ArticlePDF Available

Resumptive pronouns, A'-binding, and levels of representation in Irish

Authors:
is is a contribution from Resumptive Pronouns at the Interfaces.
Edited by Alain Rouveret.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
is electronic le may not be altered in any way.
e author(s) of this article is/are permitted to use this PDF le to generate printed copies to
be used by way of oprints, for their personal use only.
Permission is granted by the publishers to post this le on a closed server which is accessible
to members (students and sta) only of the author’s/s’ institute, it is not permitted to post
this PDF on the open internet.
For any other use of this material prior written permission should be obtained from the
publishers or through the Copyright Clearance Center (for USA: www.copyright.com).
Please contact rights@benjamins.nl or consult our website: www.benjamins.com
Tables of Contents, abstracts and guidelines are available at www.benjamins.com
John Benjamins Publishing Company
part i
Syntactic uniformity/diversity of resumption
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding,
and levels of representations in Irish
James McCloskey
University of California, Santa Cruz
At the empirical level, this paper aims to provide a reasonably systematic
overview of the distribution of resumptive pronouns in one language (Irish)
and of their behavior under certain tests. At the theoretical level, it argues that
resumptive pronouns are syntactic variables (locally Ā-bound elements) and
that there is a syntactically visible relation between the pronoun and its binder.
It follows that it must be possible for pronouns to be directly Ā-bar bound.
e paper also argues, however, that the pronominal character of resumptive
pronouns emerges in the so-called Highest Subject Restriction which is analyzed
as an anti-locality eect (reminiscent of Condition B of the Binding eory)
acting in the Ā-domain.
1. Introduction
is article has the relatively modest goal of contributing to our understanding of
resumptive pronoun structures – in Irish in particular and in a broad theoretical
perspective in general. Such structures have gured in a peripheral way in the dis-
cussion of many theoretical issues in recent years, discussion centered, for the most
part, on the related notions of “syntactic variable” and Ā-binding” and on the many
questions that in turn demand a proper understanding of those notions. Resumptive
pronoun structures have gured in only a peripheral way in these debates, in part
because the most familiar and best-studied languages largely lack robust or productive
resumptive pronoun strategies. As a consequence, there is a dearth of the kind of data
needed to resolve the various questions of theory and analysis that arise concerning
resumptive pronouns.1
1. Important contributions have, of course, been made to the study of resumptive pronouns,
most notably by Peter Sells. See Sells (1984a, 1984b, 1987), as well as Zaenen et al. (1981),
Chomsky (1982), Chao and Sells (1983), Borer (1984), Jaeggli (1984), and Safir (1986).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
Initially, here, I attempt to narrow the data gap for Irish by providing a fairly
complete and systematic overview of the distribution of resumptive pronouns and of
their behavior under various tests. Beyond this overview, the article is concerned as
well with a number of related theoretical questions. e most basic of these is whether
or not resumptive pronouns are properly construed as syntactic variables. By syntactic
variable I understand the following: an element that is syntactically bound and whose
most immediate binder is an element in an Ā-position.
As pointed out recently by Lasnik and Stowell (1987) and by May (1989), almost
all recent discussions of weak crossover, of bound variable anaphora, and of the syntax
of quantication in general proceed from the assumption (explicit or implicit) that
direct Ā-binding of a pronoun is impossible. Since an important aim of all of this
work has been to assimilate the structures produced by syntactic WH-movement
and quantier raising (QR) at LF, a consequence of the assumption is that structures
such as (1) should he legal, whereas structures such as (2) should he illegal (where
no other binder, i.e. coindexed c-commanding element, intervenes between XPj and
the element it binds).
(1) [S XP [S… tj …]]
(2) [S XP [S … PROj …]]
Now, of course, to demonstrate that structures such as (2) are in fact well formed, it
is not enough simply to point to the existence of examples involving resumptive pro-
nouns, such as (3):
(3) an fear ar labhair lena mhac
the man  spoke I with-his son
“the man that I spoke to his son
One might argue, for instance, that the pronoun in (3) is not syntactically bound at
all. It is perfectly possible to set up the mechanism of semantic interpretation so that
there is no syntactically visible relation between the “resumptive” pronoun and any
other syntactic position. Alternatively, one might argue that the pronoun is indeed
syntactically bound, but that it is coindexed with the head NP of the relative clause
structure, not with an operator within COMP. One would have to worry then about
whether or not the head position of relative clause structures should he interpreted
as an Ā-position. It is hardly obvious what the correct answer to this last question is.2
. See Safir (1986) for an ingenious argument (based on the interaction between pied piping
and the licensing of parasitic gaps) that suggests strongly that binding by a relative head would
not count as Ā-binding.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
So the question of whether or not resumptive pronouns are (in some construc-
tions and in some languages at least) Ā-bound is tied intimately with the question
of what element it is exactly that functions as antecedent to a resumptive pronoun.
e problem of identifying with any precision or condence the antecedent of a
resumptive pronoun (the head NP or some element in COMP, for instance) is a subtle
one, and it is not immediately obvious what kind of empirical evidence bears on this
issue. One of the ways in which the Irish data are interesting is that they provide a
relatively precise and robust way of arguing about the issue.
ere is another way in which arguing about the status of (3) is less than
straightforward. Since the proposals of Chomsky (1982), it is clear that one cannot
simply ask, for a given language, whether or not resumptive pronouns in that lan-
guage are or are not Ā-bound. It is perfectly possible that resumptive pronouns might
be Ā-bound at one level of representation (say, at LF), but not bound at all at other
levels of representation (at S-structure. for instance). Teasing out the consequences of
the dierent assumptions one might make in this regard is, again, a delicate matter;
but Irish also has the merit of providing data that bear on the question in a rather
direct way.
Finally, if we admit the existence in principle of Ā-bound pronouns, then cer-
tain obvious questions arise immediately for binding theory. Resumptive pronouns,
if they are taken to be directly Ā-bound, are pronominal variables, that is, they are
simultaneously pronouns and variables. Questions arise immediately about how we
should expect them to behave with respect to binding theory. Will their status as pro-
nominal variables be related to the way they behave with respect to the conditions of
binding theory?
. Background
Before addressing such questions, it is useful to review rst the background assump-
tions about the syntax of Irish that lie behind the discussion pursued throughout
this article.
.1 Clausal structure in Irish
Irish is VSO in its nite clauses. e basic facts of word order in nite clauses can be
illustrated with the example in (4).
(4) Bhéarfaidh an t-airgead do Chaaimhín i nDoire inniu
give- I the money to Kevin in Derry today
“I’ll give Kevin the money in Derry today”
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
at is, unmarked order follows the formula given in (5).3
(5) Verb < Subject < Object < Oblique Arguments < Adverbials
In nonnite clauses, however, VSO order is impossible; the subject is always initial in
such clauses, as illustrated in (6).
(6) Níar mhaith liom [Caoimhín a theacht abhaile].
I-wouldn’t-like Kevin come- home
‘I wouldn’t like Kevin to come home.
Furthermore, subjects are also initial in small clauses in Irish (Chung and McCloskey
1987).
(7) a. Ba mhinic [Caoimhín ag caoineadh].
- oen Kevin cry-
“Kevin was oen crying”
b. agus [Caoimhín ag caoineadh]
and Kevin cry-
“while Kevin was crying”
An analysis of Irish clausal structure is developed in Chung and McCloskey (1987),
which seeks to account for these clause types and their interrelationships by assuming
that all three types (small clauses, nite clauses, and nonnite clauses) share important
aspects of phrase structure. In particular, small clauses are construed as constituents,
with the internal structure in (8).
(8) SC
NP XP
Chung and McCloskey (1987) argue that small clauses (in Irish, at least) are Ss, an
assumption that brings both advantages and embarrassments. Since the issue is not
crucial for present concerns, I for now use the abbreviation “SC” for small clauses and
leave the issue of categorial identity open.
Structures such as (8) are in turn seen as important subconstituents of full clauses,
both nite and nonnite. is is achieved by assuming the structure in (9) for both
nite and nonnite clauses.
. For further exemplification and discussion, see Stenson (1981: 40–47). McCloskey
(1983a: 10–12), and Ó Siadhail (1989: 23–26).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
(9)
S
INFL SC
NP XP
e SC-constituent of (9) has an independent distribution (as illustrated, for instance,
in [7]) but functions also to build full clauses (nite and nonnite) when a sister
to INFL, as in (9). On this view, the verb-initial order seen in nite clauses can he
accounted for by assuming that in the case where XP of (9) is headed by V0, V0 moves
to INFL if INFL is [+Finite]. For nite clauses, then, one will have the kind of deriva-
tions schematized in (10).
(10) S
INFL
[+FINITE]
SC
NP VP
V0
tj
V0
(YP)
To account for the subject-initial order of nonnite clauses, it is assumed that this kind
of head movement may not apply in nonnite clauses. I have no proposal to oer as to
why this movement should take place obligatorily in nite clauses but be inapplicable in
nonnite clauses. It should be noted, however, that similar eects (the nonapplication
of V-to-INFL movement in nonnite clauses) are well attested for other languages
for Welsh, see Sproat (1985); for French, see Emonds (1978), Taraldsen (1983), Pollock
(1989), and Chomsky (1988); for Vata and Gbadi, see Koopman (1984).4
ere is another fact about the order of elements in nonnite clauses that should
be noted here. Direct objects are generally preposed to a position le of the verb and
to the right of the subject, as seen in (11).
. I assume here only V-to-INFL movement in the derivation of finite VSO order. One might
wonder if there is not further movement of the INFL-V complex to COMP, as in many studies
of the verb-second phenomenon. e absence of a pattern of complementarity between
preposed finite Vs and the appearance of lexical complementizers suggests that this further
movement does not take place in Irish. e matter is far beyond present concerns, however,
and is not discussed further here. See Guilfoyle (1988) for further discussion of the structure
of clauses in Irish. It is possible that heads other than V0 also undergo head movement to
INFL. is is arguably the appropriate analysis of finite copular clauses in Irish.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
(11) a. Níor mhaith liom [iad Ciarán a eiceáil]
I-wouldn’t-like them Ciaran see-
“I would not like them to see Ciaran
b. Níor mhaith liom [Ciarán a eiceáil]
I-wouldn’t-like Ciaran see-
“I wouldn’t like to see Ciaran”
c. Níor mhaith liom [Ciarán labhairt leat mar sin]
I-wouldn’t-like Ciaran speak- with-you like-that
“I wouldn’t like Ciaran to speak to you like that”
I assume here, following Chung and McCloskey (1987) and McCloskey and Sells
(1988), that this order reects application of a rule that moves a NP governed by V0
and le-adjoins it to the VP headed by V0. An example such as (11a) will then have the
kind of structure illustrated in (12).
(12) S
INFL
[–FINITE]
SC
NP VP
NPj
tj
Ø
VP
V NP
iad
a eiceáil
Application of this rule is subject to dierent conditions in dierent dialects. In the
northern group of dialects, it applies in all nonnite clauses; in the southern group
of dialects, it applies only if the subject is phonologically empty (i.e. in control and
raising clauses). For detailed discussion of these matters, see McCloskey (1980) and
McCloskey and Sells (1988).
. Null arguments and agreement
Irish is a null-subject language. More precisely, Irish is a null-argument language in
the following sense: any argument position whose person and number features are
identied by agreement morphology on a lexical head can be null. Under most cir-
cumstances, the condition is actually stronger. Argument positions whose person and
number features are identied by agreement morphology on a lexical head must be
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 1
null. ese patterns can be seen in the case of subjects, when the verb inects for the
person and number of its subject.
(13) a. Cuirim Ø suas é
put--1 up it
“I put it up
b. *Cuirim suas é
put--1 I up it
“I put it up
e same patterns exactly hold for the objects of prepositions, which inect for the
person and number of their objects.
(14) a. Labhair leo Ø!
speak- with-3
“Speak to them!”
b. *Labhair leo iad!
speak- with-3 them
“Speak to them!”
Finally, similar patterns hold for nouns, which take agreement prexes that identify
the number and person of possessors:
(15) a. mo theach Ø
1 house
“my house
b. *mo theach
1 house I/me
“my house
ese “null” eects have been studied in detail in McCloskey and Hale (1984) and
in McCloskey (1986b). ose papers present evidence that the empty position in
structures such as (13)–(15) is occupied by a null pronominal the element pro of
much recent work (see Chomsky, 1982; in particular). We will take pro to be subject
to an identication condition that requires (in this and similar languages) that it be
governed by AGR, taken to be a possible subcomponent of the feature complexes that
dene INFL0, P0, and N0.
All these assumptions are defended in some detail in McCloskey and Hale (1984)
and in McCloskey (1986b). For the case of subject-verb agreement, I assume that the
relevant AGR feature is a subpart of INFL, as sketched in (16).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
(16)
S
INFL
[AGR: αF]
SC
pro
αF
VP
V0jV0
tj
(YP)
A great deal of evidence is adduced in Chung and McCloskey (1987) that INFL
governs the subject position in structures such as (9). In a structure such as (16), then,
the AGR complex within INFL will govern, and hence license, the instance of PRO that
appears in subject position. e complex of INFL + AGR + fronted V0 will ultimately
be realized as a verb inected for tense and for the features of its subject.5
. Ā-binding in Irish
Before beginning a detailed analysis of resumptive pronoun structures, we should rst
consider certain facts about the syntactic realization of Ā-binding in Irish. One of the
most useful features of Irish syntax in this domain is that it provides more than one
diagnostic for identifying the presence or absence of a resumptive pronoun in a given
clause. Specically, clauses are introduced by dierent COMP-particles depending on
whether they contain a gap, a resumptive pronoun, or no syntactically bound element
at ail. Consider the latter case rst. In (17) an example is given of a structure in which
a clause is embedded as complement to a verb.
(17) Dúirt gur bhuail é
said he  struck you him
“He said that you struck him”
Notice that the embedded clause is introduced by the (past tense) complementizer gur.
Consider now, though, what is essentially the same clause with a gap in object position:
(18) an fear [S a bhuail __]
the man  struck you
“the man that you struck”
e clause now is introduced by the complementizer a.
Consider, nally, the case of a clause containing a resumptive pronoun rather
than a gap:
. See Andrews (1988) for a detailed set of proposals about how syntax and morphology
interact in this domain of Irish grammar.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
(19) an fear [S ar bhuail é]
the man  struck you him
“the man that you struck (him)”
In this case, the relative clause is introduced by the complementizer ar. So we have
here a three-way distinction of clauses that involve no Ā-binding at all, clauses that
involve an Ā-binding that terminates in a gap, and clauses (to anticipate a little) that
involve an instance of Ā-binding that terminates in a pronoun. Now the phonological
and morphological mechanisms that serve to mark the distinctions between the vari-
ous complementizers are very complex, since they depend on such factors as the tense
of the associated clause (past or nonpast), the presence of a negative particle, and the
presence of the copula.6 Furthermore, the distinction between the dierent comple-
mentizers is sometimes a distinction not in segmental phonology but rather in the
initial mutation induced on the following element (typically the verb).
We can nesse these morphophonological complexities here by indicating
the distinction, when necessary, with dierent subscripts on the glosses associated
with the dierent complementizers. Henceforth, the complementizer go/gur, which
appears in the absence of any Ā-binding, is glossed simply “COMP”; the comple-
mentizer a, which is associated with the binding of a gap (i.e. with the application of
WH-movement) is glossed “COMPt”; and the complementizer a/ar, which is associ-
ated with the appearance of a resumptive pronoun, is glossed “COMPpro. e basic
patterns at issue, then, are as illustrated in (20). e structures schematized in (20)
are relative clause structures, but, as discussed later, these patterns are the same for all
constructions involving Ā-binding.
(20) a. [NP NP [S t [S … t …]]]
b. [NP NP [S pro [Spro …]]]
It is also convenient at certain points to use the abbreviations aL for COMPt, and aN
for COMPpro. ese abbreviations are based on the fact that COMPt induces the leni-
tion mutation on a following verb, whereas COMPpro (in the present tense) induces
the nasalization mutation on the initial of a following verb.7 ese distinctions are
. For some discussion of the syntactic structures that form the basis for these complexities,
see Chung and McCloskey (1987).
