ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

Recently, there has been a lot of enthusiasm for mindfulness practice and its use in healthcare, businesses and schools. An increasing number of studies give us ground for cautious optimism about the potential of mindfulness-based interventions (MBIs) to improve people's lives across a number of dimensions. This paper identifies and addresses some of the main ethical and political questions for larger-scale MBIs. First, how far are MBIs compatible with liberal neutrality given the great diversity of lifestyles and conceptions of the good characteristic of modern societies? It will be argued that the potential benefits of contemporary secular mindfulness practice are indeed of a sufficiently primary or all-purpose nature to qualify as suitable goals of liberal public policy. Second, what challenges are brought up if mindfulness is used in contexts and applications-such as military settings-whose goals seem incompatible with the ethical and soteriological views of traditional mindfulness practice? It will be argued that, given concerns regarding liberal neutrality and reasonable disagreement about ethics, MBIs should avoid strong ethical commitments. Therefore, it should, in principle, be applicable in contexts of controversial moral value. Finally, drawing on recent discussions within the mindfulness community, it is argued that we should not overstate the case for mindfulness and not crowd out discussion of organisational and social determinants of stress, lowered well-being, and mental illness and the collective measures necessary to address them.
PAPER
The ethics and politics of mindfulness-based
interventions
Andreas T Schmidt
Correspondence to
Dr Andreas T Schmidt,
University Center for Human
Values/Woodrow Wilson
School, Princeton University,
315 Wallace Hall, Princeton,
NJ 8544, USA;
andreas.schmidt@princeton.
edu, andreastschmidt@gmail.
com
Received 9 June 2015
Revised 2 March 2016
Accepted 31 March 2016
Published Online First
20 April 2016
To cite: Schmidt AT. J Med
Ethics 2016;42:450454.
ABSTRACT
Recently, there has been a lot of enthusiasm for
mindfulness practice and its use in healthcare,
businesses and schools. An increasing number of studies
give us ground for cautious optimism about the potential
of mindfulness-based interventions (MBIs) to improve
peoples lives across a number of dimensions. This paper
identies and addresses some of the main ethical and
political questions for larger-scale MBIs. First, how far
are MBIs compatible with liberal neutrality given the
great diversity of lifestyles and conceptions of the good
characteristic of modern societies? It will be argued that
the potential benets of contemporary secular
mindfulness practice are indeed of a sufciently primary
or all-purpose nature to qualify as suitable goals of
liberal public policy. Second, what challenges are
brought up if mindfulness is used in contexts and
applicationssuch as military settingswhose goals
seem incompatible with the ethical and soteriological
views of traditional mindfulness practice? It will be
argued that, given concerns regarding liberal neutrality
and reasonable disagreement about ethics, MBIs should
avoid strong ethical commitments. Therefore, it should,
in principle, be applicable in contexts of controversial
moral value. Finally, drawing on recent discussions
within the mindfulness community, it is argued that we
should not overstate the case for mindfulness and not
crowd out discussion of organisational and social
determinants of stress, lowered well-being, and mental
illness and the collective measures necessary to address
them.
INTRODUCTION
Recently, there has been a lot of enthusiasm for
mindfulness practice and its use in healthcare, busi-
ness and education. Increasing empirical evidence
makes mindfulness-based interventions (MBIs)
seem promising across a broad range of applica-
tions, particularly so for the treatment and preven-
tion of anxiety and depression. This paper
introduces some of the ethical and political issues
surrounding MBIs to academic population-level
bioethics.
i
Particularly, it discusses how far such
interventions are compatible with liberal neutrality;
how far it is a problem that mindfulness is applied
in settings whose goals are incompatible with the
ethics of traditional mindfulness practice; and what
role such initiatives should play in situations in
which stress and mental illness have social
determinants.
MINDFULNESS AND ITS BENEFITS
Although contemporary secular mindfulness prac-
tice draws in important ways on the Buddhist trad-
ition, I will distinguish between Buddhist
mindfulness and contemporary mindfulness prac-
tice.
2
The term mindfulnessencompasses a range
of concepts and practices, all of which have import-
ant aspects in common but also differ in signicant
ways.
3
A core idea of contemporary mindfulness is
bare attention, the state of mind and metacognitive
skill of directing attention towards, and being
receptive to, whatever is happening in the present
moment both externally and internally. Bare atten-
tion is usually combined with the attitude of non-
judging acceptance, of being curious and accepting
towards thoughts and experiences as they occur.
Mindfulness-based stress reduction (MBSR) was
originally developed by John Kabat-Zinn as a
group intervention to assist patients with chronic
pain.
45
Taught in an 8 week course, MBSR typic-
ally includes body scanning, simple yoga poses and
mindfulness meditation exercises. Mindfulness-
based cognitive therapy (MBCT) combines MBSR
with elements of cognitive therapy. MBCTwas ori-
ginally designed to prevent relapse in patients with
remitting depression.
67
One of the aims is to see
negative thoughts as mental events instead of
taking them at face value so as to prevent that such
thoughts have dysphoric effects. Similar to MBSR,
MBCT is usually taught in an 8 week course.
