ChapterPDF Available

The Implicit Volition Model: The Unconscious Nature of Goal Pursuit

Authors:
400
The set of dual- process models” that
emerged from the 1970s through the 1990s
revolutionized the way we think about the
nature of consciousness and processing in
the mind that is unconscious. These mod-
els reinvigorated research on motivation in
order to better understand not merely what
motivates behavior but what motivates the
use of either systematic or heuristic thought
processes, as well as the transition from one
to the other during self- regulation. These
models of a motivated social cognition typi-
cally described a default processing system
that quickly makes sense of stimuli in a
fashion that relies on the mere triggering of
associations but one that can be modified by
a separate system where one may alter these
outputs through new processing, processing
that would allow one to initiate operations
that promote achieving some end. This regu-
lation of responding to serve the intentions
and goals of the individual is how control is
defined. Despite the utility of these models,
there are two issues that arise from research
inspired by this dual- process approach that
are the focus of analysis in this chapter
The first is that contrasting controlled
processes with automatic processes suggests
that there are some forms of social cognition
that are goal- directed and motivated (con-
trolled), and others that are not, that happen
too quickly for control to be deployed (e.g.,
Fazio, 1990). I argue here that this distinc-
tion, while a useful metaphorical device,
is likely a false dichotomy. It is true that
most dual- process models have described
these two types of processes in terms of a
continuum in which the endpoints reflect
absolute states, with most implicit process-
ing reflecting some degree of control. Bargh
(1990) distinguished between the purely
automatic process and the goal- dependent
automatic process, once again capturing the
idea that much of social cognition that hap-
pens outside awareness may still be moti-
vated. However, these distinctions do not go
far enough. All cognition is social (in that
it occurs within the norms, values, expec-
tations, and shared beliefs of the environ-
ment and culture in which it occurs), and
a defining aspect of social cognition is its
goal- directedness. Even low-level implicit
cognition, such as how and where to place
attention selectively, what from among a
complex stimulus array we perceive, how we
categorize, and the experience of the passage
of time are controlled by goals. It does not
make sense, beyond the metaphorical level,
to talk about controlled as opposed to other
types of cognitive processing. Cognitive pro-
cessing is a tool used to serve the needs of
the organism, and, therefore, is controlled.
This is linked to the second issue I analyze
in this chapter, that of consciousness and
C H A P T E R 2 7
The Implicit Volition Model
The Unconscious Nature of Goal Pursuit
Gordon B. Moskowitz
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 400 1/2/2014 12:57:43 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 401
control. In the initial wave of dual- process
models, the distinction between a motivated/
goal- directed process and an automatic pro-
cess made sense, because control was defined
as borne of the conscious will and the
explicit desire to attain an end. The defin-
ing features of an automatic process (aside
from its inability to be controlled) were said
to be its efficiency and ability to be triggered
and run to completion without conscious
intent or awareness. This implied that con-
trol had to be defined as requiring aware-
ness, effort, and conscious intent. Control
meant either (1) explicitly using processing
to modify the outputs of an automatic pro-
cess so that goals were better attained (e.g.,
Devine, 1989; Fiske & Neuberg, 1990; Gil-
bert, 1989; Strack, Schwarz, Bless, Kübler,
& Wänke, 1993), or (2) consciously setting
desired ends and engaging operations for the
explicit purpose of delivering a desired state.
In each case monitoring and feedback pro-
cesses provide requisite information about
progress toward the goal that allows the
system to know whether to continue and at
what pace (e.g., Carver & Scheier, 1981).
In the intervening years, however, a grow-
ing line of research on unconscious goals
has rendered the “automatic– controlled”
distinction muddier. It is not merely that all
cognition is controlled, but that this is pos-
sible because control need not be defined as
conscious.
The conceptualization of control as not
being synonymous with effort, inefficiency,
and conscious contemplation of goals was
first discussed in earnest in work on mind-
sets and the phases of goal pursuit (e.g.,
Gollwitzer, 1990), the theory of lay epis-
temics (Kruglanski, 1990), Bargh’s (1990)
auto- motive model, and my own research in
graduate school on goal effects on implicit
inference (Moskowitz, 1993; Uleman &
Moskowitz, 1994) and priming effects
(Thompson, Roman, Moskowitz, Chai-
ken, & Bargh, 1994). Yet it must be rec-
ognized that much of the classic theorizing
on human goal pursuit (e.g., Lewin, 1936;
Zeigarnik, 1927) and animal goal pursuit
(Tolman, 1932) had long ago conceptualized
goal pursuit as not requiring consciousness.1
Other classic approaches between the 1930s
and the implicit goal “revival” of the 1990s
were merely agnostic on the issue, with mod-
els that focused on conscious goals, but that
were amenable to the notion of unconscious
goals, had one thought to introduce them
(e.g., Atkinson, 1964; Carver & Scheier,
1981). Having consciousness does not mean
humans lack the ability to process without
it, and this key point took some time to be
rediscovered when it comes to issues relating
to control.
While synthesizing decades of research
on implicit versus explicit cognition, dual-
process models have fallen short in synthe-
sizing research on implicit versus explicit
volition. Even modern models have not
fully integrated this conceptualization of
control. For example, Payne (2006) pro-
posed a process dissociation model to
explain stereotype- based biases that persist
in responding even when one intends to be
unbiased. Payne argued that dual- process
theories such as that introduced by Payne,
Lambert, and Jacoby (2002) “attempt to
explain when, how, and why behavior is
driven by automatic versus intentionally
controlled aspects of thought. . . . [We] have
proposed a particular dual- process theory
to account for both intentional control over
decisions and the patterns of unintended
bias seen in snap judgments” (p. 288). Payne
posited that faces of black men trigger auto-
matic associations (semantic and emotional)
that dictate responding when controlled
processing fails. A “weapons task” was used
to examine whether control fails or succeeds
(and what default processing occurs when it
fails). In this task, faces of black or white men
preceded an image of either a weapon or a
tool, and participants needed to identify the
object as a weapon or tool. Results showed
that with ample time participants were accu-
rate (but still faster to decide “weapon” when
they had seen a black man’s face). However,
when pressured for time, participants could
not implement control via the “required”
effort, and control failed: Participants were
more likely to report seeing a weapon when
any image was preceded by a black face.
Payne concluded that activation of weapons
when participants saw black faces was auto-
matic. Control is relegated to a conscious/
effortful process in which the prevention
of the expression of those stereotypes may
occur. The bias even emerges when people
are instructed not to stereotype, strength-
ening Payne’s conclusion that activation of
a stereotype is more efficient than control:
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 401 1/2/2014 12:57:43 PM
402 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
“In this and other studies, the weapon bias
seems largely independent of intent. This is
important because it means that the bias can
coexist with conscious intentions to be fair
and unbiased” (p. 288). While it is true that
they can coexist, the implication that this
makes the bias uncontrollable is not true.
A striking majority of modern dual-
process accounts have yet to acknowledge
the unconscious role of goals. For example,
in the domain of prejudice, Mahzarin Ban-
aji, a developer of the Implicit Association
Test (IAT), noted on the television show The
Cycle (February 14, 2013) how we can view
the control of prejudice: “Some of us have
used the power of our conscious minds to
tell ourselves that information simply is not
correct, whereas others have not. . . . And
that’s really the difference.” The association
of bias with a group cannot be controlled,
according to this account, but behavior can
under the appropriate conditions be predi-
cated on awareness of the bias and the con-
scious motivation to rectify (overturn) the
bias.
This failure to incorporate a role for
implicit goals in control over implicit cogni-
tion, such as the activation of stereotypes or
the implicit association of negative affect to
a group, has implications not only for theory
but also for how policymakers and practi-
tioners approach the control of unwanted
bias. For example, Devine, Forscher, Austin,
and Cox (2012) developed a bias reduction
training program for medical practitioners
based on the following logic: “When they
believe they have acted with bias, people
who endorse values opposed to prejudice
are motivated to inhibit the expression of
implicit bias by seeking out information
and putting effort into tasks they believe
would help them break the prejudice habit”
(p. 1268). The intervention draws from dual-
process model notions of control, aimed at
training people to develop new conscious
responses when faced with awareness of
a bad habit (implicit bias). Such a strategy
based on effort can be effective, but fails to
acknowledge the complementary role for
goals that do not require effort.
An example of a model that has altered/
modernized its conception of control is
Sherman’s (2006) quadruple- process model.
This model identifies many types of auto-
matic and controlled processes that can be
summarized as falling within four general
categories of processes— two classes of auto-
matic and two classes of control processes.
The first class of control is what Sher-
man called regulation, or overturning bias
(OB), processes in which one is attempting
to inhibit or overturn unwanted informa-
tion that one has detected in one’s response
(e.g., the presence of a stereotype, or any
unwanted thought). The second type of con-
trol is what Sherman called discrimination
or detection processes, in which the person
exerts consciousness and effort to analyze
stimulus items in the service of a goal to get
accurate information (to determine the qual-
ity of a persuasive message, the attributes
of a person, etc.). Whether the role of con-
sciousness and effort in control is necessary
is challenged by Sherman’s model. Though
not the central purpose of that model, it has
the flexibility to incorporate unconscious
control by offering a processing model “that
does not treat automaticity/control as the
central or defining distinction among pro-
cesses. Instead, the particular nature of the
process is the key question (i.e., What does
the process do?) and the automatic versus
controlled nature of the process is only one
important feature of the process” (p. 181).
Calanchini and Sherman (2013) recently
reiterated this stance:
The operation of Detection [D] and Overcom-
ing Bias [OB] demands a more nuanced por-
trayal of automaticity and control because D
and OB possess features of both. For example,
though it is clear that their operation can be
disrupted, it also is clear that they are suffi-
ciently efficient to influence responses during
the performance of implicit tasks. This sug-
gests two important points. First, researchers
should resist the temptation to describe pro-
cesses as either automatic or controlled. . . .
Second, we need to broaden the range of pro-
cesses that may be characterized as automatic.
However, a fully explicated account of how
implicit volition is integrated into the model
has yet to be developed. For all the emerging
evidence supporting dissociating the four
processes of the quadruple- process model
(e.g., Calanchini & Sherman, 2013), none
has yet focused on unconscious goals.
Most approaches to control fall squarely
into what Sherman (2006) called an OB
response, yet do not offer the flexibility of
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 402 1/2/2014 12:57:43 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 403
Sherman’s model for conceptualizing OB as
an implicit process. And because they are
contingent on conscious awareness of a bias-
ing influence, they circumvent the possibil-
ity of unconscious control. While stages of
the control process may be automated, they
describe the enterprise of control as con-
tingent upon the existence of (1) awareness
of bias, (2) explicit motivation to counter-
act that bias, (3) the possession of a theory
regarding how to counteract the bias accu-
rately, (4) the ability (cognitive resources)
to deploy a strategy to counteract the bias,
and (5) lack of disruption from concomitant
mental operations. Indeed, this set of con-
tingencies describes not only how people
may regulate the goal of being nonbiased
but also a more general form of explicit self-
regulation that can apply to the pursuit of
any goal. This is why rather than use the
term overturning bias, the implicit volition
model (IVM) describes such control pro-
cesses as reactive control.
Reactive control is initiated as a reaction
to an existing state in which a shortcoming,
or relative failure, in the pursuit of a desired
end is detected (e.g., a goal not being met, a
bias in one’s responding). Importantly, the
IVM further stipulates that these processing
stages in reactive control that compensate
for or counteract a failure or a shortcoming
in attaining a desired goal do not need to
be conscious. The bias or shortcoming can
be implicitly triggered, as can the motiva-
tion to counteract the bias, as well as theo-
ries about the operations that need be initi-
ated to achieve the goal and the operations
themselves. Stating that the processes in
reactive control need not be conscious does
not in any way undermine the value of reac-
tive approaches to control that are rooted in
consciousness. It simply highlights that such
approaches are limited, constrained by the
assumption that control cannot be implicit.
Reactive control is only complemented and
extended by allowing for implicit goals.
The allowance for implicit goals does not
merely extend how we understand reactive
control. It also highlights a second set of
control processes that can be contrasted to
reactive controlproactive control. Rather
than seeing control as a reaction to feedback,
Sherman (2006) described “discrimination”
or “detection” processes as a set of control
processes that directs how stimulus infor-
mation is analyzed when a goal has been
adopted (e.g., a goal to get accurate informa-
tion leading to closer attention to individuat-
ing information about a person). This reflects
a classic goal- setting approach to control, in
which goal pursuit is set in motion by the
selection of a desired state (through delib-
eration among possible choices and evalua-
tion of inputs, e.g., Carver & Scheier, 1981;
Chaiken, Liberman, & Eagly, 1989; Goll-
witzer, 1990) rather than as a counteractive
response to negative feedback. The IVM
refers to such processes as proactive control,
or control that involves triggering a goal
that then directs cognition and behavior in
the service of goal attainment. Again, such
control can be wholly implicit— one need
not be aware of either the desired state or of
the processes engaged to move toward goal
attainment (the host of mental operations
initiated relating to the implementation and
strategies for pursuing the goal). For exam-
ple, in the Stroop task we see a controlled
process of naming a color interfered with by
a so- called “automatic process” of reading
words and inferring the meaning in those
words. But the latter process is no less con-
trolled than the former process. We simply
fail to recognize the goal that directs the lat-
ter process. Though participants performing
a Stroop task are explicitly asked to pursue
the goal of naming colors, they also bring
with them their habitual goal of distilling
meaning from words This latter goal has
receded into the background and operates
implicitly, but this does not make its pursuit
and influence any less controlled.
