ArticlePublisher preview available

The greatest unhappiness of the least number

Authors:
To read the full-text of this research, you can request a copy directly from the authors.

Abstract

We propose an alternative articulation of the Benthamite greatest-happiness-of-the-greatest-number principle. With ordinally measurable and interpersonally non-comparable utilities, the rule chooses those feasible alternatives that maximize the number of individuals who end up with their greatest element. This rule is tantamount to the plurality rule. Furthermore, in the spirit of Rawls’s maximin principle, we propose the greatest-unhappiness-of-the-least-number principle. In analogy to the greatest-happiness principle, the least-unhappiness principle is formally equivalent to the anti-plurality rule. Our main result is a characterization of the least-unhappiness principle.
Soc Choice Welf (2016) 47:187–205
DOI 10.1007/s00355-016-0951-6
The greatest unhappiness of the least number
Walter Bossert1·Kotaro Suzumura2
Received: 8 December 2015 / Accepted: 6 February 2016 / Published online: 22 February 2016
© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2016
Abstract We propose an alternative articulation of the Benthamite greatest-happiness-
of-the-greatest-number principle. With ordinally measurable and interpersonally
non-comparable utilities, the rule chooses those feasible alternatives that maximize
the number of individuals who end up with their greatest element. This rule is tanta-
mount to the plurality rule. Furthermore, in the spirit of Rawls’s maximin principle,
we propose the greatest-unhappiness-of-the-least-number principle. In analogy to the
greatest-happiness principle, the least-unhappiness principle is formally equivalent to
the anti-plurality rule. Our main result is a characterization of the least-unhappiness
principle.
This paper is dedicated to John Roemer with our compliments, who has been one of the major
contributors on theories of justice in such various disciplines as economics, philosophy, and political
science; see, for example, Roemer (1996). We thank Thierry Marchant and several seminar audiences for
their comments and suggestions. Financial support from a Grant-in-Aid for Specially Promoted Research
from the Ministry of Education, Culture, Sports, Science and Technology of Japan for the Project on
Economic Analysis of Intergenerational Issues (Grant number 22000001), the Fonds de Recherche sur la
Société et la Culture of Québec, and the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada is
gratefully acknowledged.
BWalter Bossert
walter.bossert@videotron.ca
Kotaro Suzumura
ktr.suzumura@gmail.com
1Centre Interuniversitaire de Recherche en Economie Quantitative (CIREQ), P.O. Box 6128,
Station Downtown, Montreal, QC H3C 3J7, Canada
2School of Political Science and Economics, Waseda University, 1-6-1 Nishi-Waseda, Shinjuku-ku,
Tokyo 169-8050, Japan
123
Content courtesy of Springer Nature, terms of use apply. Rights reserved.
... Another prominent example is the plurality voting rule. As discussed in Bossert and Suzumura (2016), this voting procedure can also be viewed as an expression of Bentham's (1776) greatest-happiness-of-the-greatest-number principle if Bentham's dictum is given an ordinalist interpretation. That Bentham himself may have been an ordinalist is suggested in a citation by Mitchell in his "Bentham's felicific calculus" (Mitchell 1937, p. 184), according to which Bentham states that " 'Tis in vain to talk of adding quantities which after the addition will continue distinct as they were before, one man's happiness will never be another man's happiness: a gain to one man is no gain to another: you might as well pretend to add 20 apples to 20 pears". ...
... The equity-oriented counterpart of the greatest-happiness principle is the greatestunhappiness-of-the-least-number principle; see, again, Bossert and Suzumura (2016). ...
Article
Full-text available
The paper proposes a general definition of positionalist voting rules. Unlike the commonly-employed scoring rules, our notion of positionalism allows for non-linear criteria to be included in the requisite class. We define a voting rule as positionalist if, for any profile of strict individual orderings, any two alternatives are compared collectively solely on the basis of their positional scores according to the individual rankings. In contrast to the class of scoring rules, however, we do not restrict attention to linear aggregation procedures. Two plausible unanimity properties are examined in the context of our new class of positionalist rules and, moreover, we characterize the lexicographic extensions that refine the plurality rule and its inverse counterpart.
