BookPDF Available

2015 OUP book "Evolutionary Syntax"

Authors:

Abstract

I n this book, Ljiljana Progovac proposes a gradualist, adaptationist approach to the evolution of syntax, subject to natural selection. She provides a specific framework for its study, combining the fields of evolutionary biology, theoretical syntax, typology, neuroscience, and genetics. The author pursues an internal reconstruction of the stages of grammar based on the syntactic theory associated with Chomskyan Minimalism and arrives at specific, testable hypotheses, which are then corroborated by an abundance of theoretically analysed 'living fossils' drawn from a variety of languages. Her approach demonstrates that these fossil structures do not just coexist alongside more modern structures, but are in fact built into the very foundation of more complex structures, leading to quirks and complexities that are suggestive of a gradualist evolutionary scenario. By reconstructing a particular path along which syntax evolved, Evolutionary Syntax sheds light on the crucial properties of language design itself, as well as on the major parameters of crosslinguistic variation. As a result, this reconstruction can be meaningfully correlated with both the hominin timeline and the ever-growing body of genetic evidence that is available. Features  Outlines novel and testable hypotheses  Contains extensive examples from many different languages  Presented in accessible language, with more technical discussion in footnotes Ljiljana Progovac is Professor of Linguistics and Director of the Linguistics Program at Wayne State University in Detroit. She received her undergraduate degree in English from the University of Novi Sad, Serbia, and her Ph.D. degree in linguistics from the University of Southern California, Los Angeles. Her research interests include syntax, Slavic syntax, and the evolution of syntax. She is the author of Negative and Positive Polarity (CUP, 1994) and A Syntax of Serbian (Slavica, 2005), as well as multiple journal articles and conference papers on language evolution, and is co-editor of The Syntax of Nonsententials (Benjamins, 2006). Order online at www.oup.com/us and enter promotion code AAFLYG6 to save 30%
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Evolutionary Syntax
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Oxford Studies in the Evolution of Language
General Editors
Kathleen R. Gibson, University of Texas at Houston,
and Maggie Tallerman, Newcastle University
RECENTLY PUBLISHED
11
The Prehistory of Language
Edited by Rudolf Botha and Chris Knight
12
The Cradle of Language
Edited by Rudolf Botha and Chris Knight
13
Language Complexity as an Evolving Variable
Edited by Geoffrey Sampson, David Gil, and Peter Trudgill
14
The Evolution of Morphology
Andrew Carstairs-McCarthy
15
The Origins of Grammar
Language in the Light of Evolution II
James R. Hurford
16
How the Brain Got Language
The Mirror System Hypothesis
Michael A. Arbib
17
The Evolutionary Emergence of Language
Evidence and Interference
Edited by Rudolf Botha and Martin Everaert
18
The Nature and Origin of Language
Denis Bouchard
19
The Social Origins of Language
Edited by Daniel Dor, Chris Knight, and Jerome Lewis
20
Evolutionary Syntax
Ljiljana Progovac
See the end of the book for a complete list of titles published
and in preparation for the series.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Evolutionary Syntax
LJILJANA PROGOVAC
1
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
3
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP,
United Kingdom
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the Universitys objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015
The moral rights of the author have been asserted
This is an open access publication, available online and distributed under the terms of a
Creative Commons Attribution Non Commercial No Derivatives 4.0
International licence (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0), a copy of which is available at
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. Subject to this license, all rights are reserved.
Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of this licence
should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Control Number: 2014957516
ISBN 9780198736547(Hbk.)
ISBN 9780198736554(Pbk.)
Printed and bound by
CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, cr04yy
Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and
for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials
contained in any third party website referenced in this work.
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
To Ana and Stefan
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Contents
Preface xi
Acknowledgments xii
List of abbreviations xiv
1. Introduction 1
1.1Background and rationale 1
1.2Proposal in a nutshell 5
1.2.1What did proto-syntax look like? 5
1.2.2A method of reconstruction based on Minimalism 8
1.3Three rough stages 12
1.4Can natural/sexual selection be relevant for syntax? 14
1.5Corroboration and testing 20
1.6A brief comparison with Jackendoff s (and other) approaches 21
1.7Syntactic theory 26
1.8Chapter-by-chapter overview 29
2. The small (clause) beginnings 33
2.1Introduction 33
2.2Root small clauses in English 34
2.3(Unaccusative) Root small clauses in Serbian 40
2.4Small clause syntax is rigid (no Move, no recursion) 44
2.5Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 49
2.5.1Language acquisition 49
2.5.2Agrammatism 52
2.5.3Neuroimaging 52
2.5.4Genetics and the FOXP2gene 53
2.5.5Stratication accounts elsewhere 55
2.6Conclusion 56
3. The intransitive two-word stage: Absolutives, unaccusatives,
and middles as precursors to transitivity 57
3.1Introduction: The two-word stage 57
3.2Intransitive absolutives 62
3.3More on living fossils: What is it that unaccusatives, exocentrics,
and absolutives have in common? 65
3.3.1Unaccusatives 66
3.3.2Exocentric compounds 68
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
3.3.3Absolutives 70
3.3.4More absolutive-like patterns in nominative/accusative
languages 73
3.3.4.1Nominals 73
3.3.4.2Dative subjects 74
3.3.4.3Clausal complements 74
3.4Precursors to transitivity 75
3.4.1Serial verb constructions 75
3.4.2The middleground 76
3.5Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 81
3.6Conclusion 85
4. Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy: Evolving
recursive grammars 86
4.1Hypothesized evolutionary stages of syntax 86
4.2Paratactic proto-syntax stage 89
4.2.1Operation Conjoin: Clause-internally and clause-externally 89
4.2.2Paratactic grammar vs. separate utterances 95
4.2.3Absolutes and correlatives: More on Conjoin 99
4.3The proto-coordination stage 102
4.4The specic functional category stage 109
4.4.1From linkers to specic functional categories 109
4.4.2CP and recursion 111
4.4.3DP and recursion 113
4.4.4Benets of subordination 115
4.4.5Possible precursors to Move 117
4.4.6Transitions and overlaps 120
4.5Corroborating evidence 123
4.5.1Corroborating evidence for the paratactic stage 123
4.5.1.1Ancient languages 123
4.5.1.2Grammaticalization 123
4.5.1.3Comparative studies: Animal communication 124
4.5.1.4Agrammatism 126
4.5.1.5Neuroscience 127
4.5.1.6Acquisition 128
4.5.2Corroborating evidence for a proto-coordination stage 128
4.6Concluding remarks 129
5. Islandhood (Subjacency) as an epiphenomenon of evolutionary
tinkering 131
5.1Introductory note 131
5.2What is islandhood/subjacency? 131
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
viii Contents
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
5.3Why there is no principled account of islandhood 135
5.4Subjacency in the light of evolution 139