To illustrate the distinction between reac-
tive and proactive control let us return to the
example of an unwanted thought associated
with a group, such as a prejudice or a stereo-
type. Models that focus on reactive control
(1) assume that control occurs to compen-
sate for bias, and that such bias is introduced
by the typical operations of the mind that
trigger stereotypes outside of awareness,
without conscious intent, even among low-
prejudice people, and (2) implicate aware-
ness of bias as necessary to engage the coun-
teractive steps deemed necessary for control.
While this is a useful procedure for reducing
bias, anything other than this reactive path
to control will be ignored by a model pos-
iting that control over implicit stereotypes
and prejudices must be more effortful than
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 403 1/2/2014 12:57:43 PM
404 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
the implicit processes that trigger them (and
such assumptions define most dual process
models). This discounts the viability of pro-
active control, because the processes that
give rise to stereotyping and prejudice would
be beyond the reach of such control, leaving
only modification of these outputs of auto-
matic processing as a viable control strategy.
The IVM proposes that not only is the
reactive approach not limited to conscious
control attempts, but also that the implica-
tion of implicit control opens the door to
proactive control of these biases. There is
no reason to assume that to prevent stereo-
typed responses is more effortful than the
processes that trigger them. For example,
when goals are accessible that are antitheti-
cal with stereotyping they proactively initi-
ate implicit processes associated with those
goals that promote goal attainment. This
includes processes that dictate how the per-
son is categorized and whether stereotypes
are activated or inhibited (Moskowitz, Goll-
witzer, Wasel, & Schaal, 1999; Moskowitz
& Li, 2011). The cognitive processes trig-
gered in response to any given target vary
from situation to situation as one’s goals
in the situation dictate. And one’s goals
need not dictate stereotypes being retrieved
from memory, despite the ease with which
this may occur when pursuing some types
of goals. A thought experiment, though
extreme, illustrates the point. Imagine a
white American injured in a terrorist attack,
who is bloodied and worrying about ampu-
tation, when a black man emerges from the
crowd and says, “Relax, I’m a doctor. I can
help you.” Will cultural stereotypes of black
people be activated? A model of implicit,
proactive control argues that they will not,
because one’s goals lead not to the recruit-
ment of those associations but to associa-
tions related to a different category (doc-
tor), inhibiting interfering associations and
inferences. From this perspective, proactive
stereotype control is more than preventing
a stereotype’s activation. Such activation is
itself serving a goal (e.g., to understand what
a person is like and likely to do, to make pre-
dictions, to feel power, to enable feelings of
ingroup superiority, etc.). It is just that the
goal is not visible.
There is no need to describe either pro-
active or reactive control as limited to con-
sciousness, or to describe one as more auto-
matic than the other (though many people
find reactive control more intuitively obvi-
ous as a conscious reaction). The implicit
operation of these forms of control may even
provide a more efficient way to achieve a
goal (e.g., not stereotyping) than explicitly
pursuing the goal (e.g., when explicitly try-
ing not to stereotype leads one ultimately
to rely on stereotypes more). As Bargh and
Huang (2009) argued, consciousness in goal
pursuit captures only a small piece of what
the goal system controls and how it exerts
control. Much of what we think of as auto-
matic is controllable, and much of what we
think of as controlled is regulated outside
conscious awareness in a manner that once
would have been called “automatic” (Bargh,
1990; Custers & Aarts, 2010; Gollwitzer &
Moskowitz, 1996; Kruglanski et al., 2002).
VOLITION NEEDS NO INFERENCES:
THE 13 POSTULATES
OF THE IMPLICIT VOLITION MODEL
The Sovereignty of the Implicit
Goal System
Definitions of control as requiring aware-
ness, consciousness, and effort are so prev-
alent that it led Wegner and Bargh (1998,
p. 453) to state: “the term ‘unconscious con-
trol’ doesn’t seem right at all.” My purpose
in this chapter is to extend the definition of
control; to highlight that the automatic–
controlled dichotomy is limited because
control may lack the features of conscious-
ness, effort, and awareness. It may be habit-
ual, triggered through associations, in the
way that automatic processes are typically
defined. Ostrom (1984) famously declared
the sovereignty of social cognition, herald-
ing the arrival of a distinct field of inquiry
that laid waste to the need to distinguish
between social and nonsocial cognition.
While undeniable that social and nonso-
cial objects have different properties (e.g.,
a rock cannot be motivated to cause harm,
nor does it change across situations) that
lead us to think about them differently, our
thoughts regarding each are, nonetheless,
social in nature. Ostrom (p. 3) proclaimed
that “all knowledge is social knowledge,
and all social knowledge derives from action
on the environment.” Ostrom’s reasoning is
extended here in a way that I hope does not
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 404 1/2/2014 12:57:43 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 405
alter his meaning: Action on the environ-
ment is always in the service of the goals of
the organism within that environment.
That is, what makes cognition social is
not merely that the content of one’s process-
ing may be people, but that the stimulus
whether person or object— must be acted
and reacted toward, and that this reaction
occurs in the service of the goals of the
person in relation to that stimulus within
a social environment (its norms, culture,
opportunities, threats) at that point in time.
What makes social cognition sovereign is
the social nature of all cognition, and what
makes it social is the motivated nature of
all cognition— any commerce with the envi-
ronment introduces needs, motives, values,
and goals that are the guiding force of any
response. Cognition is a tool servicing the
needs, intentions, and goals of the organism
accessible at that moment; it occurs in the
context of the goals of the organism in that
setting.
This point has its opponents. For example,
Bargh (1989, 1990) has argued for classify-
ing social cognition into its goal- dependent
and goal- independent forms. Bargh pro-
vides examples of preconscious automatic-
ity and postconscious automaticity, which
are meant to reflect the types of process-
ing that are independent of goals (indeed,
the only events on which such processing
is said to be contingent is the presence of
a triggering stimulus and the allocation of
attentional resources, so that these stimuli
can be detected and processed by the sen-
sory apparatus). The primary examples pro-
vided are those of social construct activa-
tion and evaluation extraction. Yet research
on implicit goals has led to a reframing of
such phenomena. Construct accessibility
is now discussed as being motivated and
understood only in a goal system (Eitam &
Higgins, 2010). Implicitly associating affect
with categories is also now conceived to be
a controlled phenomenon (e.g., Dasgupta &
Greenwald, 2001; Glaser & Knowles, 2008)
and as occurring because automatic attitude
activation helps organisms pursue survival
goals by providing fast feedback, allow-
ing them to avoid that which is harmful
and approach that which is beneficial (e.g.,
Chen & Bargh, 1999; Eder & Rothermund,
2008). And even the allocation of attention
is controlled (e.g., Moskowitz, 2002).
These developments have led some to
argue that much of conscious control is an
epiphenomenon, something experienced
to deliver a feeling of agency (e.g., van der
Weiden, Aarts, & Ruys, in press; Wegner
& Wheatley, 1999). Huang and Bargh (in
press) even argued that consciousness is an
exaptation of the unconscious. Drawing
from the animal literature, they conclude
that our evolutionarily earlier ancestors,
who lack consciousness in goal pursuit, pro-
vide an illustration that the development of
conscious goals occurs after the development
of unconscious goals. They argue that most
models have it backwards, and unconscious
goal pursuit is the evolutionarily older,
dominant, and more common form of goal
pursuit, with consciousness in goal pursuit
built upon—a scaffold to—older processing
structures.
However, I do not posit that the existence
of an implicit volition system that directs all
cognitive processing renders consciousness
as being uninvolved in control, or epiphe-
nomenal. Instead, I posit that implicit goals
have their genesis in the conscious intentions
and experiences of the individual. While it
is true that consciousness can be epiphe-
nomenal, the IVM is not contingent on a
belief that this is typically the case, or that
unconscious goals are more primary due
to processes of evolution that favor them.
Rather, the IVM argues that goal- directed
responding becomes automated over the
course of one’s lifetime, through learning,
deliberation, evaluation, and other forms
of conscious processing. The needs of the
organism specify what goals to pursue,
under which circumstances, and the specific
means to achieve those ends. Over time, the
choices made to promote needs satisfaction
that associate goals and contexts and means
become routine and automatically engaged,
as consciousness recedes from being neces-
sary for goal- directed responding. The role
of consciousness is often felt through its
impact on establishing associations formed
between cues, environments, people, means
of responding, and goals.
It was a watershed moment for psycholog-
ical science when Bargh (1990) reintroduced
these ideas in the “auto- motive” model and
amended existing models of human goal
pursuit by highlighting the question that had
been ignored: Why assume that one’s goals
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 405 1/2/2014 12:57:43 PM
406 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
in any moment arise from one’s conscious
selection of them? The IVM develops these
ideas by removing consciousness as the point
of focal interest in control and instead focus-
ing on the processes through which control
is implemented in both its reactive and pro-
active forms.
Postulate 1: Goals in Humans Are
Derived from Needs, Motives, and Values
A goal is a desired end state one has not
yet attained but is committed (to varying
degrees, as a function of its value and ones
efficacy) to approach or to avoid, with a
focus toward attaining the desired end in
the future. The “end” can range from the
concrete (“Do not think about white bears”)
to the abstract (“Maintain a rosy outlook”),
and the semantic meaning associated with
the end state (what it means to be “rosy”)
can change with the context. The most
dominant source of goals is needs (e.g., Deci
& Ryan, 1991; McClelland, 1985).2 Needs
were once defined as biological states of the
organism required to sustain life, but are
now accepted to include psychological states
that are essential for well-being and for
survival in the social world. A need speci-
fies classes of incentives, which comprise a
broad set of environmental opportunities
for action that can bring about desired out-
comes (a product of needs and the context).
Motives are broad classes of desires or pre-
ferred states that emerge from needs, a “ten-
dency to desire or be fearful of a specific type
of positive or negative experience in a par-
ticular life domain” (Elliot & Niesta, 2009,
p. 61). They develop early in life through
an infant’s experience with incentives and
become cognitively elaborated over time.
Motives provide the direction and energy for
action by linking desired end states within a
broad domain to incentives and the means
to pursue those incentives. Goals are lower
level yet within this hierarchy, and “are
viewed as the carriers or servants of higher-
order motivational propensities [that are]
. . . usually insufficiently precise to regulate
behavior effectively in that no specific stan-
dard or guideline for behavior is provided”
(Elliot & Niesta, p. 65). Research through-
out the 20th century informs us that that
those actions that are more instrumental for
attaining a goal are specified by opportuni-
ties for acquiring the incentives in the con-
text, and by one’s efficacy at pursuing those
opportunities (e.g., Bandura, 1989; Lewin,
1936; Wicklund & Gollwitzer, 1982). This
suggests that the specific goal selected at
any moment is tied to (1) its desirability
(value), which is specified by the goal’s asso-
ciation to the person’s respective need, and
(2) beliefs about how the goal can be real-
ized and whether it is feasible to expect goal
attainment.
Postulate 2: Goals Are
Cognitively Represented
Tolman (1932) posited that when, via expe-
rience, external cues in the environment
come to satisfy a given need of an animal,
this leads that organism to form an asso-
ciation between the need state and those
environmental cues. The cues come to have
value to the animal in terms of satisfying a
goal. This association among goals, values,
stimuli, and contexts was said to be “rep-
resented” (stored in memory) in the mind
of the perceiving organism so that it would
be triggered when the organism entered the
appropriate context, initiating the relevant
behavior that can deliver the value the stim-
ulus affords. Humans also develop goal rep-
resentations through associative experience.
Bargh (1990, p. 100) stated:
Goals and intents are represented in the mind
in the same fashion as are social constructs,
stereotypes, and schemas . . . goals and intents,
and the procedures . . . and plans . . . associated
with them, may become directly and automati-
cally linked in memory with representations of
environmental features to which they are fre-
quently and consistently associated.
Kruglanski (1996) elaborated on this con-
cept of goal representations by further posit-
ing them to have a hierarchical organization,
in which desired end states are superordi-
nate and processing routines and actions–
behavior routes (means) are low-order com-
ponents of the representation. This allows
the representation to be marked by equi-
finality, in which many means are linked
to one higher- order goal (e.g., Kruglanski,
Pierro, & Sheveland, 2011). It can also be
marked by multifinality (e.g., Kruglanski et
al., 2013) in which several high-order ends
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 406 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 407
are attained by the same means (killing two
birds with one stone).
A state of multifinality suggests one way
that people select an action from among the
many means they might enact (given a state
of equifinality); they select that which has
value for multiple goals, which proffers com-
pounded value. Evidence for a goal represen-
tation with such a multifinal configuration is
provided by showing that the value assigned
to multifinal means declines when a subset
of the goals served by the means is deacti-
vated and means lose their compounded
value (e.g., Chun, Kruglanski, Friedman, &
Sleeth- Keppler, 2011). Evidence for goal rep-
resentations is also provided by the transfer
of affect from superordinate to lower-order
elements of a representation (e.g., energiz-
ing means with the motivational properties
of the goal). Ferguson and Bargh (2004)
showed that the implicit evaluation of its
means is more positive when a goal is held
more strongly (see also, Fishbach, Shah, &
Kruglanski, 2004).
