under these conditions, will sometimes require
popular justice, including the punishment of deviants, and on other occasions it will be a rhetorical
varnish of calculating leaders (Plummer & FitzGibbon, 2004; Van Assche et al. 2011a). These leaders
have to manipulate the feelings of justice of the populace, because the long- term stability of the
institutions can only be guaranteed by (a group of) leaders who is willing to play dirty, who is willing
to commit vices of various sorts, against the own citizens and the citizens of neighboring regimes
(Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 17).
Justice in one community can never be justice for other communities, since their interests
will diverge, and the body politic of one can never coincide with that of another (Bernstein, 2005).
Property rights and extraction rights in and for one community will not necessarily be respected in
another one, since the rights will be subjected to different political calculations in each community
(Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.40.22). Outsider status has a political value and a political price, and
ownership by outsiders is bound to become part of factional discussions. If it is not a topic, it is likely
to become a topic; if it is not divisive, it is likely to become divisive.
Machiavelli himself loved his fatherland, but, as others have remarked earlier, that fatherland
is sometimes Florence, sometimes Tuscany, or Italy, and on some occasions it seems to be Europe
(Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 24; Machiavelli, 1988b: nr 225; De Grazia, 1989; McLean, 2007). He
gave advice to both authoritarian and democratic leaders and argued that the scale of governance
and the scale of social identification would have to shift upwards to diminish conflict. At the same
time, conflict will never go away (Machiavelli, 1988b: nr 227; Krause, 2008; Geuss, 2008). Even if
CBNRM can be subjected to a form of world governance, and a conjectured global justice, that justice
will be revised regularly, and new divisions will emerge at all scales (cf. Machiavelli, 1988A (1527);
Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): V.3; Parel, 1992). Thus, both the aspiration of world justice and
governance, and the prediction of continuous strife and new divisions, can be labeled ‘realistic’, as
emerging from his observations as a civil servant/ diplomat, and his reflections on ancient history and
theory.
4. Transparency
Lockwood, et al. consider transparency to be one of eight principals of good governance within NRM.
For them transparency refers to (a) the visibility of decision-making processes; (b) the clarity with
which the reasoning behind decisions is communicated; and (c) the ready availability of relevant
information about governance and performance in an organization. In general, all decisions about
NRM priorities and investments should be accessible to stakeholders. Transparency is required in who
has made a decision; the means by which it has been reached; and its justification.(Lockwood, et al.,
2010, cf. Dyer et al., 2014) These normative assumptions that define transparency in this quote are
partly contradicted if we revisit this concept with Machiavelli in mind.
The intended and well- delineated ambiguities pertaining to the issue of participation in
Machiavelli’s work (cf. Mansfield, 1996), transfer to the topic of transparency. Indeed, just as
vigilance and participation ought to be combined with representation, indirect government and
executive decisions, so the political system needs to retain opaque spots against a counter-pressure
of demands for transparency. These structural tensions are related, and according to Machiavelli
they are productive, and preferably part of any institutional design (Strauss, 1958). Whereas
Machiavelli clearly holds the opinions that power and money corrupt, and that corruption prefers the
dark, he argues that full transparency is impossible and undesirable (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 17;
Machiavelli, 2003 (1520)). Full transparency is impossible and undesirable not only in the relation
between government and people, and between governments, but even between different
departments and branches of government (Sick, 2008). Diplomacy is the prime example here (cf.
Berridge et al., 2001), but for example also ministries of economics, environment and planning ought
not to reveal everything to each other, and not too soon, since that would undermine the quality of
their internal decision- making. Every aspect of government has an aspect of war, and thus requires
judicious use of opacity and dissimulation (Machiavelli, 2004 (1521): IV; Machiavelli, 2003 (1520)).
At the same time, citizens, parties and corporations are expected to exert a counter-
pressure, demanding openness in policy- making, law- making and law- enforcement (Machiavelli,
1997 (ca 1515): III). If it is known which rules apply in which case, if one can expect rules to represent
a reasonable compromise between interests and that these rules will be implemented, then trust in
the institutions can grow and the structures and values of society can reproduce themselves in and
through these institutions (North, 2005). Transparency is the requirement here, as is vigilance.
Machiavelli asks of citizens to trust and distrust the government, as he asks to alternate the roles of
participant and observer (Bock et al 1990; cf. Anderson, 1999; Berkers, 2009). Trust is an asset for the
ruler and the community, but distrust, in the form of vigilance, and the expectation of corruption, is a
necessary accompaniment (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.53; cf. Fraser & Gerstle, 2005).
With regards to CBNRM, scarcity and perceived scarcity can be treated as the triggers for
shifts in trust and transparency. In times of scarcity, the paradox of government will become more
apparent, i.e. the simultaneous cry for transparency (as communal survival is at stake) and pragmatic
pressure on the leadership to take actions that circumvent the legal order or go against the
sensitivities of the public. The hard distinction between the logic of the ruler and the logic of the
ruled (Langton, 1987; Luhmann, 1995) is felt harder under such circumstances (P17), and cannot be
replaced by the distinction between private and public goods. What is private and public is likely to
be redefined in a natural resource crisis (Easterly, 2006; Lazar, 2009). The roles of various actors, and
the laws guiding their actions are likely to be modified (Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli,
1988A (1527): VIII.19; Berkers, 2009).
