ArticlePDF Available

Emotions and the Ethics of Consequence in Conservation Decisions: Lessons from Cecil the Lion

Authors:

Abstract

Though the conservation community has long premised its moral foundations on consequentialist thinking, and has embraced a dualistic worldview severing reason from emotion, the conservation community has erred by failing to address – or even acknowledge – the limitations of these fundamental tenets. This failure reemerged in 2015 when a wealthy hunter killed an African Lion named Cecil for a trophy, in turn prompting a debate within the conservation community about the appropriateness of killing Cecil. A number of conservationists 1) defended such instances of trophy hunting on the basis that money generated by trophy hunting can support conservation, and 2) ridiculed as irrational those who oppose such instances of killing in the name of conservation. We suggest this response by the conservation community represents common, but problematic, ethical reasoning. We offer a critique of both the ethical underpinning of such reasoning and the assumptions about the relationship between reason and emotion. We urge ethical and social psychological maturation on behalf of the conservation community. This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved
This article has been accepted for publication and undergone full peer review but has not been
through the copyediting, typesetting, pagination and proofreading process, which may lead to
differences between this version and the Version of Record. Please cite this article as doi:
10.1111/conl.12232.
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
Title:
Emotions and the Ethics of Consequence in Conservation Decisions: Lessons from Cecil the
Lion
Authors:
MICHAEL PAUL NELSON (mpnelson@oregonstate.edu, 541-737-9221), Oregon State
University, Department of Forest Ecosystems and Society, Corvallis, OR, 97331, USA
JEREMY T. BRUSKOTTER (bruskotter.9@osu.edu, 614-595-7036), The Ohio State University,
The School of Environment and Natural Resources, Columbus, OH, 43210, USA
JOHN A. VUCETICH (javuceti@mtu.edu, 906-487-1711), Michigan Technological University,
School of Forest Resources and Environmental Sciences, Houghton, MI, 49931, USA
GUILLAUME CHAPRON (gchapron@carnivoreconservation.org, +46-76-117-75-23), Grimsö
Wildlife Research Station, Swedish University of Agricultural Sciences, SE - 73091
Riddarhyttan, Sweden
Running Title:
Emotions and Ethics in Conservation Decisions
Keywords:
Animal Welfare, Cecil the Lion, Conservation, Consequentialism, Emotions, Environmental
Ethics, Moral Dilemma, Trophy Hunting
Type of Article:
Policy Perspectives
Number of Words in Abstract:
163
Number of Words in Manuscript:
2240
Number of References:
36
Number of Figures and Tables:
0
Corresponding Author:
MICHAEL PAUL NELSON (mpnelson@oregonstate.edu, 541-737-9221), Oregon State
University, Department of Forest Ecosystems and Society, Corvallis, OR, 97331, USA
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
2
Abstract
Though the conservation community has long premised its moral foundations on
consequentialist thinking, and has embraced a dualistic worldview severing reason from
emotion, the conservation community has erred by failing to address or even
acknowledge the limitations of these fundamental tenets. This failure reemerged in 2015
when a wealthy hunter killed an African Lion named Cecil for a trophy, in turn prompting a
debate within the conservation community about the appropriateness of killing Cecil. A
number of conservationists 1) defended such instances of trophy hunting on the basis that
money generated by trophy hunting can support conservation, and 2) ridiculed as irrational
those who oppose such instances of killing in the name of conservation. We suggest this
response by the conservation community represents common, but problematic, ethical
reasoning. We offer a critique of both the ethical underpinning of such reasoning and the
assumptions about the relationship between reason and emotion. We urge ethical and
social psychological maturation on behalf of the conservation community.
Introduction
Aldo Leopold (1933) first described wildlife management as the art of making land
produce sustained annual crops of wild game for recreational use.” Though Leopold’s views
about conservation changed dramatically over his lifetime, we still largely follow the model
he described in 1933. That is, a dominant focus of wildlife management continues to be the
treatment of wildlife as “crops” to be cultivated and harvested for human use. Yet, in recent
years, people have begun to question whether that focus is legitimate: if, for example,
killing a cougar for a trophy is the same as harvesting a deer for food. Likewise, many
question the legitimacy of certain tools used in wildlife management, objecting to the pain
and suffering inflicted. These issues often spark intense debates where well-meaning
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
3
disputants often conservationists themselves mishandle basic principles that are well
known in the scholarly fields of ethics. In this essay, we argue that discourse about the
appropriateness of killing in the name of conservation would be more constructive if
conservationists understood (a) some of the shortcomings and limitations of
consequentialism, a basic school of thought in the academic discipline of ethics, and (b) that
emotion is not easily or appropriately separated from reason in human judgment and
decision-making. We use the recent case of the killing of Cecil the lion by a trophy hunter to
illustrate.
Consequentialism
The 2015 killing of a high-profile African lion, named Cecil, by an American trophy
hunter rekindled the controversy regarding whether trophy hunting of endangered animals
is acceptable (Capecchi and Rogers 2015). This episode represents a much broader
controversy about the appropriateness of trophy hunting in the name of conservation.
Much of the discourse on this topic focuses on a key empirical question for conservation
(i.e., can trophy hunting benefit a species or population?) (Di Minin et al. 2015). But the
discourse also tends to skirt the broader ethical question sitting at the heart of the
controversy. This question, put simply, iswhat constitutes a good reason to kill an animal?
The Cecil episode also has direct policy implications because the US Fish and Wildlife
Service (USFWS), which recently listed African lions under the U.S. Endangered Species Act
(ESA), also created a special rule that allows for the importation of lion parts (normally
illegal under the ESA) obtained in legal trophy hunts from countries with “scientifically
based” harvest quotas (80 Fed. Reg. 80,016).