Postulate 3: Goals Representations Link
Ends to Multiple Means and Implicit
Processing Routines
Goal representations include not only an end
state, but associations to relevant means for
attaining the desired end. As an example,
Cacioppo, Priester, and Berntson (1993;
see also Chen & Bargh, 1999; Friedman &
Förster, 2002) had participants enact means
associated with approach and avoidance
goals. Arm flexion (pulling the arm toward
oneself) or extension (pushing it away from
oneself) was enacted during a word evalu-
ation task. They found that neutral words
were evaluated more positively during flex-
ion and negatively during extension. This
could only occur if means (flexion) were
associated with a goal (approach) and its
affect, and this affect then transferred to the
neutral object. Shah and Kruglanski (2003)
illustrated that merely thinking about means,
not enacting them, triggers goals associated
with those means, while Aarts and Dijkster-
huis (2000) showed that thinking about a
goal activates its means.
Cogntive processing routines that prepare
one for action are also part of a goal’s repre-
sentation, so the organism is tuned to detect
stimuli relevant to the goal and is precon-
sciously processing relevant information.
Gollwitzer (1990) made this point by focus-
ing on mindsets associated with distinct
phases of goal pursuit. For example, delib-
erative and implemental mindsets function
when goals are being selected versus pur-
sued. They affect thought production, recall
of task- relevant information, analysis of
desirability- related information, inferences
based on feasibility- related information, and
attention.
Processing styles are associated not only
with broad phases of goal pursuit but also
specific goal contents. Balcetis and Dun-
ning (2006) have shown that early stages of
visual processing are shaped by motives. Eye
movements governing the perception of an
ambiguous stimulus array were directed by
preferences, so that a desired interpretation
emerged as a result of implicit perceptual
processing. Balcetis, Dunning, and Granot
(2012) further showed that during binocular
rivalry (where ambiguity is created by expos-
ing each eye to different images), desires
determined which of two images was expe-
rienced. This extends research of Bruner and
colleagues (e.g., Bruner & Goodman, 1947;
Postman, Bruner, & McGinnies, 1948)
showing that values and needs control the
thresholds at which stimuli are perceived.
Many goal representations have been
shown to have associated cognitive process-
ing routines that facilitate goal attainment.
Examples include the following: A goal of
thought suppression has associated implicit
monitoring processes that provide feedback
regarding the absencepresence in the mind
of the unwanted thought (e.g., Galinsky &
Moskowitz, 2007; Macrae, Bodenhausen,
Milne, & Jetten, 1994; Wegner, 1994). A
goal of being egalitarian toward members
of a group leads to inhibition of stereotypes
associated with that group (e.g., Moskow-
itz et al., 1999; Moskowitz & Li, 2011)
and selective attention to cues related to the
group (Moskowitz, Li, Ignarri, & Stone,
2011; Moskowitz, 2002). A goal of being
creative leads to retrieval of remotely asso-
ciated knowledge (Ward, Finke, & Smith,
1995). A goal of approaching gains leads to
focusing concern on aspirations and accom-
plishments, and the strategic inclination to
approach matches to desired end states,
while a goal of avoiding risk leads to focus-
ing concern on protection/safety and the
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 407 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
408 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
strategic inclination to avoid mismatches to
desired goals (Higgins, 2009).
Postulate 4: Goal Representations Specify
Not Merely Means and Ends, but Value
Like vectors, goal representations are
marked by not only a direction in which
one is striving but also valence that marks
the affect associated with attaining the end
and its pursuit. The representation captures
anticipatory desire, a sense that reaching the
end state will have positive consequences.
Most models of goal pursuit implicate the
value of the goal state as a determining force
for commitment to a goal and whether a
goal is transformed into behavior (e.g., Fer-
guson, 2007), such that even infusing affect
(outside consciousness) to neutral seman-
tic knowledge transforms it to a goal (e.g.,
Custers, 2009; Custers & Aarts, 2005). And
decreasing positive affect associated with a
desired end state reduces the motivation to
pursue it (e.g., Aarts, Custers, & Holland,
2007; Winkielman, Berridge, & Willbarger,
2005).
Postulate 5: Goal Representations
Are Marked by Tension States Arising
from Discrepancies
A goal is a desired end state toward which
one is striving. Semantic knowledge of the
end state is not sufficient to label a represen-
tation as a goal, nor is valuing the end state.
Striving must also be represented, which is to
say that feedback regarding progress toward
the end state must indicate a shortcoming
or discrepancy between the valued end-
point and one’s current state (Lewin, 1936,
1951)—the desired end is not yet attained.
When monitoring– feedback reveal such a
discrepancy, an aversive tension arises that is
similar to the drive associated with a physi-
ological need. Lewin posited that goal dis-
crepancies also produce a tension that must
be reduced, providing motivational force
that persists until that tension is satisfied.
One is impelled to respond in goal- directed
ways to eliminate the tension.
This principle was reintroduced into mod-
ern theorizing about goals by Wicklund and
Gollwitzer (1982). They posit that when
shortcomings with respect to a goal pursuit
are encountered (discrepancy), one experi-
ences self- definitional incompleteness (ten-
sion). Tension will be greatest when an indi-
vidual is committed to a goal domain, when
it is self- defining. One manner in which peo-
ple compensate for the sense of incomplete-
ness surrounding a challenged identity is by
attempting to acquire alternative symbols of
success in the domain or new symbols sug-
gesting that one possesses positive qualities
linked to the goal.
In order to know when the discrepancy
has been reduced and the tension addressed,
to know whether to cease or to continue
responding, the processing system is engaged
in monitoring processes. Monitoring of
a goal pursuit provides two types of feed-
back regarding the discrepancy that informs
the system’s “decisions” (e.g., Jostmann &
Koole, 2009). The first type of feedback is
amount of progress toward a goal (Liber-
man & Dar, 2009). The second type is rate
of progress toward the goal that informs the
individual regarding matters of pace (Carver
& Scheier, 1998). Together, these steps of
monitoring, feedback, and operations aimed
at discrepancy reduction comprise a nega-
tive feedback loop (Carver & Scheier, 1981;
Miller et al., 1960) or closed- loop control
system (Powers, 1973) that persists until the
negative state has dissipated and the discrep-
ancy is eliminated (Martin & Tesser, 2009).
Postulate 6: Goal Activation– Selection
and Goal PursuitImplementation Need
Not Be Conscious
There is nothing in Postulates 1–5 that needs
to specify a role for consciousness in any
given goal pursuit. The goal, and its ends,
means, cognitive operations, affect, and dis-
crepancies, by virtue of being mentally repre-
sented, can be selected and pursed in a given
moment without requiring consciousness,
just as with any other mental representation.
Rather, what is specified in these postulates
is a distinction being drawn between pro-
cesses involved in the setting, selection, trig-
gering, creating, and accessibility of a goal
versus processes involved in the implementa-
tion, pursuing, monitoring, and attainment
of a goal. This parallels the more general
case of mental representation activation, in
which a distinction is drawn between a con-
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 408 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 409
struct’s activation and its application (where
the activated construct guides responding;
e.g., Devine, 1989; Gilbert, 1989; Strack et
al., 1993). Each can proceed without con-
sciousness.
Goal activation can be called unconscious
if it meets one of two criteria: (1) The stim-
ulus activating the goal is not consciously
detected (e.g., subliminal presentation) or
(2) one’s state of goal activation is not con-
sciously noticed, even if at some point either
the goal- relevant stimuli or the goal itself
had been consciously detected. Chartrand
and Bargh (1996) illustrated these criteria in
two seminal experiments. In the first, goals
were primed by subliminal exposure to goal-
relevant words; in the second, by conscious
exposure to the words as part of a “scram-
bled sentence task” (a set of words in jum-
bled order had to be arranged in a fashion
that produced a coherent sentence). In each
case the unconscious triggering of the goal
yielded the same mental operations as when
the goal in question had been consciously
introduced.
Goal pursuit can be implicit when the
processes serving the goal (1) are not con-
sciously initiated or detected, or (2) they
are consciously initiated but the connection
between the response and the goal is not
detected. Examples of the former, in which
people engage in responses without knowing,
are revealed using a host of tasks, such as eye
tracking (e.g., Balcetis & Dunning, 2006),
mouse trajectories (e.g., Freeman, Dale, &
Farmer, 2011; Packer, Miners, Ungson, and
Okten (in preparation), and reaction time
measures (e.g., facilitating response times to
a goal- relevant target when it is the focus of
attention, and reducing response times to a
focal target when it is not) are used to reveal
selective attention (e.g., Custers & Aarts,
2007; Gollwitzer, 1993; Moskowitz, 2002;
Shah, 2003). For example, Trawalter, Todd,
Baird, and Richeson (2008) showed that
white participants who had avoidance goals
related to black people (due to feelings of
threat) selectively directed attention towards
black faces, even though the faces were pre-
sented for only 30 milliseconds, too brief a
time to direct attention consciously to a face.3
Four general categories of goal pursuits
emerge when crossing the dimension of pres-
ence versus absence of consciousness with
the dimension of goal activation– setting ver-
sus goal pursuit– implementation. The first
category is the consciously primed goal that
has conscious operations (which has been
the target of much of the history of research
on goals). The second is the unconsciously
primed goal that has unconscious operations
(e.g., in the Stroop task in which goals to dis-
till meaning lead to the reading of words to
be the dominant response rather than color-
naming). The third is the consciously primed
goal with unconscious operations (e.g., when
conscious attempts at thought suppression
yield implicit monitoring processes). The
fourth category is unconsciously primed
goals with conscious operations (e.g., when
conscious flexion is influenced by implicit
approach goals). Of course, any given goal
pursuit can have a mixture of conscious and
unconscious operations, as well as any oper-
ation being able to serve multiple conscious
and unconscious goals that are activated
simultaneously.
Postulate 7: Goal Representations Vary
in Their State of Accessibility (and Can
Be Primed)
As stipulated in Postulate 6, because goals
are representations, conscious deliberation
about what goal to pursue is not neces-
sary. A goal can be passively primed (attain
a state of readiness by being accessible in
working memory) either through internal
mental operations or external cues associ-
ated with the goal (features of the environ-
ment) that serve to trigger the goal. Bargh
(1990, p. 100) stated:
The mechanism proposed here by which the
social environment may control judgments,
decisions, and behavior is the formation of
direct and automatic mental links between
representations of motives and goals in mem-
ory (and consequently the goals and plans
associated with them) and the representations
of the social situations in which those motives
have been frequently pursued in the past. The
result of this automatic associative link is that
the motive– goal–plan structure becomes acti-
vated whenever the relevant triggering situa-
tional features are present in the environment.
Goal priming, as a subtype of construct
priming more generally, is governed by the
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 409 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
410 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
principles of activation and inhibition that
apply to other representations, such as ste-
reotypes, categories, and attitudes. The
probability that goal representations are
“activated directly by environmental infor-
mation is a joint function of their applicabil-
ity to the information and their accessibil-
ity in memory” (Bargh, p. 100).4 To review
illustrations of goal priming the literature
is next divided according to ways goals are
primed.
The Unconscious Triggering of a Goal
by an Undetected Stimulus
Goals are unconsciously primed by sublimi-
nal exposure to words linked to the goal
(e.g., Chartrand & Bargh, 1996), but this
is not the only way. Since significant others
are associated with specific goals, sublimi-
nal exposure to those significant others can
prime the goal (e.g., Fitzsimons & Bargh,
2003; Shah, 2003). And not all implicit
primes are in the external environment. It
is possible to prime a goal from one’s men-
tal activity. For example, observing others’
behavior leads one to infer the goals of those
others, often without awareness that infer-
ences have been made and, implicitly prim-
ing that goal (Aarts, Gollwitzer, & Hassin,
2004).
The Unconscious Triggering of a Goal
by Consciously Detected Stimuli
Similar to the scrambled sentence task of
Chartrand and Bargh (1996), Bargh, Goll-
witzer, Lee-Chai, Barndollar, and Trötschel
(2001) triggered a goal in participants
unconsciously by having them work con-
sciously on word search puzzles containing
goal- relevant words. Aarts and Dijksterhuis
(2003) used a picture of an environment
to increase accessibility of goals associ-
ated with that environment. Williams and
Bargh (2008) showed that physical sensa-
tions associated with an object trigger goals
with which those sensations are metaphori-
cally linked. Kay, Wheeler, Bargh, and Ross
(2004) showed that goals may be primed
by objects in the room. And people with
whom we interact trigger goals linked with
those people (e.g., Moskowitz et al., 2011;
Richeson & Shelton, 2007; Trawalter et al.,
2008).
Consciously Selected Goals That Implicitly
Retain Accessibility
A goal consciously selected at one point in
time can retain its accessibility in later con-
texts in which the individual lacks aware-
ness that the goal is now accessible. This can
be illustrated when one believes that he or
she has disengaged from a goal. This type
of priming is seen in the research of Dijk-
sterhuis, Bos, Nordgren, and Van Barren
(2006), in which problem- solving goals were
consciously relinquished prior to resolving
the problem. Goal accessibility was shown
to linger by participants continuing to work
on the problem unconsciously. Research
on implementation intentions (specifying
if–then plans that link cues to responses)
is another example (e.g., Gollwitzer, 1993;
Parks-Stamm & Gollwitzer, 2009). Con-
sciousness is needed to form an intention but
not to trigger a plan. The mere presence of a
cue specified by the plan implicitly initiates
the response.