5.5Conclusion 142
6. Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils 144
6.1Introduction 144
6.2Paratactic grammar behind VN compounds 145
6.2.1Absolutive-like proto-predication 145
6.2.2Exocentricity 149
6.3A comparison with the hierarchical verbal compounds 152
6.4A surprising verb form: The imperative 156
6.5Crosslinguistic distribution and parallels 162
6.5.1VN compounds in other Slavic languages 162
6.5.2VN compounds in Romance languages 163
6.5.3VN compounds in non-Indo-European languages 166
6.6VN compounds and sexual selection 167
6.7Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 169
6.8Concluding remarks 171
6.9Appendix 1: Additional English VN compounds 171
6.10 Appendix 2: Additional (mostly coarse) VN compounds as
Serbian people and place names 172
7. The plausibility of natural selection for syntax 174
7.1Concrete and selectable advantages accrued by each stage 174
7.2From one-word to two-word utterances: Vagueness galore 175
7.3From the two-word stage to hierarchical syntax: Evolving
transitivity, displacement, and recursion 180
7.3.1Introductory remarks 180
7.3.2Grammaticalizing tense 180
7.3.3Grammaticalizing transitivity 183
7.3.4Recursion 187
7.3.5Historical change vs. language evolution 190
7.4A detailed selection scenario 193
7.5The timeline for the evolution of language 198
7.5.1Was there enough time? 198
7.5.2The timeline 199
8. Conclusion 207
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Contents ix
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Appendix
Testing grounds: Neuroimaging
Co-authored with Noa Ofen 211
References 219
Index of languages and language groups 247
Index of names 249
Index of subjects 255
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
xContents
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Preface
This monograph is meant to be readable and evaluable not only by linguistsall
kinds of linguistsbut also by non-linguists. To this end, painful efforts have been
made to write it clearly, and to present the theories and postulates it draws upon in an
accessible way, without taking away too much from the complexity of the issues
discussed. This is especially important to do in a monograph which purports to
stimulate interdisciplinary projects on language evolution. The footnotes are used to
do justice to some of the complexities, and they include some technical details of the
analysis. The reader who ignores the footnotes will still get the gist of the arguments.
However, the reader will only fully grasp the impact of this proposal after working
through at least Chapter 4, which brings it all together. Each of the Chapters 2,3,and4
considers the proposed proto-syntaxstages from a different angle, and it is only after all
these angles are taken into account that a clear picture will emerge.
This monograph draws directly upon the eld of theoretical syntax, and presents
some of its key postulates in an accessible way so that crossfertilization can be sought
between this eld and the elds of evolutionary biology, neuroscience, and genetics.
In addition, this monograph sometimes takes into account the linguistic (sub-)
disciplines such as typology and theories of grammaticalization. Doing an interdis-
ciplinary study of this kind inevitably leads to some loss of detail with each particular
eld, but my assessment is that any such loss is more than compensated for by the
synergy among these elds, yielding insights that would never be possible without
this kind of approach.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Acknowledgments
The completion of this book owes to many, many peoplecertainly more than I will
remember to mention here. First and foremost, I am deeply thankful to Martha
Ratliff, who carefully read the whole monograph and provided substantial and often
crucial feedback on every single chapter, on every single idea, not only in the context
of this book, but over the span of the past seven or so years. Her criticism,
encouragement, and friendship kept me motivated and balanced. Daniel Ross and
Robert Henderson read selected chapters and provided valuable feedback on them.
I have co-authored work on language evolution with Eugenia Casielles and John
L. Locke, and I cannot imagine better collaborators.
For countless discussions and exchanges on the topic of the evolution of syntax,
I am grateful to, in no particular order: Martha Ratliff, Brady Clark, Dorit Bar-On,
David Gil, Fritz Newmeyer, Jasmina Milićević, Ana Progovac, Stefan Progovac,
Dušan Progovac, Eugenia Casielles, Draga Zec, John L. Locke, Noa Ofen, Relja
Vulanović, Steven Franks, Tecumseh Fitch, Andrea Moro, Ray Jackendoff, Željko
Bošković, Nataša Todorović, Igor Yanovich, Dan Everett, Natasha Kondrashova,
Dan Seely, Robert Henderson, PawełRutkowski, Ellen Barton, Kate Paesani, Pat
Siple, Walter Edwards, Richard Kayne, Juan Uriagereka, Stephanie Harves, Jim
Hurford, Andrew Nevins, Mitch Green, Raffaella Zanuttini, Haiyong Liu, Franck
Floricic, Margaret Winters, Geoff Nathan, Geoffrey Sampson, John McWhorter,
Ruth Crabtree, Bernd Heine, Eric Reuland, Johanna Nichols, Ken Sar, Patricia
Schneider-Zioga, Acrisio Pires, Ileana Paul. Specic acknowledgments to those who
provided data are to be found in the relevant places in the book.
I am very grateful for receiving several grants to pursue this project, including: the
2014 Marilyn Williamson Endowed Distinguished Faculty Fellowship for the experi-
mental fMRI project In Search of Protosyntax in the Brain;2013 Keal Faculty
Fellowship, for this books manuscript preparation; 2007 Gershenson Distinguished
Faculty Award, as well as 2006 Humanities Innovative Projects in the Arts and
Humanities Grant, for the project Rudimentary Grammar in the Evolution of
Human Language.
My immense gratitude goes to the two Oxford University Press reviewers, for
providing amazingly thorough and stimulating comments, as well as to editor
Maggie Tallerman, for many thoughtful and detailed comments. Their comments
made me produce a more nuanced, more engaged, and more informed monograph.
My deep gratitude also goes to the Oxford University Press editor, Julia Steer, for her
thoughtfulness.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The ideas pursued in this monograph have been presented at various conferences
and workshops, which were crucial in shaping my proposal on the evolution of
language, and I am grateful to the audiences there for their valuable feedback: Slavic
Linguistic Society (2006); Michigan Linguistic Society (2006,2007); Georgetown
University Round Table (GURT)(2007); International Linguistics Association
(ILA), New York (2007); Max Planck Workshop on Complexity, Leipzig, Germany
(2007); Illinois State University Conference on Recursion in Human Language
(2007); Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics (FASL)(2007,2008,2012,2014);
American Association of Teachers of Slavic and East European Languages (AAT-
SEEL), Chicago (2007); DGfS Workshop on Language Universals in Bamberg,
Germany (2008); EvoLang in Barcelona, Spain (2008); Biolinguistics: Acquisition
and Language Evolution (BALE) in York, England (2008); Generative Syntax Work-
shop, Novi Sad, Serbia (2008); Ways to Protolanguage Workshop, Torún, Poland
(2009); EvoLang, Utrecht, Netherlands (2010); SyntaxFest, Bloomington, Indiana
(2010); Workshop on Protolanguage, University of Virginia, Charlottesville (2012);
Symposium on Formal Linguistics and the Measurement of Grammatical Complex-
ity, Seattle, Washington (2012); Transcending the Boundaries Workshop, Duke
Institute for Brain Sciences (2013); University of Connecticut Workshop on the
Evolution of Syntax, Storrs, Connecticut (2014).