Besides MBSR and MBCT, other methods exist
that integrate mindfulness with other measures.
ii
MBIs are used in the treatment of depression,
anxiety and relapse prevention.
1012
A growing
number of studies also look at other benets of
mindfulness, including, but not limited to, its bene-
ts in terms of emotion regulation;
13
its use for the
treatment of substance abuse, problem gambling
and binge eating;
14 15
and its use for the treatment
of somatic conditions such as chronic pain.
5
Encouraging results have also been reported regard-
ing the benets of MBSR for healthy individuals.
16
Overall, effectiveness studies of MBIs show prom-
ising results across a number of applications. There
is good evidence that MBIs are effective in the treat-
ment of depression, anxiety and relapse preven-
tion.
1012
Increasing evidence has led the National
i
Some work has been done on ethical questions arising at
the individual level, for example, those confronting
mindfulness teachers.
1
ii
Such as Acceptance and Commitment Theory
8
and
Dialectical Behaviour Therapy.
9
450 Schmidt AT. J Med Ethics 2016;42:450454. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102942
Public health ethics
Institute for Health and Care Excellence in the UK to recom-
mend MBIs for the treatment of patients with three or more epi-
sodes of depression.
iii
There is also reason to believe that MBIs
might be effective for a number of other psychological conditions
and have benets for healthy individuals. MBIs are therefore also
gaining popularity outside medical contexts, such as mindfulness
programmes for schools,
17
businesses and prisons.
18
Overall, existing empirical studies give us reason to be opti-
mistic about the potential of MBIs to reduce stress, deal with
psychological conditions and increase well-being. In this paper, I
will assume there is sufcient reason for cautious optimism
about the effectiveness of MBIs as well as sufcient reason to
start thinking about the ethical and political questions that MBIs
might bring up. I will not assume that questions regarding the
effectiveness of MBIs are settled or that we have a very clear
sense of the precise magnitude of its potential benets.
Effectiveness is of course a central element for an overall
ethical evaluation of MBIs. But there are other ethical and polit-
ical questions that MBIs might bring up to which I will turn
now.
LIBERAL NEUTRALITY
One set of worries concerns the question as to whether MBIs
constitute an illegitimate promotion of a particular worldview
or way of life. This is illustrated by criticism that has been
voiced when some schools in the USA and other countries
started integrating MBIs in their curricula. One of the most
common objections is that mindfulness practice is a religious
practice in disguise and thus has no place in secular educa-
tion.
1923
In a number of cases, parentsobjections have led
schools to discontinue their mindfulness programmes. In the
USA, it is unconstitutional to teach religious practice in public
schools. Pupils also do not have much choice over whether they
want to participate in such mindfulness practices or not. So,
worries about the historical religious roots of MBIs arise rst
and foremost in educational settings, particularly for public
schools. To some extent, however, similar worries might also
arise for MBIs in healthcare settings. We might worry about
publicly funded healthcare systems, such as the National Health
Service in the UK, using MBIs as standard treatments to
promote particular ways of living. Besides their religious roots,
MBIs also seem a potentially very far-reaching and intrusive
type of treatment. Mindfulness practice is supposed to be inte-
grated throughout the day, potentially turning even trivial activ-
itiessuch as brushing your teethinto mindful activities. By
changing the way you think,MBIs try to change the way you
live. This makes MBIs, in a sense, more intrusive and far-
reaching than other treatments. For example, prescribing medi-
cation, or incentivising smoking cessation, does not require a
change in how people think and how they go about their daily
business.
Finally, similar worries might arise, though again to a lesser
extent, when mindfulness programmes are made mandatory for
employees in private companies, particularly if these companies
have diverse workforces. We might worry about companies
exercising too much inuence over how employees should lead
their livesparticularly outside of work.
Underlying these worries might be the belief that it is not the
business of such institutions, particularly state institutions, to
promote particular lifestyles or conceptions of the good.
Philosophically, this can be expressed by a concern with liberal
neutrality: public policies should not aim to promote particular
conceptions of the good and in justifying institutions and public
policy we should only rely on reasons acceptable to people with
differing (reasonable) conceptions of the good.
24 25 iv
A strong
version of liberal neutrality would hold that a policy is strictly
impermissible, if it conicts with liberal neutrality. However,
such a strong form is typically considered implausible, even by
those working within the liberal tradition.
2729
I will thus
assume, for the sake of argument, that while neutrality is desir-
able, a concern for neutrality can be overridden by other norma-
tive considerations.
30
Accordingly, if MBIs were in conict with
liberal neutrality, this would be a consideration but not necessar-
ily a decisive argument against MBIs.
I will now argue that including MBIs in schools, healthcare
settings and organisational settings is compatible with a concern
for neutrality. Discussing this point will also give us good reason
to promote strongly secular and axiologically thinversions of
mindfulness practicesomething that will prove important in
following sections.
First, as mentioned above, many worry about the Buddhist
roots of mindfulness. Liberal neutrality implies that the state
should not promote particular religions. However, this
oft-expressed worry is not a problem for contemporary mind-
fulness practice. While MBIs in healthcare and schools draw on
and resemble traditional Buddhist meditative practices in
various ways, they do not make any metaphysical or religious
assumptions and are specically designed to be secular.