. Not all dialects have the full range of distinctions documented here. In some southern
varieties, for instance, there is not a distinction between COMPpro and the default comple-
mentizer go. In such varieties, (19) appears as in (i):
(i) an fear gur bhuail é
the man  struck you him
“the man that you struck
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
important for the clues that they provide about the proper analysis of resumptive pro-
noun structures. ey are also extremely useful in helping us detect the presence of
resumptive pronouns when their presence would not otherwise be obvious.
Recall from the previous section that Irish is a null-argument language, in the
sense that pronouns are frequently null. Specically, pronouns are obligatorily null
when governed by (and hence identied by) AGR. e evidence for the pronominal
status of the null positions identied by AGR is extremely strong (McCloskey & Hale
1984; McCloskey 1986b) and is independent of current concerns. It is important to
note from the outset, then, that with respect to the COMP-distribution phenomena
discussed here, there is no dierence whatsoever between the behavior of phonologi-
cally specied pronouns and phonologically null pronouns. Both demand the appear-
ance of COMPpro when functioning as resumptives. is is illustrated for two instance
of null pro (object of an inected preposition and possessor in a NP containing an
agreement prex) in (21).
(21) a. an fear ar labhair leis pro
the man pro spoke you with-3-
“the man that you spoke to (him)”
b. an bhean a raibh [NP a mac pro] breoite
the woman pro was 3- son ill
“the woman that her son was ill”
Put simply, the rules or principles that determine the distribution of the dierent
complementizers do not care whether pro in (20b) is phonologically empty or phono-
logically specied. is fact is illustrated as the discussion proceeds by citation, when-
ever possible, of a pair of examples – one involving an audible pronoun, the other
involving prowherever some aspect of the syntax or interpretation of pronouns is
characterized.
One further piece of information needs to be given at this point. It is a salient
feature of Ā-binding structures in Irish that they exhibit a classic “successive cyclic
eect” with respect to the distribution of complementizers. We have just seen that
the language prescribes the use of a distinctive complementizer for clauses that form
a domain in which WH-movement has applied [see (17)–(19)]. It is also crucial to
note that, in the case of “long” movement, the same complementizer must introduce
In the speech of some younger speakers, the distinction between COMPt and COMPpro
has been lost (at least in informal registers), so that COMPt (aL) is also used in resumptive
pronoun relatives:
(ii) an fear a bhí ag caint leis
the man t were you talk- to-him
“the man that you were talking to”
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
every clause that contains the WH-trace but not its ultimate antecedent. e eect is
to create a chain of COMPt-particles between (for instance) the head and the gap in a
relative clause structure, as schematized in (22) and illustrated in (23).
(22) [NP NP [S aL … [S aL … [S aL … t …]]]]
(23) an rud a shíl a dúirt a dhéanfá
the thing t thought I t said you t do--2
“the thing that I thought you said you would do
For a detailed discussion of this eect, see McCloskey (1979, 1985) and Chung and
McCloskey (1987). We return to the analysis of these facts below; for now, though,
two points should be stressed: (1) the obligatory appearance of the pattern schema-
tized in (22) is characteristic not just of relative clause structures but of all Ā-binding
constructions in the language (see McCloskey, 1979, 1985, for detailed discussion and
exemplication) and (2) the pattern of (22) is not characteristic of resumptive pro-
noun structures. e pattern classically found with resumptive pronoun binding is
one in which COMPpro appears only in the topmost COMP-position, but in which
the default complementizer gol/gur appears in all lower COMP-positions within the
relative clause:
(24) a. an rud ar dúirt go gcoinneodh ceilte é
the thing pro said he  keep- he hidden it
“the thing that he said he would keep (it) hidden
b. radharc ar bhreá liom a bheith ábalta a mhaíomh
sight pro I-would-really-like be- able claim-
go bhfacas é
 see--1 it
“a sight that I would love to be able to claim that I saw (it)”
We will return to this later.
. e distribution of resumptive pronouns
One of the important points of data that I want to establish in this article is that the
pattern of distribution of resumptive pronouns in Irish is extremely broad. By this I
mean two things:
(25) Resumptive pronouns appear in every WH-construction.
(26) Within each WH-construction, resumptive pronouns can appear in every
clausal position but one.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
e documentation of these distribution patterns is an important task, but it is also
one that makes for tedious reading. For that reason, I have assembled the relevant data
in the Appendix of this article. Here I simply summarize the principal observations
suggested by an examination of that data.
It has been customary, at least since Chomsky (1977), to classify certain construc-
tions as unied by the characteristic of being built around an instance of WH-binding
(Ā-binding). Chomsky (1977) identies the following eight constructions as being of
this type: (1) restrictive and nonrestrictive relative clauses, (2) constituent questions,
(3) cles, (4) topicalization structures, (5) comparative and equative clauses, (6) inni-
tival relatives, (7) purpose clauses, and (8) complex adjectival (“Tough Movement”)
constructions. It is a fact about Irish that the class of construction types in which
resumptive pronouns can appear is simply and exactly the class of WH-constructions
dened by Chomsky (1977).8
Consider now the second distributional question posed above: within a single
clause, what is the range of positions in which resumptive pronouns can appear?
Ihave argued at length elsewhere (McCloskey 1985) that the underlying rule governing
the distribution of gaps and resumptive pronouns in Irish is extremely straightfor-
ward unless independent principles intervene, there is a free choice between use
of a resumptive pronoun and use of a gap (WH-trace). e independent principles
that most frequently intervene are subjacency and the ECP. ere are many positions
from which WH-movement is impossible (from within NP or PP, for instance), and
in such positions the appearance of a gap at S-structure is, of course, ungrammati-
cal. For detailed discussion of these constraints, see McCloskey (1979, 1985). But, in
the familiar way, resumptive pronouns can be used in the positions from which WH-
traces are excluded, and in these circumstances use of the resumptive pronoun will
have the appearance of being obligatory. Hence the contrasts in (27) and (28), which
stand here for many similar cases. For more detailed exemplication, see McCloskey
(1979, 1985).
(27) a. na dánta sin nach bhfuil ios againn cén
the poems  pro+ is knowledge at-us what
áit ar cumadh iad
place  were-composed them
“those poems that we do not know where they were composed”
. ere is no topicalization structure distinct from cles (unless one analyzes the “reduced
cles” discussed in McCloskey 1979: 90–92, in this way). Le dislocation is considered here
in due course.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
b. *na dánta sin nach bhfuil ios againn cén
the poems  t+ is knowledge at-us what
áit ar cumadh
place  were-composed
“those poems that we do not know where were composed”
(28) a. an fear a raibh ag caint leis pro
the man pro was I talk- with-3-
“the man that I was talking to him
b. *an fear a bhí ag caint le
the man t was I talk- to
“the man that I was talking to
e binding of resumptive pronouns is not constrained by subjacency or by the ECP;
WH-movement, however, is so constrained.9 From these two assumptions, the con-
trasts seen in (27) and in (28) follow. Every case that I am aware of in which the use
of a resumptive pronoun has the appearance of being obligatory yields to this sort of
explanation: application of WH-movement is blocked by subjacency, or by the ECP
(see Chung and McCloskey 1987), and the only possible way in which the structure
can surface at all is as a resumptive pronoun structure.
But in those circumstances in which WH-movement can apply to leave an
S-structure gap, the option of using a resumptive pronoun as a bound element (with
the concomitant choice of complementizer) is also available. is pattern of systematic
optionality is illustrated for all major clausal positions in the examples cited in the
second part of the Appendix.
ere is, in fact, just one position from which resumptive pronouns are excluded.
e highest subject of a clause cannot be occupied by a resumptive pronoun.
(29) a. *an fear a raibh breoite
the man pro be- he ill
“the man that (he) was ill
b. *na daoine a rabhadar pro breoite
the people pro be--3 ill
“the people that (they) were ill”
. Irish displays a very conventional array of island effects; the complex NP-constraint
(both cases), the WH-island condition and the adjunct island condition are all observed.
For discussion and exemplification, see McCloskey (1979, 1985). is fact suggests that it
would be wrong to postulate any principled connection between the productive availability of
resumptive pronouns in a language and the apparent inapplicability of subjacency (see Sells
1984a: 255, for this suggestion; and Engdahl 1985: 10, for critical commentary).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
Note that this is a restriction that applies only to the highest subject of a WH-clause.
As we have already seen, resumptive pronouns appear freely in the subject position of
embedded clauses, nite and nonnite:
(30) a. an t-ór seo ar chreid corr-dhuine go raibh ann
this gold pro believed a few people  was it there
“this gold that a few people believed (it) was there”
b. cúpla muirear a bhféadfaí a rá go
a-few families pro one-couId say- 
rabhadar pro bocht
be--3 poor
“a few families that one could say (they) were poor”
I refer to this restriction from now on as the highest subject restriction (HSR). It gures
in an important way in argumentation at a later point, and it is discussed in greater
detail then. For now, let us merely note that the HSR determines the only clausal
position from which resumptive pronouns are excluded.10
. Resumptive pronouns as variables
Consider now the analytical implications of the distributional pattern established in
the previous section and in the Appendix. What we have established is that resump-
tive pronouns appear in all the WH-constructions in the language, and that resump-
tive pronouns can appear (alongside WH-traces) in every clausal position except that
excluded by the HSR. Given the breadth and regularity of the distributional pattern,
one clearly does not want to license resumptive pronouns by proposing rules that
are either particular to given constructions or particular to given clausal positions.
emost economical statement, and the one that does justice to the pattern we have
seen, is (31).
(31) Ā-chains in Irish can terminate in pronouns.
1. It should be pointed out, though, that there are no adjunct resumptive pronouns. at is,
there are no structures such as the following: the place that we bought a house there or the time
that we bought a house then. is could simply reflect a lexical gap (i.e. the absence of adjunct
pronouns of category NP; see Kuroda 1968; Bresnan & Grimshaw 1978), or it may require
some deeper explanation.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
ln fact, it is proposed in McCloskey and Sells (1988) that A-chains can also have pro-
nouns as their lowest elements; if that is correct, then (31) is in fact only one aspect of
a broader statement.
e chain-formation rule in (31) has the consequence, of course, that resumptive
pronouns are dened as syntactic variables, since, given (31), the closest binder for a
resumptive pronoun is some c-commanding element in an Ā-position. at being so,
resumptive pronouns should show the characteristic behavior of variables. In particu-
lar, they should be subject to Condition C of the binding theory, since variables are
among the elements subject to this condition. To be more specic, one should nd
strong crossover eects, such as illustrated in (32), for resumptive pronouns.
(32) *Whoj did you think that hej said that Mary would marry tj?
Sentence (32) is ungrammatical because it fails to meet the requirements of binding
theory. Condition C requires that names and variables be A-free (lack a c-commanding
antecedent in an argument position) in the domain of their operators (cf. Chomsky
1982). e object trace in (32) is coindexed with the pronoun he, which is in an argu-
ment position (subject position) and is also within the domain of the operator (whoj)
that binds tj. Condition C is therefore violated in (32).
e question to address at this point, then, is the following: do resumptive pro-
nouns in Irish exhibit strong crossover eects? e answer is that they do, but a certain
amount of work has to be done to establish the point. Simple translation of the English
example (32), substituting the resumptive pronoun for the trace, tells us nothing.
(33) Cé ar shíl gur dhúirt go bpósfadh
who pro thought you  said he  would-marry
Máire é?
Mary him
“Whoj did you think that hej said that Mary would marry tj?”
Sentence (33) is perfectly grammatical. But notice that it will always be possible to
analyze an example such as (33) in such a way that the lemost or highest pronoun is
the bound variable. e second pronoun is then not a variable but instead is simply
coindexed with the pronominal variable in a routine way analogous to English exam-
ples such as Whoj do you think tj said Mary would marry himj? Nothing can be deduced
from such examples. We must work a little harder to make the argument.
Specically, substituting an epithet for the c-commanding pronoun in examples
such as (33) eliminates the possibility of construing the c-commanding element
itself as a variable. For epithets cannot themselves function as resumptive pronouns
(i.e.asvariables).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
Note rst that epithets do in fact give rise to strong crossover eects when they
c-command, and are coindexed with, R-expressions (variables or lexical NP).11
(34) a. e bastardj said hej would resign.
b. *e bastardj said Johnj would resign.
c. *Whoj did the bastardj say tj would resign?
Sentence (34b) is ungrammatical because the lexical NP John is c-commanded by, and
coindexed with, the epithet the bastard. Sentence (34c) is ungrammatical because the
embedded subject trace is A-bound by the epithet the bastard, giving rise to a Condi-
tion C (strong crossover) violation. Consider now the Irish examples in (35)–(37).
(35) Sin an fear ar dhúirt le tuismitheoirí an bhastaird
that the man pro said I with parents the bastard
gur cheart é a chaitheamh isteach i bpríosún.
+ right him throw- into in prison
“at is the man that I said to the bastard’s parents that he should be thrown
into prison
(36) *Sin an fear ar dhúirt an bastard go maródh muid
that the man pro said the bastard  would-kill he us
“at is the man that the bastardj said hej would kill us”
(37) *Sin an fear ar dhúirt leis an bhastard gur
that the man pro said I with the bastard +
cheart é a chaitheamh isteach i bpríosún.
right him throw- into in prison
“at is the man that I said to the bastard that he should be thrown in prison
11. e status of epithets with respect to binding theory has been discussed by Lasnik (1976,
1989), among others. Lasnik (1989) shows in particular that epithets simultaneously exhibit
the properties of R-expressions and of pronouns with respect to the binding conditions. is
is true of their behavior both as binding and as bound elements. In particular, when func-
tioning as c-commanding antecedents to lexical NPs, epithets pattern with pronouns in giving
rise to robust Condition C violations, even in languages (such as ai and Vietnamese) in
which lexical NPs give rise to only very weak or nonexistent Condition C effects in the same
configuration. e same contrasts are palpable in English:
(i) ??Johnj said that Johnj would come.
(ii) *e idiotj said that Johnj would come.
(iii) *Hej said that Johnj would come.
Epithets thus provide a particularly good way to test for Condition C effects.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 1
Sentence (35) is grammatical. is is because the epithet does not c-command the
resumptive pronoun and there is, therefore, no Condition C violation (the vari-
able is A-free, as required). Sentence (36) is ungrammatical. Here the epithet does
c-command the resumptive pronoun, and a strong crossover conguration results.
Sentence (37) is also ungrammatical. is is because in this case, too, the epithet
c-commands the resumptive, giving rise to a strong crossover conguration.12 ese
facts fall naturally into place if resumptive pronouns are in fact Ā-bound and are
therefore syntactic variables.
. e nature of the binding relation
e distributional arguments, and the arguments from binding theory, suggest that it
is correct to construe resumptive pronouns in Irish as Ā-bound variables. But this con-
clusion still leaves a number of issues unresolved. In particular, the question of what
precisely functions as antecedent to the resumptive pronoun remains to be settled.
Second, it remains unclear at what level of representation (D-structure, S-structure,
orLF) the binding is dened. It is the purpose of this section to try to establish answers
to these and related questions.
.1 e antecedent
Consider a relative clause such as (38a) and its schematic structure (38b).
(38) a. na míreanna a leanann séimhiú iad
the particles pro follow Lenition them
“the particles that Lenition follows (them)”
b. [NP NP [S pro [Spro …]]]
1. is interpretation of (37) requires the assumption that subcategorized prepositions
(“case-marking” prepositions) do not “count” (to speak loosely) for the computation of
c-command configurations in Irish. is interpretation is required, in any case, for other
reasons (see Chung & McCloskey 1987: n. 26). One could perhaps conclude from this observa-
tion that phrase structure configurations at S-structure do not form the appropriate domain
over which to define the kind of command relations needed in the statement of anaphoric
(inthe broad sense) conditions. Alternatively, one might conclude with Stowell (1990) that the
so-called prepositions of Irish are in fact case-marking prefixes, such that the phrase leisan
bhastard of (37) will be a NP and the familiar definition of c-command will work in the
appropriate way. What is needed for our current argument is the observation itself, not the
analysis of the observation. Some speakers report a subtle difference between (36) and (37),
the latter being preferred. is difference (if real) could be related to the presence of the
governing preposition in (37). In general, judgments in this domain are surprisingly robust.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
If one asks what precisely the antecedent is for the resumptive pronoun in (38), there
are two answers that suggest themselves, that is, two hypotheses that grow naturally
out of recent thinking on these and related matters.
