Content uploaded by Will Kymlicka
Author content
All content in this area was uploaded by Will Kymlicka on Aug 17, 2021
Content may be subject to copyright.
7
Is federalism a viable alternative to
secession?
Will Kymlicka
Around the world, multi-ethnic states are in trouble. Many have proven unable
to create or sustain any sense of solidarity across ethnic lines. The members of
one ethnic group are indifferent to the rights and interests of the members of
other groups, and are unwilling to make sacrifices for them. Moreover, they
have no trust that any sacrifice they might make will be reciprocated. Recent
events in Eastern Europe and the former Soviet Union show that where this sort
of solidarity and trust is lacking, demands for secession are likely to arise.
Some commentators have argued that secession is indeed the most
appropriate response to the crisis of multi-ethnic states. On this view, the desire
of minority groups to form a separate state is often morally legitimate, and it is
unjust to force them to remain within a larger state against their will.
International law should therefore define the conditions under which a group
has the right of secession, and the procedures by which that right can be
exercised.1
Critics of this approach argue that recognising a right of secession, either at
the level of normative political theory or international law, would encourage
more secessionist movements, and thereby increase the risk of political
instability and violence around the world. On this view, secession often leads to
civil war, and may start a chain reaction in which minorities within the seceding
unit seek to secede in turn. Moreover, even if actual secession never occurs, the
very threat of secession is destabilising, enabling groups to engage in a politics
of threats and blackmail.2
I will not be directly addressing the question of whether groups have a moral
or legal right to secede. Focusing exclusively on this question may blind us to
the really significant fact of our current situation—namely, that so many people
want to secede, or are at least prepared to consider it. It is a striking (and
distressing) fact that so many groups in the world today feel that their interests
cannot be satisfied except by forming a state of their own.
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
Nor is this problem confined to the Second and Third Worlds. Various multi-
ethnic democracies in the West whose long-term stability used to be taken for
granted now seem rather more precarious. Consider recent events in Belgium
or Canada. Even though they live in prosperous liberal states, with firm
guarantees of their basic civil and political rights, the Flemish and Québécois
may be moving down the path to independence. The threat of secession has
arisen in both capitalist and Communist countries, in both democracies and
military dictatorships, in both prosperous and impoverished countries.
The prevalence of secessionist movements suggests that contemporary states
have not developed effective means for accommodating ethnocultural diversity.
Whether or not we recognise a right to secede, the fact is that secession will
remain an ever-present threat in many countries unless we learn to
accommodate ethnocultural diversity. As long as minority groups feel that their
interests cannot be accommodated within existing states, they will contemplate
secession.
In this article, therefore, I want to focus on one of the most commonly cited
mechanisms for accommodating ethnocultural pluralism—namely, federalism.
Many commentators argue that federalism provides a viable alternative to
secession, since it is uniquely able to accommodate ethnocultural diversity.
Federalism, it is said, respects the desire of groups to remain autonomous, and
to retain their cultural distinctiveness, while nonetheless acknowledging the fact
that these groups are not self-contained and isolated, but rather are increasingly
and inextricably bound to each other in relations of economic and political
interdependence. Moreover, since federalism is a notoriously flexible system, it
can accommodate the fact that different groups desire different levels or forms
of self-government.3
My aim in this article is to evaluate this claim. I will challenge this optimistic
picture of the value of federalism in accommodating ethnocultural pluralism. For
one thing, federalism is simply not relevant for many types of ethnocultural
pluralism. Moreover, while there are some circumstances where federalism is
relevant, these very same circumstances make it likely that federalism will
simply be a stepping-stone to either secession or a much looser form of
confederation. In general, it seems to me unlikely that federalism can provide an
enduring solution to the challenges of ethnocultural pluralism. It may restrain
these challenges for a period of time, but federal systems which are designed to
accommodate self-governing ethnocultural groups are likely to be plagued by
deadlock and instability.
This isn’t to say that federalism should be rejected as a tool for
accommodating ethnocultural pluralism. On the contrary, federalism often
provides the best hope for keeping certain countries together. My point, rather,
110 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
is that, where federalism is needed to keep a country together, the odds that the
country will remain together over the long-term are not great. Federalism may
be the best available response to ethnocultural pluralism, but the best may not be
good enough.
Of course, many federal systems were not designed as a response to
ethnocultural pluralism—e.g. those of the United States or Australia. In these
federal systems, the federal units do not correspond in any way with distinct
ethnocultural groups who desire to retain their self-government and cultural
distinctiveness. These sorts of federal systems can be quite stable. I will discuss
the American model of federalism below, but my focus in this article is on
countries which have adopted federalism in order to accommodate ethnocultural
pluralism.
In this article, then, I will first distinguish two forms of cultural pluralism—
which I call ‘polyethnic’ and ‘multinational’. I will then explore whether
federalism is an appropriate response to these forms of cultural pluralism. I will
argue that federalism is largely irrelevant to the accommodation of
polyethnicity, but is potentially relevant to the accommodation of multinational
pluralism (see p. 119). Whether federalism is in fact appropriate for multination
states depends on many factors—in particular, how the boundaries of federal
subunits are drawn, and how powers are distributed between different levels of
government. Contrary to popular conceptions, I will argue that federalism often
lacks the flexibility to resolve these issues in a satisfactory way (see p. 127).
Finally, I will argue that even where federalism has been designed in such a way
as to accommodate ethnocultural groups, it may not be a stable solution, but
rather may simply provide a stepping-stone to secession (see p. 138).
TWO FORMS OF ETHNOCULTURAL PLURALISM
It is a commonplace to say that modern societies are increasingly
‘multicultural’. But the term ‘multicultural’ covers many different forms of
cultural pluralism, each of which raises its own challenges. I will distinguish two
broad patterns of ethnic diversity—which I will call ‘multinational’ and
‘polyethnic’—before considering the relevance of federalism to them.
One source of cultural diversity is the coexistence within a given state of
more than one nation, where ‘nation’ means a historical community, more or
less institutionally complete, occupying a given territory or homeland, sharing a
distinct language and culture.4 A ‘nation’ in this sociological sense is closely
related to the idea of a ‘people’ or a ‘culture’—indeed, these concepts are often
defined in terms of each other. A country which contains more than one nation
is, therefore, not a nation-state but a multination state, and the smaller cultures
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 111
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
form ‘national minorities’. The incorporation of different nations into a single
state may be involuntary—as occurs when one cultural community is invaded
and conquered by another, or is ceded from one imperial power to another, or
when its homeland is overrun by colonising settlers. But the formation of a
multination state may also arise voluntarily, when different cultures agree to
form a federation for their mutual benefit.
Many Western democracies are multinational. For example, there are a
number of national minorities in the United States, including the American
Indians, Alaskan Eskimos, Puerto Ricans, the descendants of Mexicans (Chicanos)
living in the Southwest when the United States annexed Texas, New Mexico
and California after the Mexican War of 1846–8, native Hawaiians, the
Chamoros of Guam, and various other Pacific Islanders. These groups were all
involuntarily incorporated into the United States, through conquest,
colonisation or imperial cession. Had a different balance of power existed, these
groups might have retained or established their own sovereign governments.
And talk of independence occasionally surfaces in Puerto Rico or the larger
Indian tribes. However, the historical preference of these groups has not been to
leave the United States, but to seek autonomy within it.
As they were incorporated, most of these groups acquired a special political
status. For example, Indian tribes are recognised as ‘domestic dependent
nations’ with their own governments, courts and treaty rights; Puerto Rico is a
‘Commonwealth’, and Guam is a ‘protectorate’. Each of these peoples is
federated to the American polity with special powers of self-government, as
well as group-specific rights regarding language and land use. In short, national
minorities in the United States have a range of rights intended to reflect and
protect their status as distinct cultural communities, and they have fought to
retain and expand these rights.5
Most of these groups are relatively small and geographically isolated.
Together, they constitute only a fraction of the overall American population. As
a result, these groups have been marginal to the self-identity of Americans—and
indeed the very existence of national minorities, and their self-government
rights, is often ignored by American politicians and theorists.
In other countries the existence of national minorities is more obvious.
Canada’s historical development has involved the federation of three distinct
national groups (English, French and Aboriginals).6 The original incorporation of
the Québécois and Aboriginal communities into the Canadian political
community was involuntary. Indian homelands were overrun by French
settlers, who were then conquered by the English. While the possibility of
secession is very real for the Québécois, the historical preference of these groups
—as with the national minorities in the United States—has not been to leave
112 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
the federation, but to renegotiate the terms of federation, so as to increase their
autonomy within it.
Many other Western democracies are also multinational, either because they
have forcibly incorporated indigenous populations (e.g. Finland; New Zealand),
or because they were formed by the more or less voluntary union of two or
more European cultures (e.g. Belgium and Switzerland). In fact, many
countries throughout the world are multinational, in the sense that their
boundaries were drawn to include the territory occupied by pre-existing, and
often previously self-governing, cultures. This is true of most countries
throughout the former Communist bloc and the Third World.7
The second source of cultural pluralism is immigration. A country will
exhibit cultural pluralism if it accepts large numbers of individuals and families
from other cultures as immigrants and allows them to maintain some of their
ethnic particularity. This has always been a vital part of life in Australia, Canada
and the United States, which have the three highest per capita rates of
immigration in the world. Indeed, well over half of all legal immigration in the
world goes into one of these three countries.
Prior to the 1960s immigrants to these countries were expected to shed their
distinctive heritage and assimilate to existing cultural norms. This is known as
the Anglo-conformity’ model of immigration. Indeed, some groups were denied
entry if they were seen as unassimilable (e.g. restrictions on Chinese
immigration in Canada and the United States, the ‘white-only’ immigration
policy in Australia). Assimilation was seen as essential for political stability, and
was further rationalised through ethnocentric denigration of other cultures.
This shared commitment to Anglo-conformity is obscured by the popular but
misleading contrast between the American ‘melting-pot’ and the Canadian
‘ethnic mosaic’. While ‘ethnic mosaic’ implies respect for the integrity of
immigrant cultures, in practice it simply meant that immigrants to Canada had a
choice of two dominant cultures to assimilate to. As Porter puts it, the ‘uneasy
tolerance which French and English were to show towards each other was not
extended to foreigners who resisted assimilation or were believed to be
unassimilable’.8
However, beginning in the 1970s, under pressure from immigrant groups,
all three countries rejected the assimilationist model and adopted a more
tolerant and pluralistic policy which allows, and indeed encourages, immigrants
to maintain various aspects of their ethnic heritage. It is now widely (though far
from unanimously) accepted that immigrants should be free to maintain some of
their old customs regarding food, dress, religion and recreation, and to associate
with each other to maintain these practices. This is no longer seen as unpatriotic
or ‘un-American’.
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 113
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
But it is important to distinguish this sort of cultural diversity from that of
national minorities. Immigrant groups are not ‘nations’ and do not occupy
homelands. Their distinctiveness is manifested primarily in their family lives and
in voluntary associations, and is not inconsistent with their institutional
integration. They still participate within the public institutions of the dominant
culture(s) and speak the dominant language(s). For example, immigrants (except
for the elderly) must learn English to acquire citizenship in Australia and the
United States, and learning English is a mandatory part of children’s education.