Times of abundance can be dangerous too, since the cries for transparency will be muted
amidst general prosperity, and private control over natural resources can create fast wealth and can
engender corruption quickly (Ostrom, 2005; Dawood, 2007). For Machiavelli, prosperity can breed
laziness, as in diminished vigilance and participation, and laziness breeds internal corruption while
inviting attacks from the outside (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.16; Machiavelli, 1988A (1527);
Machiavelli, 1988A (1527)). Neither internal nor external environments can be pacified or unified for
a long time, for Machiavelli, so vigilance is always required (de Grazia, 1989; Viroli, 1990). New
divisions, new ambitions, desires and envies will always show up (Backstrand, 2003), and for CBNRM
that means new claims, new forces on rule- making and new causes of conflict (Machiavelli, 1988b:
nr 227; Keen et al., 2005).
So, private and governmental actors are expected to monitor each other continuously, and
are expected to develop a capacity for deciding whether to trust or distrust, since relying on either
one of them too much invites destruction. This, we argue is an essential aspect of Machiavellian
prudence. Individuals, corporations and governmental organizations with a role in CBNRM have to
make similar decisions regarding trust and distrust, but the allocation of trust enables the
reproduction of society, while the allocation of distrust prevents collapse. All these players, in their
different roles, ought to push for transparency with the others (Fitzpatrick & Sinclair, 2003), while
maintaining a private space for decision- making. This is not a contradiction in practice or theory; it is
a manifestation of political reality (and hence the reality of each community) as borne out of conflict
(Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): VII.1; Hulliung, 1983; Krause, 2008).
5. Leadership and management
The many discourses on NRM and CBNRM by definition concern the issue of management.
Leadership is often mentioned separately, as a subcategory of CBNRM, NRM or management in
general (Gruber, 2010; Dyer et al., 2014; Matthews, 1990; Lockwood et al., 2010; Wong, 2013).
Although we do not aim to provide an extensive literature review here, we believe a main distinction
can be made within the CBNRM literature between a version of leadership in which ‘the leader’ rules
top down, in a technocratic manner, directed at clearly delineated objectives, aiming to implement
policies and plans and ideas on leadership in which leadership is considered to be adaptive, a form of
co management, and a way of learning to adjust to new circumstances (Dyer et al., 2014; Gruber,
2010).
For Machiavelli, leadership is always management, management of impressions, passions and
resources (Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): III.1; Mansfield, 1989). A political
reality is defined by the impression people have of the situation in the community and the role of the
leadership, by the passions that are aroused by these impressions and in particular by the
impressions of the leadership as managers of resource flows (Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli,
1988A (1527): VII.29; Mansfield, 1979; Radin, 1996). Managing resource flows is always politics if
these resources are vital to the community, and political calculations cannot be excluded from the
management (Dawood, 2007; Van Assche et al, 2011b). Resorting to a legal blindness of rule
application or a bureaucratic blindness of optimums and objective needs does not solve anything
(Miller, 2002; by contrast: McCann et al, 2005). It only creates an impression of a de- politicized
space where de facto politics plays out in denser darkness (Ledeneva, 2005).
While Machiavelli never made the explicit distinction between legislature, judiciary and
executive branches of government (Skinner, 1981), he can be seen as the first theorist of the
executive (Mansfield, 1989, 1996), and the first theorist to underline the need for checks and
balances (Thiele, 2003). Indeed, the structure of any government out to be such that no party can
amass all power, he asserted (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515) and Machiavelli, 1988A (1527);
Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): throughout). Such structure also has the positive feature that more
different perspectives can come to the surface (cf. Luhmann, 1995). The surfacing of difference
enhances the quality of decisions and thus the adaptive capacities of government, and it reduces
opacity and the need for conspiracy (Honig, 2007). In Machiavelli’s system, the structural checks and
balances in government are part of a theory of productive conflict, where the pairs of
transparency/opacity, trust/distrust, and participation/subjugation are continuously tested against
each other by all actors.
Even so, good decisions, i.e. decisions furthering the common good and anticipating necessity
(Mansfield, 1996), do not automatically arise from this conflict- ridden interplay between actors.
Good decisions are neither reducible to good laws (laws being too generic and rigid), nor to open
discussions between various players (not necessarily eying the common good, not necessarily
producing consensus with the necessary content). They often require an executive with autonomy,
an executive (prince or group) that can act quickly and decisively if necessary (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca
1513): 5; Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): II.14), that can maintain a distance
from the people if necessary, and that can take audacious and radical decisions were the situation
asks for it (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 24). In other words, leadership is necessary, with enough
decision- space to allow for prudent and independent judgment.
Fear on both sides is required to make this work, according to Machiavelli, a fear of the
leadership, capable to do seemingly irrational things in the common interest and a fear by the leader
of the people, an anxiety to maintain public support in the longer run (Rebhorn, 1988; Langton,
1987). Managing the public is therefore a necessity for the leader, and restricting the leader, by
means of term limits, laws, and institutional checks, is a necessity for the people (Machiavelli, 1997
(ca 1515): I.11.22; cf. Skocpol, 2004).