One obvious possibility is that the head NP is the antecedent. is answer is com-
patible with the conclusions we have established so far, to the extent that it is plausible
or implausible to call the head position of a relative clause structure an Ā-position.
Corresponding hypotheses are available for the other WH-constructions in which
resumptive pronouns appear – the cleed phrase will be the antecedent in cles and
so on. For ease of exposition, I restrict attention here to the case of (restrictive) relative
clauses. e hypothesis being considered, however, can be extended, in mostly obvious
ways, to all the other WH-constructions.
e other possibility is to take the antecedent of the resumptive pronoun to be a
null operator within COMP. More specically, we can adopt the theory of the phrase
structure of clausal categories (in particular, S) developed by Chomsky (1986a). is
proposal seeks to rationalize the analysis of the categories S and S within X-bar theory.
S is taken to be a projection of the zero-level category C0 and is taken to be a com-
pletely regular projection, in that C0 has a complement and a specier:
(39) CP
XP C1
C0S (=IP)
e specier position, XP in (39), is taken to be the landing site for WH-movement
and is, therefore, the locus of the various WH-operators that function as Ā-binders
at LF. A natural extension of this view is to propose that there are also null operators
in this position for resumptive pronoun structures, and that it is these operators that
function as antecedents to resumptive pronouns.
It is the purpose of this section to argue that the rst of these hypotheses is wrong
and that the second is right. To make this case, we have to consider in more detail the
nature of the HSR and also to look more closely at the system of principles that deter-
mines the distribution of complementizer particles.
We can begin with a consideration of the HSR. Recall that this is a constraint that
bars the appearance of a resumptive pronoun in a relative clause in the subject position
immediately subjacent to the head:
(40) a. *an fear a raibh sé breoite
the man pro was he ill
“the man that (he) was ill
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
b. *na daoine a rabhadar pro breoite
the people pro be--3 ill
“the people that (they) were ill”
ese facts reect a requirement that pronouns, if bound, be nonlocally bound; that is,
they have the character of a disjoint reference eect – a Condition B eect that applies
in the domain of Ā-binding rather than in the domain of A-binding. Like ConditionB,
this is a constraint that has the eect of rendering ungrammatical those structures
in which a pronoun (a pronominal variable, in this case) is too close to its anteced-
ent. e positions in which resumptive pronouns can legally appear within a clause
(direct object, prepositional object, possessor position within NP) are all separated
from their respective antecedents by the intervention of at least one more maximal
projection boundary (VP, PP, NP) than is true in the case of subjects. Recall also that
if the resumptive pronoun appears in embedded subject position, the eect disappears
and the structure is grammatical.
(41) an fear ar dhúirt go dtiocfadh sé
the man pro said I  would-come he
“the man that I said (he) would come”
is observation, too, suggests that syntactic distance plays a role in the HSR.
e disjoint reference character of the eect can also be seen in the fact that if one
arranges for the resumptive pronoun to be embedded within a subject NP, the eect
also disappears. is is true (unsurprisingly) for possessors within the subject:
(42) an ghirseach a bhfuil a máthair breoite
the girl pro is 3- mother ill
“the girl whose mother is ill”
More surprisingly, the same eect can be observed in the case of coordinate subjects:13
(43) a. duine ar bith a mbeadh sé féin
anyone pro would-be he+
agus Tom mór le-n a chéile
and Tom great with each other
“anybody that he and Tom would be very fond of one another”
b. daoine a rabhadar pro féin agus a gclann
people pro be--3 pro+ and their family
mhac ábalta ar iascach
sons- able on shing
“people that they and their sons were capable of shing”
1. For detailed discussion of the syntax of the kind of coordinate structures seen in (43b),
and of their interaction with agreement and identification, see McCloskey (1986b).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
For these reasons and others, a great deal of previous work on this topic (includ-
ing McCloskey 1983; Borer 1984) has been based on the idea that the HSR is to be
accounted for by extending the domain of application of Condition B in some appro-
priate way, so that it encompasses Ā-binding as well as A-binding. Recent work by
Aoun and Li (1989) also explores this idea, drawing on data concerning the distribu-
tion of pronouns bound by quantier expressions in Mandarin Chinese. ey propose
that bound pronouns (those linked to antecedents that at LF occupy Ā-positions) are
subject to a requirement of Ā-disjointness” that governs the distribution of referential
pronouns. eir proposal, if modied slightly as in (44), will account for the data we
are concerned with here.
(44) A pronoun must be Ā-free in the least complete functional complex containing
the pronoun and a subject distinct from the pronoun.
e notion “complete functional complex” (CFC) is to be understood in the sense of
Chomsky (1986b: 169). e term subject in (44) refers to the NP-position of structures
such as (9) and (10). More precisely, a subject is a NP that is governed by INFL.
e basic examples in (40) will now be ungrammatical because the minimal CFC
that contains the pronoun and a subject distinct from the pronoun will be the higher
S in which the whole relative structure is embedded. e pronoun is not Ā-free in this
domain – whether one takes its antecedent to be the head NP or a null operator in
COMP, this antecedent will be contained within the higher S in violation of (44). For
the case of an embedded subject, as in (41), the minimal CFC containing the resump-
tive pronoun and a distinct subject will again be the next highest S of the relative
clauses structure. But the pronoun is Ā-free in this domain. Again, this conclusion is
independent of what one takes the immediate antecedent of the resumptive pronoun
to be. e next S up in a structure such as (41) contains neither the head NP, nor, on
the alternative conception, the null operator in Spec of COMP. For cases (42) and (43),
in which the resumptive pronoun in each instance is contained within a larger sub-
ject NP, the minimal CFC containing the pronoun and a distinct subject is simply the
minimal S containing the resumptive. But the pronoun is Ā-free in this domain, and
the structure is therefore expected to be grammatical, as is the case. Once again, this
conclusion holds no matter which hypothesis one endorses about the antecedent; both
the head NP and a null operator in Spec of COMP are external to S.
Principle (44) also accounts for some data we have not yet considered. Recall that
objects are preposed and le-adjoined to VP in nonnite clauses:
(45) a. Caithdh Ciarán a eiceáil
must I Ciaran see-
“I must see Ciaran
b. [S NPsubj [VP NPobj [VP V tobj]]]
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
Note that since the preposed object is in VP-adjoined position, it is in an Ā-position.
Ifthis is so, and if it is also correct, as we have argued, that Ā-chains can always ter-
minate in pronouns in Irish, then the question arises of why the structure illustrated
in (45) does not permit a resumptive pronoun in direct object position, as illustrated
in (46).
(46) a. *Caithdh Ciarán a eiceáil é
must I Ciaran see- him
“I must see Ciaran
b. *Caithdh Ciaran dhá eiceáil pro.
must I Ciaran 3-+see-
“I must see Ciaran
But notice that (44) provides a direct account for the ungrammaticality of (46). e
minimal CFC containing the pronoun and a subject distinct from it is the lower S;
but the pronoun is Ā-bound within this domain, and the structure therefore stands in
violation of (44).14
1. “Object” preposing also operates from the subject position of small-clause complements
to certain verbs (perception verbs, for instance; McCloskey & Sells 1988: 163–164). Peter Sells
has pointed out to me that this fact poses a potential problem for the view of object preposing
outlined in the text. If one had a coordinate subject in the small clause, one might expect a
resumptive pronoun within the coordinate subject to be bound by the preposed NP (on the
analogy of structures such as [43]). But such structures are ungrammatical:
(i) *Níor mhaith liom Eoghan a shamhlú é agus Ciarán ag imeacht
I-wouldn’t-like you Eoghan imagine him and Ciaran leave-
“I wouldn’t like you to imagine Ciaran and Eoghan leaving”
If (i) is to be declared ungrammatical by (44), the least CFC containing the resumptive
pronoun and a subject distinct from the pronoun must be the nonfinite clause headed by the
verb samhlaigh (“imagine”). is consequence, however, already follows given the definition
of subject associated with (44), namely, that it is the NP governed by INFL. e closest such
subject in (i) is the subject of the nonfinite clause. e nonfinite clause, then, defines the
domain in which the resumptive pronoun must be Ā-free. It is in fact Ā-bound in this domain,
and (i) is, as a consequence, ungrammatical.
Similar remarks apply in the case of copular clauses, as in (ii) and (iii). Sentence (iii)
represents the subclass of copular structures that are cles. As shown in (iii), it is possible for
the focus position of a cle to be occupied by a resumptive pronoun.
(ii) girseach ar de bhunadh Protastúnach í
girl pro +  of people Protestant her
“a girl who is of Protestant stock”
(iii) fear arbh é a bhí breoite
man pro +  him t was ill
“a man that it was him who was sick”
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
is interpretation of the HSR has certain empirical advantages over previous
proposals that have been made to account for the relevant data. Borer (1984) suggests
extending Condition B of the binding theory directly to Ā-binding. e idea is that
pronouns must be simply free (that is Ā-free and A-free) in their governing categories.
Subjects are taken to be unique in having two governors: INFL and COMP. Subjects
are thus distinct from all other clausal positions in having S rather than S as their gov-
erning category. Subject resumptive pronouns will always be bound within S and will
thereby always violate Condition B. Resumptive pronouns in other positions will also
be bound within S, but this will not matter since their governing category is S and in
this category they are Ā-free.
is approach can be criticized on two levels. It is, to begin with, very unclear how
it will be possible to reconcile the idea that subject NPs are governed both by INFL and
by COMP with the minimality requirement on government. Yet much recent work
suggests that minimality is a crucial condition on government relations.
Second, it seems that this approach will have diculty in making the crucial dis-
tinction between (40) and (43). e government relations in which the rst NP of a
coordinate subject is involved seem to be exactly the same as those in which a simple
subject NP is involved. at is, it is just as true of féin in (43a) that it is governed
by INFL as it is of in (40a). is is argued in some detail in McCloskey (1986) on
the basis of evidence from case marking and identication of pro. e analysis in that
study suggests that there is no dierence in government relations between the subjects
of (40) and the subjects of (43). If this line of analysis is right, then it will be dicult to
make a distinction between the ungrammatical (40) and the grammatical (43) on the
basis of the notion of “governing category.
ese observations also argue against the proposals made in Sells (1984b). ose
proposals are made within the context of a set of analytical assumptions very dier-
ent from those adopted here, but the basic idea can be translated and paraphrased as
in(47).15
ese examples will be grammatical to the extent that it is plausible to regard the resumptive
pronouns as not being subjects in the sense defined in association with (44). In fact, this
position is not only plausible but also virtually demanded when one begins to look at the
syntax of the copula in a serious way. ere is a good deal of evidence that such structures
contain a null expletive that is governed by INFL (which is arguably the copula itself). is,
and not the resumptive pronoun, is the subject of the clause. Note that this conclusion is
already suggested by the fact that the pronouns in (ii) and (iii) are nonnominative. e
resumptive pronouns in (ii) and (iii), then, will have exactly the same status as any nonsubject
resumptive pronoun.
1. See Sells (1984b: 231–266), in particular, the case domain filter (p. 239).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
(47) An operator cannot bind a pronoun in a position assigned Case by that
occurrence of  that is most closely associated with the operator.
Examples such as (40) will then be ungrammatical because they each contain an
operator-INFL complex in which INFL assigns nominative case to a pronoun bound
by the operator. But Principle (47) still fails to make the necessary distinction between
the ungrammatical (40) and the grammatical (43), since (43) is not dierent from (40)
in any sense relevant to the function of the ller in (47).16
Whatever the specic or ultimate merits of the Ā-disjointness requirement as
stated in (44), this general approach to the HSR (in which it derives from a Condition-
B-like principle operating in the domain of Ā-binding) seems right. What I want to
consider next is the interaction between this principle and the rules or principles that
determine the distribution of complementizer particles. is interaction provides an
important clue about the exact nature and position of the antecedent in resumptive
pronoun structures.
Recall from our earlier discussion that long-distance relatives are subject to a
requirement that each COMP-position between a WH-trace and its antecedent binder
must be occupied by the complementizer a, in the pattern of (48).
(48) a. an rud a shíl a dhéanfainn
the thing t thought I t do--1
“the thing that I thought I would do”
b. [NP NP [S aL … [S aL … t …]]]
Recall too that this is not the pattern that is in general found in the case of long rela-
tives built around the binding of a resumptive pronoun. In this case, one nds the
distinctive COMPpro in the highest position, but the default complementizer in the
intermediate positions.
(49) a. an fear ar shíl go dtiocfadh
the man pro thought I  come- he
“the man that I thought (he) would come
b. [NP NP [S aN … [S gopro …]]]
Now this dierence in the two complementizer patterns is very natural, given certain
widely accepted assumptions. If WH-movement is constrained by subjacency and
1. Sells notes a similar difficulty involving the corresponding Hebrew data (1984b: 252–253),
but he suggests that the resumptive pronoun might be “intrusive” in the sense of Chao and
Sells (1983), that is, not truly Ā-bound. If this were so, however, quantified head NPs should
be impossible in such structures. But this is not the case, in Irish at least, as we have already
seen in (43a).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
operates in a successive cyclic fashion, and if the appearance of the complementizer aL
is a formal mark of the application of WH-movement (in a sense soon made precise
here), then we expect the appearance of aL in every clause that has dened a domain of
application for WH-movement. But as we have already seen, the binding of a resump-
tive pronoun is not a relation constrained by subjacency, and there is, therefore, no
reason to expect that the distinctive complementizer COMPpro would appear at inter-
mediate COMP-positions.
But of more immediate concern is the fact that besides the pattern in (49), another
possibility exists for the case of long relatives with resumptive pronouns. is is the
pattern schematized in (50) and exemplied in (51)–(53):17
(50) [NP NP [S aN … [S aNpro …]]]
(51) an talamh ar mheas a raibh an ceol
the land pro thought I pro was the music
ag teacht as pro
come- from-3-
“the land that I thought the music was coming from (it)”
(52) an méid den dán ar mheas a raibh feidhm
the amount of-the poem pro thought he pro was use
leis pro
with-3-
“as much of the poem as he thought was needed”
(53) an bhean a raibh ag súil a
the woman pro was I expect- pro
bhfaighinn uaithi pro arís é
get--1 from-3- again it
“the woman from whom I was expecting that I would get it again
What we have in these structures is the appearance of the distinctive aN complemen-
tizer associated with the binding of a resumptive pronoun, at every COMP-position
between the pronoun and the head of the relative structure. is pattern is very
highly marked in comparison with the pattern in (49). Its marked character can be
seen in a number of ways. In the course of some ten years of searching for naturally
occurring examples of type (50) in speech or in writing, I have come across just the
three examples cited in (51)–(53). is contrasts with some y attested examples of
the pattern illustrated in (49). e marked character of the construction in (50) also
emerges in the degree of uncertainty and insecurity reported by native speakers in
1. Example (53) is cited in de Bhaldraithe (1956–1957). See also Ó Siadhail (1980: 90).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
their judgments about the relevant examples. Some speakers refuse to accept examples
such as (51)–(53); others report uncertainty about the status of these examples. More-
over, there is a great deal of uctuation from speaker to speaker and from session to
session in elicitation. It seems then, that the structure in (50) must have a place, albeit
a peripheral and highly marginal place, in the grammatical system of the language.
We return to the problem of accounting for the peripheral status of these structures
shortly. For the moment, we are concerned with two questions: rst, how the structures
can be licensed at all and, second, what implications the existence of such structures
has for the problem of identifying the immediate antecedent to a resumptive pronoun.
With regard to the second question, the crucial observation is this: the uncer-
tainty and insecurity that generally surround speakers’ reactions to (50) disappear
completely in the face of examples such as (54), in which the resumptive pronoun
appears in the subject position of the embedded clause. Examples such as those in
(51)–(53) are marginal but clearly acceptable to some speakers. Example (54), on the
other hand, is thoroughly and unambiguously ungrammatical.
