ArticlePDF Available

Pain as metaphor: Metaphor and medicine

Authors:

Abstract and Figures

Like many other disciplines, medicine often resorts to metaphor in order to explain complicated concepts that are imperfectly understood. But what happens when medicine's metaphors close off thinking, restricting interpretations and opinions to those of the negative kind? This paper considers the deleterious effects of destructive metaphors that cluster around pain. First, the metaphoric basis of all knowledge is introduced. Next, a particular subset of medical metaphors in the domain of neurology (doors/keys/wires) are shown to encourage mechanistic thinking. Because schematics are often used in medical textbooks to simplify the complex, this paper traces the visual metaphors implied in such schematics. Mechanistic-metaphorical thinking results in the accumulation of vast amounts of data through experimentation, but this paper asks what the real value of the information is since patients can generally only expect modest benefits - or none at all - for relief from chronic pain conditions. Elucidation of mechanism through careful experimentation creates an illusion of vast medical knowledge that, to a significant degree, is metaphor-based. This paper argues that for pain outcomes to change, our metaphors must change first. Published by the BMJ Publishing Group Limited. For permission to use (where not already granted under a licence) please go to http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions.
Content may be subject to copyright.
Pain as metaphor: metaphor and medicine
Shane Neilson
Correspondence to
Shane Neilson, Department of
English and Cultural Studies,
Chester New Hall 321,
McMaster University, 1280
Main Street West, Hamilton,
ON L8S 4L9, Canada;
neilss@mcmaster.ca
Accepted 17 July 2015
To cite: Neilson S. Med
Humanit Published Online
First: [please include Day
Month Year] doi:10.1136/
medhum-2015-010672
ABSTRACT
Like many other disciplines, medicine often resorts to
metaphor in order to explain complicated concepts that
are imperfectly understood. But what happens when
medicines metaphors close off thinking, restricting
interpretations and opinions to those of the negative
kind? This paper considers the deleterious effects of
destructive metaphors that cluster around pain. First, the
metaphoric basis of all knowledge is introduced. Next, a
particular subset of medical metaphors in the domain of
neurology (doors/keys/wires) are shown to encourage
mechanistic thinking. Because schematics are often used
in medical textbooks to simplify the complex, this paper
traces the visual metaphors implied in such schematics.
Mechanistic-metaphorical thinking results in the
accumulation of vast amounts of data through
experimentation, but this paper asks what the real value
of the information is since patients can generally only
expect modest benets or none at all for relief from
chronic pain conditions. Elucidation of mechanism
through careful experimentation creates an illusion of
vast medical knowledge that, to a signicant degree, is
metaphor-based. This paper argues that for pain
outcomes to change, our metaphors must change rst.
For most patients, pain is transient, lasting as long
as the causal illness does. Then pain disappears. For
other patients, pain transforms into a chronic
problem that usurps identity. Both types of patients
want release, for their ordeal to end. But in the lan-
guage I just used, that of patients and illness and
problem and ordeal, I have perpetuated a
problem that is consolidated in language. In her
landmark study The Body in Pain, Elaine Scarry
memorably pointed out that pain nds its way into
language almost exclusively through metaphors of
weaponry and damage.
1
I build on this observation
by arguing that pain is conceptualised and
expressed through negative and destructive meta-
phorical systems that have been appropriated by
physicians and entrenched with supplementary
neurological metaphors. I argue further that the
incredible accumulation of detail concerning pain
pathways is dependent upon these destructive meta-
phor systems. The medical understanding of pain is
reliant upon certain theoretical constructs that
might be distant in time yet are inuential in effect;
elaborations upon these theories with experimental
knowledge and minute elaboration of physical
detailthe so-called mechanistic view of pain
do not change the metaphors we use to understand
the physiological information. Because the benet
of seeing a medical practitioner skilled in the treat-
ment of pain is modest, the accumulation constitu-
tes a meaningless ubiquity, an authoritative edice
of medical knowledge that is an illusion of author-
ity. That the authority derives from knowledge that
is based on destructive metaphors should make
anyone suffering from pain circumspect.
In Metaphors We Live By, a seminal text on meta-
phor, Lakoff and Johnson dene metaphor as a
way of conceiving of one thing in terms of another,
and its primary function is understanding.
2
All
disciplines resort to metaphor for the means of
their understanding, and Lakoff and Johnson dem-
onstrate how pervasive metaphorical thinking is,
but also that much of our metaphorical thinking is
based on arbitrary conventions that arentpre-
served across cultures. Nietzsche contributed a
strange property of metaphor in On Truth and
Falsity in their Extramoral Sense:
What therefore is truth? A mobile army of meta-
phors, metonymies, anthropomorphisms: in short
a sum of human relations which became poetically
and rhetorically intensied, metamorphosed,
adorned, and after long usage seem to a nation
xed, canonic and binding; truths are illusions of
which one has forgotten that they are illusions.
3
Disciplines progress according to the strength of
their metaphors, and those metaphors are fated to
become so familiar that they transform into illu-
sions, if even thought of at all. Nietzsche adds that
in an earlier age, it was
language which has worked originally at the con-
struction of ideas; in later times it is science. Just as
the bee works at the same time at the cells and lls
them with honey, thus science works irresistibly at
that great columbarium of ideas, the cemetery of per-
ceptions, builds ever newer and higher storeys; sup-
ports, puries, renews the old cells, and endeavors
above all to ll that gigantic framework and to
arrange within it the whole of the empiric world.
4
The scientic edice will stretch past the sky like
an endless erector set but it is still built on a core
of metaphor. But what if the metaphors are inher-
ently limiting, or even counterproductive?
The problem the man of science faces is that the
impulse towards the formation of metaphors, that
fundamental impulse of man withstands and is
even used to interpret the regular and rigid new
world that comes from the pursuit of knowledge
and truth according to the scientic method.
Scientic ideas, Nietzsche explains, are constantly
confused by the construction of new gures of
speech, metaphors, metonymies such that the
existing world of waking man is ultimately ren-
dered motley, irregular, inconsequentially incoher-
ent, attractive, and eternally new as the world of
dreams is.
4
Part of the problem inherent to this
marriage of metaphor and scientic knowledge is
that individual metaphors exist within a whole
system of metaphorical conceptsconcepts that we
constantly use in living and thinking. These expres-
sions, like all other words and phrasal lexical items
Neilson S. Med Humanit 2015;0:18. doi:10.1136/medhum-2015-010672 1
Original article
JMH Online First, published on August 7, 2015 as 10.1136/medhum-2015-010672
Copyright Article author (or their employer) 2015. Produced by BMJ Publishing Group Ltd under licence.
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
in the language, are xed by convention.