Those who support trophy hunting rely primarily on two, oft-repeated, premises: (a)
trophy hunting does not jeopardize the population and (b) trophy hunting can be useful,
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
4
even necessary, for the species being hunted because it provides funding for their
conservation (e.g. Di Minin et al. 2015). In addition to a rich academic literature both
defending and challenging the empirical claim that trophy hunting benefits species and
populations (see, for example, Lindsey et al. 2007 and Treves 2009), this issue has broad
social interest as well. For example, an article published on National Geographic’s news site
noted, “Supporters say regulated hunts raise much-needed money for conservation and
help manage populations and contends, “…scientists can prove that the taking of select
individuals will not endanger the species (Howard 2015). Similarly, a piece published in the
New York Times, noted hunting advocates “argue that, if done responsibly, the selling of
expensive licenses to big-game hunters can help pay for efforts to protect endangered
species (Capecchi and Rogers 2015) and an article in The Conversation, authored by a pair
of academic scientists, lends further support, arguing that “conservation costs money” and
trophy hunting provides a means of funding conservation (Rust and Verissimo 2015).
Looking across the coverage, the message is clearthough trophy hunting is extremely
controversial, it is justified when it raises funding for conservation.
These arguments presuppose an ethical theory called “consequentialism”— which
posits that the consequences of one’s actions or a policy is the sole basis for judging
whether they are right are wrong (consequentialism is invoked, for example, by the well-
known aphorism, “the ends justify the means.). Consequentialist thinking is common in
conservation (see Gore et al. 2011). While the limitations of consequentialism are well
known to ethicists, these shortcomings are less known to the conservation community.
Below we consider three of the most pertinent shortcomings.
The first shortcoming is that in some cases the ends do not justify the means. Even if
we grant that trophy hunting does not jeopardize the population of conservation concern
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
5
and that it brings in significant funds for conservation, we are still left with the question, is
the killing justified? This question cannot be dismissed simply by appealing to the beneficial
consequences of the killing. Indeed in many other human affairs we condemn actions or
policies even if beneficial ends are obtained. For example, trafficking humans is taken to be
a wrong way to treat humans even if doing so generates revenue that would be used for
philanthropic purposes. The revenue that could be generated is not sufficient to override
the wrong that is done when we condone human trafficking. The analogous questions need
to be asked of trophy hunting in the name of conservation.
A second shortcoming of consequentialism is its tendency to underappreciate the
importance of motivation when determining the rightness or wrongness of an action. The
importance of motivation in society is highlighted, for example, by the difference between
manslaughter and murder in those two cases, the moral culpability, the crime, and the
punishment are all very different, even though the consequence of both crimes is exactly
the same. Where trophy hunting is concerned, the motivations of the hunter are critical in
determining the appropriateness of her or his actions. In the case of Cecil, the hunter was
not motivated by the need for food or to protect himself, his family, his livestock, his pets,
or his livelihood. The motivation for killing Cecil was recreation for the purpose of acquiring
a trophy. The explosion of condemnation for this hunter’s actions is a testament to the fact
that many people do not believe trophy acquisition is an appropriate motivation to kill
(Decker et al. 2015).
The controversy about the appropriateness of trophy hunting for conservation will
likely persist until opponents are given good reason to believe that trophy hunting for
conservation does not fall victim to these concerns about motivation. The importance of this
concern is further indicated by controversies surrounding such practices as, for example,
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
6
long-shot animal shooting (Petzal 2014), hunting that is tantamount to target practice (e.g.,
prairie dog shooting, Conniff 2013), and various wildlife killing contests (Bixby 2015).
Finally, consequentialist approaches demand that we accurately predict future
consequences of our actions and policies. The criticism here is blunt. Where the relationship
between humans and nature is concerned, we simply are not very good at predicting the
outcomes of our actions or policies (e.g., Holling and Meffe 1996). The concern applies to
this particular case because our ability to reliably manage a trophy hunt without harming
the population is far from certain (e.g., Packer et al. 2009, Whitman et al. 2004, Palazy et al.
2011).
Moreover, as a general principle, we tend to overestimate the benefits and
underestimate the costs of our actions, especially when we are the beneficiaries of the
action (Sagoff 2004, Weinstein 1980). This principle applies here insomuch as if one
identifies with the basic and well-justified principles of animal welfare, then one is liable to
underestimate the cost of harming a population and overestimating the cost of harming
individuals; whereas if one identifies with the basic and well-justified principles of
conservation, then one is liable to overestimate the cost of harming a population and
underestimating the cost of harming individuals.
Important antidotes to these shortcomings are reflected by the underlying principles
of other ethical frameworks, such as deontology (Alexander and Moore 2015) and virtue
theory (Hursthouse 2013). Indeed, judging whether the killing of endangered wildlife is
justified requires analysis both of the consequences for the population (or species) and the
individual organisms that are being killed, and the motivations and actions of the individual
doing the killing. We urge the conservation community to consider these other ethical
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
7
perspectives when deciding whether it should condone the various instances of killing in the
name of conservation, including trophy hunting.
