ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

Nation-states' "boundaries" are produced in time: around official working hours and terms of office, for instance, and in the historico-mythic " life of the nation. " Global human rights practices affirm and depend on nation-states' temporal authority, while also calling that authority into question. In different ways, global markets do likewise. In recent decades, the ubiquity of both finance capital and international human rights law, among other factors, may have encouraged the fracturing of time into intervals of ever-decreasing length. Temporal authority premised on the long term seems to have declining purchase, even as historicism and futurism abound, discouraging some modes of state-based politics associated with the long-term. In this context, international human rights law advocates seem increasingly preoccupied with the propagation of human rights concerns in " real time. " This orientation carries some peril, especially vis-à-vis its articulation with the temporalities of global finance capital. Even so, there is still time for political intervention on this uneven temporal terrain. Such intervention may be occasioned, this article argues, by reading international human rights law anachronistically, and reactivating the times and rhythms of the global economy, and of the nation-state, as political questions of the first order.
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
The Temporal Rivalries of Human Rights
FLEUR JOHNS
ABSTRACT
Nation-states’ “boundaries” are produced in time: around official working
hours and terms of office, for instance, and in the historico-mythic “life of the
nation.” Global human rights practices affirm and depend on nation-states’
temporal authority, while also calling that authority into question. In different
ways, global markets do likewise. In recent decades, the ubiquity of both
finance capital and international human rights law, among other factors, may
have encouraged the fracturing of time into intervals of ever-decreasing
length. Temporal authority premised on the long term seems to have declining
purchase, even as historicism and futurism abound, discouraging some modes
of state-based politics associated with the long-term. In this context,
international human rights law advocates seem increasingly preoccupied with
the propagation of human rights concerns in “real time.” This orientation
carries some peril, especially vis-à-vis its articulation with the temporalities
of global finance capital. Even so, there is still time for political intervention
on this uneven temporal terrain. Such intervention may be occasioned, this
article argues, by reading international human rights law anachronistically,
and reactivating the times and rhythms of the global economy, and of the
nation-state, as political questions of the first order.
INTRODUCTION
“While the council remains an imperfect body, we have seen distinct progress in
terms of its ability to respond to happenings in the world [with respect to human
rights] in real time,” [the U.S. ambassador to the UN Human Rights Council, Eileen
Donahoe told reporters.] “There is more shared common ground here than people
realize.”1
The “common ground” to which global international human rights law lays claim
today is, at least in part, temporally comprized. That which bearers and guardians of rights try
to hold together is less any single measure of value than a sense of unavoidable coincidence
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
Professor of Law, UNSW Australia. I am indebted to Daniel Augenstein and Hans Lindahl for the invitation
to develop a paper for the colloquium, Global Human Rights Law and the Boundaries of Statehood, held at
the Stellenbosch Institute of Advanced Study in March 2015 at which a prior version of this article was
presented, both for that invitation and for generous and insightful editorial feedback. I am grateful also to the
participants in that colloquium for their questions and suggestions, as I am to the organizers and audience
members of the UNSW Law Staff Seminar and the University of Melbourne Legal Theory Forum at which prior
versions of this paper were presented. Particular thanks are due to Cait Storr for her input as commentator and
respondent at the latter event, to Ben Golder, Lucas Lixinski, John Morss, and Rosalind Dixon for comments,
and to the editorial staff of the Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies.
1Editorial, The United Nations’ Human ‘Rights’ Council, WASH. POST, Mar. 27, 2011, at A18, available at
http://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/the-united-nations-human-rights-
council/2011/03/25/AFSRyPeB_story.html.
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
in more or less the same time frame (an effort that often fails, as discussed below). That this
coincidental time frame may be striated zonally, squared against disparate pasts and futures,
and punctuated by events evoking variable degrees and durations of concern, need not alter
its scaffolding cogency in and for international human rights law, if only it could be
sustained. Much has been made, for instance, of prospects for global human rights to unfold
“in real time”—that is, amid the sense of informational concurrence to which rapid data
processing, crowd-sourced reporting, and remote-sensing capacities afford ever more ready
access.2
Technological capacities notwithstanding, co-occurrence in time at any scale may
arguably have become harder to sustain in recent decades, especially on the temporal terrain
of statehood. Scholarly literature has recorded a “declining temporal authority of states”
before the rhythms of global finance capital.3 In light of such claims, this article asks the
following questions: to what extent, if at all, does international human rights law install or
assert rival temporalities to those commonly associated with, and mobilized for and through,
the nation-state? How might any such rival temporalities relate to the times and timings of
global finance capital? What, moreover, may be some ramifications of such rivalries for those
engaged in international legal work?
Part I of this article reviews temporal dimensions of international law writ broadly,
including international human rights law. It considers some of the functions of time and
timing in and for international law and the different forms that international legal temporality
may take. In Part II, comparison is made to time and timings characteristic of the nation-state
and the practice of assembling and maintaining nation-state authority temporally. In relation
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
2 Joanna Naples-Mitchell, Perspectives of UN Special Rapporteurs on Their Role: Inherent Tensions and
Unique Contributions to Human Rights, 15 INTL J. HUM. RTS. 232, 232-33, 244 (2011). See generally Real
Time Definition, OED ONLINE, http://www.oed.com/viewdictionaryentry/Entry/238662 (last visited Dec. 2014)
(“The actual time during which a process or event occurs, esp. one analysed by a computer, in contrast to time
subsequent to it when processing may be done, a recording replayed, etc.”).
3 Wayne Hope, Conflicting Temporalities: State, Nation, Economy and Democracy Under Global Capitalism,
18 TIME & SOCY 62, 78 (2009).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
to both of these temporal styles or endeavors, this article then, in Part III, reflects on the
declining credibility of the long-term over the course of the twentieth century, observing that
there may have been, in many respects, contraction in the temporal intervals of public
concern and experience. 4
Against this background, as I argue in Part IV, international human rights law is
advanced as a somewhat untimely discipline, not subscribing consistently either to the
temporal templates of the nation-state, nor to the accelerated rhythms and shortened spans of
the global market. Instead, international human rights law doctrine and practice—exemplified
here by the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR)—seems to foster
temporal fitfulness.5 At times, international human rights law work links, sequences, and
periodizes; elsewhere it seeks to arrest a temporal flow. Paradoxically, this fitful temporality
of international human rights law may be less about confirming rightful time—a temporality
that is “on the right path”—than a matter of insistently evoking the “disjuncture of the unjust”
through repeated alignments with, and disarticulations from, other temporal registers.6
For purposes of this argument, temporalities characteristic of the nation-state, global
finance capital or the global market, and international human rights law, respectively, are
sketched quite schematically and posited as rivals, even as complicity and reliance among
them are made apparent. In so doing, this article’s aims are two-fold. On one hand, this
triptychal re-description is intended to sharpen the visibility of relations between these
phenomena, and thereby to counter any sense that the discipline of international human rights
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
4 This is not a claim that may be verified or proven on the basis of material presented in this article. Rather, this
article relies, in Part III, upon scholarship drawn from a range of fields that is suggestive of this prospect.
Moreover, it is not essential to the argument of this article that concern for the long-term be in decline as a
general matter, for all times and for all peoples everywhere. Examples of countering tendencies are doubtless
readily available.
5 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A (XXI), U.N. Doc. A/6316 (Dec. 16,
1966) [hereinafter ICCPR] (detailing a series of agreed-upon human rights propositions, focused primarily on
freedom and equality).
6 JACQUES DERRIDA, SPECTERS OF MARX: THE STATE OF THE DEBT, THE WORK OF MOURNING, AND THE NEW
INTERNATIONAL 20-22 (Peggy Kamuf trans., Routledge 1994) (1993).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
law militates, necessarily, against the nation-state or the market.7 On the other hand, their
stylized separation is designed to recover some prospect that international human rights law
might, nonetheless, retain rivalrous potential—that is, that it might still provoke the
disjuncture of the unjust alluded to above.
In Part V, finally, this article will explore how international human rights law as a
discipline remains, nonetheless, preoccupied with trying to engender regular temporal
rhythms more or less of its own production. In past decades, this has been bound up with the
professionalization and global propagation of the human rights enterprise. More recently,
however, effort has been directed towards that enterprise’s decentralization and reseeding,
including through the cultivation of itinerant temporalities capable of lodging within and
moving with a crowd. It is with a critique of this aspiration—for human rights capable of
gathering in “real time”—with which this article will close, amid speculation as to what this
might demand of those who would engage in international human rights law work and whose
rights they would defend.