Needless to say, I have not always heeded the advice, and whether I did or not, all
errors remain mine.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Acknowledgments xiii
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
List of abbreviations
1,2,3First, Second, or Third Person
ABSL Al-Sayyid Bedouin Sign Language
ACC Accusative
BP Before Present
CP Complementizer Phrase
DOM Differential Object Marking
DP Determiner Phrase
ECM Exceptional Case Marking
F Feminine (gender)
IE Indo-European
IFG Inferior frontal gyrus
IMP Imperative
INF Innitive
M Masculine (gender)
N Neuter (gender)
mya Million years ago
NOM Nominative
NP Noun Phrase
NSL Nicaraguan Sign Language
PART Participle
PERF Perfective
PIE Proto-Indo-European
PL Plural
PRES Present
pSTS Posterior superior temporal sulcus
SC Small Clause
SG Singular
SOV Subject-Object-Verb
SVO Subject-Verb-Object
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
TAM Tense/Aspect/Mood
TP Tense Phrase
VN Verb-noun
VP Verb Phrase
vP Light Verb Phrase
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
List of abbreviations xv
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The sensations and ideas thus excited in us by music, or expressed by the cadences
of oratory, appear, from their vagueness, yet depth, like mental reversions to the
emotions and thought of a long-past age.
(Darwin 1874:595)
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
1
Introduction
1.1Background and rationale
Broadly speaking, the goal of this monograph is to provide a framework, a program
for studying the evolution of syntax, by relying on a theory of syntax. The intent is
to show that syntax can be decomposed into evolutionary primitives/layers, and
that such decomposition can not only help identify the stages of evolutionary
progression of syntax, but also shed light on the very nature of language design.
I also show that the progression through the postulated stages makes evolutionary
sense, i.e., that each new stage brings some concrete advantage(s) over the previous
stage(s), and that such advantage(s) would have been subject to natural/sexual
selection.
1
My proposal is therefore that the capacity for syntax evolved incremen-
tally, in stages, subject to selection pressures.
2
This approach leaves the door wide
open for the possibility that the pressures to evolve syntax, and language in general,
played an active role in shaping human brains, contrasting with the view that the
brains capabilities evolved for some other purpose, and then got co-opted for
language.
This monograph draws on and brings together: (i) Darwins(1859,1872,1874)
theory of gradualist evolution invoking natural/sexual selection; (ii) some key syn-
tactic postulates of the Minimalist Program for syntax (e.g. Chomsky 1995) and its
predecessors; (iii) Jackendoff s(1999,2002) idea of syntactic fossils;and (iv) the
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
1
While sexual selection is typically considered to be a subcase of natural selection, given that they both
ultimately reduce to reproduction, I sometimes use both terms in this book next to each other in order to
highlight the prominent role sexual selection might have played in language evolution. As I will argue, at
least some aspects of the evolution of syntax/language may not have been adaptive in the sense of physical
survival in the environment, but instead benecial for securing mates.
2
When I refer to the gradual evolution of syntax in this monograph, this can also be interpreted as the
gradual evolution of the capacity to use syntax, one aspect of which is the capacity to establish numerous
neural connections in the brain, as discussed in Section 1.4. But my primary intent here is to hypothesize
what kind of syntax/grammar was actually in use in each proposed stage, whether the use of simpler
grammars at these stages reected the lesser capacity for establishing a multitude of neural connections
necessary to support more complex syntax, or whether the use of simpler syntax simply reected the lack of
innovation (of more complex syntactic structures) at that point, or both.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
idea of internal reconstruction using a linguistic theory (Heine and Kuteva 2007).
3
The proposed framework is not only informed by syntactic theory, but it is also
consistent with the forces of natural/sexual selection and it is specic enough to yield
testable hypotheses that can be subjected to e.g. neuroimaging experiments. Remark-
ably, by reconstructing a particular path along which syntax evolved, this approach is
able to explain the crucial properties of language design itself, as well as some major
parameters of crosslinguistic variation.
4
In the spirit of Darwin (e.g. 1859), and as elaborated in Jacob (1977), evolution is to
be seen as a tinkerer,rather than an engineer. Unlike engineering, which designs
from scratch, with foresight and plan, and with perfection, tinkering works by
cobbling something together out of bits and pieces that happen to be available locally,
with no long-term foresight. Evolution is also known to be conservative and not to
throw a good thing away, but to build upon it, which is why one should expect to nd
constructions of previous stages (fossils) in the later stages. One of the themes of
this monograph is that the advent of a new stage does not obliterate the previous
stage(s), but rather that the older stages continue to co-exist, often in specialized or
marginalized roles, in addition to being built into the very foundation of more
complex structures.
However, many syntacticians believe that it is inconceivable for there to exist, or to
have ever existed, a human language which does not come complete with unbounded
Merge, Move, structural case, subordination, and a series of functional projections:
the hallmarks of modern syntax. The claim is often that syntax in its entirety evolved
suddenly, as a result of a single event. The following quotation from Berwick (1998:
3389) summarizes this view: In this sense, there is no possibility of an intermediate
syntax between a non-combinatorial one and full natural languageone either has
Merge in all its generative glory, or one has no combinatorial syntax at all ...(see
also Chomsky 2002,2005; Piattelli-Palmarini 2010; Moro 2008). When it comes to
language evolution, this stance has been challenged by e.g. Pinker and Bloom (1990);
Newmeyer (1991,1998,2005); Jackendoff (1999,2002); Culicover and Jackendoff
(2005); Givón (e.g. 2002a,b, 2009); Tallerman (2007,2013a,b, 2014a,b); Heine and
Kuteva (2007); Hurford (2007,2012); Progovac (2006,2009a, b, 2013b).
5
Most recently,
3
This may appear to be an uneasy alliance, especially given that Noam Chomsky himself has rejected a
gradualist approach to the evolution of syntax, as discussed below in the text (in this respect, see Clark 2013
for the argument that ones theoretical framework does not determine ones stand on language evolution).