Emotion
In addition to a more sophisticated understanding of ethical perspectives (how we
should behave with respect to wildlife), conservationists could also benefit from a more
thorough understanding of psychological explanations of how people actually make
judgments and decisions, especially the role of emotions. Some conservation professionals
expressed support for Cecil’s killing, specifically, and trophy hunting, generally, while
chastising those opposed as irrational or emotional. For example, one article chided, “While
it is sad that we sometimes have to resort to killing animals for conservation, let’s not allow
emotions to overtake our arguments (Rust and Verissimo 2015). The notion that people
oppose lethal actions because their judgment is clouded by emotion is, in our experience,
common in conservation debates. Indeed, the idea that emotion is the opposite of, or
antithetical to, reason dates back at least as far as Plato (Gardiner et al. 1937). However,
research in psychology and neuroscience reveal flaws in this idea. This research indicates
our deliberations and decision-making utilize both effortful, cognitive processes as well as
quick, intuitive emotional processes (Greene et al. 2004, Kahneman 2011), and suggest that
emotion can actually improve decision-making (Clark et al. 2008). Indeed, research on
humans with damage to ventromedial prefrontal region of the brain (a region that assists
with processing emotions) indicates that individuals with such damage have difficulties
making a variety of judgments and decisions (Bechara et al. 2000, 2004). Thus, while it may
seem desirable to eschew emotion in decision-making, research suggests this may not be
possible, let alone desirable.
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
8
Psychological research indicates that the emotion of anger is a perfectly normal and
healthy reaction to any of several kinds of perceived injustice (Batson et al. 2007, 2009). For
example, we expect people to react angrily when they themselves are hurt by someone
else’s actions. We expect and even encourage people to respond angrily when cared-for
others are harmed, whether a child, friend or even pet. Likewise, anger at a violation of a
moral principle (e.g., do unto others…), whether codified in law or scripture, is an
appropriate response in a society dependent upon complex rules for maintaining order.
Individuals who fail to respond with appropriate emotions (like empathy) when witnessing
injustice might be described as callous or anti-social. In fact, lack of empathy is associated
with narcissistic personality disorder (Ritter et al. 2011) and a variety of aggressive, anti-
social behaviors (Miller and Eisenberg 1988), while empathetic responses are associated
with a variety of helping behaviors, including pro-environmental behavior (Schultz 2000,
Berenguer 2007).
Certainly, emotional outrage is sometimes no more than irrational lunacy (just as
reason can at times turn into rationalization), and emotions can lead to less thoughtful,
systematic processing of information (Wilson 2008). But often, emotional outrage is a
reasonable (perhaps even ‘reasoned’) response to injustice and unfairness. Thus, although
the eruption of emotional outrage is sometimes grounds for dismissing those who are
outraged, it can also be a call for closer inspection for signs of injustice. (Note that we are in
no way defending some of the clearly unvirtuous behavior exhibited by some opponents of
to trophy hunting in this case, who called for violence against Cecil’s killer (see Capecchi and
Rogers 2015)).
Tools such as argument analysis (Nelson and Vucetich 2012) and conflict resolution
(Madden and McQuinn 2014) can be useful for elucidating circumstances when emotions
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
9
are, or are not, an appropriate response to some form of injustice. Where emotional
responses appear inappropriate, decision-aiding tools that encourage thoughtful, systematic
review of information can also be used to counteract emotional biases (Wilson 2008). Such
methods can also prevent one from being overly-attentive to emotions (e.g., attentive to
the point of being inappropriately distracted from relevant facts or circumstances that merit
attention). In any case, if the root cause of an emotional response is injustice, then the
appropriate response is to address the injustice.
There is increasing evidence to suggest that the public is becoming more empathetic
toward wildlife (Manfredo et al. 2009), and people seem increasingly willing to question
conservation practices they view to be morally problematic. From a practical perspective,
dismissing stakeholders’ views in an emotionally-charged environment will almost certainly
decrease trust among parties (Wilson 2008), and could undermine support for conservation
initiatives. The key for conservation professionals is recognizing that emotion is not
anathema to rational decision-making.
Conclusion
The Cecil case highlights the under-appreciated importance of the human
dimensions of conservation, in particular those pertaining to ethics and psychology. Trophy
hunting as a means of conserving species is vigorously defended by some conservationists
who implicitly rely on consequentialist ethical arguments. More than a century of
scholarship in the field of ethics reveals flaws with consequentialism, calling into question
conservation actions that rely solely on consequentialist arguments. The idea that emotion
is the antithesis of rationality is also centuries old, and is employed as a means of dismissing
people who display emotion in conservation debates. Yet, psychological research suggests
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
10
emotional reactions to injustice are normal and healthy, and emotions can be critical for
making ‘good’ judgments and decisions.
These new perspectives need not paralyze conservationists. As seen above, a variety
of practical tools are available for assisting conservationists in understanding the ethical
underpinnings of their positions, and for addressing the proper role of emotions in decision-
making.
References
Alexander, L., & Moore, M. (2015). Deontological ethics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, on line at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-deontological/
Batson, C.D., Kennedy, C.L., Nord, L.A., Stocks, E., Fleming, D.A., Marzette, C.M., Lisher, D.A.,
Hayes, R.E., Kolchinsky, L.M. & Zerger, T. (2007). Anger at unfairness: is it moral
outrage? European Journal of Social Psychology 37, 1272.
Batson, C.D., Chao, M.C., & Givens, J.M. (2009). Pursuing moral outrage: anger at torture.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45, 155-160.
Bechara, A., Tranel, D., & Damasio, H. (2000). Characterization of the decision-making
impairment of patients with bilateral lesions of the ventromedial prefrontal cortex.
Brain, 123, 21892202.
Bechara, A. (2004). The role of emotion in decision-making: evidence from neurological
patients with orbitofrontal damage. Brain and Cognition, 55, 30-40.
Berenguer, J. (2007). The effect of empathy in proenvironmental attitudes and behavior.