The management of natural resources, as a political endeavor, is also a management of
people (Sick, 2008). In the management of resources, expertise in the discerning of future necessity
and in the organization of efficient use and distribution has to be combined with the political arts.
For Machiavelli, that means that resource extraction and distribution cannot be left entirely to
private actors and that the public management of resources cannot be left entirely to bureaucratic
and scientific experts (Scott, 1998; Miller, 2002). CBNRM for Machiavelli would have to include both
careful planning and maintaining the ability to break the self- imposed policies (D. I. 33.2), both the
careful maintenance of alliances and the ability to break them if necessary (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca
1515): I.38.2), both articulate communication strategies and the willingness to evade and hide
(Garsten, 2006; Lazar, 2009).
All the vices that are expected to be available to the autonomous manager are not
considered morally good, but merely excusable, as means to further the security, stability, prosperity
and freedoms of the community (Viroli, 1998). In CBNRM, where distribution questions come to the
fore, the issue of factions ignoring the common good, intent on diverting flows and bending rules, is
of foremost importance (Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): V.6). Managing
resources is managing factions, observing them, understanding their modes and operations.
Management of factions can consist of a mere application of laws, of attempts to bind factions to a
common good defined in politics, and it can involve extraordinary measures or attempts to
reconfigure faction interest to minimize damage to a common good (Lazar, 2009; Rebhorn, 1988).
Especially in the management of resources, Machiavelli’s precept to start reasoning from how things
actually work, not how they are supposed to work, is eminently useful. Necessities and opportunities
reveal themselves in the moment, in the action (Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A
(1527): VI.13): ‘When one acts, plans reveal themselves that, to one standing still, would always be
hidden’.
The prudent manager realizes that factions and their corruptive tendencies will never go
away, but that they can be managed (Rose- Ackerman, 1999; cf. Carlsson& Berkes, 2005). It is usually
better to work with known factions than to spend precious resources to get rid of them; that will
only create a vacuum that will be filled up by a new set of factions operating along lines that are less
known, less predictable and thus risky (Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): II.17).
Conclusions
Based on a comparison and evaluation of five case studies Kellert et al. conclude that there are quite
some gaps between the promise, rhetoric, and reality of CBNRM (Kellert et al., 2000). Like us they do
not undermine the relevance and importance of CBNRM, but they argue ‘the evidence accumulated
in the five case studies examined (…) suggests the reality often falls far short of the rhetoric and
promise of C[B]NRM. The complexity of goals, interests, and organizational features of CNRM renders
its implementation exceedingly difficult’ (Kellert et al., 2000).
Our reading Machiavelli could bring us to similar conclusions, yet they also deepen the
understanding of why gaps exist between the promise, rhetoric and reality of CBNRM and moreover,
there are some important constructive lessons for CBNRM that we can learn from Machiavelli’s
work. We can take from his work the focus on practical realities. This focus helps to understand the
development and performance of management regimes and their social consequences. This would
require more attention for issues like transparency, leadership and rule avoidance in the research on
CBNRM. Secondly, we can learn from Machiavelli’s work that institutional design should be seen as
an ongoing process. The circumstances in which institutions are to function are likely to change
sooner or later, requiring an adaptation of these institutions (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): III.9;
Machiavelli, 1988A (1527); Machiavelli, 1988A (1527): throughout). Also under stable conditions the
effects of institutions will probably erode, simply because people adapt their behavior, rendering the
institutions less efficient or even useless after a while. How this is going to happen and when, can
never be predicted, but it requires a permanent state of vigilance from all actors towards current
institutions.
If we consider CBNRM as something touching upon the common good in a community, then
Machiavelli would argue it is a matter of politics, and, as such, a matter requiring skills in the art of
war (Machiavelli, 2005 (ca 1513): 6; Machiavelli, 2004 (1521): I; Machiavelli, 2003 (1520)). Current
republics might have more substantial bureaucracies and expertise than early modern states
(Martines, 1979), and their corporate structures and lobbies might be more developed (Mansfield,
1989), but Renaissance Tuscany and Classical Antiquity offered enough institutional development
and variation for Machiavelli to grasp underlying principles that can still apply today (Gilbert, 1965;
McLean, 2007). Resource management still is war, sometimes in the literal sense, but always in the
wider sense intended by Machiavelli: the art of strategy and tactics, of persuasion and bullying, in
other words, the mechanics of power (Garsten, 2006).
As many others have noticed (De Grazia, 1989; Viroli, 1998; Gramsci, 1958), Machiavelli never
relinquishes the dream of a better society and in most of his writings that does seem to be a society
that determines its own needs and goals, a society that builds on the passions of individuals,
organizations and factions without giving in to the eroding tendencies that come together with these
passions (Fishkin, 1997; Holmes, 1995; Krause, 2008). Power is both necessary and evil for
Machiavelli and harnessing all forms of power available to society is helpful in maintaining order and
expanding (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): II.2.45). Power is the fire one needs to play with. Managing
natural resources, as finite necessities for the community, is playing with fire. It is a continuous and
continuously perilous attempt to manage factions, individuals and organizations (e.g. corporations)
who are likely following a logic that is detrimental to the common good.