Second, the goal of MBIs is to introduce mindfulness into all
areas of ones life. So, while not promoting a particular religion,
one might worry that MBIs promote a particular spiritual and/
or meditative lifestyle. But, again, these worries are unfounded
for contemporary versions of mindfulness as used in schools,
businesses and healthcare settings. While MBIs include medita-
tion exercises, these exercises are not meant to replace other
activities we might nd valuable. Instead, by incorporating tech-
niques into everyday life and by strengthening particular meta-
cognitive skills, mindfulness aims to facilitate (among other
things) that people are receptive to and aware of the experiences
they have in the present moment. Whatever ones activities and
goals, MBIs are intended to help people pursue them in a more
focused manner, experience them more directly and often enjoy
them more. Importantly, MBIs are not intended to replace our
current activities or projects with meditation or spirituality. So,
while MBIs might have far-reaching effects on peoples lives, it
is compatible with a very broad range of lifestyles and not at all
committed to a spiritual, meditative or self-denying lifestyle.
Third, many liberals believe that the state should not be in
the business of making people happy. A worry about promot-
ing mindfulness, particularly in healthy populations, might be
that it seems that the stateor other public institutions or
iii
National Institute of Clinical Excellence (2004). Depression:
Management of Depression in Primary and Secondary Care. National
Clinical Practice Guidelines, Number 23. London, HMSO. Updated
2009.
iv
Neutrality is typically considered to be about state policies.
Accordingly, worries apply rst and foremost to MBIs in public
education and, to a lesser extent, publicly nanced healthcare.
Nonetheless, while maybe not a strong justice constraintfor private
social institutions (eg, businesses), neutrality might still be valuable.
(Alternatively, we could hold that such institutions are part of the
Rawlsian basic structureor reject the idea that concerns of justice apply
only to the basic structure.
26
I will not try to solve these complex issues
here.)
Schmidt AT. J Med Ethics 2016;42:450454. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102942 451
Public health ethics
corporationstakes it upon itself to make people happier.Does
this not seem like smuggling utilitarianism (or some form of
perfectionism) in through the backdoor? I think we can address
this worry without committing ourselves to utilitarianism or
perfectionism. Rawlsian liberals often believe that the goods
provided by just institutions and public policy should be such
that individuals have reason to want them whatever their
respective reasonable conception of the good (so-called primary
goods).
31
I think it is plausible to believe that the psychological
skills and benets potentially facilitated through MBIs are of
such an all-purpose or primary nature. Some of the presumed
benets relevant in this context are reduced anxiety, less stress,
better emotion regulation, improved interpersonal skills, better
attention and improved self-esteem.
13 32
These benets will
improve ones ability to pursue ones conception of the good
more or lesswhatever the precise content of that conception
might be. Therefore, if the psychological all-purpose benets of
mindfulness are real, they seem compatible with neutrality. This
also means we have reason to pursue MBIs, even if we do not
believe that the state (or private companies) should try to make
people happy.
Finally, we might worry that mindfulness promotion fails the
neutrality test, because it carries a certain ethical message. It is
sometimes argued that liberal neutrality also implies being
neutral on a class of ethical questions that are not considered
part of justice but to be decided within a persons comprehen-
sive view of the good (ones view on abortion is sometimes
given as an example). Is mindfulness committed to specic
ethical commitments that should be left to individuals to
decide? Here, we should again distinguish between more trad-
itional Buddhist practices and contemporary secular approaches.
Buddhism often includes relatively specic ethical prescriptions
(such as not to work in the meat industry). Contemporary
approaches, on the other hand, are not committed to substan-
tive ethical standards about what is good, bad, right or wrong.
While such practices often include compassion exercises, I think
the ability to be compassionate and mindful of those around
one should again be considered a general moral and social skill
rather than a particular, contentious ethical viewpoint.
So, overall, MBIs do not seem committed to any contentious
conception of the good. Instead, they can provide psychological
goods of an all-purpose or primary nature.
However, one might object that while the benets of MBIs
are potentially valuable for the great majority of conceptions of
the good, they might still be incompatible with some very spe-
cic conceptions. Imagine, for example, your conception of the
good requires overthinking everything and leading a life of
anxiety and constant self-doubt. Think of the character George
Costanza in the sitcom Seinfeld, for example. Now, mindfulness
practice does seem incompatible with such a lifestyle. Is this a
problem?
To answer this worry, consider different ways in which theor-
ists spell out liberal neutrality.
First, effect neutrality requires that policies not have the effect
of making one particular conception of the good more successful
or widespread than another. Successful MBIs are indeed incom-
patible with effect neutrality, as they are likely to reduce the
number of people leading lives like George Costanza (or other
mindlesslifestyles). However, in the literature, effect neutrality
is typically considered an implausible rendering of neutrality. It
would rule out too many policies we intuitively believe should
not be ruled out by a concern for neutrality. For very rarely do
public policies have the effect of preserving the exact proportion
of followers for different conceptions of the good.
30
Second, an alternative rendering is neutrality of procedure:
public policies should be justied without appealing to the intrin-
sic superiority of any particular conception of the good life.