Environment and Behavior, 39, 269-283.
Bixby, K. (July 31, 2015). Wildlife killing contests should be outlawed in the west. The Denver
Post, online at
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
11
http://www.denverpost.com/writersontherange/ci_27426211/wildlife-killing-
contests-should-be-outlawed-west
Capecchi, C. & Rogers K., (July 29, 2015). Killer of cecil the lion finds out that he Is a target
now, of internet vigilantism, New York Times, on line at
http://www.nytimes.com/2015/07/30/us/cecil-the-lion-walter-palmer.html
Clark, L., Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Aitken, M.R.F., Sahakian, B.J., & Robbins, T.W. (2008).
Differential effects of insular and ventromedial prefrontal cortex lesions on risky
decision-making. Brain, 131, 1311-1322.
Conniff, R. (November 26, 2013). The brutal sport of prairie dog hunting. Takepart, on line at
http://www.takepart.com/article/2013/11/26/brutal-sport-prairie-dog-hunting
Decker, D.J., Stedman, R.C, Larson, L.R., & Siemer, W.F. (2015). Hunting for wildlife
management in America. The Wildlife Professional, Spring, 26-29.
Di Minin, E., Leader-Williams, N., & Bradshaw, C. (2015). Banning trophy hunting will
exacerbate biodiversity loss. Trends in Ecology and Evolution (early on line).
Gardiner, H.M., Metcalf, R.C., & Beebe-Center, J.G. (1937). The beginnings of a doctrine of
the affections: from Heraclitus to Plato. In: Feeling and emotion: a history of
theories. American Book Publishing, Salt Lake City, UT, pp. 1-25.
Gore, M.L., Nelson, M.P., Vucetich, J.A., Smith, A., & Clark, M. (2011). Exploring the ethical
basis for conservation policy: the case of inbred wolves on Isle Royale, USA.
Conservation Letters, 4, 394-401.
Greene, J.D., Nystrom, L.E., Engell, A.D., Darley, J.M., & Cohen, J.D. (2004). The neural bases
of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron, 44, 389-400.
Holling, C.S., & Meffe, G. (1996). Command and control and the pathology of natural
resource management. Conservation Biology, 10, 328-37.
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
12
Howard, B.C. (July 29, 2015). Can lion trophy hunting support conservation? National
Geographic, on line at http://news.nationalgeographic.com/2015/07/150729-lion-
trophy-hunting-conservation-animals-cecil/
Hursthouse, R. (2013). Virtue ethics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, on line at
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. Macmillan, New York.
Leopold, A. (1933). Game management. Charles Scribner’s Sons, New York.
Lindsey, P.A., Roulet, P.A., Romañach, S.S. (2007). Economic and conservation significance of
the trophy hunting industry in sub-Saharan Africa. Biological Conservation, 134, 455-
469.
Madden, F., & McQuinn, B. (2014). Conservation’s blind spot: the case for conflict
transformation in wildlife conservation. Biological Conservation, 178, 97-106.
Manfredo, M.J., Teel, T.L., & Henry, K.L. (2009). Linking society and environment: a
multilevel model of shifting wildlife value orientations in the western United States.
Social science quarterly, 90, 407-427.
Miller, P.A., & Eisenberg, N. (1988). The relation of empathy to aggressive and
externalizing/antisocial behavior. Psychological bulletin, 103, 324.
Nelson, M.P., & Vucetich, J.A. (2012). Environmental ethics and wildlife management. In:
Human dimensions of wildlife management, 2nd ed. (eds. Decker, D.J., Riley, S.J., &
Siemer, W.F.). Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, pp. 223-37.
Packer, C., Kosmala, M., Cooley, H.S., Brink, H., Pintea, L., Garshelis, D., & Nowel, K. (2009).
Sport hunting, predator control and conservation of large carnivores. Plos One, 4,
e5941.
This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved.
13
Palazy, L., Bonenfant, C., Gaillard, J.M., & Courchamp, F. (2011). Cat dilemma: too protected
to escape trophy hunting? PloS one, 6(7).
Petzal, D.E. (August 27, 2014). The line between hunting and long-range shooting. Field and
Stream, on line at http://www.fieldandstream.com/blogs/the-gun-nuts/the-line-
between-hunting-and-long-range-shooting
Ritter, K., Dziobek, I., Preibler, S., Rüter, A., Vater, A., Fydrich, T., ... & Roepke, S. (2011). Lack
of empathy in patients with narcissistic personality disorder. Psychiatry
research, 187, 241-247.
Rust, N. and Verissimo, D. (July 29, 2015) Why killing lions like Cecil may actually be good
for conservation, The Conversation, on line at https://theconversation.com/why-
killing-lions-like-cecil-may-actually-be-good-for-conservation-45400
Sagoff, M. (2004). Price, principle, and the environment. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Schultz, P.W. (2000). Empathizing with nature: the effects of perspective taking on concern
for environmental education. Journal of Social Issues, 56, 391-406.
Treves, A. (2009). Hunting for large carnivore conservation. Journal of Applied Ecology, 46,
1350-1356.
Weinstein, N.D. (1980). Unrealistic optimism about future life events. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 39, 806-820.
Wilson, R.S. (2008). Balancing Emotion and Cognition: a Case for Decision Aiding in
Conservation Efforts. Conservation Biology, 22(6), 1452-1450.
Whitman, K., Starfield, A.M., Quadling, H.S., & Packer, C. (2004). Sustainable trophy hunting
of African lions. Nature, 428, 175-178.