2
The scientic disci-
plines use their own cosmologies of metaphor with which to
produce and disseminate understanding, and medicines central
pain metaphors that marshal a mobile army of truth are of
weapons and damage, as per Scarry, but also metaphors of neur-
ology that include doors, keys, wires and circuitry.
i
Pain was rst codied by the International Association for the
Study of Pain (IASP) in 1979 as an unpleasant sensory and
emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue
damage, or described in terms of such damage
5ii
. A single sen-
tence long, this abstraction cannot convey what pain is, what it
feels like. Textbooks that recount medical history often point
out that the denition includes the parameter of emotion,
taking pain back from the clinical, hyperphysiological viewpoint
of the 19th, 20th and 21st centuries. The disciplines denition
is a negative one restricted to metaphors of damage. That this
denition is consistent with the concept of pain operating in
general societypain as a negative experiencedoes not mean
it is an adequate denition, for as Lakoff and Johnson show, our
metaphors can work to increase or decrease understanding. It
may be that the popular discourse around painpain as nega-
tive experience as expressed by metaphors of weaponry and
damageis, in metaphorical terms, the wrong road. If pain
can only be negative, then pain will only be used for negative
purposes and have negative effects. This is an inherent obstacle
to recovery from painful conditions. What is lacking in the IASP
denition is the dissent of possibility, a description of transcend-
ent effects, of how this undeniably unpleasant experience has
useful results for individuals and for society. Perhaps the
problem is a chronological one, for acute pain is a message of
actual tissue damage, whereas chronic pain is usually pain signal
without damage. (Even so, the language used hereone of
damage’—implies a lack of value in the affected body part, a
state of affairs contested by the burgeoning eld of disability
studies.) But the possible positivity of pain, and its metaphorical
roots in acute situations, is a subject that can be taken up in
another forum. For now, it is important to recognise that the
IASP denition is inuential and provides the dominant meta-
phor for the whole branch of pain medicine
iii
and that when I
refer to pain I mean chronic pain.
What is often ignored by medical professionals is the part of
the IASP that denes pain as an experience. In present-day
North America, pain is a clinical experience that is relegated to
medicine for alleviation. In The Culture of Pain, David Morris
asserts that [t]he vast cultural shift that gives the story of pain
its hidden plot centres on the eradication of meaning by late
nineteenth-century science. . .[w]e are the heirs of the trans-
formation in medical thought whereby we think of pain as no
more than an electrical impulse speeding along the nerves.
6
Medicine and the public use hegemonic metaphors to compre-
hend pain. Morris text proceeds to examine how an inherently
metaphorical understanding of pain absorbed by the larger
public came into effect. There are problems with this wholesale
relegation of pain to medicine and I will consider these pro-
blems at length in another forum. For now, the following
summary of pain theories and their bases in metaphor constitu-
tes a real narrative of progress. Textbooks like John Bonicas
The Management of Pain, considered a standard in the eld,
briey narrate the history of pain medicine in a single chapter
before voluminously providing modern management princi-
ples.
7
In their abbreviated historical sections, such textbooks
present pain as moving from primitive to a sophisticated under-
standing. In anatomical, physiological and biochemical terms,
this is incontestable. Yet in a paradoxical way, the progress nar-
rative has been, qua Nietzsche, obliterated by the metaphor of
progress. Progress becomes the narrative, obscuring a truth
which I hope to show is one of vast, systematic and elaborate
oversimplication as encouraged by metaphorical understanding
that conceals its nature as metaphor. Though neurological meta-
phors have assisted with the accumulation of scientic knowl-
edge, their enshrinement as the means of understanding pain
has had a terrible cost. We think of pain in terms of nerves, but
nerves are not experience and nerves are not necessarily
emotion. Nerves are not pain.
The rst well-formed pain theory on record was derived by
Aristotle (384322 BC) who identied the affective component
of pain. His work forms the foundation of much current under-
standing of the topic, and pain textbooks routinely invoke
Aristotles concept of pain as passion of the soul because his
denition corresponds with IASPs modern denition that
includes emotional experience. Yet pain textbooks provide the
briefest mention of the four quoted words, leaving out
Aristotles complex denitions of passion and soul. Pain text-
books move on from Aristotle to similarly microquote from the
humoral theory of Hippocrates, the next ancient theorist on a
short (and curiously variable) list. From there, Galen. Onward
to Descartes! There are a few other pain theories, but Aristotles
denition demonstrates the major problem inherent in the
extreme summary by medical textbooks. Receding knowledge
might be cited but is rarely understood, and it is the metaphors
knowledge relies upon that are important, not knowledge itself.
Book I of De Anima begins by providing a historical survey
on the topic of soul. This is the text that sets out Aristotles
thinking about the nature of life. RD Hicks concluded from this
book that Aristotle believes that the attributes of soul cannot
properly be separated from those of the body.
8
In Book II,
Aristotle furthers his investigation by launching into his own
denition of soul. In this foundational text cited by textbooks
as proof of Aristotles thinking on pain, pain is not a central
concernit is instead a minor topic enfolded under a much
broader range of topics. Pain is really only theorised by Aristotle
in the second part of Book III within a moral framework. With
30 chapters, De Anima requires more than four words of
summary in order to understand what Aristotle truly means
when he writes on pain. Pain cannot be understood out of
context, including denitions of pain. Ironically, our underlying
neurological metaphors short-circuit understanding.
Part of this context comes in Book II when Aristotle sets out
the criteria for an organism to be called alive: (1) intellect, (2)
sense, (3) locomotion and (4) motion of nutrition, growth and
decay. He then moves to dene what constitutes an animal: a
living thing that distinguishes itself from other living things like
i
As Lakoff and Johnson point out, humans typically conceptualize the
nonphysical in terms of the physicalthat is, we conceptualize the less
clearly delineated in terms of the more clearly delineated (p. 59).
2
Even if it is never explicitly stated in contemporary texts as such, the
visual representation of cell membranes at the molecular level has a clear
wire/door appearance.
ii
The importance of Canadian contributions to the understanding of pain
cannot be underestimated. For example, the IASP denition was written by
Merksey, a former professor of Psychiatry at the University of Western
Ontario.
iii
That pain can have positive elements is a minority view in Western
culture. Though medical histories approve of the inclusion of emotion
in the IASP denition, they do not criticize the negative path
researchers, huddled around the denition, have taken. Following the
lead of medicine, culture has adopted medicines view of pain as
negative.
2 Neilson S. Med Humanit 2015;0:18. doi:10.1136/medhum-2015-010672
Original article
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
plants on the basis of sense perception. This constitutes
Aristotles rst serious mention of the senses. He mentions
touch rst out of the ve senses in order to further substantiate
what constitutes soul. Touch is mentioned to assist with
taxonomising life forms, not as a sense implicated in pain.