Such common good cannot be determined once and for all by science (Miller, 2002), or in
political consensus- building (Machiavelli, 1997 (ca 1515): I.22.6; Honig, 2007). Neither can it be
imposed on society by a set of timeless perfect laws. Administrators cannot be left to their own
devices in managing power/ knowledge, in implementing policies and enforcing laws (Machiavelli,
2005 (ca 1513): 22). The rules, knowledge and tacit agreements governing the distribution and
management of natural resources are destined to shift on a regular basis, but autonomous yet
contained executive leadership is needed to take decisions in the name of the community. While
spectacular executions and conspiracy might be out of fashion, these concepts do point out that
science, law, and established procedure are likely to be insufficient in CBNRM (cf. Mansfield, 1996;
McCormick, 2011). This applies to the governmental actors, but it also applies to the management of
the corporations involved in the natural resource game. Management on both sides of the private/
public divide has to keep the options open to deviate from established procedures if pursuing the
goals of the whole is primary (cf. Brandsen et al., 2006; Short and Winter, 1998).
One could object that the practice or the ideal of CBNRM can replace the intricate power
games of a Machiavellian democracy. Machiavelli would believe the opposite to be true. Not only has
direct participation its obvious limitations, and not only can it easily be manipulated by both princes
and opposition (Goodwin, 1998), one should also be aware that what we call participatory
management tends to blur the responsibilities of all actors in a representative democracy (Van
Assche et al, 2011b; Bergkamp, 2002). As such, it offers more openings for strategy, and hampers the
checks and balances that became accepted as part of politics.
An important lesson from Machiavelli is that a good natural resource regime will naturally
transform itself. If resources become scarce, rules will be broken and rules and alliances will be
modified. Expecting a final and stable formula for perfect management from science, law, economy
or politics is either a soothing delusion for those believing in the possibility of a harmonious society,
or the discourse of actors benefiting from this belief (Schwartzberg, 2007). The role of science,
politics, law and economy in CBNRM will be different in each time and place, as will the influence of
various actors on rules and regulations. For Machiavelli, however, politics holds a special place, since
it should be a matter of politics to decide how politics is organized. The shifting resource
management arrangements should be firmly placed within the realm of politics, with all the vigilance,
deceit, and counter- pressures, but also with the enduring belief that a common good can be defined
within politics, that it can be strived for, and that it is in the interest of both leaders and community
to do so. CBNRM is a necessity, but its plans, policies and procedures, including increased citizen
participation, cannot last eternally. They have to build and rebuild in continuous friction, scrutiny and
agility.
References
Agrawal, A., 1999. Greener pastures: Politics, markets, and community among a migrant pastoral people.
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Althusser, L. 2001. Machiavelli and us. London: Verso.
Anderson, L. ed., 1999. Transitions to democracy. New York: Columbia University Press.
Backstrand, K., 2003. Civic science for sustainability: reframing the role of experts, policy-makers and citizens in
environmental governance. Global Environmental Politics, 3 (4), 2441.
Berghöfer, A., Wittmer, H. and Rauschmayer, F., 2008. Stakeholder participation in ecosystem-based
approaches to fisheries management: a synthesis from European research projects. Marine Policy, 32 (2),
243-253.
Bergkamp, L., 2002. Corporate governance and social responsibility: a new sustainability paradigm. European
Environmental Law Review, 11 (5), 136152.
Berkers, F., 2009. Evolution of co-management: Role of knowledge generation, bridging organizations and
social learning. Journal of Environmental Management, 90 (5), 16921702.
Berkes, F., 2004. Rethinking community-based conservation. Conservation Biology, 18 (3),621630.
Bernstein, S., 2005. Legitimacy in global environmental governance. Journal of International Law and
International Relations, 1, 139166.
Berridge, G., Keens- Soper, M. and Otte, T., eds., 2001. Diplomatic theory from Machiavelli to Kissinger.
Houndmills: Ashgate.
Beunen, R., Knaap, W. v. d., & Biesbroek, G. (2009). Implementation and integration of EU environmental
directives. Experiences from the Netherlands. Environmental policy and governance, 19(1), 56-73.
Bixler, R. P., & Taylor, P. L. (2012). Toward a Community of Innovation in Community-Based Natural Resource
Management: Insights from Open Source Software. Human Organization, 71(3), 234-243.
Bock, G., Skinner, Q. and Viroli, M., eds., 1990. Machiavelli and republicanism. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Boix, Ch. 2003. Democracy and redistribution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bowles, S., Gintis, H. and Gustafsson, B., eds. 2008. Markets and democracy: participation, accountability and
efficiency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brandsen, T., Boogers, M. and Tops, P., 2006. Soft governance, hard consequences: the ambiguous status of
unofficial guidelines. Public Administration Review, 66 (4), 546-553.
Brosius, J. P., Tsing, A. L., & Zerner, C. (1998). Representing communities: Histories and politics of community
based natural resource management.
Brosius, J.P., Tsing, A. and Zerner, C., 1998. Representing communities: histories and politics of community-
based resource management. Society and Natural Resources, 11 (2), 157168.