Goals That Attain Heightened Accessibility
from Discrepancy Detection
Discrepancies can be primed (e.g., Custers &
Aarts, 2007) as well as consciously detected
(either by external agents giving feedback
or by one’s monitoring processes). Even if
consciously detected, the discrepancy can
ultimately recede into the unconscious if
responses are made at a later point in time,
when one is not aware of its lingering accessi-
bility. This occurs not only when a response
is temporally distanced from discrepancy
detection but also when the response bears
no surface resemblance to the goal and does
not seem relevant to it (e.g., Koole, Smeets,
van Knippenberg, & Dijksterhuis, 1999;
Gollwitzer, Wicklund, & Hilton, 1982;
Monteith, Ashburn- Nardo, Voils, & Czopp,
2002; Moskowitz, 2002).
Chronic Goals
Bargh (1990) provided an extensive review
of goals that, through consistent and habit-
ual pursuit, acquire a chronic state of height-
ened accessibility that persists across a vari-
ety of contexts. These goals are associated
with individuals’ long- standing interests and
are highly relevant to their most cherished
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 410 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 411
values and motives (e.g., Moskowitz, 1993,
2002; Moskowitz et al., 1999).
Consciously Selected Goals That Explicitly
Retain Accessibility
This category of goal priming occurs when
one’s goals attain heightened accessibility by
being consciously selected, with conscious
focus on the goal and its relevance to one’s
behavior both being maintained throughout
goal pursuit.
Postulate 8: Goals Are Regulated
by Compensatory Responses That Include
Implicit Cognition
Wegner and Pennebaker (1993) provide
a framework in which control of mind is
combined under the same umbrella as con-
trol of behavior. Just as a goal discrepancy
triggers tension and goal- relevant behav-
ioral responses, so too does it trigger goal-
relevant mental operations. Cognition initi-
ated in self- regulation, whether in the form
of reactive or proactive control, is compen-
satory in that it exists to counteract the ten-
sion arising from a discrepancy between a
current and a desired state. Automating such
responses facilitates goal attainment by pro-
viding greater efficiency for initiation and
regulation of a goal pursuit. It allows for
(1) heightened readiness to attend to, detect,
and respond to stimuli; (2) the retrieval and
inhibition of semantic knowledge; and (3)
activation of compatible and inhibition of
incompatible goals (a horizontal communi-
cation among goals called goal shielding;
Shah, Friedman, & Kruglanski, 2002).
Three examples illustrate the compensa-
tory nature of even extremely low-level cog-
nitive functioning. First, Van Bavel, Packer,
and Cunningham (2011) examined a variant
of “own-race bias.” Rather than study pref-
erential recall for members of one’s racial
group, they examined biased processing of
people with whom one shared a randomly
assigned group membership. They proposed
that motivation to process members of one’s
own (nonracial) group preferentially would
be reflected by implicit modulation at even
low-level stages of face processing. Since
facial recognition processes originate within
100–200 milliseconds of stimulus onset
in an area of the fusiform gyrus called the
fusiform face area (FFA), they used func-
tional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI)
to assess how FFA activity was impacted by
faces made motivationally relevant through
participants’ assignment to a randomly
determined ingroup. The results showed
greater FFA activity for these goal- relevant
faces. The goal of preferential processing of
ingroup members triggered compensatory
control processes of face perception in the
FFA.
Examples of goal shielding provide a sec-
ond illustration of the implicit nature of com-
pensatory cognition. Shah (2003) primed
two goals: a consciously set analytic reason-
ing goal and an unconsciously primed cre-
ativity goal (via subliminal presentation of a
picture of a significant other who valued the
participant’s creativity). For some partici-
pants, the conscious and unconscious goals
were compatible; for others, the goals were
irrelevant to each other. After being primed,
participants performed a reasoning task.
Goal shielding is observed in the form of
response facilitation when the two goals are
compatible. Priming with a compatible goal
(creativity) initiated implicit operations that
pulled the participant’s attention toward and
promoted reasoning goals. Aarts et al. (2007)
illustrated goal shielding among incompat-
ible goals in which we see inhibition rather
than facilitation. Inhibitory processes ward
off distractions and keep progress to a focal
goal on track. Finally, goal shielding has also
been shown to be a compensatory process
when the obstacles to a goal serve to trigger
heightened commitment to and accessibility
of that goal. For example, Fishbach, Fried-
man, and Kruglanski (2003) had participants
perform a task that exposed them to words
related to a temptation (e.g., cake) to one of
their goals (e.g., diet). This was followed by a
task that assessed the ease of thinking about
the goal compared to control items. After the
temptation, thoughts of the goal were more
prevalent. Temptation triggers a functional
response when encountered: Relevant goals
and means are brought to mind to counteract
the temptation, what Fishbach et al. called
counteractive control. This allows a tempta-
tion, ironically, to serve as a cue to avoid dis-
tractions and obstacles, and enhances stay-
ing on track in goal pursuit.
Finally, the direction of attention to goal-
relevant stimuli illustrates yet a third implicit
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 411 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
412 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
compensatory cognitive operation. Moskow-
itz (2002) gave participants the explicit goal
of identifying the direction (up or down) in
which a target item moved, while ignoring
a distracting second target that moved in a
different direction (left to right). Half of the
participants also held an implicit egalitarian
goal. Importantly, the targets in this task
were actually words that moved too quickly
to be identified as such, words that some-
times were relevant to egalitarian goals. The
results showed that attention was distracted
toward targets that were to be ignored, but
only if one had an egalitarian goal, and only
if the target was a goal- relevant word. Mos-
kowitz et al. (2011) conceptually replicated
this point using people as the goal- relevant
targets. Participants were shown an array
of four images of men and asked to iden-
tify (via a button press) which of them was
wearing a bow tie. The correct response was
always a white man in a bow tie, yet the
array at times contained an image of a black
man as one of the three nonfocal items. Par-
ticipants once again showed displaced atten-
tion at speeds too fast for conscious control,
but only if two conditions were met: (1) The
array had to contain a black man’s face, and
(2) the participant had to have been primed
previously with a goal of being egalitarian
to black men.
Postulate 9: Goal Attainment Reduces
Goal Accessibility
Once a goal is attained, the means and incen-
tives that serve that goal are divested of their
motivational force. This does not mean that
the end state no longer has value. It merely
means that striving to attain that state, enact-
ing means to approach the value linked to the
state, is not of use at that time and in that
context. A goal requires both a discrepancy
between a current state and an end state,
and value being attached to that end state.
If one values a state but there is no discrep-
ancy between one’s current state and that
desired state, one does not have a goal. This
is why one will persist at responding until a
discrepancy is reduced and tension is allevi-
ated (see Martin & Tesser, 2009). Evidence
for this “persistence until” logic is provided
by showing that so long as a discrepancy
exists, one displays classic characteristics
of motivated behavior, such as persistence
in the face of obstacles and resumption of a
disrupted task. But these characteristics are
not seen when feedback signaling significant
progress toward the goal is provided by the
system’s monitoring processes (e.g., Cesario,
Plaks, & Higgins, 2006; Förster, Liberman,
& Higgins, 2005; Koole et al., 1999; Liber-
man & Förster, 2000).
For example, Moskowitz et al. (2011,
discussed earlier) found that the attention
of white participants who held egalitarian
goals was distracted to faces of black men.
However, they also found that this act of
compensatory cognition only persisted as
long as the goal was not yet attained. When
people who held egalitarian goals next
wrote essays about success at being egalitar-
ian, their attention was no longer diverted
from the focal task. The essay afforded them
a chance to compensate for their failure at
being egalitarian, thus bringing implicit
compensatory control (selective attention) to
a halt. Moskowitz and Li (2011) also illus-
trated this principle, but using stereotype
inhibition as the compensatory response
that is halted.
Postulate 10: Goals Are Nested Within
Goal Systems That Allow for Rotation
among Goals
Kruglanski et al. (2002) described goals as
embedded in a system of many horizontally
linked goals that impact one another, with
systemwide coordination among compatible
and opposing forces. Goal systems there-
fore raise issues of how to determine what
goal to select in any moment, and which,
from among many possible means, to select
to pursue that goal. Goals linked in a sys-
tem can promote one another, and move-
ment toward one can facilitate standing on
another, but they can compete as well, and
movement toward one goal may require
inhibiting another. Which goal is selected
in a given moment, when people rotate from
one goal to another, and when one disen-
gages from a goal comprises a complex set
of issues that is beyond the scope of a com-
plete review here. However, factors that are
important to these issues are strength of
commitment to the goal, opportunities that
afford one a means to attain the goal, and
the instrumental value those means possess.
These can vary from moment to moment.
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 412 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 413
For example the value of the goal is
impacted by one’s history of goal pursuit
within the context. Baumeister, Vohs, and
Tice (2007) argued that successful goal regu-
lation has a positively reinforcing impact on
the value associated with the goal, increasing
its desirability and strengthening its affec-
tive component, increasing the likelihood
that the goal will again be set as the desired
criterion. Commitment to a goal is impacted
by a variety of factors, one of which is the
number of equifinal means associated with
the goal. Kruglanski et al. (2011) showed
that while having many means linked to
a goal decreases the commitment to any
given means, it increases commitment to the
goal (impacting subjective probability, the
expectancy, that the goal can be achieved).
Brehm and Self (1989) describe commitment
as being determined by factors such as the
strength of the need that yielded the goal
and the incentive value of the task.
Finally, because goals are hierarchically
linked to superordinate goals, motives, and
needs, it is possible that pursuit of one goal
within the system can contradict or conflict
with a superordinate goal. The goal of feel-
ing comforted may lead one to eat a cupcake
despite this conflicting with a long term
and superordinate goal of being healthy and
eating well. As opportunities afford one
chances to pursue a goal, and as the value of
a goal waxes and wanes, we may see behav-
ior that appears inconsistent. But apparent
inconsistency may merely reflect rotation
among goals as contexts and opportunities
dictate.
Postulate 11: Goal Pursuit Is Limited
by Resources
Goals are in competition for shared but
limited resources (e.g., Vohs, Kaikati, Kerk-
hof, & Schmeichel, 2009). Any goal pursuit
depletes this resource to a degree and can
result in the resource pool being usurped.
This results in a state called ego depletion,
marked by a temporary loss of self- control.
Ego depletion is not limited to the domain
responsible for depletion; it represents gen-
eral loss of ability to engage in executive
functioning (e.g., Richeson & Trawalter,
2005; Schmeichel & Baumeister, 2004) and
control (e.g., Vohs, Baumeister, & Ciarocco,
2005). Because ego depletion is a temporary
state, regulatory ability returns after rest
or other interventions. These resources can
be bolstered with training. Gailliot, Plant,
Butz, and Baumeister (2007) showed that
practice at regulation makes one resistant to
ego depletion. The biological basis for deple-
tion and replenishing of the resource pool is
not yet well understood (e.g., Molden et al.,
2012).
Postulate 12: Implicit Control Involves
Both Facilitation and Inhibition
The IVM incorporates the logic of goal
shieldingthat pursuit of a goal involves
processes that not only facilitate attain-
ment of a desired end, but also inhibit
goals, temptations, and means that would
serve as obstacles to attainment of that end.
This makes possible an assortment of con-
trol strategies that previously had not been
deemed possible according to dual- process
theories. In a view of control that is largely
conscious and reactive, the role of control
is to overcome or counteract the effects of
an implicit cognitive process that has been
brought to one’s awareness as a potential
source of bias. The conscious efforts at cor-
rection that ensue represent an important
method to regulate behavior and cognition.
But this approach blinds us to seeing goals
as more than mere conscious tools to deploy
after we become aware of a problem to be
counteracted. Control, if proactive, can pre-
vent an unwanted (biasing) response from
ever being produced. Implicit forms of pro-
active control initiate not only goal- relevant
processing that circumvents the triggering
of the unwanted response but also cogni-
tive activity that inhibits undesired outputs.
Concrete examples of such processes are
seen in research on stereotype control.
In my own laboratory (e.g., Galinsky &
Moskowitz, 2000; 2007; Moskowitz et al.,
1999, 2011; Moskowitz, Salomon, & Taylor,
2000; Moskowitz & Li, 2011; Moskowitz
& Stone, 2012; Sassenberg & Moskowitz,
2005), we have found behavioral evidence
for the interplay of facilitative and inhibitory
processes in proactive stereotype control,
both with chronic goals and goals primed
in the situation. While it is well established
that stereotypes are associated with groups,
and that thinking about the group often
activates such stereotypes outside awareness
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 413 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
414 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
(e.g., Devine, 1989), this is not an obstacle
to proactive control. Indeed, it is argued that
such efficient and effortless activation of
stereotypes is itself a form of proactive con-
trol. Some goals, such as “sense making,”
are compatible with stereotype activation—
the stereotyping is in the service of the goal.
Thus, the prevalence of implicit stereotype
activation is seen here as a reflection of the
prevalence of goals that recruit stereotypes
as part of goal operations. However, because
stereotype activation is controlled by the
self- regulatory system— it is a cognitive tool
recruited for a reason— it is argued that one
has the power quickly and efficiently not to
activate stereotypes by exercising the same
control system. Encountering a member of
a stereotyped group who is relevant to one’s
goal will not lead to stereotype activation
if that goal is incompatible with stereotyp-
ing. Rather, it will lead to heightened goal
activation, to facilitated processing of goal
relevant stimuli (such as tuning attention
to goal- relevant stimuli; Moskowitz, 2002;
Moskowitz et al., 2011; Trawalter et al.,
2008); and to goal- shielding processes of
stereotype inhibition. For example, an egali-
tarian goal is incompatible with stereotyp-
ing. Just as other goals recruit stereotypes
as part of their operations of goal pursuit,
egalitarian goals recruit compensatory cog-
nitive operations that inhibit stereotypes due
to their incompatibility with the goal.