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
7 For evidence of a still-subsisting tendency to characterize international human rights law as opposed to the
imperatives of the nation-state and the global market, see, e.g., Louis Henkin, Human Rights and State
Sovereignty, 25 GA. J. INTL & COMP. L. 31 (1995); Frank J. García, The Global Market and Human Rights:
Trading Away the Human Rights Principle, 25 BROOK. J. INTL L. 51, 53 (1999).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
I. TEMPORALITIES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
Time is often cast—alongside space—as international law’s background, or as the
medium in which international legal relations and conduct are “set.”8 This is related to the
propensity, since the nineteenth century, to set law in context amid the social.9 “Society . . .
[effects] a conceptual union of time and place”; in many scholars’ accounts, law inhabits this
unity as a phenomenon in and of the social.10 As Carol Greenhouse has shown, the
temporalities of law’s social settings—and hence law’s own temporalities—have often been
thought by recourse to Emile Durkheim’s notion of collective, symbolic “social time.”11
Yet timing is also a technique of international law: international law is a shaper of
time and a connector and divider of times. International law sequences time and distributes
humans and nonhumans within those sequences, according to narratives of progress,
modernity, and development.12 International law maps time onto the surface of the Earth:
Greenwich Mean Time and the international dateline are products of international treaty
making and the work of international organizations.13 International law gathers people into
the urgent temporality of crisis; indeed, some are lawfully consigned to conditions of
“permanent crisis.”14 It also fences people in deadlines, and channels work in a far more
mundane register: by establishing continuous cycles of reporting and review under
international human rights treaties, for instance.15
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
8 Keebet von Benda-Beckmann, Trust and the Temporalities of Law, 46 J. LEGAL PLURALISM & UNOFFICIAL L.
1, 2 (2014).
9 Cf. Duncan Kennedy, Three Globalizations of Law and Legal Thought: 18502000, in THE NEW LAW AND
ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT: A CRITICAL APPRAISAL 19, 19-22 (David M. Trubek & Alvaro Santos eds., 2006)
(describing the formalistic, classical legal thought of the late nineteenth century and early twentieth century and
the socially oriented legal thought of the twentieth century, and how these two schools gave way to modern
legal thought). See generally BRUNO LATOUR, REASSEMBLING THE SOCIAL: AN INTRODUCTION TO ACTOR-
NETWORK-THEORY (2005) (making a sustained critique of the enterprise of “social explanation,” including by
reference to “context”).
10 Carol J. Greenhouse, Just in Time: Temporality and the Cultural Legitimation of Law, 98 YALE L.J. 1631,
1638 (1989).
11 Carol J. Greenhouse, Time’s Up, Timed Out: Reflections on Social Time and Legal Pluralism, 46 J. LEGAL
PLURALISM & UNOFFICIAL L. 141, 141 (2014) (quoting EMILE DURKHEIM, THE ELEMENTARY FORMS OF
RELIGIOUS LIFE (Karen Fields trans., Free Press 1995) (1912)).
12 See generally THOMAS SKOUTERIS, THE NOTION OF PROGRESS IN INTERNATIONAL LAW DISCOURSE (2010)
(discussing and challenging what is labeled as progress in the international law context).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
International legal temporalities are often linear and oriented around the point in time:
the definite duration or the time-limited procedure; that is, the time of calendar and clock.
Consider the dating and timing of treaties’ entry into force, for example, or the insistence that
International Court of Justice decisions bind only those who come before the court in a
“particular case.”16 Consider, too, Bin Cheng’s famous contraction of customary international
lawmaking into instant custom.17
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
13 See, e.g., Francis Deák, Computation of Time in International Law, 20 AM J. INTL L. 502, 515 (1926);
George Grafton Wilson, Editorial Comment, Time and International Law, 34 AM J. INTL L. 496, 497 (1940).
14 Massimiliano Tomba, Clash of Temporalities: Capital, Democracy, and Squares, 113 S. ATLANTIC Q. 353,
354 (2014); see Hilary Charlesworth, International Law: A Discipline of Crisis, 65 MOD. L. REV. 377, 377
(2002) (discussing how international lawyers focus on crises).
15 The Universal Periodic Review mechanism of the United Nations Human Rights Council is one prominent
example. See generally Edward McMahon & Marta Ascherio, A Step Ahead in Promoting Human Rights? The
Universal Periodic Review of the UN Human Rights Council, 18 GLOBAL GOVERNANCE 231 (2012) (discussing
the Universal Periodic Review, a UN system by which states can make recommendations to each other about
human rights practices).
16 Statute of the International Court of Justice art. 59, June 26, 1945, 33 U.N.T.S. 993; see ANTHONY AUST,
MODERN TREATY LAW AND PRACTICE 168-71 (2d ed., 2007); see also Liaquat Ali Khan, Temporality of Law,
40 MCGEORGE L. REV. 55, 59-69 (2009) (breaking down temporality into points in time and duration, for legal
purposes).
17 See Bin Cheng, Custom: The Future of General State Practice in a Divided World, in THE STRUCTURE AND
PROCESS OF INTERNATIONAL LAW: ESSAYS IN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY DOCTRINE AND THEORY 513, 536 (R. St.J.
Macdonald & Douglas M. Johnston eds., 1983) (describing the Barcelona Declaration as an example of the
author’s belief that international law is created instantly by changes in what states accept and subscribe to as the
law).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
Even so, international law speaks in and to durations of unspecified length and
nonlinear dimensions: in the jurisdictional notion of “continuing acts” (where the conduct in
question commenced before the existence of the norm allegedly violated, but continued after
it came into effect);18 in limitations periods, which bar claims due to the passage of time; and
in the doctrine of intertemporal law, which requires “judicial fact[s]” to be “appreciated in the
light of the law contemporary with [them].”19 International law also extricates itself
recurrently from the movement of time; international human rights law especially: it asserts
the timelessness of its concerns, all the while worrying incessantly about its want of
timeliness and its need to “catch up.”20
The temporalities of international law are thus multiple and misaligned. Just as there
is no “general history,” so there is no general temporality of international lawfulness.21
Indeed, assertions of overarching, free-floating temporality remain troubling, insofar as they
prompt divergences to be experienced in terms of objectively ascribed “backwardness” and
“advancement,” the harms of which are well documented.22 If advocates of international law
nonetheless exhibit a common temporal disposition, this may be discerned in the aspiration to
link up disparate times and timings—in the impulse to join things together and thereby to
enjoin unlawfulness.23
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
18+Rosalyn Higgins, Time and the Law: International Perspectives on an Old Problem, 46 INTL & COMP. L.Q.
501, 506 (1997).
19 United States v. Netherlands, Hague Ct. Rep. 2d (Scott) 83, at 845 (Perm. Ct. Arb. 1928).
20 See, e.g., Christoph Bezemek et al., Topics in International Human Rights Protection, 7 VIENNA J. ON INTL
CONST. L. 127, 127 (2013) (describing freedom of communication as a “timeless, . . . never outdated topic in
human rights protection”); Colin B. Picker, A View from 40,000 Feet: International Law and the Invisible Hand
of Technology, 23 CARDOZO L. REV. 149, 184 (2001) (“Normally, delay is the rule in the formation of
international law.”).
21 JACQUES DERRIDA, POSITIONS 50 (Alan Bass trans., Continuum 2d English ed. 2004) (1972) (commenting on
Althusser’s critique of an Hegelian notion of history).
22 ANTONY ANGHIE, IMPERIALISM, SOVEREIGNTY AND THE MAKING OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 189 (2005); cf.
Louis Althusser, The Object of Capital, in READING CAPITAL 71, 106 (Ben Brewster trans., New Left Books
1970) (1968) (“[I]t is only in the specific unity of the complex structure of the whole that we can think the
concept of these so-called backwardnesses, forwardnesses, survivals and unevennesses of development which
co-exist in the structure of the real historical present . . . .”). Note the “whole” here is a contingent social
formation: a “structural unity” that “contain[s] what can be called levels or instances which are distinct and
‘relatively autonomous’ . . . [but nonetheless] articulated with one another.” Althusser, supra, at 97.