Carlsson, L. and Berkes, F., 2005. Co-management: concepts and methodological implications. Journal of
Environmental Management, 75(1), 6576.
Clarke, P., & Jupiter, S. D. (2010). Law, custom and community-based natural resource management in Kubulau
District (Fiji). Environmental Conservation, 37(01), 98-106.
Colish, M. 1971. The idea of liberty in Machiavelli. Journal of the History of Ideas, 32 (3), 323-350.
Collins, C. 2006. Clan politics in Central Asia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dawood, Y. 2007. The new inequality: constitutional democracy and the problem of wealth. Maryland Law
Review 67, 123-149.
De Grazia, S. 1989. Machiavelli in hell. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Dowdle, M., ed., 2006. Public accountability: designs, dilemma’s and experiences. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Dyer, J., Stringer, L., Dougill, A., Leventon, J., Nshimbi, M., Chama, F., Falcao, M. (2014). Assessing participatory
practices in community-based natural resource management: experiences in community engagement
from southern Africa. Journal of environmental management, 137, 137-145.
Easterly, W. 2006. The white man’s burden. why the West's efforts to aid the rest have done so much ill and so
little good. New York: Penguin Press.
Elkin, S. 2006. Reconstructing the commercial republic: Constitutional design after Madison. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Ellickson, R.C., 1991. Order without Law. How Neighbors Settle Disputers. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Ferraro, P.J., 2009. Counterfactual thinking and impact evaluation in environmental policy. New Directions for
Evaluation, 122, 75-84.
Fischer, M. 2000. Well- ordered license: on the unity of Machiavelli’s thought. Lexington, Lanham.
Fishkin, J. 1997. The voice of the people: public opinion and democracy. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Fitzpatrick, P. and Sinclair, J., 2003. Learning through public involvement in environmental assessment
hearings. Journal of Environmental Management, 67 (2), 161-174.
Fraser, S. and Gerstle, G., eds., 2005. Ruling America: a history of wealth and power in a democracy.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Garsten, B., 2006. Saving persuasion: a defense of rhetoric and judgment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Gerber, E., 1999. The populist paradox: interest group influence and the promise of direct legislation. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Geuss, R., 2008. Philosophy and real politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gilbert, F., 1965. Machiavelli and Guicciardini: Politics and History in Sixteenth- Century Florence. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Goodin, R., 2008. Innovating democracy: democratic theory and practice after the deliberative turn. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Goodwin, P.P., 1998. Hired hands or local voice: understandings and experience of local participation in
conservation. Transactions of the Institute of British Geography, 23 (4), 481499.
Gramsci, A., 1959 (1929). The modern prince and other writings. London: International.
Gruber, J. S. 2011. Perspectives of effective and sustainable community-based natural resource management:
An application of Q methodology to forest projects. Conservation and Society, 9(2), 159.
Gruber, J.S., 2010. Key Principles of Community-Based Natural Resource Management: A Synthesis and
Interpretation of Identified Effective Approaches for Managing the Commons. Environmental
Management, 45: 5266
Guinier, L., 1995. Tyranny of the majority: fundamental fairness in representative democracy. New York: Simon
and Schuster.
Held, D., 2006. Models of democracy. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Hitt, W.D., 1990. Ethics and Leadership: Putting Theory into Practice. Columbus, OH: Battelle Press.
Holmes, S., 1995. Passions and constraint: on the theory of liberal democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Honig, B., 2007. Between decision and deliberation: political paradox in democratic theory. American Policy
Science Review, 101 (1), 1-17.
Honohan, I., 2002. Civic republicanism. New York: Routledge.
Hulliung, M., 1983. Citizen Machiavelli. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Ishihara, H. and Pascual, U., 2009. Social capital in community level environmental governance: a critique.
Ecological Economics, 68, 1549-1562.
Jacobs, H.M., 1998. Who owns America?: Social conflict over property rights. Madison: The University of
Wisconsin Press.
Jensen-Lee, C., 2009. When unequals are treated equally: the commission of inquiry into Orica’s Geomelt
proposal. Journal of Environmental Management, 90 (4),16131621.
Jentoft, S., 2000. Legitimacy and disappointment in fisheries management. Marine Policy 24, 141148.
Keen, M., Brown, V. and Dyball, R., 2005. Social Learning in Environmental Management: Towards a
Sustainable Future. London: Earthscan.
Kellert, S. R., Mehta, J. N., Ebbin, S. A., & Lichtenfeld, L. L., 2000. Community natural resource management:
promise, rhetoric, and reality. Society & Natural Resources, 13(8), 705-715.
Kluxen, K., 1949. Der begriff der necessita im denken Machiavellis. Cologne: Bensberg.
Krause, S., 2008. Civil Passions: moral sentiment and democratic deliberation. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Langton, J., 1987. Machiavelli’s paradox: trapping or teaching the prince. American Policy Science Review, 81
(4), 1277-1288.
Lazar, N., 2009. States of emergency in liberal democracies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Leach, M., Mearns, M., & Scoones, I., 1999. Environmental entitlements: dynamics and institutions in
community- based natural resource management. World Development, 27(2), 225-247.