Implicit but motivated inhibition of ste-
reotypes when one is exposed to a stereo-
typed group was first illustrated by Mos-
kowitz et al. (1999). Men with (and without)
chronic egalitarian goals were recruited for
an experiment. They were primed with faces
(Experiment 3) and names (Experiment 4)
of men and women, then asked to respond
to words either related to the female stereo-
type or not. Participants without chronic
egalitarian goals had stereotypes activated
(facilitated responding to stereotypical
words following female faces). But men with
chronic egalitarian goals instead inhibited
stereotypes of women (slower reaction times
to stereotypical words following female
faces). Moskowitz and Li (2011) extended
this finding of implicit inhibition by shift-
ing the stereotyped group to black men, and
shifting the source of the goal from being
chronically held to being manipulated.
White subjects without a chronic egalitarian
goal were brought to the laboratory. Half
were primed with a goal to be egalitarian
to black men. The results revealed a similar
pattern of stereotype inhibition, this time
for people with temporarily induced egali-
tarian goalsseeing a black man slowed
responses to stereotype- relevant words (but
not to control words). But stereotype activa-
tion occurred among people without primed
egalitarian goals.
Such lack of stereotype activation is not
merely a failure at control (e.g., poor regula-
tion of a goal to stereotype), or an indica-
tion of nothing happening when a target is
encountered. It is a goal- directed set of pro-
cesses, including inhibition, being initiated
that service the goal of being egalitarian.
This is illustrated in several experiments in
a variety of ways. First, using the “persis-
tence until” logic reviewed earlier, stereo-
type inhibition ceases to occur if partici-
pants are given the opportunity to write an
essay affirming their egalitarian goal prior
to the reaction time task (e.g., Moskowitz &
Li, 2011; Moskowitz & Stone, 2012). This
indicates a motivated process being shut
down rather than the lack of processing, or
failure at an alternative goal pursuit. Mos-
kowitz et al. (2000, see also Moskowitz &
Stone, 2012) further showed that encoun-
tering goal- relevant people not only leads to
inhibitory processes but also facilitates pro-
cessing of goal- compatible stimuli and leads
to heightened accessibility of the goal itself.
There is now evidence for proactive con-
trol of stereotypes across many laboratories.
Mendoza, Gollwitzer, and Amodio (2010)
had participants form implementation inten-
tions not to stereotype. They found that
implicitly triggering these plans later using
environmental cues led to control over ste-
reotype activation (as well as improved con-
scious control). Similarly, Devine, Plant,
Amodio, Harmon-Jones, and Vance (2002)
showed that people motivated to control
prejudice for internal reasons do not respond
as quickly as other individuals to negative
words after being primed with black faces.
Cunningham, Van Bavel, Arbuckle,
Packer, and Waggoner (2012) argue that
even rapid responses to the race of a face are
controlled by goals, such that race may be
deemed irrelevant for processing. Instead,
low-level processing is directed by the goals
currently triggered, and this can include
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 414 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 415
proactively avoiding race for a more instru-
mental response. Cunningham et al. used
electroencephalography (EEG) to examine
control over processes in the first 100 milli-
seconds of face perception that lead to racial
biases in social categorization. They noted
that “although the relationship between spe-
cific brain regions and ERP [event- related
potential] waves is not perfectly precise, very
early ERP waves, such as the P100 and N170
appear to subserve early face processing”
(p. 2). They examined whether approach
goals attenuate biased processing of black
faces by collecting EEG data as partici-
pants performed a task that presented them
with faces of white and black men. Consis-
tent with prior evidence of racial bias, they
found that white faces were associated with
a larger P100 than black faces. But they also
found proactive control, in that this effect
interacted with goals. An approach goal
altered the influence of race during the first
100 milliseconds of perceptual processing.
Amodio and Devine (2010) reviewed fur-
ther neuroscience evidence to support pro-
active control. They posited that the ante-
rior cingulate cortex (ACC) brain region
monitors for conflicts between intended and
automatic responses, thus representing a
low-level, if not initial, step in control. Con-
flict is low when black targets are paired
with stereotypical items; thus, ACC activ-
ity should be low. However, pairing black
targets with nonstereotypical target items
should lead to high ACC activity, indicating
that control mechanisms are being recruited
early, without conscious deliberation or
awareness.
Postulate 13: Implicit Processes
of Goal Pursuit Need Not Be the Same
as Conscious Goal Pursuit
Implicit control in stereotyping revealed suc-
cess at inhibiting “automatic” processes.
Contrast this with findings from research on
stereotype suppression (e.g., Wegner, 1994)
and avoiding race bias (e.g., Payne, Lambert,
& Jacoby, 2002), in which explicit goal pur-
suit led to control failures. Payne et al. dem-
onstrated that explicit control is limited by
resource demands, whereas Wegner (1994)
found a more debilitating effect— ironically,
stereotype activation increases with the
explicit goal of suppressing stereotypes. A
similar contrast emerges from work on cre-
ativity. Asking people to adopt a goal of hav-
ing a creative solution to a problem leads to
strikingly uncreative responses tethered to
old examples that resemble plagiarism more
than novelty. Priming creativity outside of
consciousness produces the desired increase
in creativity (e.g., Sassenberg & Moskowitz,
2005). Examining decision making, Dijk-
sterhuis et al. (2006) revealed that providing
ample time for conscious responding reduces
the quality of the decisions reached relative
to pursuing the goal of making an accurate
decision when limited to implicit processing
(under load).
However, some examinations have illus-
trated that implicit and explicit goal pursuit
yield similar results following similar pro-
cesses. Chartrand and Bargh (1996) found
that an unconsciously primed goal to form
an impression followed the same processing
stages as when one consciously adopts the
goal of impression formation. And Pessi-
glione et al. (2007) found that on a hand-grip
task in which promise of a reward (money to
be won on a given trial) was presented sub-
liminally, the increase in effort was the same
as when promise of reward was presented
consciously, and the same region of brain
activity moderated effort on the task.
Given that they share the same mecha-
nisms of control (operations, monitoring,
feedback, tension reduction, etc.), and many
illustrations demonstrating that unconscious
and conscious control follow identical pro-
cessing steps, why do some studies demon-
strate an apparent inconsistency— conscious
goal pursuit fails, whereas implicit goal
pursuit succeeds? In some cases, conscious
processing can alter the meaning of the goal,
because deliberation can recruit interpretive
biases that yield changes to how the goal is
framed or understood. The meaning of the
goal “be a good student” can change when
defined in terms of a standard set by one’s
beliefs about personal ability versus a stan-
dard set by what one ought to be to bring
pride to others. Furthermore, conscious goals
invoke metacognition—thoughts about the
goal pursuit. This is especially likely when,
for example, with the weapons task and ste-
reotype suppression, the task itself invokes
theories about how one is biased (that may
or not be accurate) and what one needs to
do prevent/overturn bias (if it is perceived
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 415 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
do to
416 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
to have occurred). When a person is made
aware of bias, the control process is not
merely derailed by what may be incorrect
theories of how control ought to be executed,
but by processing limitations and restrictions
in cognitive capacity. Even with an accurate
theory, conscious execution of the steps may
be rendered incomplete or inexact if one
lacks ability to perform the work required,
such as when resources for control are lim-
ited or responding is at a fast pace. Implicit
control circumvents these pitfalls to control.
Consciousness may at times be an obstacle
to a goal better pursued implicitly; it can
lead one astray by focusing one’s attention
on irrelevant information or causing one to
rationalize an inappropriate response.
CONCLUSION
Dual- process models too often limit con-
trol to that which is conscious and effort-
ful. Despite the counterintuitive feel of it,
control can be, and often is, implicit. And
unlike conceptions of the role of the uncon-
scious in responding that have highlighted
it as a source of error and bias (e.g., heu-
ristic use in decision making), unconscious
goals are an efficient and functional source
for much human responding, perhaps guid-
ing all cognition. It is just as likely that con-
sciousness in control can introduce as much
error and bias as can lack of consciousness.
This suggests that consciousness is not a dis-
tinguishing factor in control: All cognition
is controlled, often implicitly, and conscious
control can have the same operations and
outcomes as unconscious control. Conscious
control need not mean a qualitatively differ-
ent type of processing than implicit control.
Nor need it suggest primacy of one form of
control over the other. As Sherman (2006)
stated: “Rather than treating automatic and
controlled processes as separate categories
of processes it would be more useful to treat
automaticity and control as features of pro-
cesses” (p. 181).
Implicit control suggests that the associa-
tions activated and inhibited when encoun-
tering a stimulus of any type are not inde-
pendent of ones goals. One can respond to
the same target in many ways as a function
of the context, the opportunities for action
within that context, and the goals of the
individual relating to that target at that time
in that context. For example, if one has the
goal of cooperating with others, it may be
that in a given context, the opportunity to
pursue that goal is best afforded by a prefer-
ence for people who share one’s racial iden-
tity, which could promote stereotyping of
outgroups. However, it may be that shared
racial identity does not afford one the best
opportunity to achieve the goal, and catego-
rizing based on race would not occur and
stereotypes would not be triggered. Alterna-
tively, one could have a goal that does pro-
mote categorizing people into racial groups
but discourages stereotype activation as the
dominant association to the group (as illus-
trated by Moskowitz et al., 2011).
Stereotyping, like many unwanted
responses, can be controlled not merely by
reactively changing how we respond when
our implicit goals encourage stereotyping.
It can be controlled by changing one’s goal
and proactively initiating processes that
never yield stereotype activation. Augment-
ing the well- elaborated power of conscious
control is what many goal researchers now
believe to be the more omnipresent form of
control— unconscious goals that implicitly
direct social cognition.
NOTES
1. Tolman (1932, p. 134) warned, regarding goal
pursuits in animals, that “the reader will per-
haps need constantly to remind himself that
the use of the terms perception, mnemoniza-
tion and memory implies nothing as to con-
sciousness.” It can be argued that the notion
of unconscious goals and operations of goal
pursuit got lost in the cognitive revolution
when models of goal pursuit shifted from ani-
mal to human participants, with conscious-
ness as the distinguishing factor elevating
human above animal goal pursuits. With that
shift came fervor for examining rationality
and conscious choice as central to control.
2. Other sources of goals are theories (theo-
ries about the nature of ability; e.g., Grant
& Dweck, 2003) and fantasies about future
hopes (especially by contrasting those fanta-
sies against a standard set by negative aspects
of current reality; e.g., Oettingen, 2000).
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 416 1/2/2014 12:57:44 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 417
3. Since conscious control is possible only after
600 milliseconds elapse once one encounters
a stimulus (e.g., Fazio, 1990), responses made
within this period occur without the benefit
of conscious control. Thus, flashing a cue that
triggers a goal can indicate an implicit goal if
the cue and the goal- directed response occur
within this period prior to consciousness.
4. However, there are also unique features of
goal priming that make it distinct from other
types of accessibility. First, accessibility
strength and its impact on responding depend
on the motivational value of a goal and instru-
mentality of opportunities in the environment
(e.g., Eitam & Higgins, 2010). Second, with
semantic knowledge, the accessibility strength
decreases as time passes from the time of con-
struct activation. The passage of time impacts
goal accessibility differently. Goal representa-
tions contain a discrepancy, the state of which
is being monitored and fed back through the
system. Such operations keep the goal con-
struct reactivated as time passes and increase
accessibility strength, so that its ability to
impact subsequent responding increases as
time passes; the goal looms larger (e.g., Bargh
et al., 2001; Curtis & D’Esposito, 2003;
Förster, Liberman, & Friedman, 2007; Liber-
man & Förster, 2000).
REFERENCES
Aarts, H., Custers, R., & Holland, R. W. (2007).
The nonconscious cessation of goal pursuit:
When goals and negative affect are coacti-
vated. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 92, 165–178.
Aarts, H., & Dijksterhuis, A. (2000). Habits as
knowledge structures: Automaticity in goal-
directed behavior. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 78(1), 53– 63.
Aarts, H., & Dijksterhuis, A. (2003). The silence
of the library: Environment, situational norm,
and social behavior. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 84, 18–28.
Aarts, H., Gollwitzer, P. M., & Hassin, R. R.
(2004). Goal contagion: Perceiving is for pur-
suing. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 87(1), 23–37.
Amodio, D. M., & Devine, P. G. (2010). Regulat-
ing behavior in the social world: Control in the
context of intergroup bias. In R. R. Hassin, K.
N. Ochsner, & Y. Trope (Eds.), Self control
in society, mind and brain (pp. 49–75). New
York: Oxford University Press.
Atkinson, J. W. (1964). An introduction to moti-
vation. Princeton, NJ: Van Nostrand.
Balcetis, E., & Dunning, D. (2006). See what
you want to see: Motivational influences on
perception. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 91, 612– 625.
Balcetis, E., Dunning, D., & Granot, Y. (2012).
Subjective value determines initial dominance
in binocular rivalry. Journal of Experimental
Social Psychology, 48, 122–129.
Bandura, A. (1989). Perceived self- efficacy in the
exercise of personal agency. The Psychologist:
Bulletin of the British Psychological Society,
2, 411–424.