23 Cf. DERRIDA, supra note 6, at 25 (“The thinking of the jointure is also a thinking of injunction.”).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
II. STATE TIMES
To a significant degree, these rivalrous international legal temporalities pivot around
the politico-legal figure of the nation-state and the temporalities constituting and sustained by
it. The “structure of feeling” instilled by and for the nation-state has a significant temporal
dimension.24 The latter—the temporality of the national—has, in Saskia Sassen’s estimation,
“remained submerged, an unnamed condition . . . partly because it is our given condition, the
assumed temporality of much social scientific practice” and, I would add, much legal practice
as well.25 Nation-state time is produced in social and legal knowledge practices, but often
tends to be illegible to them.26
Among those submerged temporalities, the generation of “synchronic” experience—a
sense of parallelism or simultaneity among those spread across great distances and divergent
geographic and life conditions—has been essential to the nation-state’s creation, prevalence
and endurance.27 Time had to be made cohabitable among scattered strangers in order for the
nation-state to attain the dominance that it did between 1500 and 1800, and for humans to
experience themselves as nation-bound “populations” or aspirants to that status.28 It was only
through “an accumulation of technological innovations in the fields of shipbuilding,
navigation, horology and cartography, mediated through print-capitalism” that “this type of
imagining [became] possible.”29
Yet state time has significant diachronic dimensions as well. Many have shown the
importance of the telling of history and myth to the ongoing project of nation-state making
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
24 Ana María Alonso, The Politics of Space, Time and Substance: State Formation, Nationalism and Ethnicity,
23 ANN. REV. ANTHROPOLOGY 379, 386-90 (1994).
25 Saskia Sassen, Spatialities and Temporalities of the Global: Elements for a Theorization, 12 PUB. CULTURE
215, 223 (2000).
26 Cf. Althusser, supra note 22, at 101 (discussing the “invisible time” of capitalist economic production, and
how that time system is not apparent to those in the system creating it).
27 BENEDICT ANDERSON, IMAGINED COMMUNITIES 188 (rev. ed., 1991) (1983).
28 On the emergence of the phenomenon of the “population,” see MICHEL FOUCAULT, SECURITY, TERRITORY,
POPULATION: LECTURES AT THE COLLÈGE DE FRANCE 1977-1978, at 42-45, 66-79 (Michel Senellart et al. eds.,
Graham Burchell, trans., 2007) (2004).
29 ANDERSON, supra note 27.
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
and remaking.30 Indeed, this is the way in which the temporality of nation-statehood has most
commonly been thought. As Tim Edensor has observed, “accounts of the temporal
constitution of national identities continue to focus upon common traditions, myths of shared
descent, and the linking of historical and future narratives.”31 Both historico-mythic time and
the presumed copresence of the nation-state in turn evoke and rely upon an “ideological base
time”: an undifferentiated emptiness or unity, through which people and things may pass, or
in which they may be held for a time.32
However empty it may seem, this “base time” underpinning the authority of the
nation-state is itself sequenced and sectioned also according to temporalities of office,
planning, and indebtedness: temporalities differentiated on their face. Such sequences include
the term of service, the duration of appointment, or the maturity of sovereign bonds. In
democratic states, time is parceled out according to the election cycle. In all political settings,
year-on-year budget cycles tend to set the national rhythm. In most settings, furthermore,
state time corresponds to budgetary and policy planning periods of longer duration, both
domestic and international: five-year plans, for example, or the pre- and post-2015 planning
and measurement surrounding the Millennium Development Goals.33
National temporalities are comprised, too, of the everyday reproduced mundanely as
“experience”—the everyday of public servants, for instance. This mode of temporality is
most obviously synchronic, but generates a sense of base time as well. Conventionally, state
time has been imagined as “slow moving” thanks to the “rule-bound public accountability of
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
30 See, e.g., ANTHONY D. SMITH, NATIONAL IDENTITY 66 (Univ. of Nev. Press 1993) (1991) (explaining the use
of history and myth as becoming inherent to a country’s ethnic character).
31 Tim Edensor, Reconsidering National Temporalities: Institutional Times, Everyday Routines, Serial Spaces
and Synchronicities, 9 EUR. J. SOC. THEORY 525, 527 (2006).
32 Althusser, supra note 22, at 104-05.
33 See, e.g., Peter T.Y. Cheung, China’s Changing Regional Development: Trends, Strategies and Challenges in
the 12th Five-Year Plan (2011-2015) Period, 53 ASIA PAC. VIEWPOINT 1, 1 (2012); Francis Collins & David
Galas, A New Five-Year Plan for the U.S. Human Genome Project, 262 SCIENCE 43, 46 (1993); Chris Ham,
Another Five Year Plan for the NHS, 340 BRIT. MED. J. 5, 5-6 (2010); U.N. Economic and Social Council,
Millennium Development Goals and Post-2015 Development Agenda,
http://www.un.org/en/ecosoc/about/mdg.shtml (last visited June 12, 2015).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
governmental processes.”34 Yet this impression may have little or no grounding in the recent
experience of government employees under pressure from incentive structures, efficiency
demands, and austerity measures.35 Increasingly, state time is the defined contract period of a
consultant’s assignment. Likewise, it may be inapt to characterize contemporary democracy
as proceeding at the “leisurely pace” of “deliberation.”36 Rather, it seems just as fitting to
temporalize democracy by reference to the 150- to 250-hertz refresh rate of an LCD screen.
Mundane temporalities comprising “base” experiences of nationhood are not,
moreover, solely the preserve of those in governmental employ. The everyday of state time is
composed just as much of broadcasting schedules, speed restrictions, opening and trading
hours, and the cycle of national holidays: all established by national or subnational law.37
Through both official and unofficial routinization, “national synchronicity is achieved
[among a populace] through temporal customs about when and where specific social
practices should occur.”38 Yet temporalities of national habit also diverge: the public holiday
may pass without notice for those on “flexible” work schedules and those engaged in
subsistence production or other forms of unpaid work.39 The maintenance of state time may
be less about the synchronization (or making diachronic) of time across any one national
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
34 Sassen, supra note 25, at 224.
35 See generally+DONALD F. KETTL, THE TRANSFORMATION OF GOVERNANCE: PUBLIC ADMINISTRATION FOR
TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY AMERICA (2002) (explaining that the study of public administration is out of sync with
its actual practice); Stephen Bach, Shrinking the State or the Big Society? Public Service Employment Relations
in an Era of Austerity, 43 INDUS. REL. J. 399 (2012) (considering the origins of Big Society and its
consequences on public service and the workforce in the UK); Peter Leisink & Stephen Bach, Economic Crisis
and Municipal Public Service Employment: Comparing Developments in Seven EU Member States, 20
TRANSFER 327 (2014) (examining the impact of austerity policies on municipal employment).
36 Contra Sheldon Wolin, What Time Is It?, THEORY & EVENT (1997),
https://muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_and_event/v001/1.1wolin.html.
37 See Edensor, supra note 31, at 530-31.
38 Id. at 534.
39 See generally Nancy Folbre, The Care Economy in Africa: Subsistence Production and Unpaid Care, 23 J.
AFR. ECON. (SUPPLEMENT 1) i128 (2014) (analyzing the care economy in Africa, including subsistence farming
and caring for dependents); Janice Peterson & Barbara Wiens-Tuers, Work Time, Gender, and Inequality: The
Conundrums of Flexibility, 48 J. ECON. ISSUES 387 (2014) (discussing flexible work schedules in the United
States, with a particular focus on the impact on women workers).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
population than the attempt to smooth over irrepressible temporal disjuncture or to organize
such disjunctions in and around relatively stable spatio-temporal containers.40
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
40 See Tomba, supra note 14, at 355 (discussing the difficulties that the diverging temporalities of democratic
processes and capital present to governments).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
III. THE DEMISE OF THE LONG-TERM
Among the conditions of possibility for these contemporary legal temporalities and
their spatio-temporal organization is the declining credibility of long-term planning and
prediction over the course of the twentieth century. This decline has political,
epistemological, cultural, technological, and economic dimensions.
Politically and epistemologically, the figure of the long-term planner and the viability
of his or her predictive foresight has come under attack from both the right and the left.