(54) *an fear ar shíl a raibh breoite
the man pro thought I pro was he ill
“the man that I thought (he) was ill”
Consider the implications of this fact. Clearly we have here another reection of the
HSR. Viewed in isolation, or viewed locally, the conguration of the embedded clause
in (54) a raibh sé breoiteis identical to the ungrammatical relative clause in the
core cases that illustrate the HSR, namely, the examples in (40). If we want to account
for these two facts by means of the same formal mechanism, then the explanation for
the ungrammaticality of (54) must be sought locally, that is, within the domain of the
embedded clause. If the Ā-disjointness requirement (or something like it) is to account
for the ungrammaticality of (54), then the subject resumptive pronoun must have an
antecedent that is “too close” to it within the embedded clause.
Now it is very dicult to see how this intuition could be given formal expression if
we make the assumption that the closest antecedent for the resumptive pronoun is the
head NP. In particular, it is very dicult to see how the robust contrast between (54)
and (55) could be accounted for in terms of the HSR.
(55) an fear ar shíl go raibh breoite
the man pro thought I  was he ill
“the man that I thought (he) was ill”
ere is no obvious sense in which the antecedent is “closer” to the resumptive pro-
noun in (54) than in (55), if we make the assumption that the antecedent is the head
NP. More specically, there seems to be no way for the Ā-disjointness requirement to
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
make any distinction between (54) and (55), if we take the position that the resumptive
pronoun is locally bound by the head NP.
But a simple and elegant connection is drawn among the ungrammaticality of (54),
the ungrammaticality of (40), and the grammaticality of (55) if we make the alterna-
tive assumption being considered here – namely, that the antecedent to the resumptive
pronoun is a null operator in Spec of COMP.
We can reason as follows. In the simplest cases, we have to deal with two kinds of
relative clauses:
(56) a. [NP NP [CP aL [… t …]]]
b. [NP NP [CP aN [… pro …]]]
ere is good reason to believe that both aL and aN are lexical complementizers; in
particular, there is rm evidence for the case of the movement type (56a) that the par-
ticle aL is not itself the moved phrase.18 What this suggests is that we are dealing with
structures such as (57).
(57)
CP
Ø
NP
[αF]j
t
[αF]j
C1
C0
[αF]
S
An Ā-chain is formed between the trace and the operator phrase in Spec of CP. It is
irrelevant for present concerns whether this chain is formed by way of movement, or
by way of base generation of the operator phrase and chain formation at S-structure.
Itseems reasonable to believe that items in the same chain must share feature speci-
cations; the morphological case of a moved WH-phrase, for instance, is normally that
assigned to the position occupied by the lowest trace it binds. If that is so, the crucial
1. See McCloskey (1979: 10–16); note, in particular, that aL can be used as a complemen-
tizer in a range of cases that clearly do not involve WH-movement:
(i) Is amhlaidh a bhí neart capaill ann
 so t was strength horse in-him
“It is a fact that he had the strength of a horse”
(ii) Sé rud a beireadh air i nDoire.
it-is thing t was-caught on-him in Derry
“e fact is he was captured in Derry”
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 1
features identifying the empty category under S as a WH-trace will also appear on
the NP in Spec of CP. ese same features will also be shared by C0 by way of the
mechanism of Spec-Head agreement discussed in Chomsky (1986a).19 e form of
resumptive pronoun relatives will be exactly analogous:
(58)
CP
Ø
NP
[αF]j
pro
[αF]j
C1
C0
[αF]
S
We thus have a way of making a connection between the character of the variable
(whether it is a gap or a pronoun) and the choice of complementizer particle in a rela-
tive structure. e connection is made by way of two mechanisms feature sharing
among elements of a chain and Sped-Head agreement – that are of considerable gen-
erality and that have much independent justication. e nal element in the analysis
is the element that must minimally be there on any account, namely, a featural distinc-
tion between the two relevant complementizers, aL and aN.20
What are the relevant features? An obvious rst guess is that they are the features
[anaphoric] and [pronominal], rst introduced in Chomsky (1981, 1982) to distin-
guish among the various nominal categories relevant to the functioning of binding
theory. Within that system of denitions, we have the specications in (59).
(59) Pronouns:a.
b. WH-traces:
+pronominal
–anaphoric
–pronominal
–anaphoric
1. See Rizzi (1990) and Chung (1990) for extensions of the mechanism of Spec-Head agree-
ment to clausal projections.
. Note that this analysis succeeds in doing what McCloskey (1979) signally failed to do:
it accounts for complementizer selection in terms of a strictly local selectional mechanism
(Spec-Head agreement).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
If we assume this featural distinction between WH-traces and pronominals, then the
features in question will eventually pass to the C0 position of the clause that contains
the binding operator (by way of the mechanisms just discussed), and the two comple-
mentizers can be distinguished thereby.21
is view of matters is a close formal expression of the intuition that the func-
tion of the complementizers aL and aN is to signal the presence of an operator of a
kind appropriate to bind either a trace or a resumptive pronoun. e function of the
complementizer go, on the other hand, is to signal the absence of a binder. e basic
facts of the HSR, as we have seen, follow from this conception since we will get HSR
eects just in case the complementizer aN signals the presence of an operator that is
“too close” (in the sense we have dened in terms of the Ā-disjointness requirement
in [144]) to a subject resumptive pronoun. When go signals the absence of such an
operator, there is no HSR eect. e contrast between (55), on the one hand, and
examples(54) and (40), on the other, thus falls out straightforwardly. e three struc-
tures are as in (60).
(60) a. [NP NP [CP Opj aN [… [CP go [V proj …]]]]] [= (55)]
b. [NP NP [CP Opj aN [… [CP Opj aN [V proj …]]]]] [= (54)]
c. [NP NP [CP Opj aN [V proj …]]] [= (40)]
is general line of analysis, then, accounts for the complete ungrammaticality of (54)
and links it to the ungrammaticality of (40) in a satisfying way.
Notice that what we are le with now is a mixed system of denitions in which
nominal categories such as anaphor, pronominal, and R-expression are dened inher-
ently in terms of the features [pronominal] and [anaphoric], but in which the notion
of variable is dened contextually. at is, a variable is an element locally bound by an
element in the Ā-position.22
Consider now the question of how the operators that bind resumptive pronouns
get to be in Spec of CP. Notice that they must be positioned there by means of base
generation. Or, at any rate, they cannot get to their ultimate position by way of move-
ment from the position they bind, since the relation between such operators and the
position they bind is not constrained by subjacency. We assume, then, that the operator
that binds resumptive pronouns is base generated in Spec of CP.
It is presumably the case that at least the topmost COMP-projection in a rela-
tive clause structure must contain a binding operator. is seems to be a general
requirement and must reect a principle whereby relative clause structures cannot
1. For the cases of Note18, I assume that the two items in question (amhlaidh and sé rud)
are lexically specified to take a complement clause headed by C0 [−pronominal, −anaphoric].
. is is also the position advocated in Safir (1984).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
be semantically interpreted unless there is a binding operator in the COMP-position
closest to the head NP. Put another way, the presence of a WH-operator in the top-
most COMP-projection is an obligatory syntactic correlate of the semantic process of
λ-abstraction that forms the property predicated of the head NP in a relative clause
structure. As a consequence of this requirement, the topmost instance of the comple-
mentizer COMPpro is also required by Spec-Head agreement.
But it is also true that, given a structure such as (61), there is no reason why
an operator, although not required, should not be base generated in the specier
position of the lower C-projection, as well as in the specier position of the higher
C-projection.
(61) [NP [CP XP C0 [S … [CP XP C0 [S pro …]]]]]
As long as the Ā-disjointness requirement in (44) is observed, nothing we have said
rules out a structure such as (62).
(62) [NP [CP Opj C0 [S … [CP Opj C0 [S pro …]]]]]
is structure gives rise to the highly marked examples seen in (50)–(53), once Spec-
Head agreement has enforced appearance of the appropriate complementizer at each
C0-position associated with an operator.
is result will be a welcome one to the extent that we can now give some account
of the marked and peripheral status of these examples. One possible account would
be to appeal to the principle of economy of representation proposed and discussed by
Chomsky (1988). It is true, of course, that the intermediate operators and the inter-
mediate links in the Ā-chain that characterize (62) and (50)–(53) are unnecessary:
their appearance is not mandated by any principle of grammar, or by the demands of
semantic interpretation. is is just the kind of situation that the principle of economy
of representation disfavors. If that principle can be appropriately interpreted not as an
absolute prohibition on the structures that are in violation of it but rather as one that
assigns a high cost realized as markedness, then we will have an account of the mar-
ginal character of (50)–(53).
ere is one last issue in this domain that we must consider before proceeding.
Wehave just seen that a resumptive pronoun can be bound by an operator in the mini-
mal clause (CP) in which it is contained. We have also seen that this is a highly marked
option. It is important to observe at this point, however, that once this marked option
is chosen, certain other requirements must be met. In particular, ifa binding operator
is present in the C-projection that most immediately dominates the resumptive pro-
noun, then each successively higher C-projection must also contain a binding operator.
at is, the successive cyclic requirement reinstates itself, so to speak, once the option is
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
taken of placing a binding operator for the resumptive pronoun in the lowest projection
of C. us, (63) contrasts with (64) in being completely ungrammatical.
(63) *an talamh ar dhúirt gur mheas a raibh
the land pro said you  thought you pro was
an ceol ag teach as
the music come- out-of-it
“the land that you said you thought the music was coming from
(64) an talamh ar dhúirt ar mheas a raibh
the land pro said you pro thought you pro was
an ceol ag teach as
the music come- out-of-it
“the land that you said you thought the music was coming from
In (63), the chain of successively subjacent aN particles has been broken by the go
particle, which signals, on our assumptions, the absence of a binding operator in the
second C-projection of the series. In (64), the chain is not broken. I want to stress at
this point that, although I believe that the contrast represented by (63)–(64) is real, we
are working here at a level of delicacy and marginality that makes it extremely dicult
to be condent that the observations one is trying to account for are real. e struc-
tures exemplied in (50)–(53) are already extremely marginal. To test for the contrast
explored in (63) and (64), we must increase the level of embedding from that seen in
(50)–(53), thus increasing one of the features that contributes to uncertainty. ese
caveats aside, there does seem to be a strongly felt contrast between (63) and (64).
What does this indicate?
ese data in fact provide a clue toward the resolution of an issue that we have
not so far addressed, namely, the nature of the null operators that we are assuming as
binders for both WH-traces and resumptive pronouns. What these observations sug-
gest is that these operators themselves must be locally bound. What principle would
ensure this?
Lasnik and Saito (1984) have shown that a trace le in COMP by successive cyclic
WH-movement is dependent on its antecedent for purposes of satisfying the ECP,
just as is a subject or adjunct phrase. Now, if the binding operators that bind resump-
tive pronouns are themselves empty categories subject to the ECP, then the operator
whose presence is marked by aN in examples such as (63)–(64) will require anteced-
ent government, as does a trace in COMP. is condition is met in (64), since each
intermediate binder is also bound by the operator in the next highest COMP, but not
in (63). In (63), the appearance of go means that there is no binder in this intermedi-
ate position to function as antecedent governor for the lowest operator (which locally
binds the resumptive pronoun). is view of matters suggests that the operators that
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
bind traces and resumptive pronouns in Irish are essentially indistinguishable from
traces in COMP – that is, they are empty categories subject to the ECP.23
We have at this point assembled an account for all the data considered so far.
We have argued that resumptive pronouns are syntactic variables (that is, they are
Ā-bound), that their immediate antecedents are not the head NP but rather null opera-
tors in the specier position of the COMP-projection (null operators that are them-
selves subject to the antecedent-government conditions of the ECP). We have also
argued that, despite being variables, resumptive pronouns preserve their pronominal
character in that they are subject to a disjoint reference (Condition B) constraint that
holds in the domain of Ā-binding – a condition that we have formulated (following
Aoun and Li, 1989) as the Ā-disjointness requirement in (44). We have also presented
a proposal about why and how the choice between use of a gap and use of a pronoun
is reected in the choice of complementizer.
e analysis as developed involves, in essence, the linking of a number of phe-
nomena. We take the appearance of the complementizer aN to signal the presence of
an operator of the appropriate type to bind a resumptive pronoun. When that operator
is present, the pronoun with which it is linked is a variable and exhibits Condition C
eects (strong crossover and an Ā-version of Condition B of the binding theory) in
the form of the highest subject restriction (analyzed in terms of the Ā-disjointness
requirement). For a given construction, then, we expect three variables to correlate:
(1) appearance of aN, (2) Condition C eects, and (3) HSR eects. I want, nally, to
consider some data that provide indirect support for the correctness of this correlation
by indicating that when one of the elements above is missing, they are all missing.
. Notice that this proposal requires (counter to Lasnik & Saito 1984) either that traces in
COMP cannot delete between S-structure and LF (on the assumption that they must meet
ECP requirements at LF), or that they must meet ECP requirements at S-structure. Stowell
(1986) argues against the proposal that traces in COMP can freely delete before LF on the
basis of certain properties of infinitival WH-constructions.
In all of the examples we have seen so far, there is a complete match between the
complementizers that appear in intermediate C-projections. However, another marked
pattern that occurs is schematized in (i) and illustrated by the (real) example in (ii).
(i) [NP [aL [… [aN [… pro…]]]]]
(ii) an galar a meastar ar cailleadh muintir an
the disease t is-thought pro was-lost people the
oileáin leis
island- with-it
“the disease from which it is thought the people of the island died
For discussion of the status (also highly marked) of this pattern, see McCloskey (1985).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
Le dislocation in Irish is of a type familiar from other languages. A constituent
(typically “heavy”) appears in initial position, separated from its associated clause by
comma intonation. e place of the dislocated constituent in the associated clause is
lled by a pronoun:
(65) An t-airgead sin a ta a iarraidh orm, bhéarfaidh
that money t are you asking on-me, give- I
duit amárach é.
to-you tomorrow it
“at money you are asking me for, I shall give it to you tomorrow”
is is a construction which one might well interpret a priori as a construction involv-
ing resumptive pronouns. But notice that the complementizers that we have taken to
be morphological signals of the presence of a binding operator (aL and aN) are absent
here. A related observation is that the element that obligatorily demands an Ā-binder,
namely, WH-trace, is impossible in this construction:
(66) *An t-airgead sin a ta a iarraidh orm, bhéarfaidh
that money t are you asking on-me, give- I
duit amárach __.
to-you tomorrow
“at money you are asking me for, I shall give it to you tomorrow”
ese observations jointly suggest strongly that le dislocation in Irish is not an
operator-binding construction of the type with which we have so far been concerned.
Ifthere were an operator in (65), we would expect its presence to be signaled by aL
or aN in the manner we have seen. Furthermore, we would expect that it would be
possible to bind a WH-trace from the same position.
But if there is no operator-variable chain in an example such as (65), then the
analysis we have built so far leads us to expect that le dislocation contrasts with the
other constructions we have been dealing with in showing neither strong crossover
nor HSR eects. e pronoun should not be subject to Condition C, since, not being
Ā-bound, it is not a variable. Furthermore, since it is not Ā-bound, the pronoun should
trivially satisfy the Ā-disjointness requirement in (44), and there should be no HSR
eects. Both of these expectations are borne out:
(67) An donán beag táillúra sin thíos, deir an duine gránna go
the runt little tailor-  down says the person ugly 
bhfuil ag dul dhá phósadh.
is he going to-be-married
“at little runt of a tailor down there, the wretchj says hej is getting married”
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
(68) a. An chéad ear eile a tháinig isteach d’aithin mé.
the rst other man t came in recognized he me
“e next man that came in, he recognized me
b. Dream eile fós, mheasadar pro gur chóir
group other again think--3 + right
don Chumann comórtas a rith.
for-the Society competition run-
“Still another group, they thought that the Society should run
a competition
Here we have strong, if indirect, conrmation that the set of connections that the anal-
ysis seeks to make is a real one.