In Canada, they must learn either of the two official languages (French or
English).
The commitment to ensuring a common language has been a constant feature
of the history of immigration policy. Indeed, as Gerald Johnson said of the
United States, ‘It is one of history’s little ironies that no polyglot empire of the
old world has dared to be so ruthless in imposing a single language upon its
whole population as was the liberal republic “dedicated to the proposition that
all men are created equal”.’9 The rejection of Anglo-conformity has not meant a
slackening in this commitment to ensuring that immigrants become
Anglophones, which is seen as essential if they are to be included in the
mainstream of economic, academic and political life of the country.
So, while immigrant groups have increasingly asserted their right to express
their ethnic particularity, they typically wish to do so within the public
institutions of the English-speaking (or in Canada French-speaking) society. In
rejecting assimilation, they are not asking to set up a parallel society, as is
typically demanded by national minorities. The United States and Australia,
therefore, have a number of ‘ethnic groups’ as loosely aggregated subcultures
within the larger English-speaking society, and so exhibit what I will call
‘polyethnicity’. Similarly, in Canada there are ethnic subcultures within both
the English- and French-speaking societies.
It is possible, in theory, for immigrants to become national minorities, if they
settle together and acquire self-governing powers. After all, this is what
happened with English colonists throughout the British Empire, Spanish
colonists in Puerto Rico, and French colonists in Quebec. These colonists did
not see themselves as ‘immigrants’, since they had no expectation of integrating
into another culture, but rather aimed to reproduce their original society in a
new land. It is an essential feature of colonisation, as distinct from individual
emigration, that it aims to create an institutionally complete society, rather than
integrating into an existing one. It would, in principle, be possible to allow or
encourage immigrants today to view themselves as colonists, if they had
extensive government support in terms of settlement, language rights and the
114 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
creation of new political units. But immigrants have not asked for or received
such support.
Many people believe that this ‘polyethnic’ model no longer applies to
Hispanic immigrants to the United States. These immigrants are said to be
uninterested in learning English or in integrating into the Anglophone society.
This is a mistaken perception, which arises because people treat Hispanics as a
single category, and so confuse the demands of Spanish-speaking national
minorities (Puerto Ricans and Chicanos) with those of Spanish-speaking
immigrants recently arrived from Latin America. If we look at Hispanic
immigrants who come to the US with the intention to stay and become citizens,
the evidence suggests that they, as much as any other immigrants, are
committed to learning English and participating in the mainstream society.
Indeed, among Latino immigrants ‘assimilation to the English group occurs
more rapidly now than it did one hundred years ago’.10 (Obviously, this doesn’t
apply to those who don’t expect to stay—e.g. Cuban refugees in the 1960s, and
illegal Mexican migrant workers today.)
Immigration is not only a ‘New World’ phenomenon. Many other countries
also accept immigrants, although not on the same scale as the United States,
Canada and Australia. Since the Second World War Britain and France have
accepted immigrants from their former colonies. Other countries which accept
few immigrants nonetheless accept refugees from throughout the world (e.g.
Sweden). In yet other countries ‘guest-workers’ who were originally seen as
only temporary residents have become de facto immigrants. For example,
Turkish guest-workers in Germany have become permanent residents,
with their families, and Germany is often the only home known to their children
(and now grandchildren). All these countries are exhibiting increasing
‘polyethnicity’.
Obviously, a single country may be both multinational (as a result of the
colonising, conquest or confederation of national communities) and polyethnic
(as a result of individual and familial immigration). Indeed all of these patterns
are present in Canada—the Indians were overrun by French settlers, the French
were conquered by the English, although the current relationship between the
two can be seen as a voluntary federation, and both the English and French have
accepted immigrants who are allowed to maintain their ethnic identity. So
Canada is both multinational and polyethnic, as is the United States.
Those labels are less popular than the term ‘multicultural’. But that term can
be confusing, precisely because it is ambiguous between multinational and
polyethnic. This ambiguity has led to unwarranted criticisms of the Canadian
‘multiculturalism’ policy, which is the term the government uses for its
post-1970 policy of promoting polyethnicity rather than assimilation for
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 115
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
immigrants. Some French-Canadians have opposed the ‘multiculturalism’ policy
because they think it reduces their claims of nationhood to the level of
immigrant ethnicity.11 Other people had the opposite fear that the policy was
intended to treat immigrant groups as nations, and hence to support the
development of institutionally complete cultures alongside the French and
English. In fact, neither fear was justified, since ‘multiculturalism’ is a policy of
supporting polyethnicity within the national institutions of the English and
French cultures. Since ‘multicultural’ invites this sort of confusion, I will use
the terms ‘multinational’ and ‘polyethnic’ to refer to the two main forms of
cultural pluralism.
It is important to note that ‘nations’, whether they be the majority national
group or a national minority, are not defined by race or descent. Due to high
rates of immigration for over 150 ye ars, Anglophone Americans or Canadians who
are of solely Anglo-Saxon descent are a (constantly shrinking) minority.
Similarly, national minorities are increasingly multi-ethnic and multiracial. For
example, while the level of immigration into French Canada was low for many
years, it is now almost as high as immigration into English Canada or the United
States, and Quebec actively seeks Francophone immigrants from West Africa
and the Caribbean. There have also been high rates of intermarriage between
the indigenous peoples of North America and the English, French and Spanish
populations. As a result, all of these national minorities are racially and
ethnically mixed. The number of French-Canadians who are of solely Gallic
descent, or American Indians who are of solely Indian descent, is also constantly
shrinking, and will ultimately become a minority in each case. In talking about
national minorities, therefore, I am not talking about racial or descent groups
but about cultural groups.12
FEDERALISM AND THE ACCOMMODATION OF
ETHNOCULTURAL GROUPS
Immigration and the incorporation of national minorities are the two most
common sources of ethnocultural diversity in modern states. Most (though not
all) ethnocultural groups can be located within one or other of these broad
categories.13 Virtually all liberal democracies are either multinational or
polyethnic, or both. The ‘challenge of multiculturalism’ is to accommodate
these national and ethnic differences in a stable and morally defensible way. In
this section, I will discuss whether federalism provides a feasible or desirable
mechanism for responding to the demands of national minorities and ethnic
groups.
116 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
There is no universally accepted definition of ‘federalism’. For the purposes
of this article, I take federalism to refer to a political system which includes a
constitutionally entrenched division of powers between a central government
and two or more subunits (provinces/ Länder/states/cantons), defined on a
territorial basis, such that each level of government has sovereign authority over
certain issues. This distinguishes federalism from both (a) administrative
decentralisation, where a central government establishes basic policy in all
areas, but then devolves the power to administer these policies to lower levels of
government, typically regional or municipal governments; and (b)
confederation, where two or more sovereign countries agree to co-ordinate
economic or military policy, and so each devolves the power to administer these
policies to a supranational body composed of delegates of each country.14
It is possible to combine elements from these different models, and some
political systems may be difficult to categorise. All of these systems involve power-
sharing, but the path by which these powers come to be shared differs. In both
administrative decentralisation and confederation the central government within
each country is assumed to possess complete decision-making authority over all
areas of policy; it then chooses to devolve some of this authority upwards or
downwards on the basis of its perceived national interest. But this devolution is
voluntary and revocable—it retains ultimate sovereignty over these areas of
policy, and so it retains the right to unilaterally reclaim the powers it has
devolved. By contrast, in a federal system both levels of government have
certain sovereign powers as a matter of legal right, not simply on a delegated
and revocable basis. Both the central government and the federal subunits
possess sovereign authority over certain policy areas, and it is unconstitutional
for one level of government to intrude on the jurisdiction of the other. The
central government cannot ‘reclaim’ the powers possessed by the federal
subunits, because those powers never belonged to the central government.
Conversely, the subunits cannot reclaim the powers possessed by the central
government, because those powers never belonged to the subunits. In short,
unlike administrative decentralisation and confederation, both levels of
government in a federal system have a constitutionally protected existence, and
do not just exist on the sufferance of some other body.
Immigrant groups
As a general rule, federalism is not relevant to immigrant groups. This is partly
because immigrant groups are rarely territorially concentrated, and hence it
would be difficult, if not impossible, to draw federal boundaries in such a way
that these groups form a majority within a federal subunit. In principle, this
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 117
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
obstacle could be overcome either by encouraging territorial concentration or
by adopting a non-territorial form of self-rule, such as the ‘millet system’ of the
Ottoman Empire, or the Cultural Councils in pre-war Estonia.15 But the fact is
that immigrant groups within the major immigrant countries historically have
not sought the sort of institutional separateness and political self-government
which federalism provides. Italian-Americans or Japanese-Canadians do not seek
to form separate and self-governing societies based on their mother tongue,
alongside the mainstream Anglophone society. They seek to integrate within the
mainstream Anglophone society.
To be sure, many immigrant groups—particularly since the ‘ethnic revival’
in the 1970s—have demanded greater accommodation of their ethnocultural
differences. For example, there have been demands for: recognition of Jewish
and Muslim religious holidays in school schedules; exemptions from school or
government dress-codes so that Muslim girls can wear headscarves and Sikh and
Jewish men can wear turbans or yarmulkas; greater recognition of the role of
ethnic groups in school history textbooks; and proportional representation of
ethnic groups in the police, judiciary or legislature. But none of these demands
involves the desire to establish a separate and self-governing society alongside the
mainstream society. On the contrary, they aim to reform mainstream
institutions so as to make immigrant groups feel more at home within them.
These measures—which I elsewhere call ‘polyethnic rights’—are consistent
with, and indeed often promote, the integration of immigrants into the public
institutions of the mainstream society, including its political structures.16
I should emphasise that I am speaking here of immigrant groups within those
liberal democratic countries where there is a tradition of welcoming
immigrants, and where it is easy for immigrants to become full citizens
regardless of their race, religion or ethnic origin. Under these circumstances,
immigrant groups have not demanded the sort of group self-government
provided by federalism. Of course, in many parts of the world—including some
Western democracies—immigrants are much less welcome, and it is far more
difficult for them to acquire equal citizenship. Where immigrants are subject to
severe prejudice and legal discrimination—and hence where full equality within
the mainstream society is unachievable—it is more likely that immigrants will
seek to create a separate and self-governing society, alongside the mainstream
society. For example, if the German government persists in making it difficult
for long-term Turkish residents (and their children and grandchildren) to gain
citizenship, one would expect Turks to press for greater powers of self-
government. Perhaps they would press for some quasi-federal or consociational
form of devolution, so that they can create and perpetuate a separate and self-
governing society alongside the German society to which they are denied entry.
118 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
But this is not the preference of the Turks, whose main goal, like that of
immigrants in other liberal democracies, is to become full and equal participants
in German society. And, while I cannot argue the point here, I believe that any
plausible account of liberal justice will insist that long-term immigrants should
be able to acquire citizenship.17 In short, the historical record suggests that
quasi-federal forms of self-government will only be sought by immigrant groups
within liberal democracies if they face unjust barriers to their full integration
and participation in the mainstream society.