... However, we need to check whether the axioms for the characterization can be relaxed or there could be an alternative approach. Bossert and Suzumura (2016) characterized the anti-plurality rule directly by anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, individual-equality independence, single-agent monotonicity, and single-agent expansion using a variable electorate and variable alternatives. ...
... As stated earlier, Baharad and Nitzan (2005) axiomatized C ap by applying Young (1975)'s theorem to axiomatize a scoring social choice rule by anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, and continuity, 5 and showed that a scoring social rule is C ap if and only if it satisfies minimal veto. 6 Furthermore, Bossert and Suzumura (2016) characterized the anti-plurality rule directly by anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, individual-equality independence, 7 single-agent monotonicity, 8 and single-agent expansion 9 using variable alternatives. ...
Article
We axiomatize the anti-plurality rule by anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, and new axioms, that is, averseness and bottoms-only. Averseness is a weaker axiom than faithfulness, and bottoms-only is the opposite of tops-only. Thus, we do not apply the characterization of a scoring social choice rule by anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, and continuity to characterize the anti-plurality rule.
... Regulations that make this kind of happiness can be protected in many ways. Compare this with the thoughts of Walter Bossert and Kotaro Suzumura in "The Greatest Unhappiness of the Least Number" [7] which offers an alternative articulation of "greatesthappiness-of-the-greatest-number" with measurable utilities, Jeffrey M. Robinson in "An Incongruent Amalgamation: John Stuart Mill's Utilitarianism on Naturalism" [8] and Katalin Martinás in "On The Teory of Human Decisions in the Age of Beneficial Globalization" [9]. ...
... According to Deschamps and Gevers, if an SWO satisfies 2 In addition to these, Sen (1974) discusses the contrast between utilitarianism and the Rawlsian maximin and leximin principles in the context of dividing a fixed amount of income among individuals. Further, Bossert and Suzumura (2016) contrast utilitarianism with the Rawlsian maximin principle from the viewpoint of their relevance to the plurality voting rule. strong Pareto, anonymity, minimal equity, separability, and cardinal full comparability, then the SWO is either the leximin SWO or a weakly utilitarian SWO, that is, an SWO that respects the strict preferences of the utilitarian SWO. 3 Strong Pareto and anonymity postulate positively sensitive and impartial evaluations, respectively. ...
Article
We examine the range of the agreement between the utilitarian social welfare ordering (SWO) and leximin SWO by analyzing the intersection of them. We characterize the intersection (in terms of subrelation) using the strong version of Pigou–Dalton equity and a new axiom on the composition of rank-preserving progressive and regressive utility transfers. Then, adding separability and cardinal full comparability, we jointly characterize the leximin SWO and the lexicographic composition of the utilitarian and leximin SWOs that applies the utilitarian SWO first. We also jointly characterize these two SWOs and the utilitarian SWO using the weak version of Pigou–Dalton equity.
Chapter
This innovative history of welfare economics challenges the view that welfare economics can be discussed without taking ethical values into account. Whatever their theoretical commitments, when economists have considered practical problems relating to public policy, they have adopted a wider range of ethical values, whether equality, justice, freedom, or democracy. Even canonical authors in the history of welfare economics are shown to have adopted ethical positions different from those with which they are commonly associated. Welfare Theory, Public Action, and Ethical Values explores the reasons and implications of this, drawing on concepts of welfarism and non-welfarism developed in modern welfare economics. The authors exemplify how economic theory, public affairs and political philosophy interact, challenging the status quo in order to push economists and historians to reconsider the nature and meaning of welfare economics.
Article
Full-text available
An Arrowian Social Welfare Function (SWF) represents a weak ordering of the alternative set derived entirely from individual preference orders. Negative voting considers only a voter’s least preferred alternative. We introduce the majority loser opposition property which requires that any alternative ranked last by a majority of voters must be ranked last in the social ordering. We show a SWF satisfies anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, continuity, and majority loser opposition if and only if it is equivalent to negative voting.