Notice, though, that nothing we have considered so far provides any evidence
at all about the level of representation at which the crucial chains are formed. It is
presumably the case that the relevant Ā-chains must be formed by LF; otherwise, we
would have operators that bind no variables at that level. But this still leaves many
options open. Are the Ā-chains that bind resumptive pronouns visible as S-structure
or as D-structure phenomena, for instance? ese are the kinds of questions addressed
in the next section.24
. I leave open here the question of whether there is, in addition to the binding of a vari-
able by an operator in COMP, a syntactic binding between the relative head and the operator
in COMP (this is the relation dubbed “R-binding” by Safir 1986). Safir (1986) suggests that
languages differ as to whether or not they require resumptive pronouns to be R-bound as
well as Ā-bound. He also suggests tentatively that Irish may be among the languages in which
resumptive pronouns need not be R-bound. e grounds for making this assessment lose
their force in the context of the analysis of questions in Irish later pursued here (an analysis
anticipated by Safir 1986: 686). However, one indication that his conclusion may nevertheless
be correct is that there is no necessary agreement in person-number features between the
relative head and the resumptive pronoun. Disparities can arise in a number of circumstances,
such as the one illustrated in (i).
(i) Is sinne an bheirt ghasúr ar dhíol ár lóistín.
- we the two boy pro paid you our lodging
“We are the two boys that you paid our lodging”
Alternatively, the grammaticality of (i) might simply indicate that person-number features are
not transferred from the resumptive pronoun to the operator or operators that bind it in an
Ā-chain. is difference might in turn provide a basis for making the necessary distinction
between resumptive pronouns (which are not subject to the ECP) and the operators that bind
resumptive pronouns (which, according to our earlier discussion, are subject to the ECP).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
 James McCloskey
. e level
ere are various ways in which one might think about trying to resolve the question
of the level at which resumptive pronouns are bound to their operators. An obvious
question to ask is whether resumptive pronouns can or cannot license the appearance
of parasitic gaps. If it is possible for resumptives to do this, then that would count as
strong evidence that they are recognizable as variables (i.e. are bound) at S-structure.
Unfortunately, the language is disobliging in this respect, since there seem to be no
parasitic gap constructions in Irish at all. e question, then, of whether resumptive
pronouns can license parasitic gaps in Irish cannot even be posed.
We have seen that resumptive pronouns must be recognizable as variables with
respect to Condition C of the binding theory since they give rise to strong crossover
eects. If it can be argued, then, that Condition C is a condition on S-structures,
these facts together will constitute evidence that resumptive pronouns are bound at
S-structure. Such an argument has been made (Chomsky 1981: 196–197, drawing on
earlier work by Brody 1979). If it can be maintained, then we have evidence for binding
of resumptive pronouns at S-structure.25
However, there is evidence of a fairly rm kind that bears on the question. is
evidence derives from a phenomenon that is peculiar to constituent questions.
Our discussion until now has focused on relative clauses (as convenient exem-
plars of WH-constructions in general). But, at this point, let us focus specically on
constituent questions, in particular, on a phenomenon characteristic of questions but
unknown in other WH-constructions. It is possible in questions to front a PP that
contains a resumptive pronoun to a position immediately to the right of the interroga-
tive phrase:
(69) a. leis a raibh ag caint?
who with-him pro were you talk-
“Who were you talking to?”
. e evidence is delicate though, having to do with the status of coreference effects under
pied piping:
(i) Which book that Johnj read did hej like?
(ii) *Hej liked every book that Johnj read.
S-structure provides the right class of representations to make the necessary distinction
between (i) and (ii): at LF they will he identical in relevant respects, and it is hard to see
how the necessary distinction could he drawn. Belletti and Rizzi (1988: 318, n. 16) discuss the
matter in terms of whether or not Condition C must be satisfied by D-structures as well as by
S-structures, but they draw no firm conclusions. e argument in the text would stand under
these assumptions.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 
b. Céard leis a ndearna é?
what with-it pro did you it
“What did you do it with?”
is fronting is typically demanded in pedagogic grammars but in fact represents only
an option in informal speech. Doublets such as those in (70) are thus possible:26
(70) a. a bhfuil fáth aige
who pro is reason at-him
“Who has a reason?”
b. Cé aige a bhfuil fuath ar a bheith ag fanacht
who at-him pro is hatred on be- wait-
“Who hates (lit. is hatred at him) to wait?”
In (70a), the PP containing the resumptive pronoun remains in the usual position in
which PPs are found; in (70b), however, the PP containing the resumptive is fronted
to a position between the interrogative phrase and the complementizer particle aN.27
e crucial initial observation about this construction is that only the PP that contains
the resumptive pronoun can be fronted. Consider an example with two unfronted PPs,
as in (71). is example is based on the collocation tá eagla ar X roimh Y (‘fear is on X
before Y), which means “X is afraid of Y.
(71) Cé a bhfuil eagla air roimhe?
who pro is fear on-him before-him
is sentence is ambiguous because there is no way to tell which of the two pronouns
is the resumptive pronoun. erefore, (71) can mean either ‘Who is he afraid of?’
(when the object of the second preposition is the resumptive) or ‘Who is afraid of
him?’ (when the object of the rst preposition is the resumptive). Once one of the PPs
is fronted, however, the ambiguity disappears, since fronting itself identies which PP
contains the resumptive:
(72) a. air a bhfuil eagla roimhe?
who on-him pro is fear before-him
“Who is afraid of him?”
b. Cé roimhe a bhfuil eagla air?
who before-him pro is fear on-him
“Who is he afraid of?”
. e thorough optionality of the fronting is indicated by the fact that the two examples in
(70) occur on the same page of the same book.
. For discussion of this construction, see McCloskey (1979: 94–97), Ó Cadhlaigh
(1940: 422–424), Ó Searcaigh (1939: 103–104), O’Nolan (1920: 138), and de Bhaldraithe
(1953: 159–160).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
1 James McCloskey
is PP-fronting is subject to a number of apparently idiosyncratic restrictions that
are ultimately, I believe, phonological in origin. In particular, the interrogative phrase
to which the PP containing a resumptive pronoun is attracted must be monosyllabic.
One consequence of this restriction is that fronting is impossible in the case of syntac-
tically complex (that is, nonpronominal) interrogative phrases:
(73) *Cén fear leis a raibh ag caint?
which man with-him pro were you talk-
“Which man were you talking to?”
Furthermore, northern dialects (unlike western and southern) have a disyllabic word
for ‘what, goidé, with a strong stress on the second syllable. In these dialects, PP-fronting
is impossible with this interrogative phrase:
(74) a. *Goidé leis a ndearna é?
what with-it pro did you it
“What did you do it with?”
b. Goidé a ndearna leis é?
what pro did you with-it it
“What did you do it with?”
Fronting is, however, possible with the monosyllabic and weakly stressed variant form
ca “what”, which is used exclusively in this environment. at is, ca functions as a sort
of allomorph of goidé in the context dened by an application of PP-fronting.
(75) a. Ca leis a ndearna é?
what with-it pro did you it
“What did you do it with?”
b. *Ca a ndearna leis é?
what pro did you with-it it
“What did you do it with?”
ese considerations suggest that there exists a strong phonological dependency
between the fronted PP and the interrogative pronoun. e same conclusion is sug-
gested by the fact that the sequence of interrogative pronoun and fronted PP forms a
stress group. As is the case with all syntactically dened stress groups in Irish, the pri-
mary stress is on the rightmost element;28 in fact, in the fronting structures, there is a
very strong contrast between the interrogative pronoun and the following PP, the latter
being heavily stressed, the former being weakly stressed to the point where one might
regard it as a (phonological) clitic dependent on the fronted PP. So for phonological
. See Ó Cúiv (1944: 68–70), Breatnach (1947: 83–88), de Bhaldraithe (1966: 64–66), and de
Burca (1970: 75–77).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 11
purposes at least, the bracketing in (76) seems to be what is called for in the case of
examples such as those in (69).
(76) [Cé leis] aN raibh tú ag caint?
Now, of course, it is dangerous and dicult to make assumptions about syntactic
phrase structure on the basis of evidence that suggests a certain bracketing is required
for phonological purposes. Nevertheless, there is also evidence of a more purely
syntactic nature which suggests that (76) is the right syntactic representation of the
fronting structures. is evidence has to do with the element eile, which translates to
English other or else but has a broader distribution.
(77) a. an fear eile
the man other
“the other man
b. duine ar bith eile
person any other
“anybody else/nobody else”
c. Bhuail siad arís eile é
struck they again other him
“ey struck him yet again/one more time
d. a oiread eile airgid agus a fuair roimhe
amount other money as t got he before
“as much money again as he had received before”
is element can modify interrogative pronouns:
(78) a. Goidé eile a chonaic tú?
what other t saw you
“What else did you see?”
b. Cé eile a raibh ag caint leis?
who other pro were you talk- to-him
“Who else were you talking to?”
When a PP is fronted in such an interrogative structure, however, it always appears
between the interrogative pronoun and eile:
(79) a. aige eile a bhfuígfeadh siad é?
who at-him other pro would-leave they it
“Who else would they leave it with?”
b. Ca leis eile a raibh ag súil?
what with-it other pro were you expect-
“What else were you expecting?”
c. h-air eile a ligfeadh amach an racht sin?
who on-him other pro would-let he out that outburst
“Before whom else would he let out that outburst?”
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
1 James McCloskey
is observation suggests strongly that when a PP is fronted in an interrogative struc-
ture, it is, as it were, folded into the interrogative pronoun itself. Expressed more mun-
danely, these facts suggest that the fronted PP is adjoined to the interrogative pronoun,
as in the (phonologically motivated) structure in (76). More precisely, the structure
will be as in (80).
(80) [CP [NP [NP Cé] leis] aN [S raibh tú ag caint]]
To explain the ordering facts with respect to eile, as illustrated in (79), that is, to account
for the fact that eile appears outside the fronted PP despite being a subconstituent of
the phrase to which the PP adjoins, we might make appeal to a rule that right-adjoins
eile to its containing NP. ere is a certain amount of motivation for such a rule, since
eile can appear either to the le or to the right of a demonstrative particle, as illustrated
in (81).29
(81) a. an fear eile seo
the man other 
“this other man
b. an fear seo eile
the man  other
“this other man
On this assumption, (81b) would derive from (81a) by way of right-adjunction of eile
to its containing NP. If there is anything to this line of thought, then there is reason to
believe that eile can be raised to adjoin to its containing NP, though why this process
should be obligatory in the context of PP-fronting, I do not know.
ere is much in this domain of facts that remains mysterious. But the cumulative
force of the observations suggests that what happens in PP-fronting in questions is
that the PP containing a resumptive adjoins to the interrogative phrase in clause-initial
position.
e question now is how this process interacts with the principles that govern
complementizer selection. In all the examples we have seen so far, the complementizer
that appears in C0-position is COMPpro (aN). It is as if the PP-fronting rule makes no
dierence to the way in which complementizer selection works; the clause contains
a resumptive pronoun and, therefore, is headed by aN. All of the examples we have
seen so far, however, are from the northern group of dialects. If we broaden our
dialectal perspective a little, then the facts quickly become more complicated and
. Both (81a) and (81b) are possible, but, at least in the dialects with which I am most fa-
miliar, there is a strong preference for (81b).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 1
more interesting. In particular, if we examine the facts in southern dialects (those of
Munster), we see that many of those dialects show COMPt – the complementizer aL,
which is normally associated with the appearance in a clause of a WH-trace – rather
than the resumptive pronoun complementizer aN. e examples cited in (82) are all
from Munster dialects.
(82) a. Cuimhnigh leis a tánn ag caint.
remember who with-him t are you talk-
“Remember who you are talking to.
b. Cad leis a chlúdaigh iad?
what with-it t covered you them
“What did you cover them with?”
c. Cad air a dhíolfá-sa do pháiste?
what on-it t sell--2 your child
“What would you sell your child for?”
I want now to address the question of how we can account for these facts and the
dialectal variation observed in this domain.30 Viewing the contrast between the two
groups of dialects in pretheoretical terms, one can say that for the northern dialects,
the principles that determine complementizer selection are blind to the fact of PP-
fronting. e southern dialects observed in (82), however, seem to take account of the
presence of the PP-gap created by PP-fronting and select the complementizer accord-
ingly. is is the intuition that we can try to make precise.
What is the structure of constituent questions in Irish? Notice that it already
follows from the analysis, as developed thus far, that interrogative phrases cannot be
in the specier position of CP. We have developed an analysis in which the appear-
ance of dierent complementizers is triggered by Spec-Head agreement between the
C0-position and the specier position within CP. If this general line of analysis is
right, then examples such as (83) show that the interrogative phrase cannot be in Spec
of COMP.
. Some Munster dialects allow both options, as seen in the following pair of examples
from the same book by the same author:
(i) Bhí ios ag cách dhó a bhí ag tagairt.
everybody knew who to-him t was he refer-
“Everybody knew who he was referring to”
(ii) Bhí ios agam cad dhó a rabh ag tagairt.
I-knew what to-it pro was she refer-
“I knew what she was referring to
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
1 James McCloskey
(83) a. a bhí __ ann?
who t was there
“Who was there?”
b. Cé a raibh ag caint leis?
who pro be- you talk- with-him
“Who were you talking to?”
Our analysis of complementizer selection is crucially local: it depends on a relation
holding between a head and a specier within the same projection. To make a dis-
tinction between (83a) and (83b) on these grounds is impossible, if the assumption is
made that the interrogative pronoun is in the specier position of CP in both cases.
For the specier position would, on this view, be occupied by apparently identical
elements in the two cases. e structure that is needed, then, must be (84). (I use “Q”
in[84] as a temporary abbreviation for the category of interrogative clauses.)
(84)
Q
NP
[+Q]
CP
Op
[αF]
C1
C0
[αF]
S
Now, in fact, this is the structure for interrogative clauses in Irish that is also suggested
by many other considerations. at case is made in some detail (but on grounds inde-
pendent of our current concerns) in McCloskey (1979).31
Consider now the structure of an interrogative clause following application of
PP-fronting:
(85)
Q
NP
[+Q]
NP
[+Q]
CP
PPi
P NPj
[PP ti ]
OpjC1
C0
aN
proleis
S
1. See Chapter3 in particular. In the way of things, not all of the arguments survive in the
context of current assumptions. e important ones do, however. See, in particular, McCloskey
(1979: 59–62, 70–71).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 1
Note that in this structure the operator in Spec of CP does not c-command the
variable that it is, so to speak, “supposedto bind, namely, the resumptive pronoun
within the preposed PP. is observation holds true if the relevant denition of
c-command is taken to be the classical denition deriving from the work of Reinhart
(1976, 1981, 1983):
(86) A node α c-commands a node β i the branching that most immediately
dominates α also dominates β, and neither α nor β dominates the other.
In (85) CP is a branching node that dominates the operator but not the preposed
resumptive pronoun. If the relevant notion is m-command (Aoun & Sportiche 1983;
Chomsky 1986a), as in (87),
(87) α m-commands β i every maximal projection that dominates α also
dominates β, and neither α nor β dominates the other.
then this relation still fails to hold between the operator in Spec of CP and the pre-
posed pronoun.32
If Opj fails to c-command the resumptive pronoun, then it also fails to bind it.
Structure (85) is thus, on the face of it, ill formed at LF, since it contains an operator
that fails to bind a variable. e operator fails to bind a variable because it fails to
c-command the preposed resumptive pronoun; but it is of the wrong type (as signaled
by the presence of the complementizer aN) to bind the PP-trace le by pronoun pre-
posing since this trace is a nonpronominal variable. erefore, (85) runs afoul of the
LF-requirement that every operator bind a variable. On this view of matters, exam-
ples such as (88) will be ungrammatical if they are inspected in their audible form by
LF principles.
(88) Cé leis a raibh ag caint?
who with-him pro were you talk-
“Who were you talking to?”
. e conclusion also holds if (as seems likely) Q is CP (or CP[+Q]), and one adopts the
segment analysis of adjunction structures (May 1985; Chomsky 1986b). e relevant sche-
matic structure is in (i):
(i)
CP
βCP
αC
Here, there is a maximal projection (i.e. CP) that includes α but does not include β (since β is
not dominated by every segment of CP). erefore, nothing in the lower CP can c-command
anything within β.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
1 James McCloskey
But notice that (85) can be saved if an operator of the appropriate kind to bind a
PP-trace is base generated in Spec of CP. In that case, the trace-binding operator
(i.e. an operator that is [−anaphoric, −pronominal]) will c-command, and therefore
bind, the trace le by PP-fronting, and the structure will not be in violation of the
LF-requirement that every operator bind a variable. Now the presence of this kind
of binding operator will be signaled on the C0-position in the usual way, that is, by
the appearance of the aL complementizer. In this way, we derive an account of the
grammaticality of the Munster examples in which PP-fronting is accompanied by the
appearance (at rst blush, unexpected) of COMPt (see [82]). eir structure will now
be as in (89).