National minorities
The situation of national minorities is very different. In most multination states,
the component nations are inclined to demand some form of political autonomy
or territorial jurisdiction, so as to ensure the full and free development of their
cultures and to promote the interests of their people. They demand certain
powers of self-government which they say were not relinquished by their (often
involuntary) incorporation into a larger state. At the extreme, nations may wish
to secede if they think their self-determination is impossible within the larger
state.
One possible mechanism for recognising claims to self-government is
federalism. Where national minorities are regionally concentrated, the
boundaries of federal subunits can be drawn so that the national minority forms
a majority in one of the subunits. Under these circumstances, federalism can
provide extensive self-government for a national minority, guaranteeing its
ability to make decisions in certain areas without being outvoted by the larger
society.
For example, under the federal division of powers in Canada the province of
Quebec (which is 80 per cent Francophone) has extensive jurisdiction over
issues that are crucial to the survival of the Francophone society, including
control over education, language and culture, as well as significant input into
immigration policy. The other nine provinces also have these powers, but the
major impetus behind the existing division of powers, and indeed behind the
entire federal system, is the need to accommodate the Québécois. At the time
when Canada was created, in 1867, most English-Canadian leaders were in
favour of a unitary state, like England, and agreed to a federal system primarily
to accommodate French-Canadians. Had Quebec not been guaranteed these
substantial powers—and hence protected from the possibility of being outvoted
on key issues by the larger Anglophone population—it is certain that Quebec
either would not have joined Canada in 1867 or would have seceded sometime
thereafter.
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 119
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
Historically, the most prominent examples of federalism being used in this
way to accommodate national minorities are Canada and Switzerland. The
apparent stability and prosperity of these countries has led other multination
countries to adopt federal systems in the post-war period (e.g. Yugoslavia) or
upon decolonisation (e.g. India, Malaysia, Nigeria). Even though many of these
federations are facing serious difficulties, we are currently witnessing yet
another burst of interest in federalism in multination countries, with some
countries in the process of adopting federal arrangements (Belgium, Spain), and
others debating whether it would provide a solution to their ethnic conflicts
(e.g. South Africa).18
This widespread interest in federalism reflects a welcome, if belated,
acknowledgement that the desire of national minorities to retain their distinct
cultures should be accommodated, not suppressed. For too long, academic
theorists and political élites assumed that modernisation would inevitably
involve the assimilation of minority nationalities, and the withering away of
their national identity. Central governments around the world have tried to
dissolve the sense amongst national minorities that they constitute distinct
peoples or nations, by eliminating previously self-governing political and
educational institutions, and/or by insisting that the majority language be used
in all public forums. However, it is increasingly recognised that these efforts
were both unjust and ineffective, and that the desire of national minorities to
maintain themselves as culturally distinct and political autonomous societies
must be accommodated.19
Federalism is one of the few mechanisms available for this purpose. Indeed, it
is quite natural that multination countries should adopt federal systems—one
would expect countries which are formed through a federation of peoples to
adopt some form of political federation. But, while the desire to satisfy the
aspirations of national minorities is welcome, we should be aware of the pitfalls
involved. Federalism is no panacea for the stresses and conflicts of multination
states. In the rest of the article I will discuss a number of qualifications regarding
the potential value of federalism in multination states. I will separate my
concerns into three areas. First, the mere fact of federalism is not sufficient for
accommodating national minorities—it all depends on how federal boundaries
are drawn and how powers are shared. Indeed, federalism can be, and has been,
used by majority groups as a tool for disempowering national minorities, by
rigging federal units so as to reduce the power of national minorities. We need
therefore to distinguish genuinely multinational federations, which seek to
accommodate national minorities, from merely territorial federations, which do
not. Second, federalism is not as flexible as its proponents often claim. Where
the subunits of a federal system vary in their territory, population and their
120 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
desire for autonomy, as is often the case, developing an ‘asymmetric’ form of
federalism has proven to be very complicated (see p. 127). Finally, even where
federalism is successfully working to accommodate the aspirations of national
minorities, its very success may simply lead minorities to seek even greater
autonomy, through secession or confederation (see p. 138).
MULTINATIONAL VS. TERRITORIAL
FEDERALISM
While federalism is increasingly being considered as a solution to the problems
of multination states, it is important to note that many federal systems arose for
reasons unrelated to ethnonational diversity.20 In fact, the most famous and
widely studied federation—the American system—makes no effort to respond
to the aspiration of national minorities for self-government.
Anglo-Saxon settlers dominated all of the original thirteen colonies which
formed the United States. As John Jay put it in The Federalist Papers, ‘Providence
has been pleased to give this one connected country to one united people—a
people descended from the same ancestors, speaking the same language,
professing the same religion, attached to the same principles of government,
very similar in their manners and customs.’ Jay was exa ggerating the ethnocultural
homogeneity of the colonial population—most obviously in ignoring blacks21—
but it was true that none of the thirteen colonies were controlled by a national
minority, and that the original division of powers within the federal system was
not defined with a view to the accommodation of ethnocultural divisions.
The status of national minorities became more of an issue as the American
government began its territorial expansion to the south and west, and eventually
into the Pacific. At each step of this expansion the American government was
incorporating the homelands of already settled, ethnoculturally distinct peoples
—including American Indian tribes, Chicanos, Alaskan Eskimos, native
Hawaiians, Puerto Ricans, and Chamoros. And at each step, the question arose
whether the American system of federalism should be used to accommodate the
desire of these groups for self-government.
It would have been quite possible in the nineteenth century to create states
dominated by the Navaho, for example, or by Chicanos, Puerto Ricans and
native Hawaiians. At the time these groups were incorporated into the United
States they formed majorities in their homelands. However, a deliberate
decision was made not to use federalism to accommodate the self-government
rights of national minorities. Instead, it was decided that no territory would be
accepted as a state unless these national groups were outnumbered within that
state. In some cases this was achieved by drawing boundaries so that Indian
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 121
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
tribes or Hispanic groups were outnumbered (Florida). In other cases, it was
achieved by delaying statehood until Anglophone settlers swamped the older
inhabitants (e.g. Hawaii; the Southwest).22 As a result, none of the fifty states
can be seen as ensuring self-government for a national minority in the way that
Quebec ensures self-government for the Québécois.
Indeed, far from helping national minorities, there is reason to believe that
American federalism has made them worse off. Throughout most of American
history Chicanos, American Indian tribes and native Hawaiians have received
better treatment from the federal government than from state governments.
State governments, controlled by colonising settlers, have often seen national
minorities as an obstacle to greater settlement and resource development, and
so have pushed to strip minorities of their traditional political institutions,
undermine their treaty rights, and dispossess them of their historic homelands.
While the federal government has, of course, been complicit in much of the
mistreatment, it has often at least attempted to prevent the most severe abuses.
We can see the same dynamic in Brazil, where the federal government is
fighting to protect the rights of Indians in Amazonia against the predations of
local state governments.
In short, American-style territorial federalism, far from serving to
accommodate national minorities, has made things worse. This should be no
surprise, since the people who devised American federalism had no interest in
accommodating these groups. In deciding how to arrange their federal system—
from the drawing of boundaries, to the division of powers and the role of the
judiciary—their aim was to consolidate and then expand a new country and to
protect the equal rights of individuals within a common national community, not
to recognise the rights of national minorities to self-government.23 As I discuss
below, insofar as national minorities in the US have achieved self-government,
it has been outside of—and, to some extent, in spite of—the federal system,
through non-federal units such as the ‘commonwealth’ of Puerto Rico, the
‘protectorate’ of Guam or the ‘domestic dependent nations’ status of American
Indian tribes.
Since American federalism was not intended to accommodate ethnocultural
groups, why then was it adopted? There are several reasons why the original
colonists, who shared a common language and ethnicity, nonetheless adopted
federalism—reasons which are famously explored in The Federalist Papers. Above
all, federalism was seen as a way to prevent a liberal democracy from
degenerating into tyranny. As Madison put it, federalism helped to prevent
‘factions’—particularly an economic class or business interest—from imposing
its will through legislation to the detriment of ‘the rights of other citizens, or to
the permanent and aggregate interests of the community’. Federalism makes it
122 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
more difficult for those who ‘have a common motive to invade the rights of
other citizens’ to ‘act in unison with each other’. The ‘influence of factious
leaders may kindle a flame within their particular States, but will be unable to
spread a general conflagration through the other States’.24 Conversely, the
existence of strong, independent state governments provided a bulwark for
individual liberties against any possible encroachment by a federal government
which is captured by sinister factions.
Federalism was just one of several mechanisms for reducing the chance of
tyranny. An equal emphasis was placed on ensuring a separation of powers
within each level of government—e.g. separating the executive, judicial and
legislative powers at both the state and federal levels. This, too, helped
minimise the amount of power that any particular faction could command, as
did the later adoption of a Bill of Rights. The adoption of federalism in the
United States should be seen in the context of this pervasive belief that the
power of government must be limited and divided so as to minimise the threat
to individual rights.
It is important to note that Madison was not thinking of ethnocultural groups
when talking about ‘factions’. Rather, he was concerned with the sorts of
conflicts of interest which arise amongst ‘a people descended from the same
ancestors, speaking the same language’. These include, above all else, economic
divisions between rich and poor, or between agricultural, mercantile and
industrial interests. Madison’s preoccupations are reflected in his list of the
‘improper or wicked projects’ which federalism will help prevent—namely, ‘A
rage for paper money, for an abolition of debts, for an equal division of
property’.25
The subsequent history of the United States suggests that federalism offers
other, more positive, benefits. For example, it has helped provide room for
policy experimentation and innovation. Faced with new issues and problems,
each state adopted differing policies, and those policies which proved most
successful were then adopted more widely. Moreover, as the United States
expanded westward and incorporated vast expanses of territory with very
different natural resources and forms of economic development, it became
increasingly difficult to conceive how a single, centralised unitary government
would be workable. Some form of territorial devolution was clearly necessary,
and the system of federalism adopted by the original thirteen colonies on the
Atlantic coast served this purpose very well.
So there are many reasons, unrelated to ethnocultural diversity, why a
country would adopt federalism. Indeed, any liberal democracy which contains
a large and diverse territory will surely be pushed in the direction of adopting
some form of federalism, regardless of its ethnocultural composition. The
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 123
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
virtues of federalism for large-scale democracies are manifested not only in the
United States but also in Australia, Brazil and Germany. In each of these cases,
federalism is firmly entrenched and widely endorsed, even though none of the
federal units is intended to enable ethnocultural groups to be self-governing.
In some countries, then, federalism is adopted, not because it accommodates
the desire of national minorities for self-government, but rather because it
provides a means by which a single national community can divide and diffuse
power. Following Philip Resnick, I will call this ‘territorial federalism’, as
distinct from ‘multinational federalism’.26
My concern in this article is with multinational federations. Most scholarly
discussions of federalism, however, have focused on territorial federalism. This
is partly due to the historical influence of American federalism. Perhaps because
the United States was the first truly democratic federation, American federalism
has become the model, not just of territorial federalism but of federalism tout
court, or at least of ‘mature’ or ‘classic’ federalism. Similarly, The Federalist
Papers are often taken to be the paradigm expression of ‘the federalist principle’.