Bargh, J. A. (1989). Conditional automaticity:
Varieties of automatic influence in social per-
ception and cognition. In J. S. Uleman, & J. A.
Bargh (Eds.), Unintended thought (pp. 3 –51).
New York: Guilford Press.
Bargh, J. A. (1990). Auto- motives: Preconscious
determinants of social interaction. In E. T.
Higgins & R. M. Sorrentino (Eds.), Hand-
book of motivation and cognition: Founda-
tions of social behavior (Vol. 2, pp. 93–130).
New York: Guilford Press.
Bargh, J. A., Gollwitzer, P. M., Lee-Chai, A.,
Barndollar, K., & Trötschel, R. (2001). The
automated will: Nonconscious activation and
pursuit of behavioral goals. Journal of Person-
ality and Social Psychology, 81, 1014–1027.
Bargh, J. A., & Huang, J. Y. (2009). The selfish
goal. In G. B. Moskowitz & H. Grant (Eds.),
The psychology of goals (pp. 127–150). New
York: Guilford Press.
Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., & Tice, D. M.
(2007). The strength model of self- control.
Current Directions in Psychological Science,
16(6), 351–355.
Brehm, J. W., & Self, E . A. (1989). The intensity
of motivation. Annual Review of Psychology,
40, 109–131.
Bruner, J. S., & Goodman, C. D. (1947). Value
and need as organizing factors in perception.
Journal of Abnormal Social Psychology, 42,
33–44.
Cacioppo, J. T., Priester, J. R., & Berntson, G.
G. (1993). Rudimentary determinants of atti-
tudes: II. Arm flexion and extension have dif-
ferent effects on attitudes. Journal of Person-
ality and Social Psychology, 65, 5–17.
Calanchini, J., & Sherman, J. W. (2013). Implicit
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 417 1/2/2014 12:57:45 PM
418 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
attitudes reflect associative, non- associative,
and non- attitudinal processes. Social and Per-
sonality Psychology Compass, 7(9), 654–667.
Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1981). Attention
and self- regulation: A control theory approach
to human behavior. New York: Springer.
Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1998). On the
self- regulation of behavior. New York: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Cesario, J., Plaks, J. E., & Higgins, E. T. (2006).
Automatic social behavior as motivated prepa-
ration to interact. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 90, 893–910.
Chaiken, S., Liberman, A., & Eagly, A. H.
(1989). Heuristic and systematic information
processing within and beyond the persuasion
context. In J. S. Uleman & J. A. Bargh (Eds.),
Unintended thought (pp. 212–252). New
York: Guilford Press.
Chartrand, T. L., & Bargh, J. A. (1996). Auto-
matic activation of impression formation and
memorization goals: Nonconscious goal prim-
ing reproduces effects of explicit task instruc-
tions. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 71(3), 464478.
Chen, M., & Bargh, J. A. (1999). Consequences
of automatic evaluation: Immediate behav-
ioral predispositions to approach or avoid the
stimulus. Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin, 25, 215–224.
Chun, W. Y., Kruglanski, A. W., Friedman, R.,
& Sleeth- Keppler, D. (2011). Multifinality in
unconscious choice. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 101, 1124–1137.
Cunningham, W. A., Van Bavel, J. J., Arbuckle,
N. L., Packer, D. J., & Waggoner, A. S. (2012).
Rapid social perception is flexible: Approach
and avoidance motivational states shape P100
responses to other-race faces. Frontiers in
Human Neuroscience, 6, 1–7.
Curtis, C. E., & D’Esposito, M. (2003). Persis-
tent activity in the prefrontal cortex during
working memory. Trends in Cognitive Sci-
ence, 7(9). 415– 423.
Custers, R. (2009). The role of affect in goal rep-
resentations. In G. B. Moskowitz, & H. Grant
(Eds.), The psychology of goals (pp. 179–202).
New York: Guilford Press.
Custers, R., & Aarts, H. (2005). Positive affect
as implicit motivator: On the nonconscious
operation of behavioral goals. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 89, 129–
142.
Custers, R., & Aarts, H. (2007). Goal- discrepant
situations prime goal- directed actions if goals
are temporarily or chronically accessible. Per-
sonality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 33,
623– 633.
Custers, R., & Aarts, H. (2010). The uncon-
scious will: How the pursuit of goals operates
outside of conscious awareness. Science, 329,
47–50.
Dasgupta, N., & Greenwald, A. G. (2001). On
the malleability of automatic attitudes: Com-
bating automatic prejudice with images of
admired and disliked individuals. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 800
814.
Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (1991). A motiva-
tional approach to self. In R. Dienstbier (Ed.),
Nebraska Symposium on Motivation (Vol. 38,
pp. 237–288). Lincoln: University of Nebraska
Press.
Devine, P. G. (1989). Stereotypes and prejudice:
Their automatic and controlled components.
Journal of Personality and Social Psycholgy,
56, 5–18.
Devine, P. G., Forscher, P. S., Austin, A. J., Cox,
& W. T. L. (2012). Long-term reduction in
implicit race bias: A prejudice habit- breaking
intervention. Journal of Experimental Social
Psychology, 48, 1267–1278
Devine, P. G., Plant, E. A., Amodio, D. M.,
Harmon-Jones, E., & Vance, S. L. (2002). The
regulations of explicit and implicit race bias:
The role of motivations to respond without
prejudice. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 82(5), 835–848.
Dijksterhuis, A., Bos, M., Nordgren, L ., & Van
Baaren, R. B. (2006). On making the right
choice: The deliberation- without- attention
effect. Science, 311, 1005–1007.
Eder, A., & Rothermund, K. (2008). When do
motor behaviors (mis)match affective stimuli?:
An evaluative coding view of approach avoid-
ance reactions. Journal of Experimental Psy-
chology: General, 137, 262–281.
Eitam, B., & Higgins, E. T. (2010). Motivation
in mental accessibility: Relevance of a repre-
sentation (ROAR) as a new framework. Social
and Personality Psychology Compass, 3, 1–17.
Elliot, A. J., & Niesta, D. (2009). Goals in the
context of the hierarchical model of approach–
avoidance motivation. In G. B. Moskowitz
& H. Grant (Eds.), The psychology of goals
(pp. 56–76). New York: Guilford Press.
Fazio, R. H. (1990). A practical guide of the use
of response latency in social psychological
review. In C. Hendrick & M. S. Clark (Eds.),
Research methods in personality and social
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 418 1/2/2014 12:57:45 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 419
psychology (pp. 74–97). Newbury Park, CA:
Sage.
Ferguson, M. J. (2007). On the automatic evalu-
ation of end- states. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 92, 596–611.
Ferguson, M. J., & Bargh, A. J. (2004). Liking is
for doing: The effects of goal pursuit on auto-
matic evaluations. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 87(5), 557–572.
Fishbach, A., Friedman, R., & Kruglanski, A.
W. (2003). Leading us not into temptation:
Momentary allurements elicit overriding goal
activation. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 84(2), 296–309.
Fishbach, A., Shah, J. Y., & Kruglanski, A.
W. (2004). Emotional transfer in goal sys-
tems. Journal of Experimental Social Psychol-
ogy, 40(6), 723–738.
Fiske, S. T., & Neuberg, S. L. (1990). A contin-
uum of impression formation, from category-
based to individuating processes: Influences of
information and motivation on attention and
interpretation. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances
in experimental social psychology (Vol. 23,
pp. 1–74). New York: Academic Press.
Fitzsimons, G. M., & Bargh, J. A. (2003). Think-
ing of you: Nonconscious pursuit of inter-
personal goals associated with relationship
partners. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 84(1), 148–163.
Förster, J., Liberman, N., & Friedman, R. S.
(2007). Seven principles of goal activation:
A systematic approach to distinguishing goal
priming from priming of non-goal constructs.
Personality and Social Psychology Review,
11, 211–233.
Förster, J., Liberman, N., & Higgins, E. T.
(2005). Accessibility from active and fulfilled
goals. Journal of Experimental Social Psy-
chology, 41(3), 220–239.
Freeman, J. B., Dale, R., & Farmer, T. A. (2011).
Hand in motion reveals mind in motion. Fron-
tiers in Psychology, 2, 59.
Friedman, R. S., & Förster, J. (2002). The influ-
ence of approach and avoidance motor actions
on creative cognition. Journal of Experimen-
tal Social Psychology, 38, 41–55.
Galinsky, A. D., & Moskowitz, G. B. (2000).
Perspective taking: Decreasing stereotype
expression, accessibility, and in-group favor-
itism. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 78, 708–724.
Galinsky, A. D., & Moskowitz, G. B. (2007).
Further ironies of suppression: Stereotype
and counter- stereotype accessibility. Journal
of Experimental Social Psychology, 42, 833
841.
Gailliot, M. T., Plant, E. A., Butz, D. A., &
Baumeister, R. F. (2007). Increasing self-
regulatory strength can reduce the depleting
effect of suppressing stereotypes. Personality
and Social Psychology Bulletin, 33, 281–294.
Gilbert, D. T. 1989. Thinking lightly about oth-
ers: Automatic components of the social infer-
ence process. In J. S. Uleman & J. A. Bargh
(Eds.), Unintended thought (pp. 189–211).
New York: Guilford Press.
Glaser, J., & Knowles, E. D. (2008). Implicit
motivation to control prejudice. Journal of
Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 164
172.
Gollwitzer, P. M. (1990). Action phases and
mind-sets. In E. T. Higgins & R. M. Sorren-
tino (Eds.), Handbook of motivation and cog-
nition (Vol. 2, pp. 53–92). New York: Guil-
ford Press.
Gollwitzer, P. M. (1993). Goal achievement: The
role of intentions. In W. Stroebe & M. Hew-
stone (Eds.), European review of social psy-
chology (Vol. 4, pp. 141–185). Chichester, UK:
Wiley.
Gollwitzer, P. M., & Moskowitz, G. B. (1996).
Goal effects on action and cognition. In E.
T. Higgins & A. Kruglanski (Eds.), Social
psychology: Handbook of basic principles
(pp. 361–399). New York: Guilford Press.
Gollwitzer, P. M., Wicklund, R. A., & Hilton, J.
L. (1982). Admission of failure and symbolic
self- completion: Extending Lewinian theory.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
43, 358–371.
Grant, H., & Dweck, C. S. (2003). Clarifying
achievement goals and their impact. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 85,
541–553.
Higgins, E. T. (2009). Regulatory fit in the
goal- pursuit process. In G. B. Moskowitz
& H. Grant (Eds.), The psychology of goals
(pp. 505–534). New York: Guilford Press.
Huang, J. Y., & Bargh, J. A. (in press). The
selfish goal: Autonomously operating moti-
vational structures as the proximal cause of
human judgment and behavior. [Target Arti-
cle] Behavioral and Brain Sciences.
Jostmann, N. B., & Koole, S. L. (2009). When
persistence is futile: A functional analysis of
action orientation and goal disengagement. In
G. B. Moskowitz & H. Grant (Eds.), The psy-
chology of goals. (pp. 337–361). New York:
The Guilford Press.
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 419 1/2/2014 12:57:45 PM
420 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
Kay, A. C., Wheeler, C. S., Bargh, J. A., & Ross,
L. D. (2004). Material priming: The influence
of mundane physical objects on situational
construal and competitive behavioral choice.
Organizational Behavior and Human Deci-
sion Processes, 95, 83–96.
Koole, S. L., Smeets, K., van Knippenberg, A.,
& Dijksterhuis, A. (1999). The cessation of
rumination through self- affirmation. Jour-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77,
111–125.
Kruglanski, A. W. (1990). Motivations for judg-
ing and knowing: Implications for causal attri-
bution. In E . T. Higgins & R. M. Sorrentino
(Eds.), Handbook of motivation and cogni-
tion (Vol. 2 , pp. 333–368). New York: Guil-
ford Press.
Kruglanski, A. W. (1996). Goals as knowledge
structures. In P. M. Gollwitzer & J. A. Bargh
(Eds.), The psychology of action (pp. 599–
618). New York: Guilford Press.
Kruglanski, A. W., Kopetz, C., Belanger, J. J.,
Chun, W. Y., Orehek, E., & Fishbach, A.
(2013). Features of multifinality. Personality
and Social Psychology Review, 17, 22–39.
Kruglanski, A. W., Pierro, A., & Sheveland, A.
(2011). How many roads lead to Rome?: Equi-
finality set-size and commitment to goals and
means. European Journal of Social Psychol-
ogy, 41, 344–352.
Kruglanski, A. W., Shah, J., Fishbach, A., Fried-
man, R., Chun, W., Sleeth- Keppler, D., et al.
(2002). A theory of goal systems. In M. P.
Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social
psychology (Vol. 34, pp. 331–378). New York:
Academic Press.
Lewin, K. (1936). Principles of topological psy-
chology. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Lewin, K. (1951). Field theory in social sci-
ence: Selected theoretical papers. New York:
Harper & Row.
Liberman, N., & Dar, R. (2009). Normal and
pathological consequences of encountering
difficulties in monitoring progress toward
goals. In G. B. Moskowitz & H. Grant (Eds.),
The psychology of goals (pp. 277–303). New
York: Guilford Press.
Liberman, N., & Förster, J. (2000). Expression
after suppression: A motivational explanation
of postsuppressional rebound. Journal of Per-
sonality and Social Psychology, 79, 190–203.