In Chapter 3 of Book II, Aristotle puts pain squarely within an
originating context of desire: But all animals have at least one
sense, touch; and, where sensation is found, there is pleasure
and pain, and that which causes pleasure and pain; and where
these are, there also is desire, desire being appetite for what is
pleasurable.
9
Aristotle links pain and pleasure together in a
moral framework. It should be clear at this point that the rereca-
pitulations of Aristotle by modern medical textbooks are quite
decontextualised. How Aristotle is represented in pain text-
books goes a long way to proving the inadequacy of the pain
textbooks as a group, for such texts constitutively reproduce
passion of the soul in what can be charitably referred to as
catachresis and less charitably as mere historical adornment.
If desire, pleasure and the good life entered into contemporary
medicines concept of pain, then our metaphors would not be
the same. As corollary, our IASP-mandated experience of pain
would not be the same.
One other thinker deserves mention in brief due to his inu-
ential scientic and metaphorical contribution to pain. Rene
Descartes (15961650)
iv
, taking his cue from Aristotle, devel-
oped his theory of dualism in The Passions of the Soul (1649).
The title and style of argument of this text are Aristotelian.
Descartes likened the body to a machine and wrote that the
mind is controlled by the soul, which he felt resided in the
pineal gland (in opposition to the accepted view in his day that
the soul resided in the heart). Descartes maintained that the
nerves of the body were acted upon by the pineal gland through
the medium of cerebrospinal uid, a marked improvement over
Hippocrates humoral theory that suggested control over the
body comes from the brain as mediated by neural structures.
Descartes inaugurates the neurological metaphor for under-
standing pain, a development which reaches an apogee in the
modern day. Ironically, Descartes writings are densely meta-
phorical. Even his theory about pain perception is expressed in
metaphorical terms: he maintains that pain travels from site of
injury to the brain just as, pulling on one end of a cord, one
simultaneously rings a bell which hangs at the opposite cord.
10
As per Morris, a cultures metaphorical system of nerves and
pain is born. But like Aristotle, Descartes thinking gets simpli-
ed over time and the complexity of pain is sidelined too.
Descartes is renowned as the great splitter of mind and body,
the great dualist, but this perception is actually a disservice to
his thought. Again, context is key, a fact literary scholar Jan
Frans van Dijkhuizen demonstrates while writing about repre-
sentations of pain in late mediaeval English literature. Consider
the passionate fusion of mind and body in Descartes six meta-
physical meditations wherein it is proved that there is a God and
that mans mind is really distinct from his body:
[T]here is nothing that this my Nature teaches me more expressly
then that I have a Body, Which is not Well when I feel Pain []
And by this sense of Pain, Hunger, Thirst, etc. My nature tells me
that I am not in my Body,asaMariner is in his Ship, but that I
am most nighly conjoynd thereto, and as it were Blended there-
with; so that I with It make up one thing; For Otherwise, when
the Body were hurt, I, who am only a Thinking Thing, should
not therefore feel Pain, but should only perceive the Hurt with
the Eye of my Understanding (as a Mariner perceives by his sight
whatever is broken in his Ship).
11
Clearly Descartes was not as absolute about the division
between mind and body as is commonly perceived: pain compli-
cates his otherwise strict dualism. Analysing the passage above,
Jan Frans van Dijkhuizen asserts that pain throws into doubt
the very distinction between mind and body/matter which
(Descartes) has rst attempted to construct, since it points to the
inescapable fact of human embodiment. Pain, more than any
other physical sensation, confronts us with the fact that we do
not just have bodies, but that we are our bodies.
12
Writing that
his body and mind are Nighly conjoined, Descartes understood
that pain complicates strict categories, making his pain concept
much like that of Aristotle and the IASP, but constitutingas
per the conventional narrativean increment of progress. The
scientic process selects certain ndings and metaphors to create
the narrative of progress, but the truth of our metaphors sug-
gests a much more fertile eld before the husbandry. Pain was
and is more complex than our current metaphors allow.
Following Descartes, pain theorists included sensory and
affective experience in their formulations but these remain
abstract up to the present day. In the absence of real understand-
ing or knowledge, the physiology of pain receives exquisite
renement instead. In the modern era, we talk about pain in the
language of science, but the language of science remains, at
bottom, the language of metaphor and as if formulations mas-
querading as authoritative knowledge. I bring the reader quickly
up to date by mentioning a few other pioneers in pain theory
and research in order to sketch in the basis of medicines neuro-
logical metaphors for understanding pain. In the 19th century,
major advances were made in pain theory predicated on a
greater understanding of neuroanatomy and neurophysiology.
Though not alone, Charles Bell, a prominent Scottish neuro-
physiologist, laid much of the groundwork for what would
eventually be known as specicity theory by writing in 1811
that
the external organs of the senses have the matter of the nerves
adapted to receive certain impressions, while the corresponding
organs of the brain are put in activity by the external excitement:
That the idea or perception is according to the part of the brain
to which the nerve is attached, and that each organ has a certain
limited number of changes to be wrought upon it by the external
impression.
That the nerves of sense, the nerves of motion, and the vital
nerves, are distinct through their whole course, though they seem
sometimes united in one bundle; and that they depend for their
attributes on the organs of the brain to which they are severally
attached.
13
Bells cold neuroanatomical descriptions, surgical induction of
lesions and elucidation of resultant effects constitute a different
kind of discourse in the Foucaldian sensea medical, neuroana-
tomical and neurophysiological discourse. Bells writings dir-
ectly led to Johannes Mullers Doctrine of Specic Nerve
Energies from 1835, which is as follows: The nerve of each
sense seems to be capable of one determinate kind of sensation
only, and not of those proper to the other organs of sense;
hence one nerve of sense cannot take the place and perform the
functions of the nerve of another sense.
14
The presence of dis-
sectible structures creates doctrines that are specic’—the
iv
Descartes is considered the rst analytic scientist of neurophysiology
by Uhtaek Oh, the revisionist editor of hard-science textbook
The Nociceptive Membrane. This is an example of how modern
discourses penetrate the older ones and claim them for their own as a
battle for primacy.
Neilson S. Med Humanit 2015;0:18. doi:10.1136/medhum-2015-010672 3
Original article
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
medical discourse is presented as authoritative even though its
true knowledge at this point is vanishingly small.