Other federal systems are then categorised on the basis of how closely they
conform to the basic attributes of the American system. Thus, for example,
Australia is typically seen as a more truly federal system than Canada or India,
since the latter deviate significantly from the American model.
Yet if our concern is with multinational federalism, then we cannot use the
United States as our model. The American federal system, and The Federalist
Papers, offer us no guidance on how to accommodate ethnocultural groups. On
the contrary, as I noted earlier, federal subunits were deliberately manipulated
to ensure that national minorities could not achieve self-government through
federalism. More generally, territorial federalism, in and of itself, is no
guarantee that ethnocultural groups will be accommodated. Whether the
allocation of powers to territorial subunits promotes the interests of national
minorities depends on how the boundaries of those subunits are drawn, and on
which powers are allocated to which level of government. If these decisions
about boundaries and powers are not made with the conscious intention of
empowering national minorities, then federalism may well serve to worsen the
position of national minorities, as has occurred in the United States, Brazil and
other territorial federalisms.
HOW FLEXIBLE IS MULTINATIONAL
FEDERALISM?
For a federal system to qualify as genuinely multinational, decisions about
boundaries and powers must consciously reflect the needs and aspirations of
124 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
minority groups.27 But to what extent can the boundaries and powers of federal
units be defined so as to accommodate these groups? As I noted earlier, many
theorists argue that federalism is appropriate precisely because it has great
flexibility in answering these questions. Even a cursory survey of federal
systems shows that there is great variety in how boundaries are drawn and
powers distributed. There seem to be few, if any, a priori rules regarding the
size, shape or powers of federal subunits.
I believe, however, that federalism is less flexible than many people suppose.
There are significant limitations on how powers can be divided, and on how
boundaries can be drawn. I will discuss these two problems in turn.
Dividing powers in a multinational federation
Let us assume that boundaries can be drawn in such a way that national
minorities form a majority in their federal subunit, as with Quebec or
Catalonia. This provides a starting-point for self-government, but whether the
resulting federal system is satisfactory to national minorities will depend on how
powers are distributed between the federal and provincial levels. The historical
record suggests that this issue may lead to intractable conflicts, because different
units may seek different powers, and it is difficult for federalism to
accommodate these divergent aspirations.
This is particularly true if only one or two of the federal units are vehicles for
self-governing national minorities, while the rest are simply regional divisions
within the majority national group. This is the case in Canada, for example,
where the province of Quebec secures self-government for the Québécois, but
the nine remaining provinces reflect regional divisions within English Canada. A
similar situation exists in Spain, where the Autonomous Communities of
Catalonia, the Basque Country and Galicia secure self-government for national
minorities, while most of the other fourteen Autonomous Communities, such
as La Mancha or Extremadura, reflect regional divisions within the majority
Spanish national group.28 In both countries, then, some units embody the desire
of national minorities to remain as culturally distinct and politically self-
governing societies (what I will call ‘nationality-based units’), while others
reflect the decision of a single national community to diffuse powers on a
regional basis (what I will call ‘regional-based units’).
It is likely that nationality-based units will seek different and more extensive
powers than regional-based units. As a general rule, we can expect nationality-
based units to seek greater and greater powers, while regional-based units are less
likely do so, and may indeed accept a gradual weakening of their powers. This is
reflected in the way the American and Canadian federal systems have
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 125
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
developed. It has often been pointed out that the United States, which began as
a strongly decentralised federation, with all residual powers attributed to the
states, has gradually become one of the most centralised; whereas Canada,
which began as a strongly centralised federation, with all residual powers
attributed to the federal government, has gradually become one of the most
decentralised. This is often said to be paradoxical, but it is understandable when
we remember that the United States is a territorial federation, composed
entirely of regional-based units. Because none of the fifty states in the United
States are nationality-based, centralisation has not been seen as a threat to
anyone’s national identity. While many Americans object to centralisation as
inefficient or undemocratic, it is not seen as a threat to the very survival of
anyone’s national group. By contrast, centralisation in Canada is often seen as a
threat to the very survival of the Québécois nation, insofar as it makes French-
Canadians more vulnerable to being outvoted by Anglophones on issues central
to the reproduction of their culture, such as education, language,
telecommunications, and immigration policy.
This difference has had a profound effect on how the US and Canada have
responded to the pressures for centralisation in this century. In both countries,
there have been many occasions—most notably the Depression and the two
World Wars—when there were great pressures to strengthen the federal
government, at least temporarily. In Canada these pressures were
counterbalanced by the unyielding insistence of French-Canadians that the self-
governing powers of Quebec be protected, so that any temporary centralisation
would ultimately be reversed. In the United States, however, there was no
similar countervailing pressure, and the various forces for greater centralisation
have gradually and cumulatively won out.
The fact that regional-based and nationality-based units typically desire
different levels of power is also reflected within both Canada and the United
States. For example, while most Québécois want an even more decentralised
division of powers, most English-Canadians favour retaining a strong central
government.29 Indeed, were it not for Quebec, there is good reason to believe
that Canadian federalism would have succumbed to the same forces of
centralisation which won out in the United States. However, while the regional-
based American states have gradually lost power, we find a very different story
if we look at the quasi-federal units used to accommodate national minorities—
e.g. the Commonwealth of Puerto Rico, Indian tribes, or the Protectorate of
Guam. In these cases of nationality-based units, we see a clear trend toward
greater powers of self-government, in order to sustain their cultural distinct
societies.30
126 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
We find the same pattern throughout Europe as well. For example, Catalonia
and the Basque Country have expressed a desire for greater autonomy than is
sought by other regional-based units in Spain. Corsica seeks greater autonomy
than other regional-based units in France. While many European countries are
engaging in forms of regional decentralisation, particularly if they had previously
been highly centralised states, this process is going much farther in countries
where the resulting units are nationality-based (e.g. Belgium) than where they
are regional-based (e.g. Italy). And of course the most extreme assertion of self-
government—namely, secession—has only been made by nationality-based
units, whether it be in the former Czechoslovakia, Yugoslavia or the Soviet
Union, and not by regional-based units.
In a federal system which contains both regional-based and nationality-based
units, therefore, it seems likely that demands will arise for some form of
asymmetrical federalism—i.e., for a system in which some federal units have
greater self-governing powers than others. Unfortunately, it has proven
extraordinarily difficult to negotiate such an asymmetrical model. There seems
to be great resistance, particularly on the part of majority groups, to accepting
the idea that federal units can differ in their rights and powers. As a result,
national minorities have found it very difficult to secure the rights and
recognition that they seek.
The difficulty in negotiating asymmetry is, in one sense, quite puzzling. If
English-Canadians want a strong federal government, and Québécois want a
strong provincial government, asymmetry would seem to give both groups
what they want. It seems perverse to insist that all subunits have the same
powers, if it means that English-Canadians have to accept a more decentralised
federation than they want, while French-Canadians have to accept a more
centralised federation than they want.
Yet most English-Canadians overwhelmingly reject the idea of ‘special status’
for Quebec. To grant special rights to one province on the grounds that it is
nationality-based, they argue, is somehow to denigrate the other provinces, and
to create two classes of citizens.31 Similar sentiments have been expressed in
Spain about the demand for asymmetrical status by the Basques and Catalans.32
Some commentators—such as Charles Taylor—argue that this simply reflects
confused moral thinking.33 Liberal democracies are deeply committed to
the principle of the moral equality of persons, and equal concern and respect for
their interests. But equality for individual citizens does not require equal
powers for federal units. On the contrary, special status for nati onality-based units
can be seen as promoting this underlying moral equality, since it ensures that
the national identity of minorities receives the same concern and respect as that
of the majority nation. Insofar as English-Canadians view the federal government
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 127
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
as their ‘national’ government, respecting their national identity requires
upholding a strong federal government; insofar as Québécois view Quebec as
their national government, respecting their national identity requires upholding
a strong provincial government. Accommodating these differing identities
through asymmetrical federalism does not involve any disrespect or invidious
discrimination.34 It is difficult to avoid the conclusion that much of the
opposition to asymmetry amongst the majority national group is rooted in a
latent ethnocentrism—i.e., a refusal to recognise that the minority has a
distinct national identity that is worthy of respect. This fits into the long history
of neglecting or denigrating the desire of national minorities to remain
culturally distinct societies, which I discussed earlier.
Another factor underlying the opposition to asymmetry is the profound
influence of the American model of federalism. As I noted earlier, many people
have supposed that American federalism is the model of federalism tout court,
and that all federalisms should aim to be purely territorial. On this view, any
special accommodations for nationality-based units are seen as merely transient
measures which are not appropriate in a ‘mature’ territorial federalism.
The problem is not simply that regional and nationality-based units happen to
desire different powers. These variations in desired powers reflect an even
deeper difference in the very conception of the nature and aims of political
federation. For national minorities, federalism is, first and foremost, a
federation of peoples, and decisions regarding the powers of federal subunits
should recognise and affirm the equal status of the founding peoples. On this
view, to grant equal powers to regional-based units and nationality-based units
is in fact to deny equality to the minority nation, by reducing its status to that of
a regional division within the majority nation. By contrast, for members of the
national majority, federalism is, first and foremost, a federation of territorial
units, and decisions regarding the division of powers should affirm and reflect
the equality of the constituent units. On this view, to grant unequal powers to
nationality-based units is to treat some of the federated units as less important
than others.
This difference in the conception of federalism can lead to conflicts even
when there is little variation in the actual powers demanded by regional-based
and nationality-based units. For example, some people have proposed a radical
across-the-board decentralisation in Canada, so that all provinces would have
the same powers currently demanded by Quebec. This is intended to avoid the
need to grant ‘special status’ to Quebec. The response by many Quebec
nationalists, however, was that this missed the point. The demand for special
status was a demand not just for this or that power but also for national
recognition. As Resnick puts it, ‘They want to see Quebec recognised as a
128 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
nation, not a mere province; this very symbolic demand cannot be finessed
through some decentralising formula applied to all provinces’.35 Quebec
nationalists want asymmetry, not just to gain this or that additional power, but
also for its own sake, as a symbolic recognition that Quebec alone is a
nationality-based unit within Canada.36
This may seem like a petty concern with symbols rather than the substance of
political power. But we find the same response in other multinational
federations. For example, prior to the breakup of Czechoslovakia some people
proposed a decentralised federation composed of three units with equal powers
—Slovakia and two Czech regions (Moravia and Bohemia). This would enable
Slovak national self-government, while also accommodating Moravia’s historical
status as a distinct region within the Czech nation. However, Slovak nationalists
dismissed this proposal, since ‘it would have meant equivalence between the
Slovak nation and Moravian cultural and historical specificity, thus lessening the
relevance of Slovak nationhood’.37
Or consider the response of Catalan and Basque nationalists to the proposal
to make the same maximal level of autonomy exercised by their nationality-
based units available to all federal units in Spain, including the regional-based units
(i.e. to ‘generalise’ autonomy):
the 1978 Constitution assumed the principle of autonomy because it was
absolutely essential to resolve the claims to self-government made by
Catalonia and the Basque country if indeed a democratic system was to be
installed which aimed not just at the freedom and rights of citizens but
also of peoples. When the attack began via what has been called the
generalisation of autonomies, the politicians tried to forget what was
originally intended.38
We can now see why disputes about the division of powers within a multinational
federalism are so difficult to resolve. The problem is not simply that units differ
in their preferences regarding the extent of autonomy. That problem can often
be resolved by reasonable people of good will. And indeed many English-
Canadians are willing to accept a more decentralised federation than they would
ideally like in order to accommodate Quebec, while many Québécois are
willing to accept a less decentralised federation than they would ideally like in
order to accommodate English Canada. Reasonable people are willing to
compromise, within limits, on the precise powers they seek for their federal
units.