24
Do
MBIs full neutrality of procedure? Above I argued that the poten-
tial benets of mindfulness are valuable across a very broad range
of conceptions of the good. Accordingly, with respect to these con-
ceptions of the good, we need not make contentious assumptions
regarding their intrinsic value. But nor do we have to assume that
mindlesslifestyles are intrinsically worse. For MBIs typically
leave it to the individual to pursue mindfulness or not.
Mindfulness practice is in some respect similar to exercise: doing
mindfulness regularly and incorporating it into oneslifeisnot
easy and requires effort and persistence. If you do not want to
practice itand prefer a mindlesslifeMBIs will not impose
any meaningful obstacles. This holds even if MBIs are a mandatory
part of a school curriculum. For even then, whether you adopt
mindfulness as part of your lifestyle is largely voluntary, as being
mindful requires effort and practice. So, the justication of MBIs
could simply be that it enhances opportunities to pursue concep-
tions of the good for a very broad range of conceptions of the
good while also leaving it open to the individual to pursue other,
incompatible lifestyles. Such a justication foregrounds the
opportunity-enhancing aspect of MBIs and does not assume that
one conception of the good is superior to another.
Third, neutrality of aims requires that public policies not
intentionally aim to favour or disfavour specic (reasonable)
conceptions of the good. MBIs are compatible with this render-
ing of neutrality for the same reasons proffered above: rst, the
aim of MBIs is to extend opportunities to pursue conceptions
of the goodmore or lesswhatever those conceptions are;
second, MBIs do not intentionally disfavour mindless lifestyles
in an objectionable way, because they leave it to the individual
whether to pursue mindfulness or not.
Finally, treatment neutrality requires that policies not treat dif-
ferent people and their conceptions of the good differently by
placing disproportional obstacles or by providing disproportional
resources to one conception over another.
30
Here, we would
again hold that while MBIs promote opportunities to pursue a
very broad range of conceptions of the good, they do not make it
signicantly difcult to pursue conceptions of the good incom-
patible with mindfulness. Because pursing a mindful life requires
effort and persistence, MBIs do not impose signicant or dispro-
portionate burdens on those wishing to lead mindlesslives.
Overall, MBIs, even those used in public schools, are compat-
ible with liberal neutrality. MBIs might contribute towards
primary psychological skills and benets that are valuable
more or lesswhatever ones life plans might be. This also gives
us reason to keep MBIs religiously, axiologically and ethically
non-committal so as to accommodate concerns of diversity and
liberal neutrality, something that will prove relevant for the
objections I discuss now.
MCMINDFULNESS
Recently, some strong criticism of contemporary mindfulness
practice has come from within the mindfulness community. The
charge is that contemporary mindfulness leaves out too much
of the original ethical and soteriological elements of Buddhist
practices necessary for right mindfulness. Contemporary mindful-
nessthusturnsanoldandrichworldviewintoMcMindfulness’—
a watered-down marketable fashion fad bearing little resemblance
to its Buddhist origin.
23334
There are, at least, three different ways to read such criticism.
First, we might understand it simply as the charge that con-
temporary mindfulness is insufciently true to its Buddhist
452 Schmidt AT. J Med Ethics 2016;42:450454. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102942
Public health ethics
origins. I hope the discussion on liberal neutrality shows that
rather than being a problem, this should be considered a posi-
tive feature. To promote mindfulness in health policy and
diverse educational and organisational contexts makes religious,
axiological and ethical neutrality desirable.
Second, maybe the objection is rather that such watering
down comes at a cost, namely that contemporary mindfulness is
less effective than Buddhist mindfulness. Monteiro et al
2
argue
that contemporary mindfulness offers at best symptomatic relief,
whereas traditional mindfulness approaches liberation from suf-
fering through a path of ardent practice focused on understand-
ing and uprooting the fundamental causes of suffering. Such a
claim might be true. But it is hard to assess without empirical
evidence. As argued above, contemporary mindfulness should
not in principle be constrained in its development by Buddhist
tradition. But, of course, that does not mean that traditional
mindfulness might not continue to be a source of inspiration that
can be integrated into new evidence-based secular practices.
35
Third, maybe moving away from Buddhist tradition comes at
a different cost, namely that MBIs are being used for unethical
purposes.
36
One discussion revolves around the adaptation of
mindfulness techniques to military contexts, something that
seems at odds with Buddhist ethics. How should we respond
when mindfulness is used for purposes that conict with
Buddhist ethical tenets? The main problem is that there is great
disagreement surrounding matters of morality. For example,
most people believe that sometimes the use of military force is
justied. Others disagree. Also, many believe it to be morally
permissible to work in the alcohol industry (which many
Buddhists will not). It is unlikely we will reach agreement on
these issues any time soon. But this does not imply that we
should not use mindfulness in contemporary pluralist societies
to improve the lives of even those who work for organisations
of controversial moral value. As seen earlier in my discussion of
neutrality, we have good reason for MBIs to be somewhat non-
committalto ensure that MBIs are widely applicable.
Moreover, there is little reason to expect that promoting con-
temporary mindfulness will make people do more bad than
good on balance. If anything, preliminary evidence suggests that
contemporary mindfulness practice can improve ethical
decision-making.