Like all theories in any discipline, adherents to a given pain
theory privilege their theory, resulting in intellectually gladiator-
ial pain discourses that compete in an academic arena for
supremacy in terms of dening how to acquire knowledge. But
because every pain theory works in an arena, the fallacy of
supremacy is demonstrated. What is supreme is the medical dis-
course itself. By the term medical discourse, I invoke
Foucaults broad conception of discourse, including speech acts
and social acts performed by medical and paramedical personnel
that are directed and grouped around political and economic
institutions like medical colleges, hospitals and journals. This
discourse also includes the images used to represent pain and
the symbolic meaning that culture attributes to those representa-
tions. Clinical in nature, medical discourse decontextualises
experience in order to isolate pain as symptom and sign. In
medical discourse, pain is expressed within language that is fun-
damentally negative in tone and implicationpain as disability,
disorder and diagnosis. But what is truly powerfulthe source
of medical power and the illusion of poweris that pain is a
problem misunderstood by neurological metaphors.
I begin this discussion of theory with the various theories that
fall under the general category of pattern theory. Pattern theory
was a prominent concept dened as patterns of activation,
spatial or temporal, in neurons that do not necessarily have time-
locked responses to painful stimuli.
15
This theory posits that
there is more to pain than the labelled line extending from stimu-
lus to brain. Rather, pain is signalled in a complex manner
through parallel neural networks and processing. Though pattern
theory has been around for over 100 years, it was elegantly
articulated in 1965 with the gate control theory of pain by Ron
Melzack and Patrick Wall, two researchers working at the
Montreal Neurological Institute. This revolutionary articulation
of theorybetraying reliance upon metaphor in the very name
of the theory with the use of gate’—was presented as follows:
We propose that (1) the substantia gelatinosa functions as a gate
control system that modulates the afferent patterns before they
inuence the T cells; (2) the afferent patterns in the dorsal
column system act, in part at least, as a central control trigger
which activates selective brain processes that inuence the modu-
lating properties of the gate control system; and (3) the T cells
activate neural mechanisms which comprise the action system
responsible for response and perception. Our theory proposes
that pain phenomena are determined by interactions among these
three systems.
16
Laurence Kirmayer, the James McGill Professor and Director
of the Division of Social and Transcultural Psychiatry at McGill
University, interprets the theory like this: [t]he key insight was
the notion of central control of peripheral processes: that affer-
ent control occurs at many different levels.
17
Note the com-
plexity of the gate-control construct as rooted in anatomy and
concept. What is proposed is not one wire connected to another
wire (ie, nerve A connects to centre B) but rather a multimodal,
regulated system. The gate-control theory created an experimen-
tally testable concept of pain that initiated a revolution in the
understanding and treatment of pain. Kirmayer adds that the
gate control theory provided a natural conceptual framework
to begin to integrate cognitive, psychological and ultimately
social and cultural processes.
17
As much of an advance as the
gate control theory was, it is no more complex than a metaphor
about policing a door. It is important to state this fact because
complexity is often explained through the use of metaphor to
provide understanding. What can be lost, what can seem illu-
sory, is the basis of understanding. The complexity remains as
science but the metaphor hides in plain sight as a commonplace.
Our inconspicuous metaphors control our understanding but
we are not aware of it. We amble through pain as unconscious
beasts (gure 1).
And, in particular, we rely upon visual metaphors as our
interpretive tools. Within the medical discourse, there is a
system of visual metaphors for pain. Such images are meant to
represent progress while ignoring their provenance as metaphor
due to the special nature of imagethat of concretised truth.
Though images are intended to be a simplication of truth, con-
temporary schematic explanations of pain represent a hearken-
ing back to 19th-century specicity theory. Morris writes, We
are the heirs of the transformation in medical thought whereby
we think of pain as no more than an electrical impulse speeding
along the nerves.
18
We are the heirs, and we are in an import-
ant way re-innovators of this idea. Although the present deluge
of diagrams and textual explanations of pain dont argue for a
return to specicity theory per se, they do pretend to an
immense knowledge of how one wire connects to another wire,
leaving out the affective dimension entirely. Mechanisms are
emphasised in medical discourse. What is pain? is a difcult
question to answer, but opiate and GABA receptors can be iden-
tied, tested in experiments, and the results published in articles
rich with schematics and diagrams. In this way, the simple is
represented simply, demonstrating the secret and dangerous
power of visual representations that avoid images of human
beings in pain. Standing on the shoulders of schematics,
Figure 1 A schematic of gate control
theory. Adapted from Melzack and
Wall.
16
4 Neilson S. Med Humanit 2015;0:18. doi:10.1136/medhum-2015-010672
Original article
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
medicine appears powerful and knowledgeable. Yet the sche-
matics are metaphors which perpetuate themselves to the detri-
ment of complex truth. Schematics are visual metaphors that
limit understanding because of extreme simplicity.
Pain medicines learning curve is a way to police the door to
understanding pain. To understand pain, one must rst assimi-
late signicant amounts of knowledge about basic neurophysi-
ology. The state of neurophysiological knowledge, as opposed
to pain perception, is advanced. Digesting basic explanations of
how nerves conduct electricity like [n]eurons communicate by
producing electrical impulses called action potentials. Action
potentials are self-regenerative electrical signals that tend to
propagate throughout a neuron and along its axon. The action
potential is a depolarisation of about 100 mV
19
leads to the
seductive inference that its not just electric impulse thats con-
ducted, it is pain that is conducted. This inference is true in that
there are certain nerve bres responsible for transmitting certain
kinds of pain. But its not true in that this signal is just thata
signal. It isnt pain. No nerve diagram with plus and minus
signs on either side of a line representing a membrane turns
knowledge into knowing (gure 2).
Who could look at such a diagram when in pain and say,
This is pain! Admittedly, no student looks to diagrams like the
one above to understand what pain is specically. Yet the
unacknowledged metaphorical basis of the diagram (nerves are
wires) and the fact that the diagram is a basic building block
common in medicobiological texts, leads to the creation of a
powerful metaphor-based illusion. Much of the understanding
of pain gets relegated to a diagram such as this one. Although to
understand pain, one must learn nerve signalling, one should
also recognise that nerve signalling serves as the physiological
basis of a metaphorical system. There is an illusion that more is
known as the state of current knowledge is vast in terms of intri-
cate mechanisms. Distortions occur among those without train-
ing and even those with training, because of the nature of
scientic progress identied by Nietzsche. There is more to pain
than can be metaphorically illustrated by nerves, but a neuro-
physiologist too can quickly forget what is only partially appre-
hended by the hegemonic metaphors. For example, incredibly
detailed mechanistic explanations of pain add little to the IASP
denition of pain. The following words from the domain of
molecular biology prove the point:
The magnitude and nature of leak conductance determines mem-
brane resistance and the impact a generator current will have on
Figure 3 The spinothalamic pathway. Adapted from Somatic Sensory
System (http://www.rci.rutgers.edu/~uzwiak/AnatPhys/
ChemicalSomaticSenses.htm).
Figure 4 An illustration by Descartes to show re pulling a thread.