Unfortunately, the problem goes deeper than this. While the majority may
be willing to compromise on the precise degree of decentralisation, they are
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 129
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
unwilling to compromise on what they take to be a basic principle of federalism
—namely, that all federal units should be equal in their rights and powers.
Conversely, while the national minority may be willing to compromise on its
demands for autonomy, it is not willing to compromise on what it takes to be a
basic principle of federalism—namely, that its status as one of the founding
peoples must be symbolically recognised through some form of asymmetry
between nationality-based and region-based units. As a result, even if both
regional-based and nationality-based units happen to desire a roughly similar set
of powers, serious conflicts are likely to remain. For each side rejects on principle
what the other side views as part of the very nature and purpose of federalism.
For the majority nation, federalism is a compact between equal territorial units,
which therefore precludes asymmetry; for the national minority, federalism is a
compact between peoples, which therefore requires asymmetry between
nationality-based units and regional-based units.
This helps explain why asymmetry has been so difficult to negotiate within
multinational federations. But there are other problems which further reduce the
flexibility of federalism in adopting asymmetry. Let’s assume that the conflicts I
have just been discussing are somehow solved, and there is a widespread
acceptance of the need for some form of asymmetry for nationality-based units.
There remain some practical problems to be solved, particularly regarding the
representation of the nationality-based unit in the federal government. These
problems are, I believe, formidable, and we have very few models around the
world of how to resolve them.
Let’s imagine, then, that an asymmetrical transfer of powers from the federal
government to Quebec occurs, so that the federal government would be passing
laws that would apply to all provinces except Quebec. Under these
circumstances, it seems only fair that Quebecers not have a vote on such
legislation (particularly if they could cast the deciding vote). For example, it
would seem unfair for Quebec’s elected representatives at the federal level to
vote on federal legislation regarding immigration, if the legislation does not
apply to Quebec. In short, insofar as the jurisdiction of the federal government
over a national minority is reduced, compared to other regional-based units,
this seems to entail that the minority group should have reduced influence (at
least on certain issues) at the federal level.
Some national minorities do have this sort of reduced influence at the federal
level. For example, because residents of Puerto Rico have special self-governing
powers which exempt them from certain federal legislation, they have reduced
representation in Washington. They help select presidential candidates in party
primaries, but do not vote in presidential elections. And they have only one
representative in Congress, a ‘commissioner’ who has a voice but no vote,
130 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
except in committees. This reduced representation is seen by some as evidence
that Puerto Rico is ‘colonised’ by the United States. But, while the details of the
existing arrangement are subject to criticism, the existence of reduced
representation can be seen as a corollary of Puerto Rican self-government, and
not just its colonial subjugation. The less a group is governed by the federal
government, the less right it has to representation in that government. An
asymmetry in powers entails an asymmetry in representation.
But how exactly should an asymmetry in the powers of subunits be reflected
in terms of representation at the federal level? If a particular subunit has greater
powers, one would expect its representatives to be fewer in number, and/or
restricted in their voting power. Both of these apply to Puerto Rico. But the
Puerto Rican model has obvious weaknesses. While Puerto Rico has very
limited federal representation, it is still very much subject to Congressional
authority in some areas. It would seem preferable, therefore, to reduce their
influence in a more issue-specific way—for example, by allowing their
Congressional representative to have a full vote on legislation which applies to
Puerto Rico, but no vote on legislation from which Puerto Rico is exempt.
Unfortunately, this is easier said than done. Many pieces of legislation deal with
areas of jurisdiction that Puerto Rico is partly exempt from, and partly subject
to. There is no way to divide up the business of government into such clear-cut
groupings. Moreover, this leaves unanswered the question of how many
representatives a nationality-based unit should have at the federal unit. A strong
asymmetry in powers for federal subunits suggests that there should be a
compensating reduction in the number of representatives, but what is a fair
trade-off here?
This has been a serious stumbling-block in developing a workable model of
asymmetrical federalism in Canada. It is increasingly accepted that a strongly
asymmetrical status for Quebec will require reducing the influence of Quebec’s
elected representatives in the federal legislature. However, there is no available
model which tells us how to do this.39 And of course this problem links up with
the previous problem of differing conceptions of federalism. Since members of
the majority are already inclined to view any form of asymmetry as an unfair
privileging of the minority, they will be keenly sensitive to any evidence that the
minority is exercising undue power at the federal level (e.g. by voting on
legislation from which they are themselves exempt).
Yet we can expect the national minority to resist any serious reduction of
their representation at the federal level. After all, they are already, by definition,
a minority at the federal level, and to reduce their influence even further will
just make the federal government seem more remote, and indeed more of a
threat. It will seem increasingly like an ‘alien’ government. The more Quebec’s
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 131
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
influence is reduced at the federal level, the more tempting it will be for
Quebecers to decide to simply go it alone, and seek secession. Why stay within
the federation if their influence on federal policy is gradually eroding? The
danger that asymmetry will eventually lead to secession is a serious one, I
believe, since there are other factors pulling in the direction of secession, which
I discuss in the next section.
So there are many reasons why federal systems have difficulty adopting
asymmetrical arrangements. Indeed, these problems are so severe that some
people have claimed that a federal system cannot survive for long if it adopts
asymmetry. This is an overstatement, but there are greater limits on the
flexibility of federalism than many proponents of federalism admit.40
The inability of federalism to accommodate asymmetry is exacerbated by the
fact that the procedure for amending the constitution in a federal system is so
cumbersome. For example, to amend the constitution in the United States
requires the consent of thirty-five states, and two-thirds of the members of
Congress. In Canada, depending on the nature of the proposed change, a
constitutional amendment requires the consent of both federal houses, plus
either seven provinces containing 50 per cent of population, or all ten
provinces. Recent experience with the Equal Rights Amendment in US, or the
Meech Lake and Charlottetown Accords in Canada, suggests that achieving this
level of agreement is very difficult. If implementing asymmetrical federalism
requires amending the powers of federal subunits, or the system of federal
representation, the obstacles are enormous. Whereas a unitary state can
typically amend its constitution by a single majority or super-majority vote,
federalism requires the consent of concurrent majorities—i.e. majorities in the
country as a whole, plus in all of its constituent units. This sets the threshold so
high that even a widely supported proposal for asymmetry may fall short.
Drawing boundaries in a multinational federation
One limitation on federalism’s ability to accommodate national minorities, then,
is that it may be difficult to achieve the desired division of powers. But, in
addition to dividing powers, we must also draw boundaries, and this raises
another limit on the flexibility of multinational federalism. For federalism to
serve as a mechanism for self-government, it must be possible to draw federal
subunits in such a way that the national minority forms a majority within a
particular subunit, as the Québécois do in Quebec. This is simply not possible
for some national minorities, including most indigenous peoples in the United
States or Canada, who are fewer in number, and who have been dispossessed of
much of their historic lands, so that their communities are often dispersed, even
132 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
across state/provincial lines. With few exceptions, indigenous peoples currently
form a small minority within existing federal units, and no redrawing of the
boundaries of these federal subunits would create a state, province or territory
with an indigenous majority.41 It would have been possible to create a state or
province dominated by an Indian tribe in the nineteenth century, but, given the
massive influx of settlers since then, it is now virtually inconceivable.
For most indigenous peoples in the US or Canada, therefore, self-government
can only be achieved outside the federal system. Self-government has been
primarily tied to the system of reserved lands (known as tribal ‘reservations’ in
the United States, and band ‘reserves’ in Canada). Substantial powers are
exercised by the tribal/band councils which govern each reserve. Indian tribes/
bands have been acquiring increasing control over health, education, family law,
policing, criminal justice and resource development. (Or, more accurately, they
have been reacquiring these powers, since, of course, they governed themselves
in all these areas before their involuntary incorporation into the larger Canadian
or American polity). They are becoming, in effect, a kind of ‘federacy’, to use
Daniel Elazar’s term, with a collection of powers that is carved out of both
federal and state/ provincial jurisdictions.42
One could, in principle, define each of these reserved lands as a new state or
province within the federal system. But that is impractical, given that there are
so many separate tribes/bands in the United States and Canada (over six
hundred in Canada alone), and that many of these groups are very small both in
population and territory, and that they are located within existing federal
subunits. Moreover, Indian peoples do not want to be treated as federal
subunits, since the sort of self-government they seek involves a very different
set of powers from that exercised by provinces. They would only accept the
status of a federal subunit if this was a strongly asymmetrical status, which
included powers typically exercised by both the federal and provincial levels.
Furthermore, Indian tribes/bands differ enormously amongst themselves in the
sorts of powers they desire. They seek not only asymmetry, but varying degrees
of asymmetry. Yet, for the reasons I’ve just discussed, it is extremely difficult to
achieve that sort of flexibility within a federal system. Hence Indians have
pursued self-government through a sort of ‘federacy’ relationship that exists
outside the normal federal system.
As the term suggests, a ‘federacy’ has important analogies with federalism—
for example, both involve a territorial division of powers. But because most
Indian tribes now form a minority even within their historic homelands, and so
are territorially located within existing states or provinces, their self-
government occurs outside of, and to some extent in opposition to, the federal
system. Rather than possessing the standard rights and powers held by federal
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 133
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
subunits, and governing under the same rules which apply to federal subunits,
they instead possess a set of group-specific powers and exemptions which
partially removes them from the federal process by reducing the jurisdiction of
both the federal and state/provincial governments over them. As I noted
earlier, federalism in the United States and Canada, far from empowering Indian
peoples, has in fact simply increased their vulnerability, by making their self-
governance subject to encroachment from both federal and state/provincial
governments. The achievement of Aboriginal self-government through
‘federacy’, therefore, involves protection against the federal system.
The fact that Indians in the United States do not control state governments
has tended to make them more vulnerable, since their self-government powers
do not have the same constitutional protection as states’ rights. They are
therefore more subject to the ‘plenary power’ of Congress, which has often
been exercised to suit the needs and prejudices of the dominant society, not of
the national minority. However, the fact that they lie outside the federal structure
has compensating advantages. In particular, it has provided much greater
flexibility in redefining those powers to suit the needs and interests of the
minority. Whereas there is pressure within federal systems to make all subunits
equal in their powers and federal representation, ‘federacy’ arrangements allow
for greater variations. Moreover, it is much easier to negotiate new self-
government provisions for the Navaho than to amend the powers of individual
states.