37 38
THE POLITICS OF MINDFULNESS
A more systematic objection to the recent mindfulness trend is
that mindfulness in its stripped-down contemporary form can
be instrumentalised to keep exploitative, stressful or otherwise
unhealthy conditions alive. Writing on the use of mindfulness in
corporate settings, Purser and Loy hold:
Curiously, the mindfulness movement has yet to engage in ser-
iously questioning as to why stress is so pervasive in modern cor-
porations. Instead, corporations have jumped on the mindfulness
bandwagon because it conveniently shifts the burden on to the
individual employee; stress is framed as a personal problem, and
mindfulness-based interventions are offered as means of helping
employees cope and work more effectively and calmly within
such toxic environments.
39
Presumably, precarious employment situations, longer work
hours, more inequality, less stable social ties and so on might all
result in reduced well-being, more stress and higher prevalence
of mental illness. Mindfulness, it could be argued, is being
instrumentalised as a coping mechanism for issues whose real
(or morally relevant) aetiology lies elsewhere. At its worst,
mindfulness might shift the burden of responsibility towards the
individual and might even lull them into accepting inhospitable
social conditions.
This objection can be interpreted in different ways. We might
rst interpret it as saying that promoting individual mindfulness
practice makes matters worse, because it prevents necessary
social change. Marxists, for example, often believe that religion
and spiritual practice are part of the superstructurethe opium
of the people’—that prevent rather than instigate real social
change. Writing from an epidemiological (not a Marxist) per-
spective, Pickett and Wilkinson argue that growing social
inequality is an important driver of stress and mental illness. In
a spirit similar to the above objectionthough writing on a dif-
ferent topicthey argue:
The solution to problems caused by inequality is not mass psy-
chotherapy [or in our case: mass mindfulness intervention] aimed
at making everyone less vulnerable. The best way of responding
to the harm done by high levels of inequality would be to reduce
inequality itself.
40
Similarly, is it not fundamentally wrong-headed to try to
solve social ills through mindfulness promotion? While I think
the worry about instrumentalising mindfulness is serious, this
should make us reect on how rather than whether we should
promote mindfulness.
First, MBIs cannot be the only measure to deal with stress,
mental illness and so on. But promoting mindfulness is of
course compatible with also promoting wider social change.
This is indeed a good argument not to overstate the role and
effectiveness of mindfulness. While mindfulness promotion is a
plausible part of a mix of policies, presenting it as a panacea
might risk either undermining its credibility or crowd out a dis-
course about necessary social change.
Second, even if the above argumentthat we should look pri-
marily to the systematic drivers of stress and mental illnessis
correct, this does not mean there is no independent role for
mindfulness (and other similar interventions). Even in a social
utopia, most people would still experience personal hardships
and stress at some point in their lives. If mindfulness helps deal
with hardships and provides individuals with psychological all-
purpose benets, then we have good reasons to consider its pro-
motion. This gives us a strong response to a Marxistcritique
of mindfulness.
v
But we can also understand the objection differently: if mind-
fulness were practiced in richer and ethically committed ways,
as it was originally intended by Buddhists, mindfulness itself
would have the potential to be socially transformative. The
recent watered-down versions of mindfulness are problematic,
precisely because they undermine the potential that Buddhist
mindfulness has to transform problematic social conditions.
39 42
How should we evaluate this critique? First, it is of course an
open empirical question as to whether Buddhist mindfulness
actually has such transformative potential. This is hard to deter-
mine from the philosophical armchair. But, second, I think it is
a methodological mistake to expect Buddhism to provide us
with the moral and explanatory resources to identify our social
ills as well as the psychological and social toolkit to address
them. I think it preferable to keep MBIs ethically and axiologi-
cally non-committal while also drawing on secular social
v
Moreover, some of the drivers of stresssuch as a growing number of
distractions and choicesmight also have benets worth keeping.
Learning how to nd peace in a frantic world
41
might thus also help
one reap the benets that come from the world being frantic.
Schmidt AT. J Med Ethics 2016;42:450454. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102942 453
Public health ethics
science, psychology, epidemiology and philosophy to help us
identify and address social ills. Finally, our worry about diversity
and liberal neutrality resurfaces again. If we seek the promotion
of mindfulness as a matter of public policy or in business envir-
onments with diverse workforces, we have good reason not to
commit ourselves to substantial ethical and soteriological views.
This will of course not solve all our social problems. But expect-
ing mindfulness promotion to affect great social change in con-
temporary pluralist societies might strike one as unrealistic in
the rst place. Achieving modest yet signicant improvements of
peoples lives through MBIs, on the other hand, might be a real
possibility.
CONCLUSIONS
Mindfulness interventions hold good promise as public policy
measure to improve peoples lives across a number of dimen-
sions. I have discussed two main areas in which ethical and pol-
itical questions arise. First, is mindfulness promotion compatible
with liberal neutrality? I have argued that it is, if we avoid tying
mindfulness to any specic views on ethics, religion and the
good life. The potential psychological benets of mindfulness
even qualify as psychological all-purposegoods such that one
has reason to want them, more or less, whatever the content of
ones conception of the good life. Second, a number of ques-
tions arise about the role of mindfulness interventions in their
social, political and economic setting. In promoting mindful-
ness, we should be careful not to overstate its case and not to
crowd out discussion of other ( particularly social) causes of
stress, lowered well-being and mental illness. So, there is ample
reason to be hopeful about the benets of mindfulness interven-
tions. But the current hype around it should not make us less
mindful of inhospitable social conditions and the collective mea-
sures necessary to address them.