(89)
Q
CPNP
[+Q]
C1
C0
aL
S
[PP ti ]
Opi
NP
[+Q]
PPi
P
cé leis pro
NPj
What emerges then is that, given the set of assumptions we have developed, it is only
when the complementizer aL, that is, COMPt, appears that PP-fronting can be legal at
all. us the existence of those Munster dialects that have (82) is rationalized.
Consider in a little more detail how this analysis will work. What is crucial for
the licensing of (89) is that the “wrong” operator, so to speak, be generated in CP. An
operator of the appropriate kind to bind a PP-trace must be generated there. is is,
presumably, simply an empty PP with the features [−anaphoric, −pronominal], the
kind of operator that appears, for instance, in a cle such as (90).
(90) Is [PP le Siobhán] [CP Opj a [S bhí ag caint [PP tj]]]
- with Siobhan t was I talk-
“It was with Siobhan that I was talking”
At D-structure there will be no variable for this operator to bind, but this will be a
harmless property of the structure since the requirement that every operator phrase
bind a variable is an LF-requirement. If an Ā-chain were to be formed between this
operator and the pronoun that later comes to be regarded as the resumptive pronoun,
there would be a featural mismatch, and the derivation would be aborted. But the
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 1
Ā-chain need not be formed at this level, and the operator and the pronoun will not
interact at all at this level. If PP-fronting now applies before S-structure, a PP-trace
will be le under S in (90). It is now crucial that this trace be bound by the operator in
Spec of CP; otherwise, this operator will be in violation of the LF-requirement that it
bind a variable. ere will now be the appropriate featural match between the operator
and its variable, and this featural match will be reected in the appearance of aL as the
complementizer in the usual way.
Notice too that in the nal structure, the fronted PPj c-commands Opj and is coin-
dexed with it. It thus identies the null operator in the familiar way and the PP-trace
under S is strongly bound in the sense of Chomsky (1986a).
is analysis is built on three assumptions: (1) chain formation is independent
of movement, (2) operators must bind variables at LF, and (3) Ā-chains can be
(but need not be) formed at any syntactic level. Assumption (2) is uncontroversial.
Assumption(3) seems like the minimal assumption one could make in this domain.
Assumption (1) has been argued for independently by Rizzi (1986) and by McCloskey
and Sells (1988).
But what of the northern dialects with which we began our discussion, those
in which PP-fronting is accompanied by the appearance of the complementizer aN
(COMPpro)? According to our earlier discussion, such structures are declared ungram-
matical by principles of LF. In particular, they violate the LF-requirement that every
operator bind a variable because the operator whose presence is signaled by aN can
bind neither the PP-trace of PP-fronting (it is of the wrong type) nor the fronted pro-
noun within that PP (it fails to c-command it). is in turn suggests that in those
dialects in which PP-fronting cooccurs with the appearance of the complementizer
aN, principles of LF never see or inspect those structures in which PP-fronting has
applied. at is, we can account for the dialectal dierences examined here by propos-
ing that in northern dialects PP-fronting applies between S-structure and PF. In Mun-
ster dialects, on the other hand, the rule applies between D-structure and S-structure,
and its eects are visible to principles whose domain of application is LF. For northern
dialects, in contrast, the eects of PP-fronting are invisible at LF; for LF purposes, the
two examples in (91) are indistinguishable.
(91) a. leis a raibh ag caint?
who with-him pro were you talk-
“Who were you talking to?”
b. Cé a raibh ag caint leis?
who pro were you talk- with-him
“Who were you talking to?”
e structure that is seen is (91b). In this structure the operator whose presence is
signaled by aN c-commands and binds a variable (the resumptive pronoun), and the
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
1 James McCloskey
sentence is unproblematic.33 Notice that this interpretation of the facts depends cru-
cially on one of the salient features of the model of grammatical organization usually
assumed in government and binding, namely, the fact that there is no sharing of infor-
mation between the levels of LF and PF, except insofar as is mediated by S-structure.
is, I think, is a reasonably satisfying account of the dialectal dierences exam-
ined here. Both groups of dialects have essentially the same rule, but it applies in dier-
ent components. But notice that, if we accept this analysis, there is an implication for
our original question, the question of whether or not resumptive pronouns are bound
at S-structure and are identiable as variables at S-structure. It seems that they must
be. e version of PP-fronting that applies in northern dialects must be able to tell the
dierence between resumptive and nonresumptive pronouns. at is, it must be able
to recognize that certain pronouns are Ā-bound and that certain others are not, for
recall that it is a crucial property of PP-fronting that it applies only to PPs that imme-
diately dominate a resumptive pronoun. Its formulation must be akin to (92).
(92) Right-adjoin [PP P proj] to NPj
[+Q]
If such a rule is to apply correctly between S-structure and PF, it seems that the infor-
mation necessary to pick out resumptive pronouns from non- Ā-bound pronouns
must be available by S-structure.34
. Summary and conclusions
At this point, we have assembled answers to most of the questions with which we
began our discussion. We have seen that there is reason to believe that resumptive
pronouns are to be considered variables, and also that there is reason to believe that
the chain-formation rule that binds a resumptive pronoun to a null operator can apply
at any level. Certain pronouns will therefore be Ā-bound at S-structure. We have also
seen that the dual nature of resumptive pronouns simultaneously pronouns and
. For those Munster dialects that allow either complementizer in the context of PP-fronting
(cf. Note30), we will, of course, allow the rule of PP-fronting to apply in either component.
. From the formulation in (92), we expect that PP-fronting will obey subjacency. is is
essentially correct: see McCloskey (1979: 95). e formulation in (92) assumes a richness of
descriptive apparatus not normally assumed in current work. I see no way at present to reduce
the statement of PP-fronting any further than (92). One might rationalize the need for this
apparatus by appealing to the peripheral and parochial character of the rule in question.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 1
variables – is reected in their behavior with respect to binding theory. Resumptive
pronouns, being variables, are subject to Condition C. But they are also, being pro-
nouns, subject to a disjointness requirement that holds in the domain of Ā-binding.
We have also seen, though, that it is not the case that every construction that looks
initially like a resumptive pronoun construction actually involves Ā-binding of a pro-
noun by an operator. Le dislocation in Irish, in particular, seems at rst glance to
be just like the other resumptive pronoun constructions examined. When examined
more closely, however, it turns out not to involve an operator-variable binding at all.
In fact, the work of Engdahl (1985) on resumptive pronouns in Swedish suggests
that there is a third phenomenon lurking in the pretheoretical category of resump-
tive pronouns. Engdahl shows that the resumptive pronouns of Swedish behave
almost entirely like WH-traces, and she suggests that they be analyzed in terms of
a mechanism that “spells out” a trace created by WH-movement. e distribution of
resumptive pronouns in Swedish is extremely limited: they appear only in the subject
positions of tensed clauses next to lexical complementizers. Notice that this pattern
is, in essence, the complement of the distributional pattern found in Irish. at dis-
tributional pattern we have accounted for here by appealing to the binding theoretic
properties of an element that is simultaneously a pronoun and a variable. is view
and Engdahl’s evidence converge to suggest that the resumptive pronouns in Irish and
Swedish are quite dierent elements pronominal variables in Irish, pure variables
in Swedish. eother class of resumptive pronouns, the class that appears in le
dislocation and exhibits no variable properties at all, is also instantiated in Swedish
(Engdahl 1985: 11).
Finally, I want to consider some of the broader theoretical questions for which
resolution of the resumptive pronoun issue is crucial.
One of the theoretical debates in which the question of the proper analysis of
resumptive pronoun structures has most prominently gured has been the debate on
weak crossover. Consider a standard weak crossover conguration such as (93).
(93) *Whoj does hisj mother dislike tj?
Since hisj in (93) is not c-commanded by the trace of WH-movement but rather is
c-commanded by and coindexed with the interrogative operator who, it is locally
Ā-bound by who. It is, therefore, an Ā-bound pronoun; in our terms, it is a resumptive
pronoun. Furthermore, both the pronoun his and the trace le by WH-movement
in(93) are variables. Given these observations, there are certain obvious ways in which
we might think of accounting for the ungrammaticality of (93).
First, we might say that pronouns (in English) cannot be Ā-bound. On this view,
(93) would be ungrammatical by virtue of containing an Ā-bound pronoun. Second, we
might maintain that what is wrong with (93) is that the operator who simultaneously
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
11 James McCloskey
binds two variables – the pronoun his and the trace of WH-movement. On this view,
(93) would be ungrammatical because it violates a principle that would hold that an
operator must bind one and only one variable. ird, we might maintain that what is
wrong with (93) is not that it contains an operator that binds two variables but rather
that the two variables bound by the same operator are of dierent types (pronominal
and nonpronominal). On this view, (93) would be ungrammatical by virtue of violat-
ing a principle that all variables bound by a single operator must he of the same type
(all pronominal or all nonpronominal). All three of these lines of thought have been
pursued in the literature on Weak Crossover. Versions of the rst have been pursued
in Chomsky (1976) and Jaeggli (1984). e second is the essential idea behind the
bijection principle of Koopman and Sportiche (1982). And the third is the parallelism
constraint on operator binding (PCOB) of Sar (1984).
What do the Irish data have to say about these issues? e basic observation is that
there are no weak crossover eects when a relative clause (for instance) contains two
resumptive pronouns, neither of which c-commands the other. e examples in (94)
are both attested.
(94) a. fear ar ág a bhean é
man pro le his wife him
“a man that his wife le”
b. an fear so ar mhairbh a bhean féin é
this-man pro killed his-own-wife him
“this man that his own wife killed
But weak crossover eects are pronounced when the second pronoun in (94) is
replaced with a trace:35
(95) a. *fear a d’ág a bhean __
man t le his wife
“a man that his wife le”
b. *an fear so a mhairbh a bhean féin __
this-man pro killed his-own-wife
“this man that his own wife killed
Now, the occurrence of any weak crossover eect at all in a language with a pro-
ductive resumptive pronoun strategy renders the rst approach, sketched above,
. In English, weak crossover effects are barely noticeable in the case of restrictive relatives
(Chomsky 1982; Safir 1984). is is not true of the Irish examples in (95), however, which
are robustly ungrammatical. It is as if the availability of a grammatical alternative (as seen in
[94]), renders the ungrammaticality of examples such as (95) more salient.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 111
implausible (this observation is made in Koopman & Sportiche 1982; Engdahl 1985;
and Sells 1984a). erefore, the ungrammaticality of (95) gives us reason to reject the
rst approach. On the other hand, the grammaticality of (94) gives us reason to reject
the second approach above, based as it is on the bijection principle. It seems clear
that we have in such examples an instance of the binding of two variables by the same
operator, particularly in light of the evidence so far accumulated here that resumptive
pronouns in Irish are in fact Ā-bound.
e only analysis of the facts of weak crossover that I know of that carries over
in a natural way to the Irish data is Sar’s PCOB, the third approach sketched above.
Notice that this approach accounts for the contrast between (95) and (94) in a straight-
forward way, with one modication. Sar’s formulation of the PCOB demands that all
the variables bound by a single operator must agree in being all lexically specied or
all lexically unspecied. Now, given the Irish data, this cannot simply mean that all the
variables must be phonologically realized or phonologically unrealized. As usual, it
makes no dierence in Irish whether one is dealing with an audible pronoun or with
pro. Notice that the grammatical examples in (94) all involve pairings of pro and an
audible pronoun. Rather, the crucial factor must be whether or not the variables agree
in being pronominal or nonpronominal.
In fact, one might speculate that the PCOB is related to some of the eects we have
already had occasion to study here. If one examines the ungrammatical examples in
(95) in light of our earlier discussion, one might be tempted to explain their ungram-
maticality in terms of principles we have already developed. One might attribute their
ungrammaticality to the fact that, since the operator binds both a pronominal and
a nonpronominal variable, the Ā-chains formed thereby will impose incompatible
and irreconcilable featural demands on the binding operator. at is, the operator is
required to be simultaneously associated with COMPt and with COMPpro. But the
mechanisms that we have assumed to account for these distributional connections in
Irish are quite general (most notably, feature sharing among the links of an Ā-chain).
It is possible that the PCOB is ultimately a reection of this same conict in a language
in which the dierence between the two classes of binding operators is not otherwise
formally marked.36
. Lasnik and Stowell (1987) base their discussion of weak crossover on the observation
that, in a range of WH-constructions in English, weak crossover effects disappear. One would
want to know now what the corresponding data are for resumptive pronouns and nonpro-
nominal variables in these constructions in Irish. is is an investigation that I must, however,
leave for future work.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
11 James McCloskey
. Appendix: e distrubution of resumptive pronouns
.1 Construction types that permit resumptive pronouns
Restrictive relatives
(96) a. daoine nár shroich an tsibhialtacht fós iad
people pro+ reached the civilization yet them
“people whom civilization has not yet reached
b. an fear a raibh ag caint leis pro
the man pro was I talk- with-3-
“the man that I was talking to (him)”
Nonrestrictive relatives
(97) a. áinig an saighdiúir eile, nach bhfaca
came the soldier other pro+ saw I
roimhe é, aníos chugainn.
before him up to-us
“e other soldier, whom I hadn’t seen before. came up to us”
b. Chonaic mo dheartháir, a mbíodh faitíos
saw I my brother pro be-- nervousness
i gconaí air pro ag éalú an doras amach
always on-3- slip- the door out
“I saw my brother, who was always nervous, slipping out the door”
Constituent questions
(98) a. d’inis siad cén turas a raibh said air pro
told they what joumey pro be- they on-3-
“they told what journey they were on (it)”
b. cén t-oigeach ar shíl go mbeadh i láthair?
which ocer pro thought you  would-be he present
“Which ocer did you think would be present?”