The same applies to other national minorities in the United States. For
example, because Puerto Rico is a ‘Commonwealth’ not a state, it has been
easier to amend its self-governing powers and to negotiate an asymmetrical
status in terms of both powers and federal representation. This might have
proved impossible had Puerto Rico been granted statehood when it was
incorporated by the United States in 1898.43
For a variety of reasons, then, federalism may lack the flexibility needed to
accommodate national minorities. It may be impossible for a small national
minority to form a majority in one of the federal subunits. For such groups, self-
government can only be achieved outside the federal system, through some special
non-federal or quasi-federal political status. And, even if the boundaries can be
drawn in such a way that the national minority forms a majority within a federal
subunit, it may be impossible to negotiate a satisfactory division of powers,
particularly if the federation includes both nationality-based and regional-based
subunits.
Therefore, in many cases, the aspirations of national minorities may best be
achieved through political institutions which operate outside the federal system
—as ‘commonwealths’, ‘federacies’, ‘protectorates’ or ‘associated states’—
134 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
rather than by controlling a standard federal subunit. Standard models of
federalism, with their implicit assumptions of equal powers and regional-based
units, and their complex amendment procedures, may not be capable of
responding to the distinctive interests and desires of nationality-based units.
FEDERALISM, SECESSION AND SOCIAL UNITY
So far, I have been discussing limits on the ability of federalism to accommodate
the needs of national minorities. Let’s imagine, however, that these problems
have been overcome. Let’s assume that national minorities are satisfied with the
boundaries of their subunit, that they possess sufficient self-governing powers to
maintain themselves as culturally distinct societies, and that some form of
asymmetry has either been accepted or proven unnecessary. In short, let’s
assume that federalism is working as its proponents envisage to combine shared
rule with respect for ethnocultural differences. There is one further problem
that is worth considering. The very success of federalism in accommodating self-
government may simply encourage national minorities to seek secession. The
more that federalism succeeds in meeting the desire for self-government, the
more it recognises and affirms the sense of national identity amongst the
minority group, and strengthens their political confidence. Where national
minorities become politically mobilised in this way, secession becomes more
likely, even with the best-designed federal institutions.
One way to describe the problem is to say that there is a disjunction between
the legal form of multinational federalism and its underlying political
foundations. Legally speaking, as I noted earlier, federalism views both levels of
government as possessing inherent sovereign authority. This distinguishes it
from a confederation, where sovereign states delegate certain powers to a
supranational body—powers which they can reclaim. In a federal system,
however, the general government has inherent, not just delegated, power to
govern its citizens. Just as the province of Quebec has the inherent authority to
govern all Quebecers—an authority which the federal government did not
delegate and cannot unilaterally revoke—so the federal government of Canada
has the inherent authority to govern all Canadians (including Quebecers), an
authority which the provincial governments did not delegate, and cannot
unilaterally revoke.
This is the legal form of federalism. But political perceptions of it are likely to
be rather different. Multinational federations are often viewed by national
minorities as if they were confederations. National minorities typically view
themselves as distinct ‘peoples’, whose existence predates that of the country
they currently belong to. As separate ‘peoples’, they possess inherent rights of
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 135
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
self-government.44 While they are currently part of a larger country, this is not
seen as a renunciation of their original right of self-government. Rather it is seen
as a matter of transferring some aspects of their powers of self-government to
the larger polity, on the condition that other powers remain in their own hands.
In countries that are formed from the federation of two or more national
groups, the (morally legitimate) authority of the central government is limited
to the powers which each constituent nation agreed to transfer to it. And these
national groups often see themselves as having the (moral) right to take back these
powers, and withdraw from the federation, if they feel threatened by the larger
community.45
Legally speaking, of course, nationality-based federal units do not have the
right to reclaim the powers exercised by the federal government. Legally, these
powers are inherently vested in the federal government, and the subunits
cannot ‘reclaim’ what was never theirs. But the political perceptions of national
minorities are unlikely to match these legal niceties. For them, the larger
country feels more like a confederation than a federation, in the sense that the
larger country’s existence is seen as morally dependent on the revocable
consent of the constituent national units. As a result, the larger political
community has a more conditional existence than a unitary state or a territorial
federalism.
In short, the basic claim made by national minorities is not simply that the
political community is culturally diverse (as immigrants, for example, typically
claim).46 Instead, the claim is that there is more than one political community,
and that the authority of the larger state cannot be assumed to take precedence
over the authority of the constituent national communities. If democracy is the
rule of ‘the people’, national minorities claim that there is more than one
people, each with the right to rule themselves. Multinational federalism divides
the people into separate ‘peoples’, each with its own historic rights, territories
and powers of self-government, and each, therefore, with its own political
community. They may view their own political community as primary and the
value and authority of the larger federation as derivative.47
The reason why multinational federalisms are likely to be unstable should
now be obvious. The more a federal system is genuinely multinational—that is,
the more it recognises and affirms the demand for self-government—the more
it will strengthen the perception amongst national minorities that the federal
system is de facto a confederal system. That is, the more successful a
multinational federal system is in accommodating national minorities, the more
it will strengthen the sense that these minorities are separate peoples with
inherent rights of self-government, whose participation in the larger country is
conditional and revocable. And if the attachment of national minorities to the
136 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
larger state is conditional, then sooner or later one can expect conditions to
change, so that staying within the federation no longer seems beneficial.
Federalism also provides national minorities with the experience of self-
government, so that they will feel more confident of their ability to go it alone,
and with an already recognised territory over which they are assumed to have
some prima facie historical claim.48
Moreover, if the secession itself can be achieved peacefully, then the costs of
going it alone as a small state have dramatically fallen. In the past, national
minorities needed to join larger countries in order to gain access to economic
markets, and/or to ensure military security. But these beneflts of federalism can
now be achieved through confederal arrangements (like the European
Community, or the North American Free Trade Agreement), and through the
gradual strengthening of international law. If Quebec or Catalonia seceded, they
would still be able to participate in continental or international free trade and
security arrangements.49
In any event, the option of secession will always be present. Indeed, in a
sense, it becomes the default position, or the baseline against which
participation in the federation is measured. Amongst national minorities, the
starting point will not be ‘Why should we seek greater autonomy?’ but rather
‘Why should we continue to accept these limits on our inherent self-
government?’. After all, there seems to be no natural stopping point to the
demands for increasing self-government. If limited autonomy is granted, this
may simply fuel the ambitions of nationalist leaders who will be satisfied with
nothing short of their own nation-state. Any restrictions on self-government—
anything short of an independent state—will need justification.
For all these reasons, it seems likely that multinational federalism will be
plagued with instability, and may eventually devolve into a confederation or
simply break up. What then can keep a multination federation together? Since
the main instrumental arguments for federation (economic markets and military
security) have lost much of their force, it seems that we need to focus more on
the intrinsic benefits of belonging to a federation—that is, the value of
belonging to a country which contains national diversity. In some
circumstances, I think this can be a very powerful argument. For example, Petr
Pithart, the former Prime Minister of Czechoslovakia, reflecting on its
dissolution, stated that:
In the last 55 years, the Czechs have lost—as co-tenants in their common
house—Germans, Jews, Ruthenians, Hungarians and Slovaks. They are
now, in effect, an ethnically cleansed country, even if it was not by their
own will. It is a great intellectual, cultural, and spiritual loss. This is
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 137
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
particularly true if we consider central Europe, which is a kind of mosaic.
We are still living touristically from the glory of Prague, which was a
Czech-German-Jewish city and a light that reached to the stars. But you
cannot win elections with that kind of argument.50
It seems to me that there often is a ‘great intellectual, cultural and spiritual loss’
when multination states dissolve. But it is not easy to articulate these losses, and,
as Pithart notes, these arguments have not always been politically effective to
date.
CONCLUSION
In this article I have outlined several reasons why federalism may not provide a
viable alternative to secession in multination states. There are limits on the ways
that boundaries can be drawn in a federal system, and on the ways that powers
can be distributed—limits which seriously reduce federalism’s ability to
accommodate the aspirations of national minorities. Moreover, even when
federalism is working well to satisfy these aspirations, it is likely simply to
reinforce the belief that the group is able and rightfully entitled to secede and
exercise full sovereignty. This indeed is the paradox of multinational federalism:
while it provides national minorities with a workable alternative to secession, it
also helps to make secession a more realistic alternative to federalism.
So it would be a mistake to think that implementing federalism will remove
the issue of secession from the political agenda. I should emphasise again that I
am not suggesting that we therefore reject federal solutions. Federalism is often
the only option available for accommodating conflicting national identities
within a multination state. And, even if a federal system eventually dissolves, it
may bequeath important lessons regarding the nature and value of democratic
tolerance.51 So federalism is certainly worth trying.
However, we shouldn’t be overly optimistic about the extent to which
federalism provides a viable long-term alternative to secession. It is wrong, I
think, to suppose that federalism provides a tried and true formula for the
successful and enduring accommodation of national differences. It provides at
best a hope for such an accommodation, but to make it work requires an
enormous degree of ingenuity and good will, and indeed good luck. And, even
with all the good fortune in the world, multinational federations are unlikely to
exist for ever. We shouldn’t expect citizens of a multinational federation to
view themselves as members of ‘one co-operative scheme in perpetuity’, as
John Rawls puts it.52 To demand that sort of unconditional allegiance is to set a
standard that multinational federations are unlikely to meet. A well-designed
138 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
federal system may defer secession—perhaps into the indefinite future. But
secession will remain a live option in the hearts and minds of national
minorities. Indeed, it is likely to form the benchmark against which federal
systems are measured.
NOTES
1 See, for example, Daniel Philpott, ‘In defense of self-determination’, Ethics, vol.
105/2, 1995, pp. 352–85; Alan Buchanan, Secession: The Morality of Political
Divorce from Fort Sumter to Lithuania and Quebec, Boulder CO, Westview Press,
1991; Michael Walzer, ‘The new tribalism’, Dissent, vol. 39, spring 1992, pp.
164–71.
2 See Donald Horowitz, ‘Self-determination: politics, philosophy, and law’, in
Will Kymlicka and Ian Shapiro (eds), Nomos 39: Ethnicity and Group Rights, New
York, New York University Press, 1997, pp. 421–63.
3 See, for example, Daniel Elazar’s Federalism and the Way to Peace, Institute of
Intergovernmental Affairs, Queen’s University, Kingston, 1994, and his Exploring
Federalism, Tuscaloosa, University of Alabama, 1987.
4 By ‘institutionally complete’, I mean containing a set of societal institutions,
encompassing both public and private spheres, which provide members with
meaningful ways of life across the full spectrum of human activities, including
social, educational, religious, economic and recreational life. For a fuller
discussion, see my Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights,
Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995, ch. 5.