Friedrich Hayek famously cast doubt on the capacity for any human to comprehend or direct
the “catallaxy” or “spontaneous order of the market” over any length of time.41 Hayek was
not, of course, averse to planning, provided that it was “good planning.” That is, it needed to
be “wise and foresighted” enough to focus on enhancing competition rather then prescribing
distributive outcomes to be realized at an “appointed time,” or insisting on common ideals or
objects to be pursued by all “at the same time.”42 In Hayek’s account, unification in planned
time signified a loss of liberty through circumscription of choice, as well as a disregard for
the imperfection of knowledge. Hayek’s purported adversary in economic thought, John
Maynard Keynes, likewise cast the future as radically unknowable and highlighted the
relativity of time measurement.43
On the left of social and political thought, temporality has been fractured and
particularized. In Louis Althusser’s account, for instance, “peculiar time[s] and histor[ies]”
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
41 2 F. A. HAYEK, The Market Order or Catallaxy, in LAW, LEGISLATION, AND LIBERTY 107, 108-09, 128-29
(1976).
42 F. A. HAYEK, THE ROAD TO SERFDOM 36, 55, 104 (1944).
43 Cf. Mogens Ove Madsen, Keynes’s Early Cognition of the Concept of Time, in KEYNESS GENERAL THEORY
FOR TODAY 98, 106-09 (Jesper Jespersen & Mogens Ove Madsen eds., 2012) (discussing how Keynes
developed a dynamic notion of time). Hayek and Keynes are described as purported adversaries because the
relationship of neoliberal (including Hayekian) thought to Keynesian thought and policy cannot be characterized
as one of straightforward opposition. Hayek’s ally Milton Friedman emphasized, for example, “what a great
economist Keynes was and how much more [Friedman] sympathize[d] with his approach and aims than those of
many of [Keynes’] followers.” Milton Friedman, Comments on the Critics, 80 J. POL. ECON. 906, 908 (1972).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
were rethought as the outcome of distinct modes of production.44 Althusser’s paired critiques
of empiricism and historicism demanded a notion of differential time that could neither be
read off the surface of events, nor understood as the continuity in which events occurred.
Rather, according to Samuel Chambers, Althusser construed temporality as “emanating from
the structure of the social formation.”45
Communication and cultural practices have also reinforced a sense of long-term
planning as declining in cogency and coherence. In the course of historicizing this decline
(rather ironically), Frederic Jameson has observed: “it is scarcely fair to expect long-term
projections . . . from minds trained in the well-nigh synchronic habits of zero-sum calculation
and of keeping an eye on profits,” all while subscribing to “pattern[s] of immediacies” in
daily life—calling people rather than making appointments, for instance.46 To Jameson, the
“end of temporality” staged in art and literature after modernism, and an associated
“reduction to the present and . . . to the body,” express the unrealizable aspirations of late
capitalism.47
However one casts the causal dice, “patterns of immediacies” have certainly
flourished and spread under late capitalism. Accelerated processing capacities and remote-
sensing and robotics technologies have been coproduced with a just-in-time preoccupation in
manufacturing, distribution, labor, and servicing. As supply chains have dispersed globally,
temporal sequencing and coordination have demanded far greater attention and effort than
ever before. Logistics—the “banal and technocratic management of the movement of
stuff”48—may have become “the central discipline of the contemporary world” in commercial
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
44 Althusser, supra note 22, at 99.
45 Samuel A. Chambers, Untimely Politics avant la lettre: The Temporality of Social Formations, 20 TIME &
SOCY 197, 208 (2011).
46+Fredric Jameson, The End of Temporality, 29 CRITICAL INQUIRY 695, 705-07, (2003).+
47 Id. at 717.
48+DEBORAH COWEN, THE DEADLY LIFE OF LOGISTICS 4 (2014).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
as much as military endeavors.49 With this has thrived a sense of time as among the elements
of the “stuff” to be managed and moved, typically with a view to minimizing stoppages and
friction.50 That “seamless” global supply chains often turn out to be “messy and violent” in
operation need not dissipate the sense of time as an endless series of micro-instances to be
smoothed, linked, and aligned. Indeed, awareness of messiness and violence may, in fact,
intensify such preoccupations.51
As noted at the outset, global financial practices have also intensified this orientation
towards intervals of ever-decreasing length. As Wayne Hope has described, “[t]he real time
profit making of financialized capitalism preclude[s] reflection on the volatilities of economic
history and the uncertainties of future economic developments” and creates conflict with
“longer term rhythms of capital accumulation centred upon production, commodity exchange
and aggregate demand.”52 The increased popularity of mathematical methods in finance from
the 1970s onwards, and the rise of automated trading, have also been associated with a
contraction in time intervals measured or modeled to the point of the infinitesimal.
Continuous-time methods, assuming that the value of particular variables is continuously
changing, have increasingly been deployed in the valuation of derivatives and other financial
instruments in asset pricing and portfolio optimization.53 More recently, the use of software
algorithms to identify and execute transactions has come to dominate securities trading.54 In
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
49 NIGEL THRIFT, NON-REPRESENTATIONAL THEORY: SPACE, POLITICS, AFFECT 95 (2008).
50+COWEN, supra note 48, at 93.
51 Id.
52 Wayne Hope, Crisis of Temporalities: Global Capitalism After the 2007-08 Financial Collapse, 20 TIME &
SOCY 94, 101, 106 (2011); see also Hope, supra note 3, at 67 (criticizing trends in global capitalism and
finance as setting the stage for currency crises). This may be less the case in certain industriesin the energy
and natural resources sector, for instancealthough these sectors may not be immune to managerial “short-
termism”. See generally Kevin J. Laverty, Managerial Myopia or Systemic Short-termism?: The Importance of
Managerial Systems in Valuing the Long Term, 42 MGMT. DECISION 949 (2004) (examining organizational
culture, processes, and routines to understand why firms undervalue the long term when trading off between
short-term and long-term results).
53 See Suresh M. Sundaresan, Continuous-Time Methods in Finance: A Review and an Assessment, 55 J. FIN.
1569, 1569 (2000).
54+See Donncha Kavanagh et al., Finance Past, Finance Future: A Brief Exploration of the Evolution of
Financial Practices, 9 MGMT. & ORG. HIST. 135, 142 (2014).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
such contexts “[m]illiseconds matter” to the realization of arbitrage opportunities in pricing
patterns only detectable by electronic means.55 For finance capital, temporality has become
less a dimension to occupy than one to chase and flee.
IV. THE UNTIMELINESS OF INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS LAW
International human rights law doctrine and practice are, in many respects, temporally
parasitic on the conditions and constructions outlined above. Acts of asserting or claiming
human rights protected by international law are typically oriented towards one or more
nation-states. As such, human rights claims often entail affirmation of some nationalist
“rationalization of time,” by evoking nationalist or protonationalist diachrony, for instance.56
One influential version of disciplinary self-understanding has cast international human rights
law as the chastened European progeny of the Second World War and the Holocaust. 57
Other versions confer upon international human rights law a more ancient national or
protonational lineage: traceable to the Stoics of Greek and Roman philosophy, medieval
scholars of natural rights, and the French, American, and sometimes the Russian
Revolutions.58 Accounts along these lines may be in the process of being usurped, among
human rights historians, by a post-1970s periodization focused on the United States.59
International human rights law scholars and practitioners are nonetheless at pains to
adapt to the rhythms of global supply chains and the lead-times of logistics. Increasingly,
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
55 Kavanagh et al., supra note 54, at 142. See generally Donald MacKenzie, How to Make Money in
Microseconds, LONDON REV. BOOKS, 19 May 2011, at 16 (discussing the use of algorithms in stock market
trading, with a focus on how quickly they facilitate trades).
56 Alonso, supra note 24, at 388.
57 See, e.g., MICHAEL IGNATIEFF, HUMAN RIGHTS AS POLITICS AND IDOLATRY 4-5 (2001).
58 See, e.g., ADAM MCBETH ET AL., THE INTERNATIONAL LAW OF HUMAN RIGHTS 36-58 (2011) (discussing the
older legal traditions that influenced the idea of human rights). On contending “precursors” advanced for human
rights among scholars and practitioners, including those mentioned here, see SAMUEL MOYN, THE LAST UTOPIA:
HUMAN RIGHTS IN HISTORY 11-43 (2010).