Acknowledgements I thank Diana Heney, Hasko von Kriegstein, Dragos Petrescu,
and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments.
Competing interests None declared.
Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
REFERENCES
1 McCown D. The ethical space of mindfulness in clinical practice: an exploratory
essay. Jessica Kingsley Publishers, 2013.
2 Monteiro LM, Musten RF, Compson J. Traditional and contemporary mindfulness:
nding the middle path in the tangle of concerns. Mindfulness 2014;6:113.
3 Bishop SR, Lau M, Shapiro S, et al. Mindfulness: a proposed operational denition.
Clin Psychol Sci Pract 2004;11:23041.
4 Kabat-Zinn J. An outpatient program in behavioral medicine for chronic pain
patients based on the practice of mindfulness meditation: theoretical considerations
and preliminary results. Gen Hosp Psychiatry 1982;4:3347.
5Kabat-ZinnJ.Full catastrophe living (revised edition): using the wisdom of your body
and mind to face stress, pain, and illness. Random House Publishing Group, 2013.
6 Coffman SJ, Dimidjian S, Baer RA. Mindfulness-based cognitive theory for prevention
of depressive relapse. In: Baer RA, ed. Mindfulness-based treatment approaches:
clinicians guide to evidence base and applications. Academic Press, 2005.
7 Segal ZV, Williams JMG, Teasdale JD. Mindfulness-based cognitive therapy for
depression: a new approach to preventing relapse. Guilford Press, 2002.
8 Hayes SC, Strosahl KD, Wilson KG. Acceptance and commitment therapy, second
edition: the process and practice of mindful change. Guilford Press, 2011.
9 Linehan M. Cognitive-behavioral treatment of borderline personality disorder.
Guilford Press, 1993.
10 Hofmann SG, Sawyer AT, Witt AA, et al. The effect of mindfulness-based therapy on
anxiety and depression: a meta-analytic review. J Consult Clin Psychol
2010;78:16983.
11 Khoury B, Lecomte T, Fortin G, et al. Mindfulness-based therapy: a comprehensive
meta-analysis. Clin Psychol Rev 2013;33:76371.
12 Piet J, Hougaard E. The effect of mindfulness-based cognitive therapy for prevention
of relapse in recurrent major depressive disorder: a systematic review and
meta-analysis. Clin Psychol Rev 2011;31:103240.
13 Brown KW, Ryan RM. The benets of being present: mindfulness and its role in
psychological well-being. J Pers Soc Psychol 2003;84:82248.
14 de Lisle SM, Dowling NA, Allen JS. Mindfulness and problem gambling: a review of
the literature. J Gambl Stud 2012;28:71939.
15 Witkiewitz K, Bowen S, Douglas H, et al. Mindfulness-based relapse prevention for
substance craving. Addict Behav 2013;38:156371.
16 Khoury B, Sharma M, Rush SE, et al. Mindfulness-based stress reduction for healthy
individuals: a meta-analysis. J Psychosom Res 2015;78:51928.
17 Burke CA. Mindfulness-based approaches with children and adolescents:
a preliminary review of current research in an emergent eld. J Child Fam Stud
2009;19:13344.
18 Shonin E, Van Gordon W, Slade K, et al. Mindfulness and other Buddhist-derived
interventions in correctional settings: a systematic review. Aggress Violent Behav
2013;18:36572.
19 Brown CG. Mindfulness Meditation in Public Schools: Side-Stepping Supreme Court
Religion Rulings. Hufngton Post. 2014. http://www.hufngtonpost.com/
candy-gunther-brown-phd/mindfulness-meditation-in_b_6276968.html (accessed
22 Oct 2015).
20 McDonagh M. The cult of mindfulness.The Spectator. http://new.spectator.co.uk/
2014/11/whats-wrong-with-mindfulness-more-than-you-might-think/ (accessed
22 Oct 2015).
21 Warsmith S. Plain Township school stops mindfulnessprogram after some in
community raise concerns. http://www.ohio.com. http://www.ohio.com/news/plain-
township-school-stops-mindfulness-program-after-some-in-community-raise-concerns-1.
389761 (accessed 22 Oct 2015).
22 Gregorie C. Parents Up In Arms Over School DistrictsEasternMindfulness
Program. Hufngton Post. 2013. http://www.hufngtonpost.com/2013/04/17/
warstler-elementary-school-ohio-mindfulness-program_n_3101741.html (accessed
28 Dec 2015).
23 Brown CG, Santorelli S. Does Mindfulness Belong in Public Schools? Tricycle. http://
www.tricycle.com/feature/does-mindfulness-belong-public-schools (accessed 1 Feb
2016).
