Following Keynes's attribution of the assumption of full employment to the classics in the General Theory (1936), it has become standard practice particularly in macroeconomics textbooks to identify classical economics' with that assumption. Among the intermediate-level texts that repeat the attribution are Abel and Bernanke [1, 426], Baily and Friedman [6, 443-44], Dornbusch and Fischer [14, 200-201], Froyen [17, 55], Galbraith and Darity [18, 44-45], Gordon [19, 165], McElroy [45, 41-51], and Sachs and Larrain [62, 55].2 Case and Fair [10, 349-50], Colander [12, 211], Samuelson and Nordhaus [63, 277], and Slavin [65, 219-20] are among introductory-level texts that state the same claim. However, devising appropriate policies to raise the standard of living, especially for the poor, and also increase employment opportunities for a growing population were the principal focus of the classical economists. See, for example, Smith [66, 1:359-60, 372, 2:208], Ricardo [58, 1:386-97], Malthus [40, 231-40, 351-60], and Mill [46, 2:356-58]. Writing in the tradition of the classics, Alfred Marshall also was equally concerned about the fate of the poor and the need to identify policies that would promote economic growth and their welfare.3 Indeed, Keynes recalls Marshall's own explanation of his transition from mathematics to economics as being influenced by his visits to "the poorest quarters of several cities and [having] walked one street after another, looking at the faces of the poorest people" on his vacations.4 Pigou [53] also firmly denies having employed the full employment assumption as Keynes alleges. Indeed such an assumption would also be inconsistent with the title of Pigou's 1933 book, The Theory of Unemployment. On the other hand, Keynes's efforts to contrast classical arguments with his own charac