5 For a survey of the rights of national minorities in the United States, see Sharon
O’Brien, ‘Cultural rights in the United States: a conflict of values’, Law and
Inequality Journal, vol. 5, 1987, pp. 267–358; Judith Resnik, ‘Dependent
sovereigns: Indian tribes, states, and the federal courts’, University of Chicago Law
Review, vol. 56, 1989, pp. 671–759; Alexander Aleinikoff, ‘Puerto Rico and the
constitution: conundrums and prospects’, Constitutional Commentary, vol. 11,
1994, pp. 15–43.
6 On the language of nationhood by Aboriginals and the Québécois, see Jane
Jenson, ‘Naming nations: making nationalist claims in Canadian public
discourse’, Canadian Review of Sociology and Anthropology, vol. 30, no. 3, 1993, pp.
337–58. I should note that Aboriginal peoples are not a single nation. Aboriginals
in Canada can be divided into eleven linguistic groups, descended from a number
of historically and culturally distinct societies. It has been estimated that there are
35–50 distinct ‘peoples’ in the Aboriginal population, see Paul Chartrand, ‘The
aboriginal peoples in Canada and renewal of the federation’, in Karen Knop et al.
(eds), Rethinking Federalism, Vancouver, University of British Columbia Press,
1995.
7 On the Communist world, see June Dreyer, China’s Forty Millions: Minority
Nationalities and National Integration in the People’s Republic of China, Cambridge
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 139
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
MA, Harvard University Press, 1979; Walker Connor, The National Question in
Marxist-Leninist Theory and Strategy, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1984.
On the Third World, see Alemante Selassie, ‘Ethnic identity and constitutional
design for Africa’, Stanford Journal of International Law, vol. 29, no. 1, 1993, pp. 1–
56; Basil Davidson, The Black Man’s Burden: Africa and the Curse of the Nation-State,
New York, Times Books, 1992.
8John Porter, The Measure of Canadian Society, Ottawa, Carleton University Press,
1987, p. 154; cf. Jeffrey Reitz and Raymond Breton, The Illusion of Difference:
Realities of Ethnicity in Canada and the United States, Ottawa, C.D.Howe Institute,
1994.
9 Gerald Johnson, Our English Heritage, Westport, Greenwood Press, 1973, p. 119.
For the history of language rights in the United States, see Heinz Kloss, The
American Bilingual Tradition, Rowley, Newbury House, 1977; Edward Sagarin and
Robert Kelly, ‘Poly-lingualism in the United States of America: A multitude of
tongues amid a monolingual majority’, in William Beer and James Jacob (eds),
Language Policy and National Unity, Totowa, Rowman and Allenheld, 1985, pp.
21–44. As both note, the imposition of English was more ‘ruthless’ for national
minorities than for immigrants, since the latter expected to integrate, whereas
imposing English on national minorities required the coercive disbanding of long-
standing educational, political and judicial institutions using the minority’s
mother-tongue.
10 M.Combs and L.Lynch, quoted in Rodolpho de la Garza and A.Trujillo, ‘Latinos
and the Official English debate in the United States’, in David Schneiderman
(ed.), Language and the State: The Law and Politics of Identity, Cowansville, Editions
Yvon Blais, 1991, p. 215; cf. Linda Chavez, Out of the Barrio: Toward a New Politics
of Hispanic Assimilation, New York, Basic Books, 1991, p. 42. Hispanic immigrant
groups have expressed an interest in bilingual education, but they view Spanish-
language education as supplementing, not displacing, the learning of English. As a
general rule, immigrants to the United States who speak Spanish are expected to
integrate into the mainstream Anglophone society just as much as immigrants
who speak Portuguese, Urdu or any other language. For a careful discussion of
this, see the article by de la Garza and Trujillo cited above.
11 I discuss this and other confusions regarding the term ‘multiculturalism’ in
Multicultural Citizenship, ch. 2.
12 Some national groups employ a descent-based definition of membership—e.g.
Germany; the Afrikaners in South Africa also have a descent-based conception of
national membership. This used to be true of French Canada as well, and twenty
per cent of Québécois still hold that immigrants cannot call themselves
Québécois, see Jean Crête and Jacques Zylberberg, ‘Une problématique floue:
l’autoreprésentation du citoyen au Quebec’, in Dominique Colas et al. (eds),
Citoyenneté et nationalite: Perspectives en France et au Quebec, Paris, Presses
Universitaires de France, 1991, pp. 425–30. However, the majority of
Quebecers, like most other national groups in the West, define membership in
terms of participation in a societal culture, not descent. On the increasing
140 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
disjunction between ethnic origin and language-group membership, see Leslie
Laczko, ‘Canada’s pluralism in comparative perspective’, Ethnic and Racial
Studies, vol. 17, no. 1, 1994, p. 29.
13 African-Americans are an important example of an ethnocultural group which
does not fit these categories. They do not fit the voluntary immigrant pattern,
not only because most were brought to America involuntarily as slaves, but also
because when they arrived they were prevented (rather than encouraged) from
integrating into the institutions of the majority culture (e.g. racial segregation;
laws against miscegenation and the teaching of literacy). Nor do they fit the
national minority pattern, since they do not have a homeland in America or a
common historical language.
They came from a variety of African cultures, with different languages, and no
attempt was made to keep together those with a common ethnic background. On
the contrary, people from the same culture (even from the same family) were
often split up once in America. And even if they shared the same African
language, slaves were forbidden to speak it, since slave-owners feared that such
speech could be used to foment rebellion. Moreover, before emancipation they
were legally prohibited from trying to recreate their own culture (e.g. all forms
of black association, except churches, were illegal). The historical situation of
African-Americans, therefore, is very unusual. They were not allowed to
integrate into the mainstream culture, nor were they allowed to maintain their
earlier languages and cultures, or to create new cultural associations and
institutions. They did not have their own homeland or territory, yet they were
physically segregated. So we should not expect policies which are appropriate for
either voluntary immigrants or national minorities to be appropriate for African-
Americans, or vice-versa. For a discussion of their unique status, and other
anomalous groups, see Multicultural Citizenship, chapters 2 and 5.
However, a recent survey of ethnocultural conflicts around the world suggests
that the two broad categories I have outlined do cover most groups involved in
these conflicts, see Ted Gurr, Minorities at Risk: A Global View of Ethnopolitical
Conflict, Washington DC, Institute of Peace Press, 1993.
14 Other characteristic features of federalism include the existence of a bicameral
legislature at the federal level, with the second cham ber intended to ensure effect ive
representation for the federal subunits in the central government. Thus, each
federal subunit is guaranteed representation in the second chamber, and smaller
subunits tend to be over-represented. Moreover, each subunit has a right to be
involved in the process of amending the federal constitution, but can unilaterally
amend its own constitution. In defining federalism in this manner, I am following
Wheare’s classic account, K.C.Wheare, Federal Government, New York, Oxford
University Press, 1964, 4th ed., chapters 1–2; cf. Jonathan Lemco, Political
Stability in Federal Governments, New York, Praeger, 1991, ch. 1. For a typology of
various ‘federal-type’ arrangements—which distinguishes federations from
confederations, consociations, federacies, legislative unions, associated states and
condominiums, see Elazar, Exploring Federalism, ch. 2.
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 141
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
15 On non-territorial forms of minority rights, see J.A.Laponce, ‘The government of
dispersed minorities: from Constantinople to Ottawa’, in Tamas Kozma and Peter
Drahos (eds), Divided Nations, Budapest, Educatio Publishing, 1993. On the
‘millet system’, see my ‘Two models of pluralism and tolerance’, Analyse & Kritik,
vol. 14/1, 1992, pp. 33–56.
16 I develop this at length (and discuss the few exceptions) in Multicultural Citizenship,
ch. 5, and ‘Social unity in a multiethnic state’, Social Philosophy and Policy, vol. 13/
1, 1996. Exceptions to this generalisation include certain immigrant-based
religious sects which seek to disassociate from the mainstream society.
17 For a defence of this claim, see Joseph Carens, ‘Membership and morality:
admission to citizenship in liberal democratic states’, in William Brubaker (ed.),
Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America, University
Press of America, 1989, pp. 31–49. Germany has recently amended its
naturalisation policies to make it easier for Turks to apply for citizenship,
although the application is still only approved on a selective and discretionary
basis, so that Turks still face great uncertainty about whether they will be able to
become equal participants in German society.
18 See the discussion of the ‘federalist revolution’ in Elazar, Exploring Federalism, ch.
1.
19 For a discussion of why national identity has been so enduring, and why national
minorities differ in this respect from immigrants, see Multicultural Citizenship,
chapters 5–6.
20 For the rest of the article, I will use the term ‘ethnonational’ in the context of
national minorities in a multination state, as distinct from the more general term
‘ethnocultural’, which encompasses both national minorities and immigrant
groups.
21 Alexander Hamilton, James Madison and John Jay, The Federalist Papers, New
York, Bantam, 1982. Jay not only ignores the sizeable black population, but also
pockets of non-English immigrants (particularly Germans), and the remnants of
Indian tribes who had been dispossessed of their lands.
22 Hence Nathan Glazer is quite wrong when he says that the division of the United
States into federal units preceded its ethnic diversity; see his Ethnic Dilemmas:
1964–1982, Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1983, pp. 276–77. This
is true of the original thirteen colonies, but decisions about the admission and
boundaries of new states were made after the incorporation of national
minorities, and these decisions were deliberately made so as to avoid creating
states dominated by national minorities.
23 See Barbara Thomas-Woolley and Edmond Keller, ‘Majority rule and minority
rights: American federalism and African experience’, Journal of Modern African
Studies, vol. 32, no. 3, 1994, pp. 416–17. Despite emphasising this difference
between the American experience and the situation of most multinational
federations, Thomas-Woolley and Keller do not, I think, fully consider its
implications for the relevance of the American model to other countries.
142 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
24 James Madison, The Federalist Papers, no. 10, New York, Bantam, 1982, pp. 54,
61. The belief that federalism helps prevent tyranny was one reason why
federalism was imposed by the Allies on Germany after World War II. It was
supposed to help prevent the re-emergence of nationalist or authoritarian
movements. For a critique of the claim that federalism is inherently more
protective of individual liberty, see Martha Minow, ‘Putting up and putting
down: tolerance reconsidered’, in Mark Tushnet (ed.), Comparative Constitutional
Federalism: Europe and America, New York, Greenwood, 1990, pp. 77–113; Franz
Neumann, ‘Federalism and freedom: a critique’, in Arthur MacMahon (ed.),
Federalism: Mature and Emergent, New York, Russell & Russell, 1962, pp. 44–57.
25 As he put it, ‘the most common and durable source of factions has been the
various and unequal distribution of property’. A lesser concern was the periodic
schisms within the Protestant churches, which often gave rise to upsurges of
religious conflict.
26 Philip Resnick, ‘Toward a multination federalism’, in Leslie Seidle (ed.), Seeking
a New Canadian Partnership: Asymmetrical and Confederal Options, Montreal, Institute
for Research on Public Policy, 1994, p. 71.