Ledeneva, A., 2005. How Russia really works. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Little, A., 2002. The Politics of Community. Theory and Practice. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Lockwood, M., Davidson, J., Curtis, A., Stratford, E., & Griffith, R., 2010. Governance principles for natural
resource management. Society and Natural Resources, 23(10), 986-1001.
Luhmann. N., 1995. Social systems. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Machiavelli, N. 1988a (1527) Florentine Histories. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Machiavelli, N. 1988b. The letters of Machiavelli. (Ed. and selection A. Gilbert). Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Machiavelli, N. 1997 (ca 1515) Discourses on Livy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Machiavelli, N. 2003 (1520) Life of Castruccio Castraccani. London: Hesperus
Machiavelli, N. 2004 (1521) The art of war. In The Prince and the art of war. New York: Barnes and Noble.
Machiavelli, N. 2005 (ca 1513) The Prince. Boston: Bedford.
Manent, P. 1977. Naissances de la politique moderne: Machiavel, Hobbes, Rousseau. Paris: Payot.
Mansfield, H., 1979. Machiavelli’s new modes and orders. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Mansfield, H., 1989. Taming the prince. The ambivalence of modern executive power. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press.
Mansfield, H., 1996. Machiavelli’s virtue. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Martines, L., 1979. Power and imagination: City- states in renaissance Italy. New York: Knopf.
Matthews, J. T., 1990 Preserving the Global Environment: The Challenge of Shared Leadership.
McCann, L., et al., 2005. Transaction cost measurement for evaluating environmental policies. Ecological
Economics, 52, 527-542.
McCormick, J., 2011. Machiavellian democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
McLean, P., 2007. The art of the network. Strategic interaction and patronage in renaissance Florence. Durham:
Duke University Press.
Miller, H.T., 2002. Postmodern public policy. Albany: SUNY Press.
Mitchell, B., 2005. Participatory partnerships: Engaging and empowering to enhance environmental
management and quality of life? Social Indicators Research, 71, 123-144.
Mulale, K., Chanda, R., Perkins, J. S., Magole, L., Sebego, R. J., Atlhopheng, J. R., Reed, M. S., 2014. Formal
institutions and their role in promoting sustainable land management in Boteti, Botswana. Land
Degradation & Development, 25(1), 80-91.
Natcher, D. C., Davis, S., & Hickey, C. G., 2005. Co-management: managing relationships, not resources. Human
Organization, 64(3), 240-250.
Natcher, D.C., Davis, S. and Hickey, C.G., 2005. Co-management: managing relationships, not resources. Human
Organization, 64 (3), 240250.
North, D., 2005 Understanding the process of economic change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ostrom, E., 1990. Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Ostrom, E., 1999. Coping with tragedies of the commons. Annual Review of Political Science, 2, 493535.
Parel, J., 1992. The Machiavellian cosmos. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Parkins, J., Mitchell, R., 2005. Public participation as public debate: a deliberative turn in natural resource
management. Society and Natural Resources, 18, 529-540.
Plummer, R. and FitzGibbon, J., 2004. Some observations on the terminology in co-operative environmental
management. Journal of Environmental Management, 70, 63-72.
Pocock, J., 1975. The Machiavellian moment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Pollard, S., & Cousins, T., 2014. Legal pluralism and the governance of freshwater resources in southern Africa.
Governance for Justice and Environmental Sustainability: Lessons Across Natural Resource Sectors in
Sub-Saharan Africa, 220.
Putnam, R., 1993. Bowling alone. The collapse and revival of American community. New York: Simon and
Schuster.
Quinn, C.H., Huby, M., Kiwasila, H. and Lovett, J.C., 2007. Design principles and common pool resource
management: An institutional approach to evaluating community management in semi-arid Tanzania.
Journal of Environmental Management, 84, 100113.
Radin, M.J., 1996. Contested commodities. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rahman, H., Hickey, G. M., & Sarker, S. K., 2012. A framework for evaluating collective action and informal
institutional dynamics under a resource management policy of decentralization. Ecological Economics,
83, 32-41.
Rebhorn, W., 1988. Foxes and lions. Machiavelli’s confidence men. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Reed, M.S. et al., 2009. Who’s in and why? A typology of stakeholder analysis methods for natural resource
management. Journal of Environmental Management, 90 (2009) 19331949.
Reida, H., & Faulknerb, L., 2014, Assessing How Participatory/Community-Based Natural Resource
Management Initiatives Contribute to Climate Change Adaptation in Ethiopia.
Rose- Ackerman, S., 1999. Corruption and government: causes, consequences and reform. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Schwartzberg, M., 2007. Democracy and legal change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Scott, J., 1998. Seeing like a state. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Short, C. and Winter, M., 1999. The problem of common land: towards stakeholder governance. Journal of
Environmental Planning and Management 42, 613630.
Sick, D., 2008. Social context and consequences of institutional change in common-pool resources. Society and
Natural Resources, 21(2) 94-105.
Skinner, Q., 1981. Machiavelli. New York: Hill and Wang.
Skocpol, T. 2004. Diminished democracy: from membership to management in American civic life. Norman:
University of Oklahoma Press.
Strauss, L. 1958. Thoughts on Machiavelli. Glencoe: Free Press.