To my mind, a syntactic program such as Minimalism is not the truth about language, but it is a framework
which provides tools that can be used to search for the truth (see Section 1.7). The tools of other approaches
can certainly be used as well.
4
As put in Givón (2002b: 39), like other biological phenomena, language cannot be fully understood
without reference to its evolution, whether proven or hypothesized.An even stronger claim to thiseffect can be
found in Dobzhanskys(1973) article titled Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution.
5
For a thorough overview of the recent approaches to language evolution, the reader is referred to the
introductory chapter of Heine and Kuteva (2007), as well as to Tallerman and Gibson (2012).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
2Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
on the other hand, Berwick and Chomsky (2011:2931) assert again that the simplest
assumption, hence the one we adopt ..., is that the generative procedure emerged
suddenly as the result of a minor mutation. In that case we would expect the
generative procedure to be very simple ...The generative process is optimal. ...Lan-
guage is something like a snowake, assuming its particular form by virtue of laws of
nature ...Optimally, recursion can be reduced to Merge ...
6
There is no room in this
picture for any precursors to languagesay a language-like system with only short
sentences. The same holds for language acquisition, despite appearances...
7
This monograph shows that there is in fact ample room for a language system with
short (and at) sentences, and that such constructs are not just something we can
postulate for the evolution of syntax, but that they are also found as living fossils
throughout present-day languages (see e.g. Jackendoff 1999,2002 for the idea of living
fossils of syntax). In biological literature, living fossils are dened as species that have
changed little from their fossil ancestors in the distant past, e.g. lungsh (Ridley
1993).
8
Signicantly, such fossil structures in syntax are clearly characterizeable using
the tools of Minimalism, and their properties follow precisely from the reconstruc-
tion formula introduced in the following section. For something to qualify as a
syntactic fossil, I argue, it has to be theoretically proven to be measurably simpler
than its more complex/more modern counterparts, and yet show clear continuity
with them. Strikingly, there is evidence that these (proto-syntactic) fossils provide a
foundation upon which more complex syntactic structures are built.
Jackendoff (1999,2002) considers paratactic grammars as evolutionarily more
primary than hierarchical grammars, and identies some fossils of such grammars,
including compounds and adjunction processes (see Section 1.6for more details
regarding Jackendoff s approach). Parataxis can be considered as a loose combin-
ation or concatenation of two or more elements. Jackendoff s claim is that the
achievements of the previous stages are still there, co-existing side by side with
more complex hierarchical constructions. This monograph shows that one can
make an even stronger and more specic claim than this, which is that these
paratactic (fossil) structures are built into the very foundation of every modern clause
6
This idea that syntax is optimal in some sense can be found in various recent papers on Minimalism.
According to the so-called Strong Minimalist Thesis (SMT), language is an optimal solution to legibility
conditions (e.g. Chomsky 2000:96; see also Epstein, Kitahara, and Seely 2010). However, what optimal
should mean in this context has not been dened, and this makes it impossible to falsify these claims, or
to respond to them in a meaningful way (see also the discussion in Johnson and Lappin 1999).
7
In fact, saltationist views sometimes irt with the idea that not just syntax, but language in its entirety,
arose as one single event. While most claims are vague in this respect, Piattelli-Palmarini (2010:160) states
that it is illusoryto think that words can exist outside of full-blown syntax, or that any protolanguage can
be reconstructed in which words are used, but not full-blown syntax.
8
Linguistic fossils are also discussed in Bickerton (1990,1998), although Bickerton claims that there is
no continuity between such fossils, found e.g. in pidgin languages and early childrens speech, and modern
grammars. In addition, Givón (e.g. 1979) also refers to vestiges of previous stages of language in present-day
languages, in a very similar sense.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Background and rationale 3
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
or phrase, as will be seen below. Conside r also that Jack endoff s (and Bickertons
1990) concatenation protolanguage stage differs from mine in another important
respect: while theirs allows more than one argument per verb from the very start,
I argue that the initial stage of proto-syntax was necessarily intransitive, as well as
absolutive-like (Section 1.2).
9
Bickerton (1990, and subsequent work) claims that what he terms protolanguage
does not have syntax, and is in fact not real language for that reason (see also
Section 1.6). My use of the term proto-syntaxis meant to imply that this is a
stage which shows syntax, although of a different, simpler kind.
10
Postulating an
absolutive-like two-word stage allows for a more ne-grained identication of stages,
which in turn makes it easier to identify the pressures, as well as precursors, for
evolving hierarchical grammars, including transitivity. The postulation of an
intransitive absolutive-like stage also opens up the possibility of using crosslinguistic
variation in the expression of transitivity to correlate these stages with the hominin
timeline (Chapter 7).
This monograph thus challenges the view that syntax is an all-or-nothing package,
and that it evolved suddenly in all its complexity. My position is instead that the
capacity for syntax evolved gradually, in stages, subject to selection pressures.
11
It is
based on very specic claims, whose feasibility can be evaluated and tested both in the
theory of syntax and in neuroscience, as well as corroborated by the ndings in other
relevant elds or subelds, including language acquisition, grammaticalization the-
ory, typology, aphasia, and genetics. There are several components of this proposal
that set it apart from the other approaches to the evolution of language. First, this
approach pursues an internal reconstruction of the stages of grammar based on the
syntactic theory, to arrive at precise, specic, and tangible hypotheses. Second, it
provides an abundance of theoretically analyzed living fossilsfor each postulated
stage, drawn from a variety of languages. Third, the postulated stages, as well as
fossils, are at the appropriate level of granularity to reveal the selection pressures that
would have driven the progression through stages. Fourth, this approach offers a very
9
The meaning of the term absolutive-likewill be made much clearer in Chapter 3. For now, it is to be
understood as a construction with a verb and one single argument whose status as a subject vs. as an object
of the verb is not syntactically specied. This characterization pertains most clearly to constructions which
are ergative/absolutive both syntactically and morphologically, as will be explained in Chapter 3.
10
In this book, to avoid confusion, I will reserve the term protolanguagefor presyntactic (non-
combinatorial) stages of language, as is the one-word stage, even though, in principle, the term protolanguage
could be taken to encompass proto-syntax as well.
11
A reviewer has wondered if the term gradualcan be interpreted to mean continuous,as that
would not be the correct characterization of what I mean here. The term has been associated with
Darwinian adaptationism, and has been used in this context, with a clear sense of incremental processes,
using small steps rather than leaps, as discussed at length in e.g. Dawkins (1996); see also Fitch (2010:46).