27 If the United States is the paradigm of territorial federalism, what is the prototype
of multinational federalism? Elazar argues that Switzerland is ‘the first modern
federation built upon indigenous ethnic and linguistic differences that were
considered permanent and worth accommodating’; see Daniel Elazar, ‘The Role
of federalism in political integration’, in D.Elazar (ed.), Federalism and Political
Integration, Ramat Gan, Turtledove Publishing, 1987, p. 20. Yet, as Murray
Forsyth notes, the old Swiss confederation, which existed for almost five hundred
years, was composed entirely of Germanic cantons, in terms of ethnic origin and
language. While French- and Italian-speaking cantons were added in 1815, the
decision to adopt a federal structure was not primarily taken to accommodate
these ethnolinguistic differences. According to Forsyth, the Canadian federation
of 1867 was the first case where a federal structure was adopted to accommodate
ethnocultural differences. This is reflected in the fact that the 1867 Constitution
not only united a number of separate provinces into one country, it also divided
the largest province into two separate political units—English-speaking Ontario
and French-speaking Quebec—to accommodate ethnocultural divisions, see
Murray Forsyth, ‘Introduction,’ in M.Forsyth (ed.), Federalism and Nationalism,
Leicester, Leicester University Press, 1989, pp. 3–4.
28 Some of the remaining fourteen Communities are not simply regional divisions,
but form culturally distinct societies, even if they are not self-identified as distinct
‘nations’. This is true, for example, of the Balearic Islands, Valencia and Asturias,
where distinct languages or dialects are spoken. But many of the Autonomous
Communities do not reflect distinct ethnocultural or linguistic groups. For a
discussion of Spain’s Autonomous Communities, and their varying levels of
ethnocultural distinctiveness, see Audrey Brassloff, ‘Spain: the state of the
autonomies’, in Forsyth (ed.), Federalism and Nationalism, pp. 24–50.
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 143
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
29 See Citizen’s Forum on Canada’s Future, Report to the People and Government of
Canada, Ottawa, Supply and Services, 1991, figure 2, p. 158. See also Philip
Resnick, p. 73, and the references in note 31 below.
30 See the references in note 5 above.
31 On English-Canadian opposition to special status, see Alan Cairns, ‘Constitutional
change and the three equalities’, in Ronald Watts and Douglas Brown (eds),
Options for a New Canada, University of Toronto Press, 1991, pp. 77–110; David
Milne, ‘Equality or asymmetry: why choose?’, in ibid., pp. 285–307; Andrew
Stark, ‘English-Canadian opposition to Quebec nationalism’, in R.Kent Weaver
(ed.), The Collapse of Canada?, Washington DC, Brookings Institution, 1992, pp.
123–58. Stephane Dion, ‘La fédéralisme fortement asymétrique’, in Seidle (ed.),
Seeking a New Canadian Partnership, pp. 133–52, cites a poll showing 83 per cent
opposition to special status. See also the articles by Resnick and Milne in ibid. A
certain amount of de facto asymmetry in powers has been a long-standing aspect
of Canadian federalism, but, as these authors discuss, most English-Canadians
have been unwilling to formally recognise or entrench this in the constitution, let
alone to extend it.
32 Brassloff, p. 44.
33 Charles Taylor, ‘Shared and divergent values’, in Ronald Watts and D.Brown (eds),
Options for a New Canada, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 1991, pp. 53–
76; Jeremy Webber, Reimagining Canada: Language, Culture Community and the
Canadian Constitution, Montreal, McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1994, pp.
232–51.
34 English-Canadians often say to Quebecers, ‘Why can’t we all be Canadians first,
and members of provinces second?’, without realising that this involves asking the
Québécois to subordinate their national identity, whereas for English-Canadians
it simply involves strengthening their national identity vis-à-vis their regional
identity.
35 Philip Resnick, p. 77.
36 As I note below (note 41), changes to the boundaries of the Northwest
Territories will soon create a new nationality-based unit, controlled by the Inuit,
to be known as ‘Nunavut’.
37 Petr Pithart, ‘Czechoslovakia: The loss of the old partnership’, in Seidle (ed.),
Seeking a New Canadian Partnership, p. 164.
38 M.Fernandez, quoted in Brassloff, p. 35
39 For an attempt to develop a workable model of asymmetrical federal
representation, see Philip Resnick, op. cit; cf. my ‘Group representation in
Canadian politics’, in Leslie Seidle (ed.), Equity and Community: The Charter,
Interest Advocacy, and Representation, Montreal, Institute for Research on Public
Policy, 1993, pp. 61–89.
40 For a survey of various forms of asymmetrical federalism, see Elazar, Exploring
Federalism, pp. 54–7; and Dion, op. cit.
41 Two exceptions would be the Navaho in the American Southwest, and the Inuit
in the Canadian Northwest. And indeed the boundaries of the Northwest
144 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
Territories in Canada are being redrawn so as to create an Inuit-majority unit
within the federation.
42 Elazar, Exploring Federalism, p. 229. For the relation of Indian self-government to
federalism, see Frank Cassidy and Robert Bish, Indian Government: Its Meaning in
Practice, Halifax, Institute for Research on Public Policy, 1989; J.A.Long,
‘Federalism and ethnic self-determination: native Indians in Canada’, Journal of
Commonwealth and Comparative Politics, vol. 29/2, 1991, pp. 192–211; Judith
Resnik, ‘Dependent sovereigns’; David Elkins, Where Should the Majority Rule?
Reflections on Non-Territorial Provinces and Other Constitutional Proposals, University of
Alberta, Centre for Constitutional Studies, 1992.
43 On Puerto Rico’s status, and the limits of potential statehood, see Alvin
Rubinstein, ‘Is statehood for Puerto Rico in the national interest?’, In Depth: A
Journal for Values and Public Policy, Spring 1993, pp. 87–99; Aleinikoff, op. cit.
44 The right of national groups to self-determination is affirmed in international law.
According to the United Nations Charter, for example, ‘all peoples have the right
to self-determination’. However, the UN has not defined ‘peoples’, and it has
generally applied the principle of self-determination only to overseas colonies, not
internal national minorities, even when the latter were subject to the same sort of
colonisation and conquest as the former. This limitation on self-determination to
overseas colonies (known as the ‘saltwater thesis’) is widely seen as arbitrary,
and many national minorities insist that they too are ‘peoples’ or ‘nations’, and,
as such, have the right of self-determination.
45 I should emphasise that I am speaking of political perceptions, not historical facts.
A rigorous historical examination may show that the existence of the national
minority as a separate people did not predate that of the larger country. In some
cases, the sense of national distinctiveness arose concurrently with the
development of the larger federation, rather than preceding it, so that the
original formation of the larger country was not, historically speaking, a
‘federation of peoples’. While nationalist leaders often imply that their nation has
existed since time immemorial, historians have shown that the sense of national
distinctiveness is often quite recent, and indeed deliberately invented; see
Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of
Nationalism, London, New Left Books, 1983; Ernest Gellner, Nations and
Nationalism, Oxford, Blackwell, 1983. What matters, however, is not historical
reality, but present-day perceptions. If a minority group today has a strong sense
of national identity, and a strong belief in its right of self-government, then it will
tend to view the federation as having only derivative authority, whatever the
historical facts.
46 I noted earlier that immigrants are increasingly demanding special political
recognition in the form of certain ‘polyethnic’ rights. But this is rarely a threat to
political stability, since in making these demands, immigrants generally take the
authority of the larger political community for granted. They assume, as John
Rawls puts it, that citizens are members of ‘one co-operative scheme in
perpetuity’ (A Theory of Justice, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972).
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 145
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
Immigrants assume that they will work within the economic and political
institutions of the larger society, demanding only that these institutions be
adapted to reflect the increasing cultural diversity of the population they serve.
National minorities, by contrast, question the legitimacy and permanence of the
larger country.
47 To reduce this danger, federal governments have encouraged national minorities
to identify with, and feel loyalty towards, the federal government. This new
identification, it is hoped, would then compete with, and possibly even
supersede, their original national identity. However, the historical record
suggests that these efforts have limited success. See, on this, Kenneth Wheare,
‘Federalism and the making of nations’, in A.MacMahon (ed.), Federalism Mature
and Emergent, pp. 28–43; Robert Howse and Karen Knop, ‘Federalism, secession,
and the limits of ethnic accommodation: a Canadian perspective’, New Europe Law
Review, vol. 1/2, 1993, pp. 269–320; Wayne Norman, ‘Towards a normative
theory of federalism’, in Judith Baker (ed.), Group Rights, University of Toronto
Press, 1994; and my Multicultural Citizenship, cit., ch. 9.
48 Of course, this is only a prima facie claim, since the territory encompassed by the
federal subunit may include the homeland of other national groups. This is a
serious issue in Quebec, where the northern part of the province is the historic
homeland of various indigenous peoples. These indigenous groups argue that
their right of self-determination is as strong as that of the Québécois, and that if
Quebecers vote to secede, they may decide to stay in Canada, so that an
independent Quebec would only include the southern part of the province. See,
on this, Mary Ellen Turpel, ‘Does the road to Quebec sovereignty run through
Aboriginal territory?’, in D.Drache and R.Perin (ed.), Negotiating with a Sovereign
Quebec, Toronto, Lorimer, 1992.
49 On the importance of external threats in the formation and maintenance of
federations, see Lemco, op. cit., chapter 8. This is particularly important for
understanding the Swiss federation. Switzerland is often cited as an example of a
stable multinational federation, with a strong sense of shared loyalty. But what
made the development of a Swiss patriotism possible was the shared experience,
over some five hundred years, of having common enemies, and having to rely on
each other’s military support. Insofar as international bodies reduce the threat of
war, the result, paradoxically, may be to undermine one of the few factors which
supported the development of stable multinational federations.
50 Pithart, p. 198.
51 For example, even if Canadian federalism eventually fails, it would not have been
a moral failure. On the contrary, I would argue that it has been a remarkable
moral success (whatever happens with Quebec), since it has enabled Canadians to
achieve prosperity and freedom with an almost complete absence of violence.
Moreover, federalism has made possible the development of strong liberal and
democratic traditions within both English and French Canada. As a result, should
Canadian federalism fail, the result would almost surely be two peaceful and
prosperous liberal democracies where there used to be one. Multinational
146 WILL KYMLICKA
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
federalism in Canada may prove to be just a transitional phase between British
colonisation and the birth of two independent liberal-de mocratic states; if so, it will
have been a good midwife. For a more detailed evaluation of the prospects for
federalism in Canada, see my Finding Our Way: Ethnocultural Relations in Canada,
Toronto, Oxford University Press, forthcoming.
52 In developing his well-known contractarian theory of distributive justice, John
Rawls argued that the parties to the social contract should view themselves as
members of ‘one co-operative scheme in perpetuity’. This might be a reasonable
assumption in the case of unitary states or territorial federations. But it is not a
plausible assumption, either sociologically or morally, in the case of multinational
federations.
IS FEDERALISM A VIABLE ALTERNATIVE TO SECESSION? 147
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.
148
Theories of Secession, edited by Percy B. Lehning, Taylor & Francis Group, 1998. ProQuest Ebook Central,
http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/queen-ebooks/detail.action?docID=237431.
Created from queen-ebooks on 2021-08-17 18:14:41.
Copyright © 1998. Taylor & Francis Group. All rights reserved.