Retrieved from Wikipedia (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/History_of_pain_
theory). Original illustration appeared in Descartes Treatise of Man
(1664).
Figure 2 A schematic of action potential propagation. Adapted from
Review of Membrane and Action Potentials (http://www.life.umd.edu/
classroom/bsci440/higgins/lecture2.html).
Neilson S. Med Humanit 2015;0:18. doi:10.1136/medhum-2015-010672 5
Original article
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
the membrane potential. . .[g]iven the fact that there is consider-
able variation in the biophysical properties of Na+ channels
depending on which (alpha) and (beta) subunits are present, the
relative density of these subunits will have a signicant impact on
action potential threshold.
20
Knowing which subunit communicates with another is
important at the level of possible intervention sites for pharma-
cological therapy, but this knowledge does not augment the
IASP denition. Yet such is the frontier of pain research, a per-
petual spelunking of microdetail that lls the pages of the most
prestigious journals. Pain researchers investigate the domain of
receptor, ion and protein fold. Molecular biology, neurophysi-
ology and reproductive neurobiology are the ascendant medical
discourses of pain, and they are intoxicating precisely because of
their reductive power. The dangerand, I argue, implicit
messageis that one doesnt need to bother with politics, reli-
gion or power when viewing such diagrams.
But one does. In Descartes day and for some time before
that, Christianity provided the Western world with a hegemonic
pain discourse other than the medical. By building an iconog-
raphy around Jesus Christ, Christianity used Christs last days
after re-entering Jerusalem (tellingly titled the Passion in
English) in a framework of human sufferingthat pain serves as
a conduit to God, that suffering intensies ones relationship
with the maker. This relationship was presented as a pleasurable
and even sexual one. Albeit problematic, the Christian attitude
towards pain is more positivist than that of the clinic. And
ignoring politics in the conceptualisation of pain is to ignore the
maimed, war-torn world that pain makes.
Mechanistic discourses are possibly inferior than religious
ones in terms of articulating pain because of their inherent lack
of meaning. When modern-day Rene burns his nger, he knows
that physical pain is the result of nociceptors sending a signal
from the periphery to the brain, as well as top-down processes
modulating that same signal, as well as (perhaps) a God oversee-
ing the process. But Rene also knows much more that science
doesnt know yet: Rene knows he can reach for certain medica-
tions that will give him analgesia (he knows he can thank the
mechanistic discourse for that) but if he wishes to make sense of
his pain, his knowledge of the spinothalamic tract wont help
him. If the re was due to poor enforcement of building codes,
or Rene lost his job due to a global nancial crisis, turned to
state-taxed alcohol in order to numb his pain, and inadvertently
left a cigarette burning in bed, resulting in extensive burns. . .
knowing wire A leads to wire B wont help Rene cope on the
burn unit. He has a problem meaning, not a problem of neur-
ology. Meaning is inherently bound up in metaphor and Rene
needs better metaphors to reect the complexity of his plight.
To demonstrate the rootedness of this problem of metaphor, I
provide a specic series of diagrams that are metaphors mas-
querading as hard knowledge. Contextualisation in the form of
narratives can expose the reductive nature of visual metaphors.
Visual metaphors are the sine qua non of the medical pain dis-
course of the late 20th century onwards because they are more
concrete than those channelled by words. Consider gure 3,a
diagram documenting the pain pathway as it relates to thermal
sensation, one like it included in every textbook of pain (and
ubiquitous on the internet):
The pedigree of the above diagram extends far back in
history. Because the diagram shows a peripheral stimulus
sending a signal to central structures (a wire system), the
diagram is conceptually as simple as Descartes thread running
from the skin to the brain:
In gure 4, pain caused by intense heat pulls the string of a
nerve causing the tethered brain, now recognising the sensation
of pain, to send a signal to the foot to withdraw. This
call-and-response model chimes with contemporary diagrams of
cell membranes, including the amorphous balls in University of
Figure 5 Diagram from p. 24 of Allan Feins Nociceptors and the
Perception of Pain, 2012.
Figure 6 A schematic of ion channels. Adaptedfrom Uhtaek.
21
6 Neilson S. Med Humanit 2015;0:18. doi:10.1136/medhum-2015-010672
Original article
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
Connecticut professor Alan Feins Nociceptors and the
Perception of Pain (gure 5):
No more than a simple picture matching a simple concept,
Feins door to the outside world opens in response to a stimu-
lus. We remain in the metaphorical system of gate/door. What if
the representation is more complex, such as one informed with
contemporary neurophysiology?
The same ideology is at work in this diagram. At the level of
supercial inspection, this diagram is more complex than Feins,
but on closer inspection it is just another wire/door metaphor
with more elaborate knobs and tubes. Indeed, acronyms become
the doors textual keys. Perhaps the image of the synapse comes
closer to communicating pain experience than the spinothalamic
tract diagram, for the synapse metaphorically represents the real
gap between knowledge and knowing. But if metaphor is whats
required to bridge the gap between knowledge and knowing,
then science must be honest about its fundamental basis in
metaphor.
The obvious riposte is that images like the one above are not
meant to represent pain in total at all, that instead these gures
demonstrate an innitesimal piece of the puzzle of pain. But
medicine focuses on these details to the detriment of the puzzle.
Figure 7 Plate I from Charles
Darwin.
22
Neilson S. Med Humanit 2015;0:18. doi:10.1136/medhum-2015-010672 7
Original article
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
The puzzle can never be solved because of the pursuit of parts.
Elucidating components is simpler than understanding the
whole. Whats missing in these diagrams is the complex truth.
The caption features a pile-up of acronymic explanations. To
the non-specialist, images like these would seem like a perpetual
wash, one spilling into the next thats meant to diagrammatise
obscure molecular concepts. Figure 6 replicates the Cartesian
human machine receiving some signal or other through means
of doorbells and wires, albeit in a rened way. Yet the diagrams
are no more informative than Descartes.
Consider the photographs included in Charles Darwins The
Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (1872) where
photographs of infants in pain are included. Looking at these
faces, are we not staring at (or in) the face of pain (gure 7)?
Contemporary science has offered an explanation of what is
happening within the pictures and by the viewer of those pic-
tures. Validated pain face scales quantify the level of pain experi-
enced by the sufferer, and the work of Damasio, Tranel and
Damasio has found that peripheral nociceptors connect to the
thalamus, a structure that regulates emotional content. In turn,
the thalamus sends a signal to the fusiform gyrus to effect con-
sequent facial expression.
23
Somehow the image of an infant in
painknowing the infant is in painsupersedes such scientic
knowledge. An observer is moved by what she sees through an
affective response. This interior drama matches the exterior one
and is an important part of the narrative.