59 See MOYN, supra note 58, at 3-6 (noting how human rights came into popular consciousness in the 1970s);
Yves Dezalay & Bryant Garth, From the Cold War to Kosovo: The Rise and Renewal of the Field of
International Human Rights, 2 ANN. REV. L. & SOC. SCI. 231, 240-53 (2006) (discussing human rights with a
primary focus on the United States in the 1970s and 1980s); see also SAMUEL MOYN, HUMAN RIGHTS AND THE
USES OF HISTORY 86 (2014) (“[T]he lesson of the actual history of human rights is that they are not so much a
timeless or ancient inheritance to preserve as a recent invention to remakeor even leave behind . . . .”).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
effort is directed towards the insertion of tiny packets of human rights review along the
length of a global supply or value chain. Potentially open-ended claim-making and
negotiation must be condensed, accordingly, into relatively rapid-fire certifications or audits,
as market movements are broken down into interlaced milliseconds.60
International human rights law scholars and practitioners do, nevertheless, exhibit
some ambivalence about the submerged or invisible temporalities of nation-state and
capitalist economy, even as they frequently pace their work according to those rhythms. At
times, as in the quote with which this article opened, human rights advocates set an event-
focused empiricism against such “background” temporalities. Foregrounding “happenings in
the world,” framed in human rights terms, is frequently a way of trying to cut across the
white noise and base time of nation and market.61
Within international human rights law doctrine, it is also possible to discern some
effort to install some “base time” other than the vacant passageways or indifferent cycles of
national history or global economy remarked on above. The ICCPR is, for example, strangely
untimely.62
At first, the ICCPR seems hooked to a definite point in time: its dates of adoption and
entry into force. Otherwise, however, it works to generate a patently fictional sense of States
Parties’ co-occurrence in and around the “present Covenant”: a temporality plainly out of
step with experience and impervious to measurement.63 Obligations in the ICCPR are
expressed in the present tense: each State Party “undertakes” various commitments, even as
the date of that initial undertaking will have been spread across many years, even decades, as
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
60 See Sarianna M. Lundan & Peter Muchlinski, Human Rights Due Diligence in Global Value Chains, in 7
PROGRESS IN INTERNATIONAL BUSINESS RESEARCH 184 (Rob Van Tulder et al. eds., 2012). See generally Peter
Lund-Thomsen & Adam Lindgreen, Corporate Social Responsibility in Global Value Chains: Where Are We
Now and Where Are We Going?, 123 J. BUS. ETHICS 11 (2014) (discussing and critiquing protections for
workers in global value chains).
61 See generally Fleur Johns et al., Introduction to EVENTS: THE FORCE OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 1 (Fleur Johns
et al. eds., 2011) (discussing how international law makes events of certain occurrences and the ramifications of
it so doing).
62 ICCPR, supra note 5.
63+Id. at art. 1(3).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
states ratify or accede to the instrument and declare themselves subject to the jurisdiction of
the Human Rights Committee.64
Within this “present” of the ICCPR, allowance is made for interruptions: in “time of
public emergency,” certain derogations are permitted.65 Requirements flowing from rights’
recognition are also afforded different pacing. Some steps must be taken “immediately,
“promptly,” “at the time of arrest,” or “without undue delay.”. Others “shall be” taken at an
unspecified rate or with allowance for “adequate time.”66 Still others follow very specific
calendar timings, as in the requirement to submit reports “[w]ithin one year of the entry into
force of the present Covenant for the States Parties concerned.”67 At some points in the
ICCPR text, biological time seems to be exerting a powerful undertow, literally or
metaphorically: some requirements are triggered by a child’s birth, while others track the
“life of the nation.”68 Much of the text, however, has little if anything to do with biological
time.
These interlocking rhythms evade empiricism in precisely the way that the timing of
economic production has been shown to do. Consider the following from Louis Althusser’s
portion of Reading Capital:
In the capitalist mode of production, . . . the time of economic production has
absolutely nothing to do with the obviousness of everyday practice’s
ideological time: of course, it is rooted in certain determinate sites, in
biological time, but . . . it is not at all identified with this biological time, and
in no sense is it a time that can be read immediately in the flow of any given
process. It is an invisible time…as invisible and as opaque as the reality of the
total capitalist production process itself. This time, as a complex
“intersection” of . . . different times, rhythms, turnovers, . . . is only
accessible in its concept, which, like every concept is never completely
“given”, [sic] never legible in visible reality: like every concept this concept
must be produced, constructed.69
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
64 Id. at art. 2(1)-(3).
65 Id. at art. 4(1).
66 Id. at arts. 4(3), 9(2)-(3), 14(3)(a)-(c), 24(2).
67 Id. at art. 40(1)(a).
68 Id. at arts. 4(1), 24(2).
69 Althusser, supra note 22, at 101. In drawing a parallel to Althusser’s notion of base time, the intention here is
not to posit a claim that the temporalities of international human rights law or of nation-states are uniformly
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
It is, nonetheless, questionable whether the work of international human rights law since the
late twentieth century has effectively produced some “invisible” time or times through which
other timings might pass, across or against rival temporalities, in the manner of which
Althusser writes. Temporally, international human rights law doctrine, such as that set forth
in the ICCPR, is irreducible to the composite times of nation and market, even as it
occasionally evokes one or both of those. Yet international human rights law doctrine seems
too temporally obstreperous and erratic to have become taken for granted. Here, it works to
smooth over temporal divergence in the name of some universal time or timelessness; there,
it ramps up temporal disjunction.70
Regardless of the success of efforts to reconfigure base time, it may be that the
contemporary prevalence of human rights claims and consciousness has contributed to the
“patterns of immediacies” remarked on above. International human rights practice certainly
encourages planning: the Millennium Development Goals project mentioned earlier is
illustrative of this.71 Nonetheless, human rights claims do seem designed for continuous time
(meted out in infinitesimal intervals), or the time of the instant, rather than for discrete time
of prescribed duration. Such claims are meant to be both ever-present individual
accompaniments and actionable, in relation to any instance of infraction, with relative
promptness.
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
determined by, or responsive to, the rhythms of the capitalist means of production. In this article, base time is
employed to elucidate temporalities that elude empiricism yet nonetheless seem to exert a metronomic
compulsion in relation to other times and timingstemporalities that may, in this article’s account, be multiple
and contending.
70 See, e.g., Neil J. Kritz, Coming to Terms with Atrocities: A Review of Accountability Mechanisms for Mass
Violations of Human Rights, 59 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 127, 127-28 (1996) (“Dealing with the grieving, with
accountability and forgiveness, and with the rehabilitation of victims and perpetrators will . . . take time
certainly longer than the time generally allotted for technical tasks”; yet, “[a] public airing and condemnation . .
. may be the best way to draw a line between past and present, lest the public perceive the new order as simply
more of the same.”).
71 U.N. Economic and Social Council, supra note 33.
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
One possible understanding of the temporality of international human rights law
doctrine and practice is that they install, or seek to install, a “timeless…presence.”72 That is,
the attribution and bearing of human rights might be taken to express that temporality that
Hannah Arendt regarded as characteristic of both modernity and totalitarianism, whereby
time is seized by “a superior process of movement”73 of which individuals become “walking
embodiments.”74 In Arendt’s account, this temporal logic subordinates all individuated tasks
and intervals—including the interval of a human lifespan—to an “ever ongoing process of
purge and elimination” towards some future condition forever in the making.75 Thus the
preamble to the ICCPR places the individual, in the present, “under a responsibility to strive
for the promotion and observance of the rights recognized in the present Covenant,” in
service of “the inherent dignity of the human person.”76 Read together with Arendt, this
inherent dignity presumed by the ICCPR seems to call forth a “deadly eternity” whereby
individuals’ dignity is the natural residue of, and material for, the necessary unfolding of the
international human rights law project, rather than something to be realized variably and
agentially.77
To read international human rights law’s temporalities so, however, would be to elide
the sense of temporal dislocation that they repeatedly evoke. Into the compressed “time of
public emergency,” when the “exigencies of the situation” otherwise fill the frame, the
ICCPR inserts an atemporal “no” in the form of the “no derogation” language of Article
4(2).78 Amid the dreamy timelessness of “[a]ll persons shall be equal before the courts and
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
72 1 HANNAH ARENDT, Thinking, in THE LIFE OF THE MIND 1, 207 (Mary McCarthy ed., 1978). I am indebted to
Daniel Augenstein and Hans Lindahl for prompting me to consider this prospect.
73+Kathrin Braun, Biopolitics and Temporality in Arendt and Foucault, 16 TIME & SOCY 5, 12 (2007) (quoting
an independently translated phrase from HANNAH ARENDT, ELEMENTE UND URSPRÜNGE TOTALER HERRSCHAFT:
ANTISEMITISMUS, IMPERIALISMUS, TOTALE HERRSCAFT 952 (Piper Verlag 5th ed. 1996) (1955)).
74 HANNAH ARENDT, On the Nature of Totalitarianism: An Essay in Understanding, in ESSAYS IN
UNDERSTANDING: 1930-1954, at 328, 340 (Jerome Kohn ed., Schocken Books 2005) (1994).