24 Larmore CE. Patterns of moral complexity. Cambridge University Press, 1987.
25 Rawls J. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.
26 Cohen GA. Where the action is: on the site of distributive justice. Philos Public Aff
1997;26:330.
27 Raz J. The morality of freedom. Oxford University Press, 1986.
28 Sher G. Beyond neutrality: perfectionism and politics. Cambridge University Press,
1997.
29 Wall S. Liberalism, perfectionism and restraint. Cambridge University Press, 1998.
30 Patten A. Liberal neutrality: a reinterpretation and defense*. J Polit Philos
2012;20:24972.
31 Rawls J. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971.
32 Randal C, Pratt D, Bucci S. Mindfulness and self-esteem: a systematic review.
Mindfulness 2015;113.
33 Purser RE, Loy D. Beyond McMindfulness. Hufngton Post. 2013. http://www.
hufngtonpost.com/ron-purser/beyond-mcmindfulness_b_3519289.html (accessed
14 Apr 2015).
34 Safran JD. McMindfulness. Psychol. Today. 2014. http://www.psychologytoday.com/
blog/straight-talk/201406/mcmindfulness (accessed 4 May 2015).
35 Lindahl JR. Why right mindfulness might not be right for mindfulness. Mindfulness
2014;6:5762.
36 Titmuss C. The Buddha of Mindfulness. A Stress Destruction Programme. 2013. http://
christophertitmuss.org/blog/the-buddha-of-mindfulness-the-politics-of-mindfulness
(accessed 4 May 2015).
37 Ruedy NE, Schweitzer ME. In the moment: the effect of mindfulness on ethical
decision making. J Bus Ethics 2011;95:7387.
38 Shapiro SL, Jazaieri H, Goldin PR. Mindfulness-based stress reduction effects on
moral reasoning and decision making. J Posit Psychol 2012;7:50415.
39 Purser RE, Milillo J. Mindfulness revisited a Buddhist-based conceptualization.
J Manag Inq 2015;24:324.
40 Wilkinson RG, Pickett K. The spirit level: why equality is better for everyone.
Penguin Books, 2010.
41 Williams M, Penman D. Mindfulness: an eight-week plan for nding peace in a
frantic world. Rodale, 2012.
42 Healey K. Searching for integrity: the politics of mindfulness in the digital economy.
Nomos Journal 2013. http://nomosjournal.org/2013/08/searching-for-integrity/
(accessed 4 May 2015).
454 Schmidt AT. J Med Ethics 2016;42:450454. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102942
Public health ethics
... 1-13;Stanley 2015, pp. 89-113;Schmidt 2016). In certain situations, mindfulness can thus be utilized for aims alien if not contradictory to Buddhist ethical teachings or practices, such as soldiers developing their military skills, which has been termed "the mindful sniper" (Vörös 2016, p. 7;Bruyea 2017). ...
Article
Full-text available
The Republic of Ireland has undergone a seismic religious and social transformation in recent decades. Through the processes of secularization and detraditionalization, as well as several major scandals within the Irish Catholic Church, irreligiosity has become an increasing reality in terms of the hitherto overwhelmingly Catholic population. At a time of spiritual climate change in this post-Catholic Ireland, the contemporary phenomenon of mindfulness has exploded in popularity across various elements of society. Against this backdrop, three distinctive modes or strands of mindfulness are proposed as being operative in the Irish context, each catering to the needs of different practitioners. The proposed modes include psychological and clinical mindfulness and commodified and post-secular spirituality. Within the lacuna created by the receding of Catholic belief and practice, the emergence of mindfulness in the Irish context is explored, mapping how this originally Buddhist practice has gained such a foothold in contemporary spiritual discourse.
... This question becomes particularly acute in today's diverse societies where individuals often have very different conceptions of the good. 39 While some ethical guidelines, such as doing no harm and speaking the truth, might be uncontroversial and justifiable from a broad range of ethical belief systems, ethical guidelines in traditional yoga can be far-reaching, ranging from a duty to refrain from eating meat, sexual intercourse, indulgent eating and drinking, and a duty to retreat from public life completely and refrain from all worldly desires. Modern guidebooks on yoga often contain detailed descriptions of these ethical guidelines, such as specific practices for personal hygiene, diet, and fasting. ...
... The third theme, labelled 'Heterogeneous McMindfulness' explores how Kabat Zinn's traditional mindfulness-based stress reduction (MBSR) format is compromised in response to conflicting organisational needs (Eby et al., 2019). The fourth theme suggested that employees and managers experience practical hurdles to the practice, such as noisy workplaces, workload, and time constraints Schmidt, 2016;Eby et al., 2017). The fifth and final theme suggests a 'Vicious Circle'. ...
Chapter
This chapter explores developing and implementing mindfulness-based interventions (MBIs) tailored for entrepreneurs to reduce stress and enhance well-being. Recognizing the unique challenges faced by entrepreneurs, the chapter examines the theoretical foundations of mindfulness and its relevance to entrepreneurship. It outlines practical strategies for creating effective MBIs, including considerations for diverse populations and the integration of technology. The chapter also discusses the importance of measuring the effectiveness of these interventions and addresses potential challenges, such as participant resistance and sustainability of practices. By highlighting future directions for research, practice, and policy, this chapter aims to contribute to a deeper understanding of how mindfulness can transform entrepreneurial experiences, foster resilience and promote a healthier entrepreneurial ecosystem.