... Alternatively, opponents commonly argue that trophy hunting can have negative ecological (Coltman et al., 2003;Creel et al., 2016;Rashid et al., 2020;Ripple et al., 2016;Whitman et al., 2004) and social consequences (Brandt, 2016;Brandt & Spierenburg, 2014;Koot, 2019;Thomsen et al., 2021;Yasuda, 2011), potentially undermining conservation and public trust (Popescu et al., 2021). Opponents also appeal to the rights of targeted animals (Ahmad, 2016;Morris, 2020;Nelson et al., 2016) or argue that people who enjoy trophy hunting lack virtue, which can fuel public outrage and present a 'moral quandary' (Batavia, Bruskotter, et al., 2019;Beattie, 2020;Ghasemi, 2021). ...
... The extracted dimensions of moral concern provided a basis for further analysing conservation scholars' judgement concerning trophy hunting's morality. We also included moral conviction the key driver of the trophy hunting debate (Macdonald, Johnson, et al., 2016;Nelson et al., 2016;Vucetich et al., 2019). Last, we included moral conviction, given that it has previously been shown to influence moral judgement and contribute to polarization (Garrett & Bankert, 2020;Skitka et al., 2015). ...
... your position on the morality of trophy hunting?Brandt, 2016;Brandt & Spierenburg, 2014;Yasuda, 2011;Thomsen et al., 2021; Abebe et al., et al., 2018; Thomsen et al., MacdonaldNelson et al., 2013;Yasuda, 2011;Nordbø et al., 2018; Abebe et al., 2020; Gargallo & Kalvelage, DubeFischer et al., 2015; Di Minin et al., 2016a; Macdonald, Johnson, et al., 2016; Gunn, 2001; Gargallo & Kalvelage, 2021 Ecological Consequences to the number of threatened species 4et al., 2020; Creel et al., 2016; Nelson et al., 2013; Nordbø et al., 2018; Whitman et al., et al., 2016; Di Minin et al., 2016a; Dickman et al., 2019; Di Minin et al., 2016b;Gunn, Batavia, Nelson, et al., 2019;Beattie, 2020;Gunn, 2001; Fischer et al., Batavia, Nelson, et al., 2019;Beattie, 2020;Gunn, 2001 Individual animals Welfare of the individual animals who getNelson et al., 2016;Ghasemi, 2021; Macdonald, Jacobsen, et al., 2016;Hart et al., 2020; Darimont et al.Nelson et al., 2016;Ghasemi, 2021;Popescu et al., 2021 a All responses ranged from not at all important (1) to extremely important (5). ...
Article
Full-text available
Trophy hunting is one of the most contentious issues in recent biodiversity conservation discourse, eliciting opposition and support for the practice. Ethical concerns are often at the heart of the debate. To investigate moral views about trophy hunting, we conducted an online survey of randomly selected scholars worldwide who had published on biodiversity conservation ( n = 2315). Scholars expressed divergent views on the moral acceptability of trophy hunting as a conservation practice. Moral convictions were significantly related to the perspectives of scholars. The most important factor in predicting the moral views of the respondents was the consequences of trophy hunting for local human communities. The results also indicated that utilitarian (versus deontological) decision‐making in conservation, ecological consequences of trophy hunting and animal welfare issues contribute to the divergent views. The findings emphasize the need for interdisciplinary work on ethical issues concerning animal rights and welfare in conservation, as well as providing robust and comprehensive evidence on the consequences of trophy hunting for local communities. We caution that polarization among conservation scholars may negatively affect conservation efforts. Based on the literature and our findings, we provide some recommendations to narrow the gap and consider different management options. Read the free Plain Language Summary for this article on the Journal blog.
... However, it is worth discussing research on emotions and wildlife interactions to frame this research. Researchers have suggested that understanding the impacts of emotional factors on human-animal interactions would have positive impacts on the conservation and human relations (Castillo-Huitrón et al., 2020;Nelson et al., 2016). ...
... For example, it was found in a 2015 study that emotional dispositions mediated the relationship between attitudes and symbolic beliefs on the lethal management of coyotes in certain situations (Sponarski et al., 2015). Other research agree that understanding the psychological components, such as emotions, relating to how people make ethical judgements is beneficial (Nelson et al., 2016). ...
Article
Full-text available
Recent research has indicated that hunting tourism is growing and that hunters tend to act more unethically when hunting as tourists. Informed by an Aristotelian Virtue-Ethics theoretical framework, the researchers propose and test a link between emotional intelligence and ethical decision-making. Specifically, survey-based research tests the relationship between emotional intelligence and ethical decision-making by measuring a hunter's perception of ethical behaviour of self. The multiple regression findings support a relationship between emotional intelligence and ethical decision-making. The proposed theoretical framework and results should inform the development of new evidence and theory-based hunter-education platforms. The framework and results should also provide novel theoretical and evidence-based grounds to study further and enhance the hunting tourism industry. ARTICLE HISTORY
... The philosophical, medical, veterinary, husbandry, and ecological literature is replete with robust debate on the acceptability of killing various animals in diverse circumstances, and it is clear that many people support or accept animal killing in one way or another while many others oppose it (e.g. Singer 1975;Regan 1983;Lehman 1988;Miller 2012;Deckers 2016;Inglis 2016;Nelson et al. 2016; Fischer 2019; Lamey 2019; Lecerf 2020; Bobier and Allen 2022a). However, we have observed that much of the "for vs. against" multidisciplinary literature on this subject typically fails to put contemporary animal killing behaviour by humans into an evolutionary or ecological context, and an explanation for how humans kill animals and why it is necessary has not been well articulated. ...