Article
Full-text available
Models for supporting climate adaptation and mitigation planning, mostly in the form of Integrated Assessment Models, are poorly equipped for aiding questions related to fairness of adaptation and mitigation strategies, because they often disregard distributional outcomes. When evaluating policies using such models, the costs and benefits are typically aggregated across all actors in the system, and over the entire planning horizon. While a policy may be beneficial when considering the aggregate outcome, it can be harmful to some people, somewhere, at some point in time. The practice of aggregating over all actors and over time thus gives rise to problems of justice; it could also exacerbate existing injustices. While the literature discusses some of these injustices in ad‐hoc and case specific manner, a systematic approach for considering distributive justice in model‐based climate change planning is lacking. This study aims to fill this gap by proposing 11 requirements that an Integrated Assessment Model should meet in order to enable the assessment of distributive justice in climate mitigation and adaptation policies. We derive the requirements from various ethical imperatives stemming from the theory of distributive justice. More specifically, we consider both intra‐generational (among people within one generation) and intergenerational (between generations) distributive justice. We investigate to what extent the 11 requirements are being met in recent model‐based climate planning studies, and highlight several directions for future research to advance the accounting for distributive justice in model‐based support for climate change planning. This article is categorized under: Climate, Nature, and Ethics > Climate Change and Global Justice
Article
Full-text available
Despite the importance of pioneering work by such precursors as Jean-Charles de Borda and Marquis de Condorcet in the 18th century, it was Kenneth Arrow and his general impossibility theorem that elevated the scientific status of social choice theory into an unprecedented plateau. This paper tries to highlight several unique features of his research program of social choice theory vis-à-vis the classical contributions of Borda and Condorcet, on the one hand, and the “new” welfare economics à la Bergson and Samuelson, on the other hand, as well as to identify several channels through which his impossibility impasse could be circumvented. It is concluded with several personal reminiscences of Kenneth Arrow based on the author’s own experiences with him over four decades.
Chapter
This book is a collection of essays written in honor of Abram Bergson, the father of modern Soviet economic studies and modern welfare economics. The first part deals with Soviet economics, whereas the second part is devoted to welfare economics and includes essays by four Nobel laureates, Samuelson, Arrow, Tinbemen and Kuznets. All of the essays in the book are important contributions in their own right.
Chapter
Nicholas Kaldor (1908–1986) was born in Budapest and educated in Budapest, Berlin, and at the London School of Economics. In addition to an academic career, which was centered at Cambridge University, Kaldor served as an advisor to several governments and was instrumental in devising the value added tax (VAT). In this brief essay, originally published in 1939, he argues that the net benefit of a policy – the amount that “winners” would be willing to pay minus the amount that “losers” would need to be compensated – provides a measure of the capacity of an economy to satisfy preferences that does not require interpersonal comparisons or any judgment concerning the justice of different distributions. In a separate essay published in the same year, John Hicks defends the same idea, and assessment of alternatives in terms of net benefits is often called “the Kaldor-Hicks efficiency criterion.” In the December 1938 issue of the Economic Journal Professor Robbins returns to the question of the status of interpersonal comparisons of utility. It is not the purpose of this note to question Professor Robbins' view regarding the scientific status of such comparisons; with this the present writer is in entire agreement. Its purpose is rather to examine the relevance of this whole question to what is commonly called “welfare economics.” In previous discussions of this problem it has been rather too readily assumed, on both sides, that the scientific justification of such comparisons determines whether “economics as a science can say anything by way of prescription.”
Article
We consider an axiomatic characterization of the plurality rule, which selects the alternative(s) most preferred by the largest number of individuals. We strengthen the characterization result of Yeh [Yeh, C.-H., 2008. An efficiency characterization of plurality rule in collective choice problems. Economic Theory 34, 575-583] by replacing efficiency axiom by the weaker axiom called faithfulness. Formally, we show that the plurality rule is the only rule satisfying anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, tops-only, and faithfulness.
Article
When there are only two alternatives to choose from, the method of simple majority rule seems to be the most natural and commonly used social choice function. However, a great variety of rules are used in practice for group decision making when three or more alternatives are involved. The object of this paper is to study two natural conditions on social choice functions, and to describe precisely the family of all functions satisfying these two conditions.