75 Braun, supra note 74, at 13.
76 ICCPR, supra note 5, Preamble.
77 Braun, supra note 74, at 15.
78 ICCPR, supra note 5, at art. 4(1)-(2).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
tribunals,” in Article 14, one is called to pay close attention to practicalities, including
ensuring that a person facing criminal charge has “adequate time and facilities for the
preparation of his [or her] defence.”79 It is possible to press much of the ICCPR into the
temporal service of nationhood, market, family, and narratives of historical progress. Yet it is
also possible to read and perform international human rights law anachronistically and
thereby to amplify its “radical untimeliness.”80
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
79 Id. at art. 14(1), (3)(b).
80 DERRIDA, supra note 6, at 25 (writing of that “anachrony on the basis of which we are trying here to think the
ghost” in the course of developing a reading of spectral dimensions of Karl Marx’s work). This article is not
concerned with the historiography of international human rights law, nor that of international law more broadly.
For this reason, it takes no explicit part in debates to which Anne Orford has contributed her own forceful
defense of anachronism. See Anne Orford, The Past as Law or History? The Relevance of Imperialism for
Modern International Law (NYU Institute for International Law and Justice, Working Paper No. 2012/2
(History and Theory of International Law Series), June 2012). See also Martti Koskenniemi, Histories of
International Law: Significance and Problems for a Critical View, 27 TEMPLE INTL & COMP. LJ. 215, 226-32
(2013).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
V. THE CALL OF THE CROWD
If international human rights law doctrine and practice tend towards the temporally
unruly—perhaps even radical anachrony—they nonetheless remain oriented towards
representation and rallying. Indeed, crucial to all the temporalities discussed so far is the
prospect of their being produced as a mode of experience. Even the elusive temporalities of
economy and nation-state must be made accessible or recordable in some sense, however
indirectly. This in turn demands that the time or timing in question having some
constituency—some people loyal (consciously or otherwise) to that temporality’s production
and reproduction.
As to how that constituency might be assembled and held together temporally, some
historical differentiation seems in order. In international human rights law work, the period
from the 1970s through the 2000s was broadly preoccupied with human rights law’s
professionalization and global inculcation. One aspect of this work was temporal. It entailed
encouraging an ever-broadening range of actors to engage in the regular, ritualized recitation
of human rights norms: through governmental and intergovernmental reporting (or
nongovernmental shadow reporting) and state submission to periodic review, for instance, as
well as participation in seasonal cycles of conference attendance and multilateral meeting.81 It
is by such means that more and more people have been encouraged to locate themselves amid
a progressive temporality marked out in human rights terms—to envisage themselves moving
away from rights-infringing pasts towards rights-respecting futures.82
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
81 See, e.g., David Kennedy, Autumn Weekends: An Essay on Law and Everyday Life, in LAW AND EVERYDAY
LIFE 191, 191-96 (Austin Sarat & Thomas R. Kearns eds., 1993) (discussing the author’s trip to Lisbon for an
international law conference focused on East Timor); Video Lecture by Hilary Charlesworth, Rituals and
Ritualism in the International Human Rights System, LONDON SCH. ECON. & POL. SCI. (Oct. 21, 2014),
http://www.lse.ac.uk/newsAndMedia/videoAndAudio/channels/publicLecturesAndEvents/player.aspx?id=2660
(discussing the U.N.’s role in human rights and the ritualized dimensions of that work).
82 See Joseph R. Slaughter, Enabling Fictions and Novel Subjects: The Bildungsroman and International Human
Rights Law, 121 PMLA 1405, 1410 (2006) (discussing a type of coming-of-age novel genre called
“Bildungsroman” and discussing how it, and modern international human rights, encourage a progressive
perspective). See generally SKOUTERIS, supra note 12.
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
As far as rivalry between such a rights-oriented time scale and temporalities of
nationhood is concerned, this seems to have been intermittent. Much international human
rights law work of this period tracked the rhythms of state-to-state diplomacy, or sought to
rewrite national myth.83 At the same time, this work sought to instill the perception of rights
bearing as an everyday popular occurrence: as routine for many as consumer choice (at least
for those with the requisite economic means). Moreover, international human rights law work
of these decades remained self-consciously ruptive: it was designed to stop the clock on any
“business as usual” deemed to have violated rights.84
By 2010, however, it was possible to regard this work of professionalization and
routinization as largely done, human rights having attained “ideological ascendancy,and
international human rights law’s heroes, defenders, and norms attracting, in many circles,
“uncritical wonderment.” 85 Henceforth, even as the above-mentioned rituals remained
ongoing, attention would turn to producing new times in which human rights awareness
might occur and recur.
In this regard, it seems to have become harder, in recent decades, to treat time in any
register as common terrain across which all people must pass and through which all must
come to pass. The narratives of development and progress with which international human
rights law doctrine has long been inflected do not seem to stabilize or explain to the extent
that they might once have done. In what sense, for instance, might a young, unskilled,
unemployed person in the United States, a subsistence rice farmer in Laos, and an asylum
seeker eking out the days of a hunger strike in detention in Australia be understood to occupy
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
83 See, e.g., Katharine E. McGregor, Memory Studies and Human Rights in Indonesia, 37 ASIAN STUD. REV.
350, 357-59 (2013) (discussing how Indonesian human rights proponents reassessed late 1960s violence against
communists). But see George E. Edwards, Assessing the Effectiveness of Human Rights Non-Governmental
Organizations (NGOs) from the Birth of the United Nations to the 21st Century: Ten Attributes of Highly
Successful Human Rights NGOs, 18 MICH. ST. J. INTL L. 165 (2010) (focusing on the importance of non-state
actors in international human rights law).
84 See, e.g., Kritz, supra note 71, at 127-28.
85 MOYN, supra note 58, at 6-7.
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
the same time scale? Where should we place these figures on a progressive timeline
ostensibly spanning the globe? Even if such placement were possible, the passage of time
often seems otherwise contrary to the aims of human rights activists.86
In the face of such challenges, as well as the decline of some forms of nation-state
temporal authority discussed above, international human rights law doctrine and practice
seem to have become somewhat less oriented around whispering ad nauseam in the ear of
political elites (in the mode encouraged by postwar policy science).87 Instead, emphasis
seems to now rest upon rallying or following crowds in some here-and-now—in a courtroom
or at a protest, for instance—and maximizing the amplitude of the instant.88 This is, it seems,
to be an era for rights in real time, or at least in some carefully sliced sections of real time.
Champions of international human rights law seem to oscillate between appealing for a time
of ubiquitous witnessing and unedited loops, and calling for such time to be punctuated and
segmented so that collective attention might be apportioned, directed, and intensified. The
former recalls “Andy Warhol's ideal of filming real events in real time – life isn't edited, why
should its record be edited?”—an aspiration now realized in countless blogs, remote-sensing
facilities, and video diaries.89 The latter seems to evoke the piecemeal concreteness,
diagnostic suggestiveness, and asocial “time depth” of the sequenced genome.90
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
86 See Bruce Robbins, Temporizing: Time and Politics in the Humanities and Human Rights, BOUNDARY 2,
Spring 2005, at 191, 193 (“Time protects those who are already too well protected. And since the goal of human
rights activists is to deny impunity, to bring to account, for them . . . time has been an antagonist . . . .”).
87 Cf. Myres S. McDougal et al., Human Rights and World Public Order: A Framework for Policy-Oriented
Inquiry, 63 AM. J. INTL L. 237, 258-64 (1969) (discussing human rights law of the time in the context of state-
to-state relations and elites).
88 See Sam Gregory, Cameras Everywhere: Ubiquitous Video Documentation of Human Rights, New Forms of
Video Advocacy, and Considerations of Safety, Security, Dignity and Consent, 2 J. HUM. RTS. PRAC. 191, 193-
94 (2010); see also Philip E. Agre, Real-Time Politics: The Internet and the Political Process, 18 INFO. SOCY
311, 317, 321-22 (2002) (discussing the amplification model of internet advocacy, and the idea that technology
fosters spacing among people by providing them with individual outlets while also allowing them to remain
connected). See generally Heather Ford, Crowd Wisdom, INDEX ON CENSORSHIP, Dec. 2012, at 33 (discussing
an online software platform for citizens to report human rights abuses in Kenya); Samuel Greengard, Following
the Crowd, COMM. AMC, Feb. 2011, at 20 (discussing the potential of crowdsourcing, including as a tool for
reporting on human rights abuses).