... Recreational hunting and fishing, or killing animals for sport or entertainment, is a particularly contentious form of animal killing by humans (Cohen 2014;Darimont et al. 2017;Batavia et al. 2019; see also Nelson et al. 2016). This practice is also distinguished from other types of animal killing by its motivation. ...
Article
Full-text available
Killing animals has been a ubiquitous human behaviour throughout history, yet it is becoming increasingly controversial and criticised in some parts of contemporary human society. Here we review 10 primary reasons why humans kill animals, discuss the necessity (or not) of these forms of killing, and describe the global ecological context for human killing of animals. Humans historically and currently kill animals either directly or indirectly for the following reasons: (1) wild harvest or food acquisition, (2) human health and safety, (3) agriculture and aquaculture, (4) urbanisation and industrialisation, (5) invasive, overabundant or nuisance wildlife control, (6) threatened species conservation, (7) recreation, sport or entertainment, (8) mercy or compassion, (9) cultural and religious practice, and (10) research, education and testing. While the necessity of some forms of animal killing is debatable and further depends on individual values, we emphasise that several of these forms of animal killing are a necessary component of our inescapable involvement in a single, functioning, finite, global food web. We conclude that humans (and all other animals) cannot live in a way that does not require animal killing either directly or indirectly, but humans can modify some of these killing behaviours in ways that improve the welfare of animals while they are alive, or to reduce animal suffering whenever they must be killed. We encourage a constructive dialogue that (1) accepts and permits human participation in one enormous global food web dependent on animal killing and (2) focuses on animal welfare and environmental sustainability. Doing so will improve the lives of both wild and domestic animals to a greater extent than efforts to avoid, prohibit or vilify human animal-killing behaviour.
... The "worstmotive fallacy" suggests that people are negatively biased in their moral evaluations of the motivations of others and therefore more likely to assume, for example, that hunters are motivated by bloodlust or wanting to show off than by the hunting experience more broadly. Nelson et al. (2016) argue that the general trophy hunting discourse "tends to skirt the broader ethical question sitting at the heart of the controversy. This question, put simply, is-what constitutes a good reason to kill an animal?" ...
... The morality question is, however, usually an add-on to the main conservation subject and not front and centre. Macdonald et al. 2016b;Nelson et al. 2016;Batavia et al. 2018;Hsiao 2018;Batavia et al. 2020; Ghasemi 2020 and Morris 2020. We will be referring to some of these authors in this chapter. ...
Chapter
The most basic moral dilemma in sport hunting is the dispute between deontologists, arguing that animals have inalienable rights to life, and consequentialists, arguing that hunting can lead to less total suffering and the conservation of species and habitats. This dilemma has already been presented in the historical chapter, mainly in Chapters 2.9 and 2.10.What we will attempt to demonstrate in Chapter 8 is that deontology vs. consequentialism is not the only important conflict between paradigms of normative ethics in the trophy hunting discourse. What seems to be unique about the conflict over trophy hunting compared to the conflict over sport hunting is that there is less emphasis on the death of animals per se and more emphasis on the persons who cause said deaths. The emphasis is on the character, motivations, behaviour, and attributes of the hunter.Our claim, following from this observation, is that in order to understand the moral conflicts underlying the trophy hunting discourse, it is no longer enough to understand the obvious incompatibilities between deontology and consequentialism. We must also be open to the possibility of incompatibilities between virtue ethics (i.e. the character of hunters) and consequentialism.To illustrate this, we present in Chapter 8.1 and 8.2 our observations from Twitter, where comments to trophy photos were categorized as pertaining to either the character of hunters or animals/the death of animals. A far greater number of comments about the character of hunters were found, supporting the notion that virtue ethics play an important role in antihunting sentiments.
... The "worstmotive fallacy" suggests that people are negatively biased in their moral evaluations of the motivations of others and therefore more likely to assume, for example, that hunters are motivated by bloodlust or wanting to show off than by the hunting experience more broadly. Nelson et al. (2016) argue that the general trophy hunting discourse "tends to skirt the broader ethical question sitting at the heart of the controversy. This question, put simply, is-what constitutes a good reason to kill an animal?" ...
... The morality question is, however, usually an add-on to the main conservation subject and not front and centre. Macdonald et al. 2016b;Nelson et al. 2016;Batavia et al. 2018;Hsiao 2018;Batavia et al. 2020; Ghasemi 2020 and Morris 2020. We will be referring to some of these authors in this chapter. ...
Chapter
“Sport Hunting” is highly contentious and confusing, because it can have two meanings. One meaning of sport hunting is to hunt in a sporting way and give the animal a sporting chance. This is equivalent to the ideal of fair chase. The other meaning is to hunt for sport. It portrays hunting as competition and fun.In Chapter 6, we summarize the history of these terms – also discussed in Chapter 2 already – and discuss the meaning of sport hunting. We then discuss how fair chase is sought achieved by decreasing the power gap between hunter and prey through technological handicaps (like using a bow instead of a rifle – Chapter 6.1) and behavioural handicaps (like not shooting a deer on ice or in water or deep snow – Chapter 6.2).We then cover in Chapter 6.3 what we suggest could be an inverse relationship between fair chase and animal welfare. Bowhunting is one such example where, by making the hunt more difficult and therefore “fair,” evidence suggests that wounding rates and thereby animal suffering may increase.Finally, canned hunting is the practice of hunting animals that are fenced in, thus limiting their chance of escape. We discuss the very controversial issue of canned hunting in Chapter 6.4, as it is generally held up as an example of the opposite of fair chase. Plenty of hunting ranches in America, notably Texas, offer canned hunting, and captive-bred lions in South Africa for lion-petting tourism and canned hunting has until now been a big industry but seems to be shutting down. We cover all of this in 6.4.