Macrae, C. N., Bodenhausen, G. V., Milne, A.
B., & Jetten, J. (1994). Out of mind but back
in sight: Stereotypes on the rebound. Jour-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67,
808–817.
Martin, L. L., & Tesser, A. (2009). Five mark-
ers of motivated behavior. In G. B. Moskowitz
and H. Grant (Eds.), The psychology of goals
(pp. 257–276). New York: Guilford Press.
McClelland, D. C. (1985). Human motivation.
Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman.
Mendoza, S. A., Gollwitzer, P. M., & Amodio, D.
A. (2010). Reducing the expression of implicit
stereotypes: Reflexive control through imple-
mentation intentions. Personality and Social
Psychology Bulletin, 36, 512–523.
Miller, G. A., Galanter, E., & Pribram, K. H.
(1960). Plans and the structure of behavior.
New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Molden, D. C., Hui, C. M., Scholer, A. A., Meier,
B. P. Noreen, E. E., D’Agostino, P. R., & Mar-
tin, V. (2012). Motivational versus metabolic
effects of carbohydrates on self- control. Psy-
chological Science, 23(10), 1137–1144.
Monteith, M. J., Ashburn- Nardo, L., Voils, C. I.,
& Czopp, A. M. (2002). Putting the brakes on
prejudice: On the development and operation
of cues for control. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 83, 1029–1050.
Moskowitz, G. B. (1993). Individual differences
in social categorization: The effects of per-
sonal need for structure on spontaneous trait
inferences. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 65, 132–142.
Moskowitz, G. B. (2002). Preconscious effects
of temporary goals on attention. Journal of
Experimental Social Psychology, 38, 397–
404.
Moskowitz, G. B., Gollwitzer, P. M., Wasel, W.,
& Schaal, B. (1999). Preconscious control of
stereotype activation through chronic egali-
tarian goals. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 77, 167–184.
Moskowitz, G. B., & Li, P. (2011). Egalitarian
goals trigger stereotype inhibition: A proactive
form of stereotype control. Journal of Experi-
mental Social Psychology, 47(1), 103–116.
Moskowitz, G. B., Li, P., Ignarri, C., & Stone,
J. (2011). Compensatory cognition associated
with egalitarian goals. Journal of Experimen-
tal Social Psychology, 47(2), 365–370.
Moskowitz, G. B., Salomon, A. R., & Taylor, C.
M. (2000). Preconsciously controlling stereo-
typing: Implicitly activated egalitarian goals
prevent the activation of stereotypes. Social
Cognition, 18, 151–177.
Moskowitz, G. B., & Stone, J. (2012). The proac-
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 420 1/2/2014 12:57:45 PM
The Implicit Volition Model 421
tive control of stereotype activation: Implicit
goals to not stereotype. Journal of Psychol-
ogy, 220(3), 172–179.
Oettingen, G. (2000). Expectancy effects on
behavior depend on self- regulatory thought.
Social Cognition, 18, 101–129.
Ostrom, T. (1984). The sovereignty of social
cognition. In R. S. Wyer, & T. K. Srull
(Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (Vol. 1,
pp. 1–38). Hilsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Packer, D. J., Miners, C. T. H., Ungson, N., &
Okten, I. O. (in preparation). Opportunities to
influence group decisions decrease conformity
in an Asch-like paradigm .
Parks-Stamm, E. J., & Gollwitzer, P. M. (2009).
Goal implementation: The benefits and costs
of IF–THEN planning. In G. B. Moskowitz
& H. Grant (Eds.), The psychology of goals
(pp. 362–391). New York: Guilford Press.
Payne, B. K. (2006). Weapon bias: Split second
decision and unintended stereotyping. Cur-
rent Directions in Psychological Science,
15(6), 287–291.
Payne, B. K., Lambert, A. J., & Jacoby, L. L.
(2002). Best laid plans: Effects of goals on
accessibility bias and cognitive control in race
based misperceptions of weapons. Journal of
Experimental Social Psychology, 38, 384
396.
Pessiglione, M., Schmidt, L., Draganski, B.,
Kalisch, R., Lau, H., Dolan, R., et al. (2007).
How the brain translates money into force: A
neuroimaging study of subliminal motivation.
Science, 316, 904–906.
Postman, L., Bruner, J. S., & McGinnies, E.
(1948). Personal factors as selective factors in
perception. Journal of Abnormal and Social
Psychology, 43, 142–154.
Powers, W. T. (1973). Behavior: The control of
perception. Chicago: Aldine.
Richeson, J. A., & Shelton, J. N. (2007). Nego-
tiating interracial interactions: Costs, conse-
quences, and possibilities. Current Directions
in Psychological Science, 16, 316–320.
Richeson, J. A., & Trawalter, S. (2005). Why do
interracial interactions impair executive func-
tion?: A resource depletion account. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 88,
934–947.
Sassenberg, K., & Moskowitz, G. B. (2005). Do
not stereotype, think different!: Overcoming
automatic stereotype activation by mindset
priming. Journal of Experimental Social Psy-
chology, 41 (5), 317–413.
Schmeichel B. J., & Baumeister, R. F. (2004).
Self- regulatory strength. In R. F. Baumeis-
ter & K. D. Vohs (Eds.), Handbook of self-
regulation: Research, theory, and applications
(pp. 84–98). New York: Guilford Press.
Shah, J. (2003). Automatic for the people: How
representations of significant others implicitly
affect goal pursuit. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 84(4), 661–681.
Shah, J. Y., Friedman, R., & Kruglanski, A. W.
(2002). Forgetting all else: On the antecedents
and consequences of goal shielding. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 1261–
1280.
Shah, J. Y., & Kruglanski, A. W. (2003) When
opportunity knocks: Bottom-up priming
of goals by means and its effects on self-
regulation. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 84(6), 1109–1122.
Sherman, J. W. (2006). On building a better pro-
cess model: It’s not only how many, but which
ones and by which means? Psychological
Inquiry, 17(3), 173–184.
Strack, F., Schwarz, N., Bless, H., Kübler, A., &
Wänke, M. (1993). Awareness of the influence
as a determinant of assimilation versus con-
trast. European Journal of Social Psychology,
23, 5362.
Thompson, E. P., Roman, R. J., Moskowitz, G.
B., Chaiken, S., & Bargh, J. A. (1994). Accu-
racy motivation attenuates covert priming
effects: The systematic reprocessing of social
information. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 66, 259–288.
Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive behavior in
animals and men. Oxford, UK: Appleton-
Century.
Trawalter, S., Todd, A. R., Baird, A. A., &
Richeson, J. A. (2008). Attending to threat:
Race-based patterns of selective attention.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology
44, 1322–1327.
Uleman, J. S., & Moskowitz, G. B. (1994). Unin-
tended effects of goals on unintended infer-
ences. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 66, 490 501.
Van Bavel, J. J., Packer,D. J., & Cunningham,
W. A. (2011). Modulation of the fusiform face
area following minimal exposure to motiva-
tionally relevant faces: Evidence of in-group
enhancement (not out-group disregard). Jour-
nal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23, 3343–
3354.
van der Weiden, A., Aarts, H., & Ruys, K.
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 421 1/2/2014 12:57:45 PM
422 HA B I TS, G OAL S , A N D MOT I V ATI O N
(in press). Inferring oneself as the cause of
intended and unintended outcomes. Social and
Personality Psychology Compass.
Vohs, K. D., Baumeister, R. F., & Ciarocco,
N. J. (2005). Self- regulation and self-
presentation: regulatory resource depletion
impairs impression management and effortful
self- presentation. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 88, 632–657.
Vohs, K. D., Kaikati, A. M., Kerkhof, P., & Sch-
meichel, B. J. (2009). Self- regulatory resource
depletion: A model for understanding the lim-
ited nature of goal pursuit. In G. B. Moskowitz
and H. Grant (Eds.), The psychology of goals
(pp. 423– 446). New York: Guilford Press.
Ward, T. B., Finke, R. A., & Smith, S. M. (1995).
Creativity and the mind: Discovering the
genius within. New York: Plenum.
Wegner, D. M. (1994). Ironic processes of mental
control. Psychological Review, 101, 34–52.
Wegner, D. M., & Bargh, J. A. (1998). Control
and automaticity in social life. In D. T. Gil-
bert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), The
handbook of social psychology (4th ed., Vol.
1, pp. 446496). Boston: McGraw-Hill.
Wegner, D. M., & Pennebaker, J. W. (1993). An
introduction to mental control. In D. M. Weg-
ner & J. W. Pennebaker (Eds.), Handbook of
mental control (pp. 1–12). Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice Hall.
Wegner, D. M., & Wheatley, T. (1999). Appar-
ent mental causation: Sources of the experi-
ence of will. American Psychologist, 54(7),
480492.
Wicklund, R. A., & Gollwitzer, P. M. (1982).
Symbolic self- completion. Hillsdale, NJ: Erl-
baum.
Williams, L. E., & Bargh, J. A. (2008). Expe-
riencing physical warmth promotes interper-
sonal warmth. Science, 322, 606 607.
Winkielman, P., Berridge, K. C., & Wilbarger,
J. L. (2005). Unconscious affective reactions
to masked happy versus angry faces influ-
ence consumption behavior and judgments of
value. Personality and Social Psychology Bul-
letin, 31(1), 121–135.
Zeigarnik, B. (1927). Das Behalten erledigter
und unerledigter Handlungen [The retention
of completed and uncompleted actions]. Psy-
chologische Forschung, 9, 1–85.
Sherman_DualProcessTheoriesSocialMind.indb 422 1/2/2014 12:57:45 PM
... Importantly, the view of implicit evaluations emerging from a slow-learning, purely associative system has been challenged in several lines of early and contemporary empirical work focusing on (a) debiasing interventions (e.g., Blair, 2002); (b) the goaldependent nature of implicit evaluation (e.g., Ferguson & Bargh, 2008;Moskowitz, 2014); and (c) the rapid revision of implicit evaluations (e.g., Cone et al., 2017;Ferguson et al., 2019). Taken together, these literatures have provided evidence for the remarkable flexibility of implicit evaluations in the face of a variety of inputs going well beyond repeated co-occurrences of stimuli in the environment. ...
... By contrast, more recent propositional accounts (De Houwer, 2014;De Houwer & Hughes, 2016;Kurdi & Dunham, 2020;Mandelbaum, 2016) tend to highlight the role of propositional reasoning in implicit evaluation. As such, the latter accounts, along with other approaches emphasizing the flexibility of implicit evaluation more generally (e.g., Blair, 2002;Cone et al., 2017;Ferguson et al., 2019;Moskowitz, 2014), would be considerably easier to reconcile with ubiquitous effects of relational information on implicit evaluations. ...
Article
Full-text available
Based on 660 effect sizes obtained from 23,255 adult participants across 51 reports of experimental studies, this meta-analysis investigates whether and when explicit (self-reported) and implicit (indirectly revealed) evaluations reflect relational information (how stimuli are related to each other) over and above co-occurrence information (the fact that stimuli have been paired with each other). Using a mixed-effects metaregression, relational information was found to dominate over contradictory co-occurrence information in shifting both explicit (mean Hedges' g = 0.97, 95% CI [0.89, 1.05], 95% PI [0.24, 1.70]) and implicit evaluations (g = 0.27, 95% CI [0.19, 0.35], 95% PI [-0.46, 1.00]). However, considerable heterogeneity in relational effects on implicit evaluation made moderator analyses necessary. Implicit evaluations were particularly sensitive to relational information (a) in between-participant (rather than within-participant) designs; when (b) co-occurrence information was held constant (rather than manipulated); (c) targets were novel (rather than known); implicit evaluations were measured (d) first (rather than last) and (e) using an affect misattribution procedure (rather than an Implicit Association Test or evaluative priming task); and (f) relational and co-occurrence information were presented in temporal proximity (rather than far apart in time). Overall, the present findings suggest that both implicit and explicit evaluations emerge from a combination of co-occurrence information and relational information, with relational information usually playing the dominant role. Critically, variability in these effects highlights a need to refocus attention from existence proof demonstrations toward theoretical and empirical work on the determinants and boundary conditions of the influences of co-occurrence and relational information on explicit and implicit evaluations. (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2022 APA, all rights reserved).
... Importantly, the view of implicit evaluations emerging from a slow-learning, purely associative system has been challenged in several lines of early and contemporary empirical work focusing on (a) debiasing interventions (e.g., Blair, 2002); (b) the goal-dependent nature of implicit evaluation (e.g., Ferguson & Bargh, 2008;Moskowitz, 2014); and (c) the rapid revision of implicit evaluations (e.g., Cone et al., 2017;Ferguson et al., 2019). Taken together, these literatures have provided evidence for the remarkable flexibility of implicit evaluations in the face of a variety of inputs going well beyond repeated co-occurrences of stimuli in the environment. ...
... (De Houwer, 2014;De Houwer & Hughes, 2016;Kurdi & Dunham, 2020;Mandelbaum, 2016) tend to highlight the role of propositional reasoning in implicit evaluation. As such, the latter accounts, along with other approaches emphasizing the flexibility of implicit evaluation more generally (e.g., Blair, 2002;Cone et al., 2017;Ferguson et al., 2019;Moskowitz, 2014), would be considerably easier to reconcile with ubiquitous effects of relational information on implicit evaluations. ...