As Dawkins (1996) explains, by situating Darwins writings within the context of the debates of his own
time, one can clearly see that Darwin was not a constant-rate gradualist, as is sometimes suggested by
punctuated equilibrium advocates.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
4Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
specic experimental design for testing the proposed hypotheses. Last but not least, it
arrives at a reconstruction which can be meaningfully correlated with the hominin
timeline.
This monograph draws directly upon the eld of theoretical syntax, and presents
some of its key postulates in an accessible way so that cross-fertilization can be
sought between this eld and the elds of e.g. evolutionary biology, neuroscience, and
genetics. An interdisciplinary endeavor of this scope will inevitably lead to some loss
of depth and technical detail with each particular eld, including when it comes to
the theory of syntax, but my assessment is that any such loss is more than compen-
sated for by the potential to cross-fertilize these elds, yielding insights that would
never be possible by looking at each eld separately. As much as this book is about
reconstructing the evolutionary path for syntax, it is also deeply about what syntax
actually is, as the two questions are inextricably linked. This particular evolutionary
scenario offers a reconstruction of how communicative benets may have been
involved in the shaping of the formal design of language itself.
1.2Proposal in a nutshell
1.2.1What did proto-syntax look like?
Specically, my proposal is that the rst sentenceswere paratactic (not hierarchical,
not headed) combinations of e.g. a verband a noun(akin to present-day
intransitive small clauses), in which the noun, the only argument of the verb, was
absolutive-like, specied as neither subject nor object.
12
To put it in less technical
terms, I propose that a proto-sentence was somewhat like a two-slot mold, which
could t just two words, for example one verb and one noun, and as such it could not
be transitive, as a transitive structure requires three basic elements, a verb, a subject,
and an object. While postulating two-slot proto-grammars may seem far-fetched at
rst sight, the (fossil) structures that clearly exhibit properties of such grammars are
easily found across various constructions in all present-day languages, if not at the
level of the sentence, then at the level of the noun phrase or at the level of the
compound. My basic argument is that such fossil small clauses have been built into
more complex hierarchical structures, rather than have been replaced by them.
12
More accurately, instead of using the term sentencehere, one can talk about combinations of nouns
and verbs, as some of these combinations appear to be compounds used as names/nicknames. In addition,
some of these combinations may involve predicates other than verbs, but the majority of the examples
I consider in the monograph consists of a verb and a noun, which is also in line with Heine and Kutevas
(2007) conclusion that nouns and verbs were the rst (proto-)word categories to emerge in the evolution of
human language. A reviewer points out that noun-noun compounds may also be of interest for this
approach, as well as verb-verb combinations, as attested in serial verb constructions in some languages.
I return to serial verb constructions in Sections 1.6and 3.4.1, and to noun-noun compounding in
Section 1.6.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Proposal in a nutshell 5
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
There are additional reasons to believe that the rst syntactic combinations were
short (and binary), that is, that they consisted of only two (main) elements loosely/
paratactically combined. First of all, binary branching in syntactic theory (including
in Minimalism) is considered to be a syntactic universal, that is, it is considered that
all syntactic operations can only join two elements at a time. The overwhelming
majority of compounds across languages are binary, consisting of only two free
morphemes. Child language acquisition is typically reported to proceed from a
one-word stage to a two-word stage, before combining more words into single
utterances becomes available (e.g. Bloom 1970).
13
In addition, where (small) clauses
themselves are combined paratactically with other such clauses (as in e.g. Nothing
ventured, nothing gained;Easy come, easy go;Come one, come all), the number of
clauses that combine is again overwhelmingly just two.
14
There are some exceptions, such as No shoes, no shirt, no service; however,
combining more than two expressions paratactically often becomes very difcult to
process, as the following example helps illustrate:
(1) Nothing ventured, nothing gained, nothing lost.
Oneisnotsurewhattheaboveexamplemeans.Doesitmeanthatifnothingis
ventured, and nothing is gained, then nothing is lost either? Or does it mean that if
nothing is ventured, then nothing is either gained or lost? Or something else? This
is not grammatically specied in the example in (1), and our brains do not seem
prepared to readily assign meanings to such ternary structures. The only way to
unambiguously accommodate three or more clauses like that into a single utter-
ance is by creating hierarchical syntax, using function words such as if, then,
and,etc.
If our ancestors started with the capacity to use small (clause) paratactic gram-
mars of the kind approximated above, they would have faced ample evolutionary
pressures to develop a capacity for more elaborated grammars, that is, grammars
that can accommodate a combination of more than just two clauses, as well as
transitive grammars, which can accommodate more than two words/phrases. In
other words, my claim is that the two-slot proto-syntax (an early stage in the
evolution of syntax) characterized by paratactic union (#), operated both inside the
sentence (to produce intransitive two-word proto-sentences, such as Come # all),
and at the level of clause union (to produce binary combinations of the kind Come
one, # come all).
13
In his Overview to the edited collection, Bloom (1994) species that the two-word stage is typically
observed between the ages of eighteen months and two and a half years.
14
There is a wealth of data from a variety of languages which follow this AB-AC formula, and these are
typically fossilized expressions, although in some languages, such as Hmong, they can be in productive use,
exemplifying true living fossils (Chapters 2,3, and 4).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
6Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
It has been hypothesized by several researchers that there was a simpler stage of
syntax in the evolution of human language, involving elements loosely concatenated
into a single utterance (e.g. by Givón 1979,2002a,b; Dwyer 1986; Bickerton 1990,1998;
Jackendoff 1999,2002; Culicover and Jackendoff 2005; Deutscher 2005; Burling 2005;
Gil 2005; Tallerman 2007,2013a,b, 2014a,b; Hurford 2007,2012; Progovac 2006,2008a,
b, 2009a,b; Jackendoff and Wittenberg 2014; and many others. My approach builds
on these claims, and takes them signicantly further, to hypothesize an intransitive,
absolutive-like, two-word (small clause) stage (Progovac 2014a,b).
Using crosslinguistic data, Progovac (e.g. 2006,2008a,b, 2009a,b) has extended the
idea of paratactic proto-grammars (i.e. early evolutionary stages of grammar) to what
is referred to in the literature as small clausesin embedded contexts, but which are
also found in isolation as root small clauses (2,4). According to this proposal, clauses
in (2) and (4) are relevant fossils of the two-word stage, as they are not only
intransitive, but also lack (at least) the TP (Tense Phrase) layer of structure, typically
associated with modern nite sentences in Minimalism (3,5). They can be reduced to
a single layer of structure, the layer of the small clause.
(2) Problem solved. Case closed. Me rst! Him worry?!
(3) The problem has been solved. The case has been closed.