Medicine uses negative (damage/weapon) and neurological
metaphors to the detriment of people in pain. How the uncer-
tain and hypothetical nature of metaphor is elided in favour of
the illusion of authority and competence has done pain sufferers
a disservice. By accumulating mountains of mechanistic detail,
the affective component has been lost as has the unstable nature
of the understanding provided by science. Although negative
and neurological metaphors explain pain to some extent, they
are not sufcient. Other metaphors are necessary, as is realising
the contribution of narrative to the study of pain. Pain is more
than neurological metaphor. Pain is what we say it is over time.
Pain is also the context in which we feel pain, and that context
need not be a clinicoapocalyptical one of damage, weaponry or
live wires.
Competing interests None declared.
Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
Open Access This is an Open Access article distributed in accordance with the
Creative Commons Attribution Non Commercial (CC BY-NC 4.0) license, which
permits others to distribute, remix, adapt, build upon this work non-commercially,
and license their derivative works on different terms, provided the original work is
properly cited and the use is non-commercial. See: http://creativecommons.org/
licenses/by-nc/4.0/
REFERENCES
1 Scarry, E. The body in pain: the making and unmaking of the world. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1985:15.
2 Lakoff G, Johnson M. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2003:36.
3 Nietzsche F. On truth and falsity in their extramoral sense. In: Shibles W, ed. Essays
on metaphor. Whitewater: The Language Press, 1972:5.
4 Nietzsche, F. On truth and falsity in their extramoral sense. In: Shibles W, ed. Essays
on metaphor. Whitewater: The Language Press, 1972:10.
5 Merskey, H. Pain terms: a list with denitions and notes on usage. Pain 1979;6
(3):247.
6 Morris, D. The culture of pain. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991:8.
7 Bonica, J. The management of pain. 2nd edn. London: Lea and Febiger, 1990.
8 Aristotle. De Anima. Trans. RD Hicks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1907:xxxvii.
9 Aristotle. De Anima. Trans. RD Hicks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1907:59.
10 Descartes R. Treatise of man. Trans. Thomas Steele Hall. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1972:34.
11 Descartes R. Six medical meditations wherein it is proved that there is a God and
that mans mind is really distinct from his body, trl. William Molyneux. London: B.G.
for Benjamin Tooke 1680:978.
12 Frans van Dijkhuizen J. Pain and compassion in early modern english literature and
culture. Cambridge: D.S. Brewer, 2012.
13 Bell C. Reprint of the Idea of a New Anatomy of the Brain, with Letters &c. J Anat
Physiol 1868;3:(Pt 1):14782. US National Library of Medicine, 5 May 2014.
14 OMalley CD, Clarke E. The human brain and spinal cord: a historical study
illustrated by writings from antiquity to the twentieth century. 2nd edn.
San Francisco: Norman Publishing, 1996:206.
15 Cervero F. Pain theories. Science of pain. Basbaum A I, Bushnell MC. eds.
New York: Elsevier, 2009:5.
16 Melzack R, Wall PD. Pain mechanisms: a new theory. Science 1965;150:9719.
17 Kirmayer LJ. On the cultural mediation of pain. Pain and its transformations.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007:68.
18 Morris D. The culture of pain. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991:4. Print.
19 Waxman SG. Clinical neuroanatomy. 27th edn. New York: McGraw-Hill,
2013:201.
20 Gold MS, Caterina MJ. Molecular biology of the nociceptor/transduction.
In: Basbaum AI, Catherine Bushnell M. eds. Science of pain. New York: Elsevier,
2009:56.
21 Uhtaek O, ed. The nociceptiv
e membrane. New York: Elsevier, 2006.
22 Darwin C. The expression of the emotion in man and animals . London: John
Murray, 1872. Darwin Online, 14 May 2014.
23 Damasio, AR, Tranel D, Damasio H. Face agnosia and the neural substrates of
memory. Ann Rev Neurosci 2014;13:89110.
8 Neilson S. Med Humanit 2015;0:18. doi:10.1136/medhum-2015-010672
Original article
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
Pain as metaphor: metaphor and medicine
Shane Neilson
published online August 7, 2015Med Humanities
http://mh.bmj.com/content/early/2015/08/07/medhum-2015-010672
Updated information and services can be found at:
These include:
References
#BIBL
http://mh.bmj.com/content/early/2015/08/07/medhum-2015-010672
This article cites 4 articles, 1 of which you can access for free at:
Open Access
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/non-commercial. See:
provided the original work is properly cited and the use is
non-commercially, and license their derivative works on different terms,
permits others to distribute, remix, adapt, build upon this work
Commons Attribution Non Commercial (CC BY-NC 4.0) license, which
This is an Open Access article distributed in accordance with the Creative
service
Email alerting
box at the top right corner of the online article.
Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article. Sign up in the
Collections
Topic
Articles on similar topics can be found in the following collections
(13)Open access
Notes
http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions
To request permissions go to:
http://journals.bmj.com/cgi/reprintform
To order reprints go to:
http://group.bmj.com/subscribe/
To subscribe to BMJ go to:
group.bmj.com on September 29, 2015 - Published by http://mh.bmj.com/Downloaded from
... Thus, a disturbing picture emerges of chronic pain that seems to elude all medical progress, entails a large burden of disease and high social costs, is seldom 'in the picture' and is still barely understood (Bourke, 2014, pp. 22-26;Neilson, 2016;Van der Graaf, 2020). However, there may be light on the horizon in the form of the new, 11th edition of the International Classification of Diseases (ICD), which will be implemented in 2022. ...
... These researchers demonstrated that pain was a more complex phenomenon than had been traditionally thought (Bourke, 2014, pp. 10-11, 229;Corns, 2020, 87-103;Crul, 1999;Meldrum, 2007;Neilson, 2016;Reynolds & Tansey, 2004) Bonica and Saunders also received support from clinical quarters, including the British anesthesiologists, neurologists, neurosurgeons, psychiatrists and psychologists who founded the Intractable Pain Society in 1969 (from 1973 the British chapter of the IASP). These and other pioneering clinicians wanted to combat under-treatment of pain with more sophisticated techniques of anesthesiologic nerve blocks, new generations of analgesic drugs and new forms of behavioral and psychotherapy (Bourke, 2014, pp. ...
... All elements of this definition have been intensely debated (Ayede, 2017(Ayede, , 2019(Corns, 2020, 20-21, 160-166;Derbyshire, 2016, p. 24): Is 'unpleasant' an adequate and sufficient description of the pain experience (Neilson, 2016;Williams & Craig, 2016)? How problematic is the understanding of pain as a personal experience, as it implies the adoption of a subjective criterion of pain than any objective measure (Corns, 2020, pp. ...