... The "worstmotive fallacy" suggests that people are negatively biased in their moral evaluations of the motivations of others and therefore more likely to assume, for example, that hunters are motivated by bloodlust or wanting to show off than by the hunting experience more broadly. Nelson et al. (2016) argue that the general trophy hunting discourse "tends to skirt the broader ethical question sitting at the heart of the controversy. This question, put simply, is-what constitutes a good reason to kill an animal?" ...
... The morality question is, however, usually an add-on to the main conservation subject and not front and centre. Macdonald et al. 2016b;Nelson et al. 2016;Batavia et al. 2018;Hsiao 2018;Batavia et al. 2020; Ghasemi 2020 and Morris 2020. We will be referring to some of these authors in this chapter. ...
Chapter
This chapter investigates conservation claims and issues as they pertain to hunting. After a description of the major regulations governing trophy hunting imports and exports (5.1 Trophy Hunting Regulations), this chapter examines the conservation situation in two geographically different sections.The first section (5.2 Hunting and Conservation in Africa) concerns the stereotypical perception of trophy hunting. The trophy hunting situation and conservation issues are completely different in Africa than in Europe and USA and the problems are more diverse and complex. African hunting is more controversial because the species involved (lions, elephants, giraffes, etc.) are iconic, highly anthropomorphized, and sometimes endangered. Both species extinction and species overpopulation are issues in Africa. Corruption, poverty, poaching, and the West imposing their wildlife ideals on Africa are also important factors that we cover here.The second section (5.3 Hunting and Conservation in Eurasia and the Americas) concerns trophy hunting mostly in Europe and USA, where they have few natural predators of deer, so hunting is broadly considered the most feasible way of keeping deer populations from outgrowing carrying capacities of habitats. There are issues, however, with keeping populations down, because hunters favour bucks (because of trophy-fixations and ingrained fair chase ideals), and shooting bucks does little to keep populations in check. Also, shooting the wrong bucks or shooting them too early leads to genetic problems in the populations. These are the primary conservation issues that we discuss in a European- and US context.Other conservation-related matters discussed in this chapter are hunting and genetics, management alternatives to hunting, photography, and poaching.
... The "worstmotive fallacy" suggests that people are negatively biased in their moral evaluations of the motivations of others and therefore more likely to assume, for example, that hunters are motivated by bloodlust or wanting to show off than by the hunting experience more broadly. Nelson et al. (2016) argue that the general trophy hunting discourse "tends to skirt the broader ethical question sitting at the heart of the controversy. This question, put simply, is-what constitutes a good reason to kill an animal?" ...
... The morality question is, however, usually an add-on to the main conservation subject and not front and centre. Macdonald et al. 2016b;Nelson et al. 2016;Batavia et al. 2018;Hsiao 2018;Batavia et al. 2020; Ghasemi 2020 and Morris 2020. We will be referring to some of these authors in this chapter. ...
Chapter
In this final chapter, we present the challenges that recent years and especially 2020–21 have presented in the context of trophy hunting.In Chapter 9.1, we cover Covid-19 and how it has affected hunting and conservation differently in Africa, Europe, and the US. African countries and communities have suffered greatly economically from a lack of tourism, which has led to increased poaching and habitat loss; British venison could not be offhanded as it is largely supplied to restaurants, which have been closed because of Covid; and rural hunting and self-sufficiency mentality has increased in the US.In Chapter 9.2, we deal with the increasingly prominent issues of misinformation and disinformation in science communication and communication about trophy hunting especially, and with how social media amplifies misinformation. We describe a couple of the major trophy hunting disinformation campaigns on both sides of the fence and note how both celebrities and certain celebrity scientists seem to use anti trophy hunting campaigning as a popularity booster.
... The "worstmotive fallacy" suggests that people are negatively biased in their moral evaluations of the motivations of others and therefore more likely to assume, for example, that hunters are motivated by bloodlust or wanting to show off than by the hunting experience more broadly. Nelson et al. (2016) argue that the general trophy hunting discourse "tends to skirt the broader ethical question sitting at the heart of the controversy. This question, put simply, is-what constitutes a good reason to kill an animal?" ...
... The morality question is, however, usually an add-on to the main conservation subject and not front and centre. Macdonald et al. 2016b;Nelson et al. 2016;Batavia et al. 2018;Hsiao 2018;Batavia et al. 2020; Ghasemi 2020 and Morris 2020. We will be referring to some of these authors in this chapter. ...
... The "worstmotive fallacy" suggests that people are negatively biased in their moral evaluations of the motivations of others and therefore more likely to assume, for example, that hunters are motivated by bloodlust or wanting to show off than by the hunting experience more broadly. Nelson et al. (2016) argue that the general trophy hunting discourse "tends to skirt the broader ethical question sitting at the heart of the controversy. This question, put simply, is-what constitutes a good reason to kill an animal?" ...
... The morality question is, however, usually an add-on to the main conservation subject and not front and centre. Macdonald et al. 2016b;Nelson et al. 2016;Batavia et al. 2018;Hsiao 2018;Batavia et al. 2020; Ghasemi 2020 and Morris 2020. We will be referring to some of these authors in this chapter. ...