Thiele, L. 2003. Thinking politics. Perspectives in ancient, modern a postmodern political theory. New York:
Chatham House.
Van Assche, K., Beunen, R., Jacobs, A.J. and Teampau, P., 2011a. Crossing trails in the marshes: rigidity and
flexibility in the governance of the Danube Delta. Journal of Environmental Planning and Management, 54
(8), 997-1018.
Van Assche, K., Duineveld, M., Beunen, R. and Teampau, P., 2011b. Delineating locals: Transformations of
knowledge/power and the governance of the Danube delta. Journal of Environmental Policy and Planning,
13 (1), 1-21.
Van Assche, K., Beunen, R., Smit, A., & Verschraegen, G. (2015). Planning and Law in Evolving Governance. In R.
Beunen, K. Van Assche & M. Duineveld (Eds.), Evolutionary Governance Theory: Theory and
Applications Heidelberg: Springer.
Van Assche, K., Van., Beunen, R., & Duineveld, M. (2014). Evolutionary Governance Theory. An Introduction.
Heidelberg: Springer
Verdery, K., 2003. The vanishing hectare. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Viroli, M., 1998. Machiavelli. Oxord: Oxford University Press.
Von Clausewitz, C., 1976 (1831) On War, edited and translated by Howard, M. Paret, P. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Wilson, A. 2005. Virtual politics. Faking democracy in the Post- Soviet world. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Wong, S., 2013. Challenges to the elite exclusioninclusion dichotomyreconsidering elite capture in
community-based natural resource management. South African Journal of International Affairs, 20(3),
379-391.
Wootton, D., ed., 1997. Modern Political Thought. Readings from Machiavelli to Nietzsche. Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company.
Young, I. 2006. Inclusion and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
... Tools of coordination are temporary but, even in the absence of consensus, the conversation on anchors for environmental governance should continue, perhaps with a new form of foundational institution. Even imperfect and temporary institutions can find common ground and stabilization [19,20], and the authors argue for a new social-natural contract suitable for the dire situation of our social-ecological systems. ...
... Conflicts can be productive as well and, as with shocks, that productivity can be both positive and negative [20,40]. A difference-a crucial difference-is that conflicts can easily restructure memory and identity, through polarization of topics beyond the original bone of contention. ...
Article
Full-text available
This Special Issue explores evolutionary perspectives on environmental policy and governance [...]
... Military planning is too focused exclusively; whether it is a preferred concept will jeopardize the inclusiveness mandated by nature and the character of the subject. War planning has a strong focus but is not exclusively precise, at least in the literal sense it is necessary to plan for peace [19]. ...
Article
Full-text available
National defense is faced with an uncertain changing strategic environment. For this reason, in order for a country to be able to maintain the sovereignty and security of its people, a state defense strategy strategy is needed that is adaptive to all changes and potential threats. The strategy of holding power during the COVID-19 pandemic is different from previous conditions. This study focuses on developing a strategy for deploying defense forces that are appropriate to deal with all these threats. The research uses qualitative methods with data collection techniques from literature studies. The results of the study prove that the concept of a grand strategy which is a universal defense system has principles that are suitable for dealing with increasingly complex threats in the future.
... This brings us back to the idea of reflexive learning as a basis for all the other types of learning (cf Voss et al., 2006), and the idea of dialectical learning as the destination in governance or, at the very least, a necessary step (Van Assche et al., 2020). It also hints at a principle embraced by many before: the value of truly different perspectives in governance, and of carefully guarded mechanisms to maintain such diversity, and to let the differences be exposed and become productive in dialectical learning (Mingers, 2003;Van Assche et al., 2016;Vaughan & Rafanell, 2012). Carlsen (2016) speaks of the "narrative unconscious" in organizational identity, in an analysis which connects well with Czarniawska's (2004) understanding of the necessarily enabling and disabling, including and excluding character of narratives in guiding the functioning of organizations. ...
Article
Full-text available
This essay introduces and frames the contributions to the special issue on learning and co-evolution in governance. It develops the argument that learning, dark learning and non-learning are necessarily entwined in governance, moreover, entwined in a pattern unique to each governance configuration and path. What can be learned collectively for the common good, what kind of knowledge and learning can be strategically used and shamelessly abused, and which forms of knowledge remain invisible, intentionally and unintentionally, emerges in a history of co-evolution of actors and institutions, power and knowledge, in governance. Learning becomes possible in a particular form of management of observation, of transparency and opacity, where contingency is precariously mastered by governance systems expected to provide certainty for communities.
Article
We argue a re-appraisal of asset mapping is needed based on revisiting the concept of assets. Asset mapping is useful for inter/trans-disciplinary work involving complex systems: organizations, administrations, governance systems, social-ecological systems, etc. Asset mapping can be an integrative method, allowing a combination of different disciplinary insights and knowledge types; co-defining what is valuable in and for a system. We propose a new version of asset mapping that combines contextual, iterative, and virtual asset mapping in different manners depending on the system and situation. The unpredictable character of co-evolution makes iterative asset mapping important, contextual asset mapping allows different delineations of relevant contexts, and virtual asset mapping entails recognizing assets in different futures, either scenario-based or as strategy options. We argue that this novel approach is particularly important for planning, in the broad sense, because it provides a bridging opportunity with other fields, connecting discourses and policy.