Article
Full-text available
Chronic pain entails a large burden of disease and high social costs, but is seldom 'in the picture' and barely understood. Until recently, it was not systematically classified but instead viewed as a symptom or sign. In the new International Classification of Diseases, (ICD)-11, to be implemented in 2022, 'chronic' pain is now classified as a separate disease category and, to a certain extent, approached as a 'disease in its own right'. Reasons that have been given for this are not based so much on new scientific insights, but are rather of pragmatic nature. To explore the background of these recent changes in definition and classification of chronic pain, this paper provides a historical-philosophical analysis. By sketching a brief history of how pain experts have been working on the definition and taxonomy since the 1970s, we demonstrate the various social and practical functions that underlie the new ICD-11 classification of chronic pain. Building on this historical-empirical basis, we discuss philosophical issues regarding defining and classifying chronic pain, in particular performativity and pragmatism, and discuss their implications for the broader philosophical debate on health and disease.
... Mas a linguagem da ciência também é, ela própria, uma linguagem metafórica disfarçada com vestes de autoridade. No lugar do conhecimento emerge o discurso, o "discurso biomédico", afirmando a sua supremacia à custa de atos sociais e discursivos em diferentes contextos institucionais, das escolas médicas aos hospitais e à comunicação social (Neilson, 2015). Mas no lugar da lesão tissular estão muitas vezes outros fatores causais ou de manutenção, incluindo conflitos familiares ou interpessoais, perdas ou privações afetivas, num passado remoto. ...
... Precisamos de fazer uma leitura dos modos como as dimensões sociais e políticas influenciam o bem -estar das pessoas menos providas de poder e oportunidades (Barker, 2005). Os perigos da biologia molecular e neurofisiologia, com os seus diagramas ou esquemas visualmente apelativos, mais "concretos" e "objetivos", residem na sua potencial capacidade de obliterar a importância da política, da religião e do poder na vida das pessoas (Neilson, 2015). No encontro clínico, precisamos de uma dimensão moral que saiba reconhecer o que é realmente importante para os doentes. ...
... The shift from Galen's holistic view of pain resulting from humoural imbalance to a neuromechanistic model of pain has provided great advances in the understanding of nociception, sensitisation, bioplasticity and neuroimmune function. Neilson argues that the neuro-mechanistic view of pain is an "illusion of great scientific progress" because the vast accumulation of physiological knowledge conceals a model that does not explain the subjective experience of pain i.e., the hard problem of consciousness (50). A consequence of conflating nociception (neurophysiology) and pain (51) has been to decontextualise physiological processes from the lived experience (42) resulting in neglect of the socio-ecological factors that shape a person's lifeworld and contribute to painogenicity (13,52). ...
Article
Historical records provide knowledge about the way people lived in the past. Our perspective is that historical analyses of the Medieval Period provide insights to inform a fuller understanding of pain in the present era. In this article, we appraise critiques of the writings of people living with pain during the mid (high) to late Medieval Period (c. 1,000-1,500 AD) to gain insights into the nature, attitudes, lived experience, and sense-making of pain. In the Medieval Period, pain was understood in terms of Galen's four humours and the Church's doctrine of pain as a "divine gift", "punishment for sin" and/or "sacrificial offering". Many treatments for pain were precursors of those used in modern time and society considered pain to be a "shared experience". We argue that sharing personal stories of life is a fundamental human attribute to foster social cohesion, and that nowadays sharing personal stories about pain is difficult during biomedically-focussed time-constrained clinical consultations. Exploring pain through a medieval lens demonstrates the importance of sharing stories of living with pain that are flexible in meaning, so that people can connect with a sense of self and their social world. We advocate a role for community-centred approaches to support people in the creation and sharing of their personal pain stories. Contributions from non-biomedical disciplines, such as history and the arts, can inform a fuller understanding of pain and its prevention and management.
... Analogies and metaphors are not to be accepted uncritically, as they can in some cases be rather misleading and harmful (Neilson, 2016). For example, illustrations that relate to broken machines have long been commonly applied with serious impacts on pain research and treatment, including the self-understanding of patients and clinical practitioners (Jevne, 2015;Setchell et al., 2017;. ...
Article
Full-text available
Chronic pain is one of the most disabling medical conditions globally, yet, to date, we lack a satisfying theoretical framework for research and clinical practice. Over the prior decades, several frameworks have been presented with biopsychosocial models as the most promising. However, in translation to clinical practice, these models are often applied in an overly reductionist manner, leaving much to be desired. In particular, they often fail to characterize the complexities and dynamics of the lived experience of chronic pain. Recently, an enactive, affordance-based approach has been proposed, opening up new ways to view chronic pain. This model characterizes how the persistence of pain alters a person’s field of affordances: the unfolding set of action possibilities that a person perceives as available to them. The affordance-based model provides a promising perspective on chronic pain as it allows for a systematic investigation of the interactive relation between patients and their environment, including characteristic alterations in the experience of their bodies and the space they inhabit. To help bridge the gap from philosophy to clinical practice, we unpack in this paper the core concepts of an affordance-based approach to chronic pain and their clinical implications, highlighting aspects that have so far received insufficient attention. We do so with an analogy to playing video games, as we consider such comparative illustration a useful tool to convey the complex concepts in an affordance-based model and further explore central aspects of the lived experience of chronic pain.
Article
Full-text available
Metaphorical language is used to convey one thing as representative or symbolic of something else. Metaphor is used in figurative language but is much more than a means of delivering “poetic imagination”. A metaphor is a conceptual tool for categorising, organizing, thinking about, and ultimately shaping reality. Thus, metaphor underpins the way humans think. Our viewpoint is that metaphorical thought and communication contribute to “painogenicity”, the tendency of socio-ecological environments (settings) to promote the persistence of pain. In this perspectives article, we explore the insidious nature of metaphor used in pain language and conceptual models of pain. We explain how metaphor shapes mental organisation to govern the way humans perceive, navigate and gain insight into the nature of the world, i.e., creating experience. We explain how people use metaphors to “project” their private sensations, feelings, and thoughts onto objects and events in the external world. This helps people to understand their pain and promotes sharing of pain experience with others, including health care professionals. We explore the insidious nature of “warmongering” and damage-based metaphors in daily parlance and demonstrate how this is detrimental to health and wellbeing. We explore how metaphors shape the development and communication of complex, abstract ideas, theories, and models and how scientific understanding of pain is metaphorical in nature. We argue that overly simplistic neuro-mechanistic metaphors of pain contribute to fallacies and misnomers and an unhealthy focus on biomedical research, in the hope of developing medical interventions that “prevent pain transmission [sic]”. We advocate reconfiguring pain language towards constructive metaphors that foster a salutogenic view of pain, focusing on health and well-being. We advocate reconfiguring metaphors to align with contemporary pain science, to encourage acceptance of non-medicalised strategies to aid health and well-being. We explore the role of enactive metaphors to facilitate reconfiguration. We conclude that being cognisant of the pervasive nature of metaphors will assist progress toward a more coherent conceptual understanding of pain and the use of healthier pain language. We hope our article catalyses debate and reflection.