Cles
37
(99) a. Is a bhfuil an deallramh maith ort pro
- you pro is the appearance good on-2
“It is you that looks weIl”
. Traditional grammars oen claim (in effect) that resumptive pronouns are impossible
in cles. In earlier work (McCloskey 1978: 181) I accepted this claim. More careful investiga-
tion, however, has shown clearly that the claim is wrong, as the examples cited in the text
demonstrate. Many more counterexamples could have been cited. e grammaticality of such
examples has also been documented and discussed recently by Mac Cana (1985).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 11
b. Tig beag caol ar mhaireamar ann pro
house little narrow pro live--1 in-3-
“It was a narrow little house that we lived in (it)”
c. Siobhán a bhfuil buaite aici pro
Siobhan pro is won by-3-
“It is Siobhan that has won
Lit. “It is Siobhan that has been won by her”
Comparative clauses
(100) a. áinig níos mó daoine a raibh
came more people than pro was
súil leo pro
expectation with-3
“More people came than were expected”
b. Do fuair leaba chó math agus ar lui
get- he bed as good as pro lie- he
riamh uirthi pro
ever on-3-
“He got a bed as good as he ever lay on (it)”
“Tough-movement” constructions
(101) a. Bhí Ristéard doiligh cur suas leis pro
was Richard dicult put- up with-3-
“Richard was hard to put up with (him)”
b. Beidh an gasúr sin deacair fail réitithe leis pro
be- that-boy hard get- rid with-3-
“at boy will be hard to get rid of (him)”
Ready-class of adjectival complements
(102) Bhí na putóga ullamh ansan chun iad a líonadh.
were the intestines ready then to them ll-
“e intestines were ready then to ll (them)”
Innitival relatives and purpose clauses
38
(103) a. rabh a’n duine aige le labhairt leis pro
 was anybody at-him to talk- with-3-
“He had nobody to talk to (him)”
. It is notoriously difficult to distinguish reliably between infinitival relatives and purpose
clauses. e problems and issues seem to be much the same in Irish as they are in English. I
am content here with citing some relevant examples and trusting that their general similarity
to the corresponding English construction will be enough to establish the relevant point.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
11 James McCloskey
b. Bhí mórán aige le smaointeamh air pro
was a-lot at-him to think- on-3-
“He had a lot to think about (it)”
. Clausal positions in which resumptive pronouns appear
Direct object of highest clause
(104) a. an ghirseach ar ghoid na síogaí í
the girl pro stole the fairies her
“the girl whom the fairies stole”
b. an ghirseach a ghoid na síogaí __
the girl t stole the fairies
“the girl whom the fairies stole”
Subject of embedded nite clause
(105) a. na caiple sin a n-abrann sealgairí go mbíonn siad
those horses pro say hunters  be- they
ag léimnigh agus ag damhsa
jump- and dance-
“those horses that hunters say are always jumping and dancing”
b. no caiple sin a deireann sealgairí a bhíonn __
those horses t say hunters  be-
ag leimnigh agus ag damhsa
jump- and dance-
“those horses that hunters say are always jumping and dancing”
(106) a. cúpla muirear a bhféadfaí a rá go
a-few families pro one-could say- 
rabhadar pro bocht
be-3 poor
“a few families that one could say (they) were poor”
b. cúpla muirear a d’hféadfaí a rá a bhí __ bocht
a-few families t one-could say- t be- poor
“a few families that one could say were poor”
Object of embedded nite clause
(107) a. an rud céanna a dtug orm mionnú go
the thing same pro took he on-me swear- 
gcoinneoinn ceilte é
keep--1 concealed it
“the same thing that he made me swear that I would keep (it) hidden
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 11
b. an rud céanna a thug orm mionnú a
the thing same t took he on-me swear- t
choinneoinn ceilte
keep--1 concealed
“the same thing that he made me swear that I would keep hidden
Subject of embedded nonnite clause
(108) a. duine ar bith ar mhaith leat é beannú sa
person any pro you-would-like him greet- in-the
tsráid duit
street to-you
“anybody that you would like him to greet you in the street”
b. duine ar bith a ba mhaith leat beannú sa tsráid duit
person any t you-would-like greet- in-the street to-you
“anybody that you would like to greet you in the street”
Object of embedded nonnite clause
(109) a. na Dílseoirí seo ar theastaigh ón Uasal Ó hEadhra
these Loyalists pro wanted from Mr. O’Hara
iad a thabhairt isteach sa ghluaiseacht
them bring- in into-the movement
“these Loyalists that Mr. O’Hara wanted to bring (them) into
the movement”
b. na Dílseoirí seo a theastaigh ón Uasal Ó hEadhra __
these Loyalists t wanted from Mr. O’Hara
a thabhairt isteach sa ghluaiseacht
bring- in into-the movement
“these Loyalists that Mr. O’Hara wanted to bring into the movement
Object of progressive phrase
39
(110) a. an rud a raibh siad dhá chuartú pro
the thing pro were they 3- seek-
“the thing that they were seeking (it)”
b. an rud a bhí siad a chuartú __
the thing t were they seek-
“the thing that they were seeking”
. For detailed analysis of progressive phrases in Irish, see McCloskey (1983a). See also
Chung and McCloskey (1987) and Clements et al. (1983).
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
11 James McCloskey
Copular clauses
40
(111) a. rud arbh iú cuid mhór é
thing pro+ worth a-lot it
“a thing that it was worth a lot
b. rud a b’iú cuid mhór __
thing t +worth a-lot
“a thing that was worth a lot
is set of examples is given only for relative clauses, but an exactly comparable set of examples
could be provided (where applicable) for the full range of WH-constructions cited in the previ-
ous section.41
Acknowledgments
This article was completed under difficult circumstances. My thanks to Randy
Hendrick for his patience and persistence, and to Sandy Chung for her help. anks
are also due Siobhán Ní Laoire, Róise Ní Bhaoill, Liam Mac Con Iomaire, Caitlín Mhic
Niallais, Alan Harrison, and Nicholas Williams for their help in establishing the data.
e work reported on here was supported by NSF Grant BNS86-17274, awarded to the
University of California, Santa Cruz.
References
Andrews, Avery. 1990. Unication and morphological blocking. Natural Language and Linguistic
eory 8: 507–557.
Aoun, Joseph & Y.-H. Audrey Li. 1989. ree cases of logical relations: Relative scope, bound
pronouns, and anaphoric relations. University of Southern California, ms.
. e syntax of copular clauses in Irish is very poorly understood. But one point is clear:
their syntax is very different from the syntax of verbal clauses. For a comprehensive account
of the facts, see Ó Siadhail (1989).
1. In almost every case where a free choice exists between use of the resumptive pronoun
structure and use of the WH-movement structure, the latter is more commonly used. is is
presumably a reflection of Chomsky’s (1981) avoid pronoun principle, interpreted not as an
absolute grammatical prohibition but rather as a measure of preferred usages.
ere is one exception to the generalization noted here: in copular clauses [cf. (111)], the
preferences are reversed, and the WH-movement option is felt to be formal, marginal, and
highly marked. is is just one of the puzzles that mark this domain of Irish syntax as special.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 11
Aoun, Joseph & Dominique Sportiche. 1983. On the formal theory of government. Linguistic
Review 3: 211–235.
Belletti, Adriana & Luigi Rizzi. 1988. Psych-verbs and theta-theory. Natural Language and
Linguistic eory 6: 291–352.
Borer, Hagit. 1984. Restrictive relatives in Modern Hebrew. Natural Language and Linguistic
eory 2: 219–260.
Breatnach, Risteard. 1947. e Irish of Ring, Co. Waterford. Institute for Advanced Studies, Dublin.
Bresnan, Joan & Jane Grimshaw. 1978. e syntax of free relatives in English. Linguistic Inquiry
9: 331–391.
Brody, Micheal. 1979. Innitivals, relative clauses, and deletions. University of London, ms.
Browning, M. 1987. Null Operator Constructions. Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts Institute
of Technology, Cambridge.
Chao, Wyn & Peter Sells. 1983. On the interpretation of resumptive pronouns. NELS 13:47–61.
Chomsky, Noam. 1976. Conditions on rules of grammar. Linguistic Analysis 2: 303–351.
Chomsky, Noam. 1977. On WH-movement. In Formal Syntax, P.W. Culicover, A. Akmajian &
T. Wasow (eds.). Academic Press, New York.
Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on Government and Binding. Foris, Dordrecht.
Chomsky, Noam. 1982. Some Concepts and Consequences of the eory of Government and
Binding. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Chomsky, Noam. 1986a. Barriers. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Chomsky, Noam. 1986b. Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. Praeger, New York.
Chomsky, Noam. 1988. Some notes on economy of derivation and representation. Massachusetts
Institute of Technology, ms.
Chung, Sandra. 1990. Sentential subjects and proper government in Chamorro. In Interdisci-
plinary Approach to Language. Essays in Honor of Yuki Kuroda, Carol Georgopoulos &
Roberta Ishihara (eds.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Chung, Sandra & James McCloskey. 1987. Government, barriers, and small clauses in Modern
Irish. Linguistic Inquiry 18: 173–237.
Clements, Nick, James McCloskey Joan Maling & Annie Zaenen. 1983. String vacuous rule
application. Linguistic Inquiry 14: 1–17.
de Bhaldraithe, Tomas. 1953. Gaeilge Chois Fhairrge – An Deilbhíocht. Institúid Ard-Léinn
Bhaile Átha Cliath, Dublin.
de Bhaldraithe, Tomas. 1956–1957. Nótaí comhréire. Éigse 8: 242–246.
de Bhaldraithe, Tomas. 1966. e Irish of Cois Fhairrge, Co. Galway. Institute for Advanced
Studies, Dublin.
de Burca, Sean. 1970. e Irish of Tourmakeady. Institute for Advanced Studies, Dublin.
Emonds, Joseph. 1978. e verbal complex V-V in French. Linguistic Inquiry 9: 151–175.
Engdahl, Elisabet. 1985. Parasitic gaps, resumptive pronouns, and subject extractions. Linguistics
23: 3–44.
Guilfoyle, Eithne. 1988. Parameters and functional projection. Paper presented at the Eighteenth
Annual Meeting of the North-Eastern Linguistic Society.
Jaeggli, Osvaldo. 1984. Subject extraction and the null subject parameter. NELS 14: 132–153.
Koopman, Hilda. 1984. e Syntax of Verbs: From Verb-Movement Rules in the Kru Languages to
Universal Grammar. Foris, Dordrecht.
Koopman, Hilda & Dominique Sportiche. 1982. Variables and the bijection principle. Linguistic
Review 2: 139–160.
Kuroda, Sige Yuki. 1968. English relativization and certain related problems. Language 44:244–266.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
11 James McCloskey
Lasnik, Howard. 1976. Remarks on coreference. Linguistic Analysis 2: 1–22.
Lasnik, Howard. 1989. On the necessity of binding conditions. In Principles and Parameters in
Comparative Grammar, R. Freidin (ed.). MIT Press, Cambridge. Mass.
Lasnik, Howard & Mamoru Saito. 1984. On the nature of proper government. Linguistic Inquiry
15: 235–289.
Lasnik, Howard & Timothy Stowell. 1991. Weakest crossover. Linguistic Inquiry 22: 687–720.
Mac Cana, Proinsias. 1985. Varia xii: A note on the prepositional relative. Éiru 36: 210–212.
May, Robert. 1985. Logical form. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
May, Robert. 1989. Bound variable anaphora. In Mental Representations: e Interface Between
Language and Reality, R. Kempson (ed.), Cambridge University Press, London.
McCloskey, James. 1978. A Fragment of a Grammar of Modern Irish. Doctoral dissertation,
University of Texas. Published as Texas Linguistic Forum, 12. Department of Linguistics,
University of Texas at Austin.
McCloskey, James. 1979. Transformational syntax and model theoretic semantics. A Case Study
in Modern Irish. Reidel, Dordrecht.
McCloskey, James. 1980. Is there raising in Modern Irish? Ériu 31: 59–99.
McCloskey, James. 1983. On the binding of resumptive pronouns in Modern Irish. Paper pre-
sented to the annual meeting of GLOW. University of York.
McCloskey, James. 1985. e Modern Irish double relative and syntactic binding. Ériu 36: 46–84.
McCloskey, James. 1986. Inection and conjunction in Modern Irish. Natural Language and
Linguistic eory 4: 183–186.
McCloskey, James & Kenneth Hale. 1984. On the syntax of person-number inection in
Modern Irish. Natural Language and Linguistic eory 1: 487–533.
McCloskey, James & Peter Sells. 1988. Control and A-chains in Modern Irish. Natural Language
and Linguistic eory 6: 143–189.
Ó Cadhlaigh, Cormac. 1940. Gnás na Gaeilge. Oifg an tSoláthair, Dublin.
Ó Cuív, Brian. 1944. e Irish of West Muskerry, Co. Cork. Institute for Advanced Studies, Dublin.
Ó Nolan, Gerald. 1920. Studies in Modern Irish. Educational Company of Ireland, Ltd., Dublin
and Cork.
Ó Rahilly, omas Francis. 1946. Irish Dialects Past and Present. Institute for Advanced Studies,
Dublin.
Ó Searcaigh, Seamus. 1939. Coimhréir Ghailge an Tuaiscirt. Government Publications Oce,
Dublin.
Ó Siadhail, Micheal. 1980. Learning Irish. Institute for Advanced Studies, Dublin.
Ó Siadhail, Micheal. 1989. Modern Irish Grammatical Structure and Dialectical Variation.
Cambridge University Press, London. To appear.
Pollock, Jean-Yves. 1989. Verb movement, UG, and the structure of IP. Linguistic Inquiry
20:365–424.
Reinhart, Tanya. 1976. e Syntactic Domain of Anaphora. Doctoral dissertation. Massachusetts
Institute of Technology, Cambridge.
Reinhart, Tanya. 1981. Denite NP anaphora and C-command domains. Linguistic Inquiry
12:605–636.
Reinhart, Tanya. 1983. Anaphora and Semantic Interpretation. Croom Helm, London.
Rizzi, Luigi. 1986. On chain formation. In e Syntax of Pronominal Clitics: Syntax and Semantics
19, H. Borer (ed.). Academic Press, New York.
Rizzi, Luigi. 1990. Relativized Minimality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
Resumptive pronouns, Ā-binding, and levels of representation 11
Sar, Kenneth. 1984. Multiple variable binding. Linguistic Inquiry 15: 603–638.
Safir, Kenneth. 1986. Relative clauses in a theory of binding and levels. Linguistic Inquiry
17:663–689.
Sells, Peter. 1984a. Syntax and Semantics of Resumptive Pronouns. Doctoral dissertation, University
of Massachusetts at Amherst.
Sells, Peter. 1984b. Resumptive pronouns and weak crossover. WCCFL 3.
Sells, Peter. 1987. Binding resumptive pronouns. Linguistics and Philosophy 10: 261–298.
Sproat, Richard. 1985. Welsh syntax and VSO structure. Natural Language and Linguistic eory
3: 173–216.
Stenson, Nancy. 1981. Studies in Irish Syntax. Gunter Narr Verlag, Tübingen.
Stowell, Timothy. 1986. Null antecedents and proper government. NELS 16: 476–493.
Taraldsen, Knud Tarald. 1983. Parametric Variation in Phrase Structure: A Case Study. Doctoral
dissertation, University of Tromsø.
Zaenen, Annie, Elisabet Engdahl & Joan Maling. 1981. Resumptive pronouns can be syntactically
bound. Linguistic Inquiry 12: 679–682.
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
© 2011. John Benjamins Publishing Company
All rights reserved
... However, this resumptive element is disallowed in the relativization site of subject DPs in both full and free relatives (see also Shlonsky 2002;Al-Momani 2010). The ban on resumptive pronouns in the subject position is ascribed to McCloskey's (1990) Highest Subject Restriction which prohibits the occurrence of a resumptive pronoun in the highest subject position inside the relative clause (Shlonsky 2002). ...
... However, this resumptive element is disallowed in the relativization site of subject DPs in free relatives (see also Shlonsky 2002;Al-Momani 2010). The ban on resumptive pronouns in the subject position is ascribed to McCloskey's (1990) Highest Subject Restriction which prohibits the occurrence of a resumptive pronoun in the highest subject position inside the relative clause (Shlonsky 2002). Thus, it can be said that the presence or absence of resumption in this wh-construction has nothing to do with any interrogative strategy (contra Aoun et al 2010); rather, resumption is a side-effect of the characteristics of the free relative clause involved in this wh-construction. ...
... After that, the subject wh-phrase in the resulting verbless structure can freely undergo left-dislocation as the resulting subject pronoun (PRON) in the TP-internal subject position in this case will no longer violate the null subject parameter, and the result is a new topic-comment structure with the format [DP [PRON DP]]. The subject inside the relative clause is then deleted due to McCloskey's (1990) Highest Subject Restriction which prohibits the occurrence of a resumptive pronoun in the highest subject position inside the relative clause, yielding the structure in (43d). In other words, relativization can be considered a last-resort strategy to void the null subject parameter in the case of subject left-dislocation in verbal contexts. ...
Thesis
Full-text available
This thesis provides an in-depth analysis of wh-question formation in Jordanian Arabic (JA) and presents a uniform approach that can accommodate all of its various wh-constructions. JA makes use of five different wh-constructions, four of which involve clause-initial wh-phrases and the fifth is a typical in-situ wh-construction. Although wh-phrases surface clause-initially in four different wh-constructions in JA, I propose that bona fide wh-movement to [Spec, CP] does not occur in any of these constructions, whether overtly in syntax or covertly at LF. I abandon the classification of JA as a wh-movement language (Abdel Razaq 2011) and focus instead on identifying the syntactic role that wh-phrases realize and the underlying structures that feed each wh-construction. I propose that the clause-initial position of the wh-phrase results either from the syntactic function that the wh-phrase serves or from other syntactic operations that are independently attested in JA. There are three clause-initial positions that the wh-phrase can occupy: it surfaces in [Spec, TP] when functioning as the subject of a verbal or verbless structure, in [Spec, TopP] when functioning as a clitic-left-dislocated element (as in CLLD questions and ʔilli-interrogatives involving PRON), or in [Spec, FocP] when undergoing focus fronting. Thus, all instances of clause-initial wh-phrases in JA constitute what I refer to as-pseudo wh-fronting‖, as the clause-initial position of the wh-phrase arises from mechanisms other than canonical wh-movement to [Spec, CP]. To account for the interpretation of wh-phrases in JA, I adopt a binding approach in which a null interrogative morpheme (Baker 1970; Pesetsky 1987; Chomsky 1995) unselectively binds the wh-phrase regardless of its surface position, whether clause-initial or clause-internal (in-situ). A major implication of this analysis is that JA is a concealed wh-in-situ language of the Chinese type although it looks at a cursory glance as though it were a wh-movement language of the English type. A broader typological implication of my analysis is the convergence of Cheng's (1991) Clausal Typing Hypothesis to which JA previously appeared to constitute a counterexample. The recognition of the null interrogative particle, or its optional overt realization as the Q-particle huwweh, as the locus of interrogative clause typing in all JA wh-questions entails that JA employs just one unique strategy to type a clause as a wh-question, as predicted by Cheng's Clausal Typing Hypothesis, regardless of whether the wh-phrase surfaces clause-initially or clause-internally. ii
... In McCloskey (1990), among others, a resumptive pronoun is defined as a personal pronoun that occupies the position corresponding to the grammatical function of the head noun. In the case under analysis, this is the subject. ...