89 Susan Sontag, Regarding the Torture of Others, N.Y. TIMES MAG., May 23, 2004, at 24, 27.
90 Kaja Finkler, Family, Kinship, Memory and Temporality in the Age of the New Genetics, 61 SOC. SCI. & MED.
1059, 1065-67 (2005).
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
Producing instances or streams of shareable time has always taken work, but that
work seems in many respects more difficult and less definitive than ever. Global human
rights law doctrine and practice—specifically, the expectation that anyone, at any time,
should be able to reach for a juridical right more or less instantly fungible with others’
rights—seems both to have contributed to that difficulty and adapted to accommodate it. At
the expense of radical anachrony, international human rights law doctrine and practice seem
increasingly fixated on maximizing accumulated “interface time”; that is, “the physical span
of time that [a] reader interacts” with a human rights-related text.91
CONCLUSION
What, then, might the prevailing impulse to sustain and occupy “real time,” as against
its temporal rivals, reveal about international human rights law work and workers today?
Perhaps such “real time” preoccupations might be regarded as symptomatic of undue
orientation toward times of crisis and associated inattention to “injustices of everyday life,
amid the desire for “immediate, intense relevance.” 92 Today, however, international human
rights law seems too expansive and too settled in its occupation of the everyday for critique
along these lines to have much purchase. With so much mundane report filing and official
investigation underway worldwide, it is unclear how much of an “alternative” an
“international [human rights] law of everyday life” might pose.93 Moreover, the “real time”
that human rights would tap is more often a source of preventative data than it is necessarily
laden with crisis. The “real time” with which recurrent contact is sought among international
human rights law advocates is precisely the time of the everyday, avant la crise.
More troublingly, it may be that this orientation among international human rights law
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
91 Marjorie C. Luesebrink, The Moment in Hypertext: A Brief Lexicon of Time, in HYPERTEXT 98 -
PROCEEDINGS OF THE NINTH ACM CONFERENCE ON HYPERTEXT AND HYPERMEDIA 106, 107 (Frank Shipman et
al. eds., 1998).
92 Charlesworth, supra note 14, at 377, 392.
93 Id. at 377, 391.
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
practitioners signals abandonment of much by way of a claim to power over the longue
durée—the “cadres résistants”—of living and working conditions.94 Perhaps international
human rights law doctrine and practice have, for the most part, now left the demarcation of
invisible base time to the global economy, with its “real time” gatherings, protests, and live-
streams little more than diversions from, or elaborations on, the accelerating cadence of the
market. It certainly appears, at times, as though global concern for capital (and temporal)
redistribution might have dissipated in favor of concern for connectivity, liquidity, risk
arbitrage, and continuous motion, the latter often explicitly rights inflected.95 Perhaps, in the
alternative, the real time aspirations of international human rights law work represent little
more than a new iteration of the “given condition” of state time, with a renewed thrust for
national synchronicity as their primary output. 96 Consider, for example, how the much-
vaunted, crowd-sourced happenings of the Arab Spring gave way to divergent, yet similarly
bleak, national winters.97
There is still time, though. If such abandonment or acquiescence has occurred, it is
neither complete nor fully conceded. The base times of the nation-state and the global
economy may be invisible, but the tolls that they sometimes exact do not go undetected.
Everywhere one looks, the “proud, angry poor” are voicing and enacting dissatisfaction.98 If
the ambition of this collection of writings is to “recover[ ] the public and political nature of
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
94 Fernand Braudel, Histoire et Sciences Sociales: La Longue Durée, 13 ANNALES. ÉCONOMIES, SOCIÉTÉS,
CIVILISATIONS 725, 733 (1958) (Fr.).
95 Since 2011, for example, the World Bank has published a Global Financial Inclusion (Global Findex)
Database, funded by the Bill & Melinda Gates Foundation, which measures how adults in 148 countries save,
borrow, make payments and manage risk. Asli Demirguc-Kunt et al., The Global Findex Database 2014:
Measuring Financial Inclusion Around the World, (World Bank Grp. Dev. Research Grp. Fin. and Private
Sector Dev. Team, Policy Research Working Paper No. 7255, 2015), available at
http://go.worldbank.org/1F2V9ZK8C0.
96 Sassen, supra note 25, at 223.
97 See, e.g., David W. Lesch, The Arab Spring and Winter in Syria, 23 GLOBAL CHANGE, PEACE & SECURITY
421, 422-25 (2011) (discussing Bashar al-Asad’s crackdown on the opposition in Syria); Mary Ann Tétreault,
The Winter of the Arab Spring in the Gulf Monarchies, 8 GLOBALIZATIONS 629, 631-33 (2011) (discussing the
methods the governments of the Gulf countries used to combat Arab Spring unrest). See generally Lisa
Anderson, Demystifying the Arab Spring, FOREIGN AFF., May/June 2011, at 2 (2011) (discussing the different
experiences of the Arab Spring in Libya, Egypt, and Tunisia).
98 Frances Fox Piven, A Proud, Angry Poor, THE NATION, Jan. 2, 2012, at 33, 33.
Forthcoming+in+Indiana&Journal&of&Global&Legal&Studies,&vol.+23.1+(2015)+
+
human rights law,” 99 then this may be, at least in part, a question of reactivating the
“times…[and] rhythms” of the global economy, and of the nation-state, as political questions
of the first order.100 By way of doing so, international human rights law doctrine and practice
offer ways of experiencing the here and now anachronistically, against the necessity of
building futures or redeeming pasts, and against the “deadly eternity” of inherent dignity.101
++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
99 Daniel Augenstein & Hans Lindahl, Introduction: Global Human Rights Law and the Boundaries of
Statehood, 23 IND. J. GLOBAL LEGAL STUD. XX (2015).
100+Althusser, supra note 22, at 101.+
101 Braun, supra note 74, at 15.
... Fleur Johns has recently called to 'reactivate' competing notions of time 'as political questions of the first order' under international law. 92 Her call points to the need for new ways of recognising and engaging the productive power and political character of time technologies and temporal regulation. 93 Engaging the productive power of time technologies and temporal regulation today means intervening in the flow architecture described by Knorr Cetina, and the in-the-moment register of governance that it promotes. ...
Article
Full-text available
This article explores international legal entanglements with the infrastructure of Coordinated Universal Time (UTC), a socio-technical construction that comprises the globally definitive measure of seconds, minutes and hours working in lockstep around the world. UTC is produced and maintained with international law, through international administration with social, political, material and technical dimensions. In analysing mutual entanglements of international law with infrastructural relations organized around UTC, the article assesses their imbrication in globalized governance routines and distributive patterns, instantiated here with reference to the field of finance. The article further considers ways to engage legal-infrastructural relations for material change in patterns of governance.
... Earlier articles and books by 'law and society' and 'law and anthropology' scholars, had explored the rationalities of time inhabited by distinct communities and what these had to say about mechanisms of sociality and governance (Engel, 1987;Greenhouse, 1996;Richland, 2013). Over the years, this scholarship had been augmented and further enriched by reflections from feminist legal theory (Chryssostalis and Drakopoulou, 2013;Conaghan, 2006;van Marle, 2003), post and anti-colonialist perspectives (Keenan, 2015;Mawani, 2014), international law and human rights (Craven et al., 2006;Johns, 2016), and critical legal theory (McNeilly, 2017;Valverde, 2015). To indulge in a bit of ad-hoc periodization, it is arguably possible to identify a period running from a couple of years before the network began, right up to the present moment when research on law and time has only just become a more regular feature of academic events, projects and publications. ...
Article
Full-text available
Justice and the idea of the moral good pervade legal philosophy and underlie much of legal practice in different contexts. They are particularly resonant in the law of equity and the remedies it makes available. This article uses equity and conceptions of justice explores the role of narratives, fairness and values through the lens of the constructive trust, science fiction, temporality, the counterfactual imagination and creativity. This special edition’s theme of intersectionalities within law is a central analytical thread. Power dynamics and the place of equity in social dialogues around justice and fairness are set alongside socioeconomic vulnerability and othering in understanding how the law succeeds and fails in managing emerging inequalities. A lack of autonomy and voicelessness is often revealed through constrained access to law and legal services, as well as a more vulnerable relationship with time. Engaging the constructive trust provides interesting opportunities to examine the role of the trust within law, and through that explore wider discussions about the nature of legal systems and the remedies they may give rise to. Science fiction has always provided opportunities to create counterfactual worlds and engage hypothetical questions, many of which might illuminate contemporary debates or resonate forward to emerging concerns. Imagination is a central tenet of these worlds, as well as, increasingly, within law when faced with emerging technologies and the issues they present. The article concludes with an acknowledgement that such narratives and opportunities to question social norms can be a valuable tool in grounding societal change.