I will be rst! He worries?!
(4) a. Pala vlada. (Serbian)
15
fall.
PART
government
b. Pao sneg.
fall.
PART
snow
c. Stigla pošta.
arrive.
PART
mail
(5) a. Vlada je pala.
AUX
The government has fallen.
b. Pao je sneg.
It has snowed.
c. Stigla je pošta.
The mail has arrived.
My argument is that comparable small clauses served as precursors to more complex
sentences (TPs) in the evolution of human language, given that they are syntactically
15
The form of the verb in the examples in (4) is a perfective participle form, indicating perfective/
completed aspect. There is no past tense marking in these examples. In contrast, the past tense is marked in
the examples in (5) by the auxiliary je.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Proposal in a nutshell 7
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
measurably simpler, and given that, according to the theory, they provide a founda-
tion for building TPs (Sections 1.2.2;1.7).
16
The argument for the proposed progression from a small clause to a TP stage has
three prongs to it: (i) providing evidence of tinkeringwith the language design, in
the sense that older structures (i.e. small clauses) get built into more complex
structures (i.e. TPs); (ii) identifying living fossilsof the small clause stage in modern
languages; and (iii) identifying existing or potential corroborating evidence and
testing grounds, from language acquisition, agrammatism, genetics, and neurosci-
ence. In addition, the argument is that the progression from a small clause stage to a
TP stage brings with it concrete communicative advantages, which could have been
subject to natural/sexual selection (see Section 1.4).
It is important to keep in mind here that the fossils discussed in this monograph
can only be seen as rough approximations of the structures once used in the deep
evolutionary past. Depending on the language in question, such fossils in present-day
languages may show morphological markings, e.g. case marking and aspect marking.
It is in no way implied in this monograph that the proto-syntax in evolutionary times
had any such morphology. The structures identied as fossils in this monograph
count as fossils in some relevant respect under consideration, for example, in their
lack of a TP, but not in all their properties. It also seems that some of the fossils
discussed in the monograph (such as exocentric verb-noun (VN) compounds, e.g.
cry-baby,pick-pocket,hunch-back,rattle-snake) are closer approximations of the
proto-syntactic constructs than others, for the reasons given in e.g. Chapter 6,
which discusses such compounds in great detail.
It is also of interest that different languages can use the foundational, fossil
structures in different ways, and in different constructions. In some languages, the
fossil constructions are still in productive use, as is the case with e.g. Serbian
unaccusative small clauses in (4), to be covered in Chapter 2, and Hmong AB-AC
formulae, as discussed in Chapters 2,3, and 4. Looking at more languages in this light
would uncover more types of fossil structures, and provide further insights into the
evolution and nature of human language.
1.2.2A method of reconstruction based on Minimalism
The method used in this monograph for hypothesizing the stages of proto-syntax can
be characterized as internal reconstruction based on the theory of clause/sentence
16
In this respect,my analysis of small clauses being transformed into full sentences/TPsresembles, to some
extent, the development of the heart (thanks to Garrett Mitchener, p.c. April 2013, for the analogy). The
embryo initially has only a small precursor to the heart,consisting of two simple tubeswhich merge (primitive
heart), andthis precursor gradually bulges and expands to become the complex heart. A reviewerhas pointed
out that the analogy is not complete, as the complex human heart no longer has the two tubes discernible.
Perhaps the analogy can at least be taken to show that the complex human heart does not come into existence
in its full complexity, but that there is a simple precursor, however hard it may be to imagine one.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
8Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
structure adopted in Minimalism (e.g. Chomsky 1995) and its predecessors. The
simplied hierarchy of functional projections/layers characterizing modern clauses/
sentences in Minimalism is given in (6).
(6) CP > TP > vP > VP/SC
Very roughly speaking, the inner VP (Verb Phrase)/SC (Small Clause) layer accom-
modates the verb/predicate and one argument, while vP (Light Verb Phrase) accom-
modates an additional argument, such as agent, in transitive structures. TP (Tense
Phrase) accommodates the expression of tense and niteness, while CP (Comple-
mentizer Phrase) accommodates subordination/embedding, among other processes
(see Section 1.7for more discussion).
This hierarchy is a theoretical construct which offers a natural and precise method
of reconstructing previous syntactic stages in language evolution, as outlined in (7).
(7) Internal Reconstruction, based on syntactic theory
Structure X is considered to be primary relative to Structure Y if
X can be composed independently of Y, but Y can only be built
upon the foundation of X.
17
While SCs/VPs can be composed without the TP layer, TPs must be built on the
foundation of a small clause/VP, as postulated in the theory of syntax.
18
Likewise,
while TPs can be composed without CPs, CPs require the foundation of a TP. One
can thus reconstruct a stage of proto-syntax which had no TPs or CPs, but had SCs/
VPs, and possibly also vPs. To put it differently, one can reconstruct a stage in the
evolution of syntax in which it was possible to compose structures comparable to
those in (2) and (4), but not structures comparable to those in (3) and (5).
Similarly, while SCs/VPs can be composed without a vP layer, the vP can only
build its shell upon the foundation of a SC/VP. One can thus reconstruct a vP-less
(intransitive) stage in the evolution of syntax, reduced to only SC/VP. By removing
these three layers of hierarchical structure, one is essentially left with an intransitive
at small clause, which is arguably absolutive-like, and which approximates the small
clause beginnings without functional projections, and without the possibility of
distinguishing subjects from objects (see Section 1.2.1). I focus on reconstructing
the properties of these TP-less and vP-less stages of proto-syntax in Chapters 2and 3
respectively. The signicance of the emergence of CP is discussed in Chapters 4,5,
and 6, but the focus of this book is on the earliest stages of proto-syntax, as they are
17
The term primaryis used here in the sense that there was a stage in language evolution when the
primary structure X was in use, but not the non-primary structure Y. This is also the sense in which the
internal reconstruction method is used by Heine and Kuteva (2007), as elaborated below.
18
The idea that a sentence (TP) is built upon the foundation of a small clause is one of the most stable
postulates in the theory (Section 1.7).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Proposal in a nutshell 9
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
most relevant for the biological evolution of language, as well as most difcult to
reconstruct.
The absence of each functional projection has concrete and observable conse-
quences, as established based on the theory of syntax, as well as on the abundance
of fossil data taken from across languages. A variety of these fossil constructions
will be exemplied and discussed from this viewpoint throughout the monograph,
including absolutives, unaccusatives, exocentrics, and middles. Consistent with the
gradualist approach advocated here, it is signicant that these fossils include
constructions which straddle the boundary between transitivity and intransitivity:
the so-called middles.