... (14) Accessibility hierarchy (Keenan and Comrie 1977) Subject > Direct object > Indirect object > Oblique > Genitive McCloskey (1990) defines the fact that a resumptive pronoun generally does not appear in the subject position immediately subjacent to the head noun as the Highest Subject Restriction (McCloskey 1990). In Italian Venetan, this restriction is violated, as a resumptive pronoun is realised precisely in this context. ...
... (14) Accessibility hierarchy (Keenan and Comrie 1977) Subject > Direct object > Indirect object > Oblique > Genitive McCloskey (1990) defines the fact that a resumptive pronoun generally does not appear in the subject position immediately subjacent to the head noun as the Highest Subject Restriction (McCloskey 1990). In Italian Venetan, this restriction is violated, as a resumptive pronoun is realised precisely in this context. ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper addresses the question of structural change in relative clauses in heritage speakers of two varieties of Venetan, a northern Italo-Romance language. It will be shown that appositive and restrictive relative clauses are not structurally distinguished in Brazilian Venetan, while they display different structural properties in Italian Venetan. It will be proposed that the phenomenon described in the paper does not depend on transfer from another language and it is not exclusively a matter of processing. The approach presented here aims to account for structural change in syntactic terms, without resorting to extra-linguistic factors. Heritage grammars are autonomous systems and follow predictable paths of language variation, as such, variation may take place at an interface level and at a syntactic level alike. This does not exclude possible influences from the dominant language, which, however, do not need to be taken as the only triggers of change.
... In McCloskey (1990), among others, a resumptive pronoun is defined as a personal pronoun that occupies the position corresponding to the grammatical function of the head noun. In the case under analysis, this is the subject. ...
... (14) Accessibility hierarchy (Keenan & Comrie 1977) Subject > Direct object > Indirect object > Oblique > Genitive McCloskey (1990) defines the fact that a resumptive pronoun generally does not appear in the subject position immediately subjacent to the head noun as the Highest Subject Restriction (McCloskey 1990). In Italian Venetan this restriction is violated, as a resumptive pronoun is realised precisely in this context. ...
... (14) Accessibility hierarchy (Keenan & Comrie 1977) Subject > Direct object > Indirect object > Oblique > Genitive McCloskey (1990) defines the fact that a resumptive pronoun generally does not appear in the subject position immediately subjacent to the head noun as the Highest Subject Restriction (McCloskey 1990). In Italian Venetan this restriction is violated, as a resumptive pronoun is realised precisely in this context. ...
... Since base-generation always terminates in an RP in Igbo, we would also have an explanation for the occurrence of the RP in the four contexts. In fact, this scenario has been described for other languages, e.g., for Lebanese Arabic (Aoun et al. 2001) and Irish (McCloskey 1990(McCloskey , 2001(McCloskey , 2002: when a movement derivation is blocked by an island, the language employs the base-generation strategy instead. We can check whether this holds for Igbo, too, by applying the movement tests from Sect. 3 to the four RP-contexts (15)-(18). ...
... For instance, DO-relativization in Swiss German leaves gaps and prohibits RPs; but when a conjunct is extracted from a DO-&P, an RP is mandatory (Salzmann 2017: 337,354). The same holds for Czech (Toman 1998), Slovene (Hladnik 2015), Irish (McCloskey 1990), Polish (Bondaruk 1995). That conjuncts cannot be null is presumably also related to their prosodic prominence: (Nominal) &Ps as well as the contained conjuncts have been analyzed as prosodic phrases; &Ps thus involve recursion of prosodic units (see Wagner (2010); Féry and Kentner (2013)). ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper investigates the morphosyntax of resumption in Igbo (Benue-Congo). The first part addresses the syntax and argues that Igbo has two types of resumptive pronouns (RPs): (i) RPs that terminate base-generation Ā-dependencies, and (ii) RPs at the bottom of Ā-movement dependencies. While similar splits have been claimed to exist in a few other languages, established with a limited data set, Igbo provides pervasive evidence for the co-existence of both types within the same language: type-(ii) RPs occur in all Ā-movement dependencies, and there is comprehensive evidence from a variety of movement tests, including also cyclicity effects, parasitic gap licensing, and language-specific diagnostics. We pursue a spell-out approach to type-(ii) RPs à la Pesetsky (1998) and Landau (2006), and discuss potential reasons behind their restricted distribution: type-(ii) RPs only surface in PPs, DPs, and &Ps, which are thus not (absolute) islands in Igbo. The second part of the paper deals with the morphological side of resumption, viz., with phi- and (alleged) case mismatches between the RP and its antecedent. The phi-mismatch provides further evidence for two types of RPs in Igbo. Moreover, it is more complex than the mismatches reported so far in the literature since the loss of phi-information depends on the type of antecedent (pro/noun, coordination). This pattern poses a challenge for previous accounts of phi-mismatches with movement-derived RPs that are based on static deletion domains. We propose that the cross-linguistic variation in phi-mismatches can be captured in a partial copy deletion approach along the lines of van Urk (2018) if the amount of structure that is deleted is defined dynamically. This further supports the relevance of dynamic domains in morphosyntax, in particular in postsyntactic operations, as previously identified in other areas, e.g., in Moskal’s (2015b) work on contextual allomorphy. Finally, we show that the “case” mismatch is a consequence of the (supra)segmental nature of the relevant exponent and the relative timing of the operations involved.
... While some scholars, such as Sichel (2014) for Hebrew and Aoun et al., (2001) for Lebanese Arabic, argue that resumptive pronouns compete with gaps, others have posited that the competition is actually due to whether or not the C head selected in the derivation either blocks movement, thereby requiring an RP structure, or allows movement. This position was taken by McCloskey (1990) for Irish, Rasin (2017) for Hebrew, a.o. A design where the code-switch location occurs right before the C head takes into account these theoretical approaches for both wh-in situ and wh-resumptive structures. ...
Thesis
This dissertation investigates the extent to which bilingual speakers’ cognitive representations of the syntactic structures of their two languages are interconnected. This is a substantially understudied domain despite the widespread existence of bilingual/multilingual communities in the world, including the US. To draw solid conclusions about bilingual individuals’ linguistic representations of syntactic structures, in this dissertation we test bilingual individuals’ sensitivity to island and non-island wh-questions in both unilingual and code-switched contexts. Code-switching is a particularly relevant domain of investigation for determining how structures with similar surface word orders, but either similar or different derivations across the two languages, are processed as by bilingual individuals. The logic here is: if two structures share a syntactic derivation, which we classify as a shared structure, then these structures will be sensitive to the same well-formedness conditions in both unilingual and code-switched contexts. If the two structures have different syntactic derivations, which we classify as separate structures, then we will see divergent sensitivities to well-formedness conditions across the two unilingual contexts, as well as the code-switched contexts. We focused our attention on wh-in situ and wh-resumptive structures in Egyptian Arabic and English. The wh-in situ structure was chosen because, in the right pragmatic context, it has been argued to have a similar syntactic derivation across the two languages, while the wh-resumptive structure was chosen because it has been argued to have a different syntactic derivation across the two languages. We conducted a four-block experiment administered within one experimental session, testing wh-in-situ, wh-resumptive and wh-gap structures in each block. The first block tested the wh-structures in unilingual Egyptian Arabic sentences. The second block tested them in unilingual English sentences. The third and fourth blocks tested the acceptability of the wh-structures in code-switched Egyptian Arabic/English sentences. To test both island and non-island wh-in situ and wh-resumptive structures, we used a factorial design to isolate island effects from extra grammatical processing effects. Based on the results of the experiment we concluded the following: First, in line with the predictions of previous literature, we argue that the wh-in situ structure is not only similar in the surface order across both languages, but the wh-in situ structure in Egyptian Arabic and English share the same derivational properties. Second, based on the reported island sensitivity in the code-switched conditions, we argue that the wh-resumptive structure of Egyptian Arabic is formed via movement in a manner like how clause-initial wh-constituents are formed in English, but that the island sensitivities are masked in the unilingual Egyptian Arabic contexts as the distribution of resumptive pronouns is subject to both phonological and syntactic well-formedness conditions. Based on this discussion, we conclude that the wh-resumptive structure across Egyptian Arabic and English is a partially overlapping structure for the population of speakers recruited in this study, since the clause initial wh-element is formed via movement in both languages, but the insertion of resumptive pronouns is generated as part of the derivation in Egyptian Arabic, but as the result of a production effect in English.
... However, as demonstrated in Pan (2011), obligatory wh-fronting is required in the Across-The-Board (ATB) construction. Resumptive pronouns can exist in ATB constructions in Chinese, as demonstrated in (16) McCloskey (1990) also notes that resumptive pronouns can also appear in wh-questions in Irish, as shown in (18). Given that there is no wh-movement in Chinese, resumptive wh-questions do not exist in Chinese. ...
Article
Full-text available
Resumptive pronouns (RPs) exist in different types of A'-dependencies in Mandarin Chinese, such as relativization, Left-Dislocation (LD) structures, cleft-sentences, Across-The-Board (ATB) constructions, etc. Diachronically, resumptive dislocation structures have already been documented in the literature around 502 B.C. In modern Chinese, the obligatory use, the systematical use, and the intrusive use of RPs are all observed. When a prepositional object is A'-extracted, the extraction site must be occupied by an RP given that Chinese does not permit preposition stranding. In certain island free contexts, an RP and a gap are free alternatives in relatives and in LD-structures. However, RP can only redeem the potential violation of island constraints in an LD-structure but not in a relative clause. Gap strategy is always subject to locality constraints. Resumptive strategy only gives rise to island effects in relatives but not in LD-structures. In addition, two empty categories should be distinguished one from the other: gap and pro. The extraction of the direct object of action verbs causing direct physical effects on the object-patient, such as ōudǎ 'beat', will leave a gap, which potentially gives rise to island effects. By contrast, the extraction of the object of stative and psycho verbs which do not cause any physical effects on the object, such as xīnshǎng 'appreciate', never gives rise to island effects. It is assumed that these verbs take pro as their complement and pro functions as an RP in these structures, which saves the sentence from the potential violation of island constraints. Based on the syntactic distribution of gap, RP and pro in relatives and in LD-structures, the minimalist derivation of A'-dependencies involving these elements will be demonstrated.
... It has sometimes been claimed that matrix subjects cannot be resumed, while embedded subjects are associated with a resumptive in a number of languages, e.g. in Hebrew and Irish. This constraint is known as the Highest Subject Restriction(McCloskey 1990). However, this restriction is not universal, as a number of languages that also allow for matrix subject resumption have been found, seeKlein (2016);Salzmann (2017) for recent overviews. ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper investigates the principles that govern subject marking in Awing (Grassfields Bantu). We observe that the subject marker (SM) that doubles the subject is sometimes obligatory, sometimes optional and sometimes prohibited. We argue that it is the referentiality of the subject that controls the distribution of the SM in Awing, rather than factors such as its morpho-syntactic features or its information structural status, which have been identified to govern argument doubling in a number of other languages with a similar phenomenon. The empirical evidence leads us to conclude that the SM is a pronominal element in Awing rather than an agreement marker. When it occurs, it functions as the argument of the verb and the associated subject NP is base-generated in the left periphery of the clause; when it is absent, the NP is the verbal argument. Awing thus qualifies as a pronominal argument language in the sense of Jelinek (1984); Bresnan and Mchombo (1987); Baker (1996).
Article
This study investigates the sensitivity of grammatical resumption to islands in wh -interrogative and relative clause dependencies in Southern Jordanian Arabic ( JA ). An offline acceptability judgment task and an eye-tracking reading experiment were conducted. The results reveal that resumption in southern JA exhibits sensitivity to strong islands, such as adjunct islands, in both dependencies. The findings also suggest that the southern JA parser posits a resumptive pronoun ( RP ) inside islands that allow resumption. However, the parser does not predict an RP inside islands that disallow resumption. Furthermore, quantitative data show that wh -interrogative and relative clause dependencies pattern similarly in their sensitivity to islands.
Preprint
Full-text available
This study discusses the structure and the properties of pronominal clitics from the perspective of heritage Romance and Slavic languages, focussing in particular on changes in clitic paradigms of heritage Venetan and Bulgarian. While the former displays a peculiar distribution of subject clitics, the latter displays a parallel behaviour for object clitics. The two types of clitics are clearly very different, both in terms of grammatical function as well as placement restrictions, but they allow for parallel analyses in heritage varieties of the two languages. The behaviour of these clitics challenges previous models of structural deficiency of functional words, allowing for an analysis that takes into account predictable change patterns in heritage languages. The final goal of the present contribution is to propose a theoretical framework for the analysis of clitics in heritage languages, with respect to their structural and distributional properties.
Article
In many introspective and corpus studies, inserting a resumptive pronoun in place of a gap in island-violating wh-dependency structures in English is said to amnesty, ameliorate, or repair the island violation, improving the acceptability of otherwise unacceptable structures. Most experimental studies on the acceptability of such resumptive structures, however, report that native speakers of English do not judge island-violating dependency structures with resumptive pronouns to be more acceptable than the ones with gaps. But studies testing the comprehensibility and processing of resumption report that resumptive pronouns increase the comprehensibility of island-violating structures and facilitate processing of long dependencies. These results taken together suggest that although resumptive pronouns in islands do not have an ameliorating effect on grammaticality, they may confer a processing benefit. A question, however, remains as to whether the reported enhanced comprehensibility and ease in processing actually increase the accuracy in interpreting the resumptive pronouns.
Chapter
The Extended Standard Theory elaborated in Chomsky (1977) and Chomsky and Lasnik (1977) postulates the existence of an autonomous interpretive level: the Logical Form (LF) component. Representations at this level are derived from S-Structure representations via transformations (see May (1977)). These representations represent the structural meaning of a sentence and abstract away from other aspects of meaning such as word meaning or pragmatics: I. D-Structure — → S-Structure— → LF-Structure
Chapter
The problems of representation posed by VSO languages arise in some form in every current syntactic theory. How is clause structure represented in these languages, what is its relationship to surface word order, and how does it differ (if at all) from the clause structure of languages such as English? One way of approaching these questions within Government-Binding Theory is to rephrase them as questions about the government properties of the subject. If the subject position in VSO languages could be shown to be properly governed, then there would be some reason for supposing that the clause has an S-structure different from that assumed for English: either a flat S-structure, as in (1a), or else an S-structure in which Infi supported by V (1b), or perhaps Infi alone (1c), properly governs the subject. (For discussion of the specifics of the structures shown below, see the works cited.)
Chapter
I will be concerned in this paper with the binding conditions — the structural requirements governing certain anaphoric relations. I will give particular attention to “Condition C” effects, and will argue that, contrary to a currently popular view, something like Condition C does indeed exist. That is, I will display a wide variety of facts motivating Condition C which cannot be handled by, for example, independently motivated pragmatic constraints (see Reinhart (1983) for extensive discussion of such constraints) or by core properties of the theory of “Linking” (Higginbotham (1983)). A number of the arguments will be seen to carry over to Condition B as well. [It is on these grounds, of course, rather than on logical or biological grounds, that I will attempt to motivate the “necessity” of binding conditions, as one can surely conceive of an organism, even an evolutionarily successful one, whose linguistic system allows, say, the binding of a pronoun within its governing category.] In the course of the discssion, it will become evident that a partial reformulation of Condition C is in order, but its basic nature as a structural constraint on binding will remain intact.