Article
Full-text available
In this paper, we present a framework for the analysis of shock and conflict in social-ecological systems and investigate the implications of this perspective for the understanding of environmental governance, particularly its evolutionary patterns and drivers. We dwell on the distinction between shock and conflict. In mapping the relation between shock and conflict, we invoke a different potentiality for altering rigidity and flexibility in governance; different possibilities for recall, revival and trauma; and different pathways for restructuring the relation between governance, community and environment. Shock and conflict can be both productive and eroding, and for each, one can observe that productivity can be positive or negative. These different effects in governance can be analyzed in terms of object and subject creation, path creation and in terms of the dependencies recognized by evolutionary governance theory: path, inter-, goal and material dependencies. Thus, shock and conflict are mapped in their potential consequences to not only shift a path of governance, but also to transform the pattern of self-transformation in such path. Finally, we reflect on what this means for the interpretation of adaptive governance of social-ecological systems.
Article
We develop a novel perspective on the interplay between causes and effects of resource policy (and more generally development strategy) at local level. We do this by deploying a theoretical framework built around both psychoanalytic notions and concepts from governance theory to analyze the evolution and the construction of futures in the Canadian mining community of the Crowsnest Pass, Alberta. It is argued that the growth and decline of mining created social identities and governance features which severely hamper the articulation of alternative futures. The case study highlights the importance of collective trauma, both stemming from rapid development and decline, in the understanding of fantasy as it plays out in evolving governance, the understanding of replayed scenarios of hope and disillusion. The case analysis contributes to the broader discussion of path dependencies in community development by multiplying the potential effects of key events in the development of the community, beyond effects on conscious collective memory, beyond institutional structures and processes. Freud's foundational idea of nachtragligkeit, the potential of events to steer development in a direction but also to resurface much later in the manner of symptoms limiting reflexivity and adaptation, is thus given a translation at community level, with special implications for resource communities and policies.
Article
We draw on research in Western Newfoundland (Canada) to investigate the possibilities and limits of community reinvention, defined as radical change in the nature of the community, as perceived by local residents. Community reinvention is understood as an extreme form of strategic change in communities, one typically embraced under extreme circumstances. As such, reinvention offers a privileged vantage point on the utility of strategy to effectuate community change. We examine three communities in western Newfoundland, a region that has experienced a prolonged economic decline and is therefore keen on changing its development path. We coin the concepts of reinvention paths to grasp the set of transformation options available to a community, a matrix that can be reconstructed through analysis of the governance path(s) of a community. The concept of reinvention paradox is devised to point out that envisioned strategic change amounting to reinvention is likely to significantly alter, and perhaps even ultimately undermine, that strategy by altering, if successful, the actors, perspectives, power relations and identities at play. This paradox will unfold over time and, it is argued, can be amenable to adaptive management.
Article
We investigate the nature and potential of strategy in governance and emphasize the importance of understanding strategy in its (potential) relations to long-term perspectives or narratives about the long term. Strategy is understood as both a narrative and an institution itself. Narratives about the long term, both inside and outside the sphere of governance, have to be mapped and acknowledged. This can inspire, in strategy formulation, a link to such existing perspectives or the production of a new one. Such strategy ought to be persuasive enough to coordinate action and create reality effects. We focus on strategy which aims to guide complex governance configurations associated with a set of actors, institutions and collective goals. The double nature of governance strategy enables it to coordinate other institutions and narratives, and from there, to coordinate, even integrate policy domains. That might be a sine qua non for dealing with long-term threats and the pursuit of public goods. The longest term might be the most relevant yet the least knowable and the most difficult to steer towards with existing governance tools. Nonetheless, evolving strategy, evolving assessment of linkages to long-term perspectives and possible forms of policy integration might be our best way forward.
Article
Property regimes are based on fundamental values of the society or group that designs and reproduces them. This paper analyses the ethical underpinnings of Progressive Commons in comparison to the values underlying private property and traditional Commons. Against this backdrop, we discuss the potential of Progressive Commons to address major challenges in context of the twenty-first century economy. Seed Commons serve as an example. Our analysis shows that Progressive Commons respond to contemporary societal and environmental challenges by re-interpreting the classical values underlying traditional private and common property regimes, turning them to sovereignty, re-democratization, and social-ecological sustainability in the global context.
Book
Since ancient Athens, democrats have taken pride in their power and inclination to change their laws, yet they have also sought to counter this capacity by creating immutable laws. In Democracy and Legal Change, Melissa Schwartzberg argues that modifying law is a fundamental and attractive democratic activity. Against those who would defend the use of 'entrenchment clauses' to protect key constitutional provisions from revision, Schwartzberg seeks to demonstrate historically the strategic and even unjust purposes unamendable laws have typically served, and to highlight the regrettable consequences that entrenchment may have for democracies today. Drawing on historical evidence, classical political theory, and contemporary constitutional and democratic theory, Democracy and Legal Change reexamines the relationship between democracy and the rule of law from a new, and often surprising, set of vantage points.