Preprint
Full-text available
Based on 660 effect sizes obtained from 23,255 adult participants across 51 reports of experimental studies, this meta-analysis investigates whether and when explicit (self-reported) and implicit (indirectly revealed) evaluations reflect relational information (how stimuli are related to each other) over and above co-occurrence information (the fact that stimuli have been paired with each other). Using a mixed-effects meta-regression, relational information was found to dominate over contradictory co-occurrence information in shifting both explicit (mean Hedges’ g = 0.97, 95-percent CI: [0.89; 1.05], 95-percent PI: [0.24; 1.70]) and implicit evaluations (g = 0.27, 95-percent CI: [0.19; 0.35], 95-percent PI: [ 0.46; 1.00]). However, considerable heterogeneity in relational effects on implicit evaluation made moderator analyses necessary. Implicit evaluations were particularly sensitive to relational information (a) in between-participant (rather than within-participant) designs; when (b) co-occurrence information was held constant (rather than manipulated); (c) targets were novel (rather than known); implicit evaluations were measured (d) first (rather than last) and (e) using an AMP (rather than an IAT or EPT); and (f) relational and co-occurrence information were presented in temporal proximity (rather than far apart in time). Overall, the present findings suggest that both implicit and explicit evaluations emerge from a combination of co-occurrence information and relational information, with relational information usually playing the dominant role. Critically, variability in these effects highlights a need to refocus attention from existence proof demonstrations toward theoretical and empirical work on the determinants and boundary conditions of the influences of co-occurrence and relational information on explicit and implicit evaluation.
... For instance, implicit evaluations have been shown to be situationally malleable (16). Specifically, implicit evaluations respond to motivational states, such as nicotine deprivation, thirst, and hunger (17), as well as to higher-order goals, such as the goal to be egalitarian (18). At the same time, contrary to the prediction by a single-process propositional perspective, implicit evaluations are not indiscriminately sensitive to verbal interventions that have been demonstrated to shift explicit evaluations (19). ...
... Moreover, when it comes to purely language-based learning (12,13), the present results suggest that the effectiveness of verbal statements in updating implicit evaluations may be moderated by the complexity of the propositional reasoning required to assign the appropriate truth value to those verbal statements or, in the terminology of reinforcement learning, by the complexity of the implied causal model. Moreover, the present results, as well as a general reinforcement learning framework, provide a perspective on what is usually described as the sensitivity of implicit evaluations to higher-order goals (17,18). In studies of this kind, activation of a goal (e.g., hunger, achievement, or egalitarianism) leads to a modulation of implicit evaluations such that objects that can contribute to achieving the goal are temporarily evaluated more positively until the goal is successfully completed. ...
Article
Full-text available
Evaluating stimuli along a good–bad dimension is a fundamental computation performed by the human mind. In recent decades, research has documented dissociations and associations between explicit (i.e., self-reported) and implicit (i.e., indirectly measured) forms of evaluations. However, it is unclear whether such dissociations arise from relatively more superficial differences in measurement techniques or from deeper differences in the processes by which explicit and implicit evaluations are acquired and represented. The present project (total N = 2,354) relies on the computationally well-specified distinction between model-based and model-free reinforcement learning to investigate the unique and shared aspects of explicit and implicit evaluations. Study 1 used a revaluation procedure to reveal that, whereas explicit evaluations of novel targets are updated via model-free and model-based processes, implicit evaluations depend on the former but are impervious to the latter. Studies 2 and 3 demonstrated the robustness of this effect to (i) the number of stimulus exposures in the revaluation phase and (ii) the deterministic vs. probabilistic nature of initial reinforcement. These findings provide a framework, going beyond traditional dual-process and single-process accounts, to highlight the context-sensitivity and long-term recalcitrance of implicit evaluations as well as variations in their relationship with their explicit counterparts. These results also suggest avenues for designing theoretically guided interventions to produce change in implicit evaluations.
... First (and more importantly) it identifies any negative discrepancy between the current and desired states, and directs action to reduce it (Carver & Scheier 1982;Miller et al., 1960;Powers, 1973aPowers, , 1973b. Hence, discrepancy is an important early focus in goal monitoring (Vohs et al., 2008) and points to the direction and magnitude of needed actions (Moskowitz, 2014;Liberman & Dar, 2009). ...
... It attracts early processing (Carver & Scheier, 1982;Miller et al., 1960;Powers, 1973b;Vohs et al., 2008) and generates tension (Lewin, 1951) that keeps the goal active. For maintenance goals, the current and desired states match, and there is no discrepancy to create the initial tension (Martin & Tesser, 2009). 1 Hence, the discrepancy (small or large) for attainment goals should receive more processing and have more influence on difficulty judgments and goal choices than the match for maintenance goals (Moskowitz, 2014). ...
Article
Full-text available
We argue that individuals monitor and evaluate attainment and maintenance goals differently. Attainment goals feature a salient current-end state discrepancy that is processed more than the corresponding match for maintenance goals. For maintenance goals, for which a salient discrepancy is absent, contextual influences on goal success/failure receive more processing than for attainment goals. Thus, objectively more difficult attainment goals may be judged as easier than maintenance goals, when they feature sufficiently small discrepancies, or when context information is unfavorable. Study 1 establishes this core effect. Study 2 shows that thought listings capturing the relative processing of the current-end state discrepancy (match) and context information mediate perceived goal difficulty. Study 3 shows that the favorability of context information moderates the effect. Study 4 establishes joint difficulty evaluations as a boundary condition. Studies 5 and 6 (and Appendix B) show that such goal difficulty judgments affect consequential goal choices in real-world financial, workplace, and shopping situations.
... Both psychology and audit research indicate the framing of information can influence an individual's conscious and unconscious goals (Moskowitz 2014;Griffith et al. 2016), in turn affecting the individual's attitudes and behaviors (Nelson, Oxley, and Clawson 1997). Prior audit research finds several types of task framing can affect auditor judgment and decision-making, including goals to support a client's preferred accounting treatment (Kadous et al. 2003), complete tasks within budget and on time (McDaniel 1990), question management's representations (Griffith et al. 2021), and draw appropriate conclusions (Lambert and Agoglia 2011). ...
Article
Negative feedback can induce adverse responses. This is problematic in auditing as negative feedback is common during workpaper reviews, and auditors’ follow-through on this feedback is essential to staff development and audit quality. Psychology research suggests supervisors’ framing of feedback can impact subordinates’ feedback reactions and subsequent performance, and this effect might vary depending on their relative receptivity to feedback (i.e., feedback orientation). In a 2 × 2 between-subjects experiment, using a review notes task, I examine the joint influence of these factors and find divergent effects. Results show novice auditors with stronger feedback orientations have more positive reactions to negative feedback when reviewers emphasize learning goals, but framing does not influence performance. However, those with weaker feedback orientations react poorly regardless of framing, but learning goals improve their performance. These results enhance understanding of effects of goal framing on audit quality and help guide reviewers on how to frame negative feedback. JEL Classifications: M40; M42.
... Thus, if responses on a measure are determined to be associative in nature, it may be taken as evidence that the process must operate in an automatic fashion (e.g., Fazio et al., 1995;Strack and Deutsch, 2004;Gawronski and Bodenhausen, 2006). However, there is now ample evidence that self-regulatory processes (e.g., Glaser and Kihlstrom, 2006;Moskowitz, 2014) and propositional reasoning (e.g., De Houwer, 2014) Using an indirect measure (e.g., SMT) to assess the activation of stereotypic associations and a direct measure (e.g., Modern Racism Scale) to assess how those activated associations are applied ...
Article
Full-text available
In this article, we describe four theoretical and methodological problems that have impeded implicit attitude research and the popular understanding of its findings. The problems all revolve around assumptions made about the relationships among measures (indirect vs. versus direct), constructs (implicit vs. explicit attitudes), cognitive processes (e.g., associative vs. propositional), and features of processing (automatic vs. controlled). These assumptions have confused our understandings of exactly what we are measuring, the processes that produce implicit evaluations, the meaning of differences in implicit evaluations across people and contexts, the meaning of changes in implicit evaluations in response to intervention, and how implicit evaluations predict behavior. We describe formal modeling as one means to address these problems, and provide illustrative examples. Clarifying these issues has important implications for our understanding of who has particular implicit evaluations and why, when those evaluations are likely to be particularly problematic, how we might best try to change them, and what interventions are best suited to minimize the effects of implicit evaluations on behavior.
Article
Full-text available
The study focused on the relationship between success attributions and academic achievement of secondary school students in Anambra State. Six research questions and six null hypotheses guided the study. Using a multi-stage sampling technique, the study adopted a correlation design with a sample size of 600 senior secondary two students drawn from the population of 11,417 co-educational students. The instrument for data collection was the Students’ Attribution Style Questionnaire. Students’ Achievement Scores were used to obtain students’ academic achievement. The reliability of the instrument was established using the Cronbach Alpha method, which yielded a reliability of .84. The Pearson Product Moment correlation was used to answer the research questions, while the t-test of the significance of the correlation was used to test the null hypotheses at a .05 level of significance. Findings from the study revealed a medium positive correlation between attributions and academic achievement scores of students with internal success attributions. Also, the finding revealed a significant relationship between attributions and academic achievement scores of students with internal success attributions. Based on these findings, it was recommended that teachers always emphasize the effort to adopt the success attribution approach in the learning process as the basis for students’ success in their academic activities and also improve the learning environment to minimize environmental constraints.
Chapter
Full-text available
Although temporal conceptualizations of motivational processes have not held center stage in motivation science, the situation is currently changing. Drawing on work in the subfield of language learning motivation, where the motivational endurance needed to master a second language has been a major concern, the aim of this article is to contribute to the body of work currently exploring motivational persistence. After outlining the broader academic context of motivation and time, and describing the disciplinary trajectory of research into language learning motivation, we present two interrelated and multifaceted frameworks that seek to explain long-term motivation and motivational persistence: (a) the notion of a “directed motivational current,” which refers to a period of intense, enduring, and self-sustaining engagement within an activity-sequence, and which is phenomenologically akin to an extended flow experience, and (b) a multicomponent framework of long-term motivation that offers a general account of sustained effort in learning. This framework integrates diverse components, such as self-concordant vision, habitual actions, progress checks, and affirmative feedback, and references a motivational process that is characterized by positive emotional loading and passion, and is supported by self-control capacity and self-regulatory skills.
Article
Background: Postural deviations such as forward head posture (FHP) are associated with adverse health effects. The causes of these deviations are poorly understood. We hypothesized that anticipating target-directed movement could cause the head to get "ahead of" the body, interfering with optimal head/neck posture, and that the effect may be exacerbated by task difficulty and/or poor inhibitory control. Method: We assessed posture in 45 healthy young adults standing quietly and when they anticipated walking to place a tray: in a simple condition and in conditions requiring that they bend low or balance an object on the tray. We defined FHP as neck angle relative to torso; we also measured head angle relative to neck and total neck length. We assessed inhibitory control using a Go/No-Go task, Stroop task, and Mindful Attention Awareness Scale (MAAS). Results: FHP increased when participants anticipated movement, particularly for more difficult movements. Worse Stroop performance and lower MAAS scores correlated with higher FHP. False alarms on the Go/No-Go task correlated with a more extended head relative to the neck and with shortening of the neck when anticipating movement. Conclusions: Maintaining neutral posture may require inhibition of an impulse to put the head forward of the body when anticipating target-directed movement.
Article
Three studies examined the moderating role of motivations to respond without prejudice (e.g., internal and external) in expressions of explicit and implicit race bias. In all studies, participants reported their explicit attitudes toward Blacks. Implicit measures consisted of a sequential priming task (Study 1) and the Implicit Association Test (Studies 2 and 3). Study 3 used a cognitive busyness manipulation to preclude effects of controlled processing on implicit responses. In each study, explicit race bias was moderated by internal motivation to respond without prejudice, whereas implicit race bias was moderated by the interaction of internal and external motivation to respond without prejudice. Specifically, high internal, low external participants exhibited lower levels of implicit race bias than did all other participants. Implications for the development of effective self-regulation of race bias are discussed.
Article
Six studies explore the role of goal shielding in self-regulation:by examining how the activation of focal goals to which the individual is committed inhibits the accessibility, of alternative goals. Consistent evidence was found for such goal shielding, and a number of its moderators were identified: Individuals' level of commitment to the focal goal, their degree of anxiety and depression, their need for cognitive closure, and differences in their goal-related tenacity. Moreover, inhibition of alternative goals was found to be, more pronounced when they serve the same overarching purpose as the focal goal, but lessened when the alternative goals facilitate focal goal attainment. Finally; goal shielding was shown to have beneficial consequences for goal pursuit and attainment.
Article
This study rested the idea of habits as a form of goal-directed automatic behavior. Expanding on the idea that habits are mentally represented as associations between goals and actions, it was proposed that goals are capable of activating the habitual action. More specific, when habits are established (e.g., frequent cycling to the university), the very activation of the goal to act (e.g., having to attend lectures at the university) automatically evokes the habitual response (e.g., bicycle). Indeed, it was tested and confirmed that, when behavior is habitual, behavioral responses are activated automatically. in addition, the results of 3 experiments indicated that (a) the automaticity in habits is conditional on the presence of an active goal (cf. goal-dependent automaticity; J. A. Bargh, 1989), supporting the idea that habits are mentally represented as goal-action links, and (b) the formation of implementation intentions (i.e., the creation of a strong mental link between a goal and action) may simulate goal-directed automaticity in habits.