Chapter
We have three goals in Chapter 4.The first goal is to describe who hunters are (and to a lesser extent antihunters). Demographical information about hunters is much better for USA than for Europe, and trophy hunting is ten times the scale in USA as in the rest of the world combined, so we focus on a portrayal of American hunters. We use mainly the United States Fish and Wildlife Service statistics and the Virginia based Responsive Management survey research firm combined with demographical information about members of the Boone and Crockett Club and Safari Club International. Education, income, gender, ages, race, hunting efforts, and prey species of American hunters is laid out in Chapter 4.1, and we discuss common backgrounds of antihunters in Chapter 4.4.Our second goal (in Chapter 4.2 Hunting, Privilege, and Social Schisms) is to present and defend the hypothesis that hunter-antihunter conflicts are not just about hunting, but about many other social and sociocultural differences and conflicts. The trophy hunter stereotype (based on the demographics described in Chapter 4.1) is a male, white, conservative, protestant, wealthy, pro-gun, business owner. The antihunter (Chapter 4.4) is typically a female, non-white, liberal, anti-gun student. Hunting is just one representation of a mutual dislike that stems from many underlying societal tensions.Our third goal (in Chapters 4.3 and 4.5) is to explore why hunters hunt. We take our departure in the works of Stephen R. Kellert, and supplement with scholars like Jan E. Dizard, Simon Bronner, and Allen Morris Jones to discuss the three different archetypes of hunters (the nature hunter, the meat hunter, and the sport hunter), their reasons for hunting, and what hunting means to them. In Chapter 4.5, we discuss hunting motivations outside or not fully covered by Kellert’s framework and motivations that pertain specifically to trophies.
... Trophy hunting elicits contentious debates, with some arguing for the potential of trophy hunting in biodiversity conservation, and others arguing that it cannot be a sustainable form of conservation [5] [7] [8] [9] [10]. The diverse perspectives on trophy hunting have resulted in various national governments debating bans on trophy imports into their countries, and some airlines banning the transportation of trophies from countries conducting trophy hunting [11] [12] [13]. ...
Article
Full-text available
International pressure to ban trophy hunting is increasing. However, we argue that trophy hunting can be an important conservation tool, provided it can be done in controlled manner to benefit biodiversity conservation and local people. Where political, and governance structures are adequate, trophy hunting can help address the ongoing loss of species.
Article
Full-text available
Unaddressed or poorly addressed conflicts present increasingly difficult obstacles to effective conservation and management of many wildlife species around the world. The material, visible manifestations of such conflicts are often rooted in less visible, more complex social conflicts between people and groups. Current efforts to incorporate stakeholder engagement typically do not fully acknowledge or address the social conflicts that lie beneath the surface of conservation issues, nor do they consistently create the necessary conditions for productive transformation of the root causes of conflict. Yet, the ultimate level of social carrying capacity for many species will depend on the extent to which conservation can reconcile these social conflicts, thereby increasing social receptivity to conservation goals. To this end, conservation conflict transformation (CCT) offers a new perspective on, and approach to, how conservationists identify, understand, prevent, and reconcile conflict. Principles and processes from the peacebuilding field inform CCT and offer useful guidance for revealing and addressing social conflicts to improve the effectiveness of conservation efforts. The Human-Wildlife Conflict Collaboration (HWCC) has adapted and demonstrated these principles for application in conservation through capacity building and conflict interventions, transforming how many practitioners in the conservation field address conflict. In this article, we discuss current limitations of practice when addressing conflict in conservation, define conflict transformation, illustrate two analytical models to orient the reader to the benefits of CCT, and present two case studies where CCT was applied usefully to a conservation-related conflict.
Article
Full-text available
Previous studies have pointed out the importance of empathy in improving attitudes toward stigmatized groups and toward the environment. In the present article, it is argued that environmental behaviors and attitudes can be improved using empathic perspective-taking for inducing empathy. Based on Batson’s Model of Altruism, it was predicted that higher levels of empathy would improve environmental attitudes and behaviors. It was also predicted that a causal model could be established between empathy and environmental attitudes and behaviors. A study using a factorial design (2 × 2) is reported on the relationship between empathy level (high or low), natural object viewed (bird or tree), and environmental attitudes and behaviors. The results of this study indicate that participants who showed a high empathy level displayed stronger environmental behaviors and attitudes. Additionally, a path analysis shows the moderating effects of evoking empathy for a natural object (bird or tree) on willingness to act in a way that protects the environment (attitudes and behaviors).
Book
Mark Sagoff has written an engaging and provocative book about the contribution economics can make to environmental policy. Sagoff argues that economics can be helpful in designing institutions and processes through which people can settle environmental disputes. However, he contends that economic analysis fails completely when it attempts to attach value to environmental goods. It fails because preference-satisfaction has no relation to any good. Economic valuation lacks data because preferences cannot be observed. Willingness to pay is benchmarked on market price and thus may reflect producer cost not consumer benefit. Moreover, economists cannot second-guess market outcomes because they have no better information than market participants. Mark Sagoff's conclusion is that environmental policy turns on principles that are best identified and applied through political processes. Written with verve and fluency, this book will be eagerly sought out by students and professionals in environmental policy as well as informed general readers.
Article
Moral outrage—anger at violation of a moral standard—should be distinguished from anger at the harm caused by standard-violating behavior. Recent research that used experimental manipulation to disentangle these different forms of anger found evidence of personal and empathic anger, but not of moral outrage. We sought to extend this research by assessing anger at a more extreme moral violation: torture. If the person tortured is a member of one’s group (nationality), anger may not be over the moral violation but over the harm done to one of “us.” In an experiment designed to create the necessary appraisal conditions, we found clear evidence of identity-relevant personal anger (anger when a person from one’s nationality is tortured) but little evidence of moral outrage (anger even when a person from an identity-irrelevant nationality is tortured). Implications for understanding moral emotion and moral motivation are discussed.