Chapter
This chapter examines the transformative advantages of incorporating mindfulness and meditation into educational environments. It emphasizes cognitive function, emotional regulation, and attention improvements, promoting resilience and a positive outlook. In addition to their impact on academic performance, these practices foster general welfare and inspiration. Individuals who are emotionally resilient, socially proficient, and intrinsically motivated result from the long-term effects. It promotes the adoption of mindfulness among educators, emphasizing serving as a role model for students and cultivating an all-encompassing educational methodology. To equip students with the means to envision a more promising and resilient future, educators are encouraged to persist by modifying instructional methods, given the apparent benefits.
Article
Full-text available
This essay delves into the multifaceted concept of resilience in the context of the workplace, exploring its implications for individuals' emotional well-being. Resilience, a recognized quality in psychology, empowers individuals to navigate stress, adversity, and trauma. In the realm of employment, it serves as a pivotal indicator of an applicant's ability to manage workplace stress. However, the essay contends that both inadequate and excessive resilience can lead to detrimental outcomes. Therefore, the pursuit of a well-rounded and moderate form of resilience, through effective leadership, communication, and support resources, is key to maintaining a healthy work environment that values resilience while acknowledging its limitations and ensures both individual well-being and sustained organizational success.
Chapter
This chapter provides a comprehensive overview of the ethical considerations involved in teaching mindfulness to children and adolescents. It begins by examining the debate surrounding the transformation of a traditional Buddhist meditative practice into a secular mindfulness program. Subsequently, it delves into a discussion of ethical concerns within four key areas, the development of program content, implementation of the program, teacher training and development, and awareness of the potential misuse of mindfulness practices by participants. Furthermore, the chapter identifies areas that require attention for the advancement of MBPs and suggests avenues for further research.
Article
Full-text available
Interest in applications of mindfulness-based approaches with adults has grown rapidly in recent times, and there is an expanding research base that suggests these are efficacious approaches to promoting psychological health and well-being. Interest has spread to applications of mindfulness-based approaches with children and adolescents, yet the research is still in its infancy. I aim to provide a preliminary review of the current research base of mindfulness-based approaches with children and adolescents, focusing on MBSR/MBCT models, which place the regular practice of mindfulness meditation at the core of the intervention. Overall, the current research base provides support for the feasibility of mindfulness-based interventions with children and adolescents, however there is no generalized empirical evidence of the efficacy of these interventions. For the field to advance, I suggest that research needs to shift away from feasibility studies towards large, well-designed studies with robust methodologies, and adopt standardized formats for interventions, allowing for replication and comparison studies, to develop a firm research evidence base. KeywordsMindfulness meditation-Children-Adolescents-Families-Schools
Book
Many people, including many contemporary philosophers, believe that the state has no business trying to improve people's characters, elevating their tastes, or preventing them from living degraded lives. They believe that governments should remain absolutely neutral when it comes to the consideration of competing conceptions of the good. One fundamental aim of George Sher's book is to show that this view is indefensible. A second complementary aim is to articulate a conception of the good that is worthy of promotion by the state. The first part of the book analyses attempts to ground the neutrality thesis in the value of autonomy, respect for autonomy, the dangers of a non-neutral state, and scepticism about the good. The second part defends an objective conception of the good which remains sensitive to some of the considerations that make subjectivism attractive.
Book
Since the original publication of this seminal work, acceptance and commitment therapy (ACT) has come into its own as a widely practiced approach to helping people change. This book provides the definitive statement of ACT—from conceptual and empirical foundations to clinical techniques—written by its originators. ACT is based on the idea that psychological rigidity is a root cause of a wide range of clinical problems. The authors describe effective, innovative ways to cultivate psychological flexibility by detecting and targeting six key processes: defusion, acceptance, attention to the present moment, self-awareness, values, and committed action. Sample therapeutic exercises and patient–therapist dialogues are integrated throughout. New to This Edition *Reflects tremendous advances in ACT clinical applications, theory building, and research. *Psychological flexibility is now the central organizing focus. *Expanded coverage of mindfulness, the therapeutic relationship, relational learning, and case formulation. *Restructured to be more clinician friendly and accessible; focuses on the moment-by-moment process of therapy.
Chapter
Mindfulness-based cognitive therapy (MBCT) is an 8-week group protocol, which is developed to prevent the relapse of depression episodes in future. MBCT is based on a theoretical model that describes factors contributing to vulnerability to relapse and recurrence of major depression and the efficiency of cognitive therapy in reducing this vulnerability. MBCT combines mindfulness strategies with traditional cognitive behavioral strategies for treatment. It is designed to help patients with histories of depression and prevent the relapse and recurrence of depression in the future. MBCT provides a cost-effective approach for relapse prevention in patients whose previous episode was treated with antidepressant medication. This chapter reviews the rationale and background of the model, as well as relevant research. A case illustration is presented to provide additional detail about the use of common treatment strategies and client responses, describing the experience of one client who benefited tremendously from the treatment.