Article
Full-text available
People struggle to tell their story of living with pain and when they do it is articulated in a way that may not be understood, heard or taken seriously. Unmasking Pain is an artist-led project that explored creative approaches to tell stories of life with pain. The project was led by a dance theatre company that specialises in storytelling and emotional experiences for players and audiences. The project involved artists and people living with ongoing pain co-creating activities and environments to curiously explore “oneself”, through imagination and creative expression. This article discusses insights and perspectives emerging from the project. The project revealed the power of art to make-sense of oneself with or without pain, and how art facilitates expression of complex inner experience and personal stories. People described Unmasking Pain as “explorative joy despite pain”, and “a new set of rules” that contrasts with those experienced during clinical encounters. We discuss how art has the potential to improve clinical encounters and promote health and well-being, and whether artist-led activities are an intervention, therapy, or something else. Pain rehabilitation specialists from the project described Unmasking Pain as “freeing-up thinking”, allowing conceptual thought beyond the biopsychosocial model of pain. We conclude that art has the potential to shift people living with pain from “I can't do, I am not willing to do it” to “Perhaps I can, I'll give it a go, I enjoyed”.
Article
College students who experience chronic pain are a frequently overlooked population. This research attempts to provide insight into the language that college students use to describe their experiences with chronic pain, challenges they face and coping strategies they use. Over the course of 4 consecutive days, participants responded to an expressive writing prompt asking them to reflect on their emotions and thoughts related to being a college student with chronic pain. Writing samples were then analysed to identify themes pertaining to words with a positive or negative emotional valence, terms used to characterise pain, metaphors used to describe pain, challenges faced, and positive and negative coping strategies used. Results showed that participants were more likely to use negatively valenced words than positively valenced words to describe their pain. Several common words and phrases were used to characterise pain, including metaphors. Finally, participants reported a number of challenges associated with their lived-experience of chronic pain, as well as positive and negative strategies used to cope with those challenges. These findings help to put into perspective the language used to understand, and attempt to cope with, the challenges faced by college students experiencing chronic pain. Research must continue to investigate the needs of this population so that they can be properly supported physically, emotionally, socially and academically.
Article
The importance of honoring and attending to human expressions, including metaphor, is more than an exercise in rhetorical flourish. Attending to metaphorical expressions is an inherent whole-in-motion connection of living the art of humanbecoming with the attention to honoring personal values and choices. The humanbecoming paradigm offers a person-centered approach and thus advances the trust of persons within the various communities receiving healthcare.
Article
Full-text available
War metaphors have been found to be the most frequently used metaphors for conceptualizing diseases, epidemic and medicine. During the COVID-19 epidemic, war metaphors have been found to be widely used in both online and offline coverage. This study mainly focuses on how war metaphors were used in Chinese social media coverage about the COVID-19 epidemic. Using the method of semantic network analysis and the account of The People's Daily on the Chinese social media platform Weibo as an example, the findings show that war metaphors are widely used in the digital coverage of COVID-19. Compared with defensive metaphors and war process metaphors, offensive war metaphors are appearing much more frequently in digital coverage, and often with the use of national collective subjects. These two characteristics highlight how digital coverage uses militarized metaphors to mobilize and inspire enthusiasm among the Chinese people, and to strengthen the Chinese government's control in dealing with the COVID-19 epidemic.
Book
The now-classic Metaphors We Live By changed our understanding of metaphor and its role in language and the mind. Metaphor, the authors explain, is a fundamental mechanism of mind, one that allows us to use what we know about our physical and social experience to provide understanding of countless other subjects. Because such metaphors structure our most basic understandings of our experience, they are "metaphors we live by"--metaphors that can shape our perceptions and actions without our ever noticing them. In this updated edition of Lakoff and Johnson's influential book, the authors supply an afterword surveying how their theory of metaphor has developed within the cognitive sciences to become central to the contemporary understanding of how we think and how we express our thoughts in language.
Article
Pain is initiated by the activation of specialized sensory neurons called nociceptors. These neurons are called upon to detect and report on a wide array of potentially injurious stimuli in a manner appropriate to the physical nature and intensity of these stimuli. In this chapter, we describe characteristic anatomical and physiological features of the nociceptor that shape their sensory and output properties. We next describe several major classes of cell-surface proteins - ion channels, neurotrophin receptors, and G protein-coupled receptors - that account for many of the sensory and signaling functions of nociceptors. We also discuss how molecular polymodality, molecular redundancy, and molecular interaction contribute to emergent properties of nociceptive neurons. Finally, we illustrate how specific changes in expression levels, subcellular localization, and functional properties of the components of the nociceptor molecular toolbox can contribute to pathological pain in the context of inflammation and nerve injury.
Article
Biology and Medicine - The Human Brain and Spinal Cord. A Historical Study Illustrated by Writings from Antiquity to the Twentieth Century. By ClarkEdwin and O'MalleyC. D.. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. 1968. Pp. xiii + 926. $25.00. - Volume 4 Issue 4 - M. D. Grmek
Article
This second edition of The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals was edited by his son Francis Darwin and published in 1890. As Sir Francis notes in his brief preface, because the first edition did not sell out in Charles Darwin’s lifetime, ‘he had no opportunity of publishing the material collected with a view to a second edition.’ This material, in the form of ‘a mass of letters, extracts from and references to books’ was utilised in the second edition, as were Darwin’s pencilled corrections in his own volume of the first. The book is a study of the muscular movements of the face (both human and animal) triggered by the emotions being felt - a ‘physical’ response to a ‘mental’ sensation. Darwin’s detailed analysis of what actually happens to a body in a state of fear, or joy, or anger is illustrated by photographic images.
Article
This is a book about the meanings we make out of pain. The greatest surprise I encountered in discussing this topic over the past ten years was the consistency with which I was asked a single unvarying question: Are you writing about physical pain or mental pain? The overwhelming consistency of this response convinces me that modern culture rests upon and underlying belief so strong that it grips us with the force of a founding myth. Call it the Myth of Two Pains. We live in an era when many people believe - as a basic, unexamined foundation of thought - that pain comes divided into separate types: physical and mental. These two types of pain, so the myth goes, are as different as land and sea. You feel physical pain if your arm breaks, and you feel mental pain if your heart breaks. Between these two different events we seem to imagine a gulf so wide and deep that it might as well be filled by a sea that is impossible to navigate.