Article
Full-text available
Metrics of success, status, and justice are founded on subjective narratives of spatialized pasts and futures. This article considers three moralised space-times – chronotopes – and their relations to people’s mobility within and from sub-Saharan Africa. The first stems from European efforts to promote ‘development at home’ which places Africans on a separate temporal trajectory. By discursively positioning Africans outside global space and futures, Europe subsequently denies claims to European space or lives beyond African territory. Moreover, coding border crossing as deviant justifies an apparatus to return Africans to their space-time where they can achieve justice. The latter two chronotopes emerge dialogically among citizens and immigrants in South Africa’s ‘global city.’ Amidst Johannesburg’s polyrhythmicity, citizens position themselves in a chronotope of stalled transformation where justice comes by remedying deprivations inherited from an apartheid past. This rubs against international migrants operating in a mode of deferred distanciation: using the city to achieve rights and recognition in future elsewhere. These competing temporalities deny possibilities of a mutually shared definition of justice or spatial claim making. This article ultimately positions chronotopes as critical elements in migration infrastructures that shape movements, conditioning interactions, and foreclosing (or opening) possibilities for justice across or within space.
Chapter
When discussing the nature and functioning of global and transnational modes of regulation, scholars embark upon what may be defined as ‘postnational normative ontology.’ While the debate on this subject has proved to be insightful from several perspectives of inquiry, global and transnational legal theorists have not concerned themselves with three fundamental interrogatives regarding the relationship between legal positivism, state law, and postnational regimes. These are: whether positivist theories of law are informed by a peculiar form of temporality; if so, what kind of temporality that is; and finally, whether such temporality also underpins the working logic of global and transnational regulatory dynamics. This theoretical shortage reveals a ‘meta-ontological’ difficulty, being meta-ontology the study of the questions with which ontology—even in its normative fashion—concerns itself. Using modern secularisation and social conventionalism as case studies, this chapter engages with this difficulty by taking the first step towards a postnational contextualisation of legal positivism’s temporality. In doing so, it argues that legal positivism is a technique of world-construction (tekhnē) in the sense that it interprets social facts constructively (i.e. it transcends them rationally and systematically) to tell what the (concept of) law is. Further, it shows that in producing (or positing) social facts, the positivist law-ascertaining method is never merely descriptive but always regulatory. Finally, it contends that legal positivism’s metaphysical and epistemological constructions are informed by an effectual (i.e. progressive and future-oriented) form of temporality which global and transnational legal theorists should start exploring. Uncovering the meta-ontological dynamics which inform the conceptualisation and functioning of modern (i.e. positivist) law will, in turn, help scholars reflect on how the performativity of postnational regulatory mechanisms is theorised and operationalised.
Article
Human rights were a defining discourse of the 20th century. The opening decades of the twenty-first, however, have witnessed increasing claims that the time of this discourse as an emancipatory tool is up. Focusing on international human rights law, I offer a response to these claims. Drawing from Elizabeth Grosz, Drucilla Cornell and Judith Butler, I propose that a productive future for this area of law in facilitating radical social change can be envisaged by considering more closely the relationship between human rights and temporality and by thinking through a conception of rights which is untimely. This involves abandoning commitment to linearity, progression and predictability in understanding international human rights law and its development and viewing such as based on a conception of the future that is unknown and uncontrollable, that does not progressively follow from the present, and that is open to embrace of the new.
Article
Full-text available
International legal work involves trying to verify the condition of the world. This aspect of international legal work is changing in light of growing automation. The range of persons capable of engaging with this work, and ways of contesting what can be experienced in common, are shifting. With this comes redistribution of the power to govern and other juridical capacities on the global plane. Taking IAEA and UNHCR practices as exemplars, this article argues for renewed attention to these shifts.
Article
Full-text available
With a strong focus on social practices under plural legal conditions, the papers in this volume discuss how people operate within the various temporalities of law. The papers show that the competence to navigate the complex web of temporalities and legal orders is highly unequally distributed. Most papers in this volume testify to the stratifying implications of time when asymmetrically instrumentalised within the context of these social practices. The introduction discusses various classifications of time and argues that are important for analysing law's temporalities in the sense of the temporal validity of law, temporal aspects of legislation, decision making, and of evidence and causation. They serve to clarify that the nature of the problems differs depending on whether they arise from social or specific legal temporalities. The paper suggests studying not only temporalities of law but paying special attention to the temporalities within law. This is followed by a discussion of how law connect past, present and the future, with special attention to memories of the past. While the third section is devoted to problems that arise when law ‘borrows’ the temporalities of other disciplines, the fourth section deals with the contradictions and frictions arising from acceleration and hyperregulation. In the last section of this paper, speculations are made on how the issues analysed in this volume might affect uncertainty, risk and trust in law.
Article
Full-text available
Peter Gabriel and other allies created WITNESS nearly 20 years ago – shortly after the Rodney King incident in Los Angeles. At the time, our founders asked: ‘What if every human rights worker had a camera in their hands? What would they be able to document? What would they be able to change?’ Since 1992 WITNESS has engaged with the risks, opportunities and possibilities for action that emerge from the power of moving images – training and supporting human rights activists worldwide to create real change through our methodology of ‘video advocacy’. Yet now an increasing number of people worldwide have cameras. Participants, witnesses and perpetrators are all filming. Videos (particularly mobile video) make it possible to document and publicize human rights struggles – from monks marching for freedom in Rangoon and the election protestors in Tehran, to individual voices speaking out against injustice on YouTube. However, despite the growing online circulation of images of human rights violations, of victims and survivors, there is limited discussion of crucial safety, consent and ethical concerns – particularly for people who are filmed. Issues around consent, representation and re-victimization and retaliation have emerged even more clearly in an open and networked online environment. Video is being reworked, remixed and recirculated by many more people. New possibilities for action by a global citizenry have arisen, but these carry with them real dangers. The human rights and technology communities can help lead the way in confronting these challenges. The article concludes with suggestions for approaches based on norms, technology solutions, and other ideas that could be deployed to begin to address these emerging issues.
Article
This essay connects two longstanding anthropological themes by reconsidering Durkheim's distinction between social time and personal time through the lens of legal pluralism; I also turn the temporal lens the other way, to reflect on legal pluralism. Drawing on the work of the von Benda-Beckmanns, I begin by suggesting that we might look for illuminating connections between social time and legal pluralism wherever people make urgent demands of law, and wherever states turn to law as a means of social engineering. That possibility informs my essay and choice of examples, all from the United States. First, I review two major pieces of social legislation that were explicit in their social engineering goals. Next, I consider the temporalities inscribed in the eligibility requirements for social programs set up under the broad terms of those acts. In the conclusion, I return to the question of how social time and legal pluralism might be mutually informing in ways that shed fresh light on both themes – blurring the line between social time and personal time, and considering legal pluralism as extending to the interrelation of memberships and subjective attachments.
Article
Syrian President Bashar al-Asad officially took the constitutional oath of office and delivered his inaugural speech on 17 July 2000 in Damascus. By Syrian standards, it was a remarkably enlightened speech, replete with criticisms of certain policies in the past, even those of his predecessor and father, Hafiz al-Asad, who ruled Syria from 1970 until his death in June 2000. The frankness of the speech confirmed the hopes among many in and outside of Syria that indeed Bashar was a breath of fresh air who would lead the country in a new direction.
Article
Article
I begin by confessing a general fascination with the concept of time. I puzzle endlessly over the relationship between time and matter, and the insistence of scientists that before the Big Bang time did not exist. I grapple with the relationship between time and speed, and the fact that if we could travel at the speed of light time would not move. I seek to grasp Stephen Hawking's recent conversion to the view that, in the physical world, time may yet run in reverse. I am intrigued that our concepts of time came to Australia only with the First Fleet, for aboriginal time was cyclical rather than linear. Events could recur, dead people could live again. I find exhilarating the idea that we see at this moment, through our telescopes, stars that no longer exist. I love the objective reality of the equator and the total artificiality of the meridian, and the intention that this felicitous fiction is the place for us to see in the “real beginning” of the next century.