The recurring theme of this monograph is that each new stage preserves, and
builds upon, the achievements of the previous stage(s). Thus, a TP is built upon
the foundation of the small clause (which might or might not include a vP),
and transitive structures (vP/VP shells), as well as middles,are built upon
the foundation of intransitive (absolutive-like) VPs/SCs. In brain stratication
accounts (see e.g. Vygotsky 1979 and Jean Piagets work, as outlined in e.g.
Gruber and Vonèche 1977), as well as in the triune brain proposals (e.g. MacLean
1949), the common theme is the inclusion of attainments of earlier stages in the
structures of later stages (Section 2.5.5). This kind of scaffolding nds corroboration
in the processes of language acquisition and language loss, as well as in language
disorders.
A method of internal reconstruction is also used in Heine and Kuteva (2007), but
based on a different linguistic theory: a theory of grammaticalization. Since gram-
maticalization typically works in the direction of developing a functional (gram-
matical) category out of a lexical category (or a more abstract category out of a
more concrete category), but not the other way around, the authors reconstruct a
stage in the evolution of human language which only had lexical (content) cat-
egories, but not functional categories. In that sense, lexical categories are primary
with respect to corresponding functional categories (see Footnote 17). Importantly,
the proposed syntactic reconstruction in (67) leads to a convergent result: strip-
ping away functional layers (such as CP, TP, and vP) leaves one with a bare small
clause, consisting typically only of a verb and a noun, with no functional projec-
tions on top. What these two methods share is that they use a linguistic theory,as
well as a wealth of linguistic data behind these theories, to arrive at hypotheses
about language evolution, and it is signicant that these two approaches lead to a
convergent result.
The sense in which the term internal reconstructionis used by Heine and Kuteva
(2007:24), as well as in this book, is based on the assumption that languages reveal
evidence of past changes in their present structures, and that certain kinds of present
alternation in a language can be reconstructed back to an earlier stage in which there
was no alternation of that kind (see also e.g. Comrie 2002). The internal reconstruction
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
10 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
method contrasts with the comparative method, which necessarily looks at more than
one language in order to reconstruct the language of the common ancestor.
19
My approach does not lead to identical results to those reached by Heine and
Kuteva (2007), but rather to results that complement each other, and reinforce each
other. Heine and Kutevas(2007) focus is on the lexicon, that is, word categories,
while the focus here is on syntax/grammar, that is, on how the words in that lexicon
were combined, and how these syntactic combinations got to be more complex
over time.
It is worth pointing out, however, that the capacity for abstract vocabulary
building is not unrelated to the emergence of functional categories and hierarchical
syntax. Grammaticalization processes typically take more concrete words, such as go,
say, etc., and metaphorically extend their meanings to the point when they become
e.g. highly abstract functional categories (such as tense markers, or subordination
markers; see e.g. Heine and Kuteva 2007 and references there). Thus, the capacity for
hierarchical syntax probably presupposes the capacity for abstract vocabulary build-
ing based on metaphorical extension. According to e.g. Givón (2002a: 1512), one
reason to believe that some basic words used in isolation (one-word stage) preceded a
syntactic stage is that grammatical categories are more abstract than lexical categories
(see also Tallerman 2014a).
While my approach identies specic syntactic stages of language evolution, as
well as evolutionary pressures that would have driven the progression through stages,
Heine and Kuteva do not explore the role of natural/sexual selection in the evolution
of the lexicon or syntax. Even though the nal evidence regarding the origins of
human language may have to come from other disciplines, perhaps neuroscience and
genetics, only linguistics can provide specic and linguistically sound hypotheses for
these elds to engage.
This book thus contributes to the view that language, and in particular syntax,
emerged gradually, through evolutionary tinkering. However, the gradualist view of
the evolution of language is sometimes dismissed by pointing out that recently
observed language changes are not always linear/directional, and that it is possible
19
It should be pointed out here that internal reconstruction (as opposed to the comparative method)
has been used much less in phonological reconstruction, and that syntactic reconstruction in particular is
much newer and less successful than phonological reconstruction. However, it is pointed out in e.g.
Newman (2014:13), as well as references cited there, that internal reconstruction has a lot to offer:
Although internal reconstruction (IR) is not as well understood nor commonly utilized as the comparative
method, it has a long pedigree in historical linguistics (see Hoenigswald 1944; Kuryłowicz 1973). While
recognizing the limitations of IR, most historical linguists appreciate its value in historical linguistics and
would agree with Hock (1991:550) when he concludes: internal reconstruction is an extremely useful and
generally quite accurate tool for the reconstruction of linguistic prehistory.’” Newman also says in a
footnote that Ringe (2003)isacurious exceptionin rejecting the IR method. This controversy aside,
when it comes to the evolution of syntax, the internal reconstruction method is the only one available. It is
also a method used for reconstructing language isolates, such as Basque.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Proposal in a nutshell 11
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
both to develop certain (more complex) forms, and to revert back to the original
(simpler) forms. So the question here is, once you evolve more complex structures,
can you or can you not revert to a paratactic (small clause) grammar?
The basic claim of this monograph is that the foundational, paratactic structures
remain built into the very foundation of the hierarchical grammars, and that they
also continue to live in various marginal, and sometimes not so marginal, construc-
tions, which can be characterized as living fossilsof the paratactic stage. If so, then
it should not be impossible to fall back onto these simpler, paratactic strategies, still
alive in the brain, especially in the case of adversity, such as agrammatism, pidginiza-
tion, and second language acquisition. Evolution should be able to revert back to
more robust, foundational strategies. According to the so-called last in, rst out
principle, used in e.g. computer science and psychology (see e.g. Code 2005), what is
acquired last is the most shallow/fragile layer that is the easiest to lose, and vice versa.
When it comes to complex syntax, such loss can take place in pidginization and in
agrammatic aphasia (see also Gil 2005 for the development of Riau Indonesian; also
Heine and Kuteva 2007).
In fact, there are reversals elsewhere in the evolution of organisms. As observed e.g.
in the work of Richard Dawkins, body hair is one of those traits that can recede and
reappear a number of times in the history of a species (e.g. with mammoths, who
rapidly became wooly in the most recent ice ages in Eurasia). In addition, some recent
genetic studies reveal that reversals and losses are possible even in the evolution of
multi-cellularity, a major transition in the history of life. For example, Schirrmeister,
Antonelli, and Bagheri (2011) report that the majority of extant cyanobacteria, one of
the oldest phyla still alive, including many single-celled species, descend from multi-
cellular ancestors, and that reversals to unicellularity occurred at least ve times. In a
sense, then, pidginization, and other similar losses of syntactic suprastructure, can be
seen as comparable to the return to a simpler, unicellular mode of existence.
1.3Three rough stages
As outlined in the previous sections, this monograph focuses on intransitive fossil
clauses of various kinds, lacking the layers of functional structure characterizing
modern clauses, including TP and vP layers. This monograph is further concerned
with the nature of the bond between the merged elements in these proto-syntactic
constructs, as well as with how that bond evolves over time to be able to support
processes such as coordination and subordination. In this respect, I identify the
following three rough stages in the evolution of syntactic bond (iiii), following a
hypothetical non-syntactic one-word stage (0). This progression is meant to shed
light on the emergence of functional categories, as well as on the nature of modern
language design, and the existence of various transitional, ambivalent structures (see
Chapter 4for details).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
12 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(0) One-word stage (no combinatorial power/no syntax)
This stage is characterized by single words intended as complete utterances (as in e.g.
Run!Snake!Out!)
(i) Paratactic stage (proto-syntax)
In this paratactic stage, prosody/supra-segmentals provide the only glue for (proto-)
Merge. In other words, in this stage there is prosodic evidence, but not any segmental
evidence, that the words/constituents are Merged.
20
The proto-syntax of this stage can
be characterized by an operation Conjoin (or proto-Merge), rather than Merge proper
as conceived in Minimalism. As explained at length in Chapter 4, Conjoin, which is
akin to Adjoin, does not create headedness or hierarchy, and the products of Conjoin
are at structures, which do not allow Move or recursion, as can be corroborated by
looking at the present-day fossils which approximate this stage (Chapter 2). Adjunc-
tion itself is known to be rigid when it comes to Move, and adjuncts are well-known
islands for movement, as discussed below (see also Chapter 5on Subjacency).
(ii) Proto-coordination stage
This is a stage in which, in addition to prosody, a conjunction/linker provides all-
purpose segmental glue to hold the utterance together. In this stage, the evidence for
(proto-)Merge is more robust, as it retains the prosodic evidence (the only type of
evidence available in the previous stage(s)), and adds to it segmental evidence (the
linker), even though in this stage the segmental piece does not provide any more
specic information regarding the nature of the categories and projections. In other
words, in this stage the evidence for proto-Merge is dual: both prosodic (retained
from the paratactic stage), and segmental (in the form of a linker), an innovation of
this stage. This stage is arguably still syntactically at/non-hierarchical, and still does
not allow Move, which is consistent with the well-known fact that coordination
structures even today constitute islands for Move (Chapter 5). The proposal is that
the meaningless linkers/proto-conjunctions, best approximated by the conjunction
of the type and in present-day languages, were among the rst functional categories,
whose initial purpose was only to consolidate the important achievement of Stage (i),
the ability to (proto-)Merge, i.e. to Conjoin.
(iii) Specic functional category stage (hierarchical/subordination stage)
In this hierarchical stage, in addition to prosody and to segmental glue, specic
functional categories become available, providing specialized syntactic glue for con-
stituent cohesion, including tense particles and subordinators/complementizers. In
20
Roughly speaking, prosody refers to the rhythm, stress, and intonation of speech, while segments
refer to specic sounds.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Three rough stages 13
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
other words, this stage includes all the attainments of the previous stages (prosody
and linkers), and adds another, which is to use the segmental piece (linker) also to
identify the type of the constituent created by Merge. I argue that it is only at this
stage that hierarchical structure, Move, and recursion become available.
21
These postulated stages mark a progression from least syntactically elaborated
(parataxis), to more elaborated (coordination), to most elaborated (specialized func-
tional categories/projections). My claim is that each of these grammars can operate
both clause-internally, e.g. to combine a subject and a predicate into a small clause
(e.g. Come winter,...), and clause-externally, to combine two such clauses into a
single utterance (e.g. Come one, come all). As will be shown, all the hierarchical
phenomena discussed in this book, including transitivity and CP subordination,
seem to have alternative, paratactic routes.
This approach can explain why adjuncts and conjuncts are islands for Move, and
more generally why languages exhibit Subjacency/islandhood effects in the rst place
(Chapter 5). It also sheds light on the vast overlap and indeterminacy between coord-
ination structures and paratactic structures, at one end of the spectrum, as well as
between coordination structures and subordination structures at the other end. The
overlap is expected if each stage is taken to gradually integrate into the next (Chapter 4).
1.4Can natural/sexual selection be relevant for syntax?
One encounters three main types of argument against subjecting syntax to a grad-
ualist evolutionary approach. The rst, as pointed out in Section 1, are the claims that
syntax itself is an all-or-nothing package, and that syntax cannot be decomposed into
evolutionary primitives or stages. Second, even if syntax can be decomposed in some
fashion, the progression to a more complex syntax stage would involve the acquisi-
tion of principles such as Subjacency, which are just too abstract and arbitrary to be
targeted by evolutionary forces. Third, it has been claimed that there was not enough
evolutionary time to allow natural/sexual selection to operate on syntax or language
in general (see e.g. Hornstein 2009).
22
I briey address each of these objections below,
21
What I mean by recursion in this monograph corresponds to what linguists typically mean by it: the
embedding of a constituent of a certain syntactic category (e.g. a clause/CP) within another constitutent of
the same category (another clause/CP), as in (i) below (but see e.g. Tomalin 2011 for the confusion
surrounding the term). Also typically associated with the use of the term recursion by linguists is the
assumption that you can repeat the procedure in principle any number of times. This is essentially what
Heine and Kuteva (2007:68) call productive recursion.I return to recursion, and its different charac-
terizations, in Chapter 4(see also Section 1.7).
(i) I believe [
CP
that Henry knows [
CP
that Peter doubts [
CP
that recursion is real.]]]
22
Another potential problem is raised by Christiansen and Chater (2008), which has to do with the
constant and rapid language change. According to the authors, the linguistic environment over which
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
14 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
but in much more detail in Chapter 7. Chapter 7also considers the basic timeline for
the evolution of syntax, consistent with the postulated stages. Even in this broadest
outline, this approach can help choose among some proposed hypotheses regarding
the evolution of human species.
Regarding the rst objection, this monograph not only shows that syntax can be
decomposed into primitives, but also that the progression through these basic
syntactic stages can be successfully reconstructed given syntactic theory, as discussed
in the previous sections, and as will be elaborated in much more detail in subsequent
chapters. As for the second objection, the intent of this monograph is also to show
that the progression through the identied syntactic stages makes evolutionary sense,
i.e. that each new stage brings some tangible advantage(s) over the previous stage(s),
and that such advantage(s) were signicant enough to have been subject to natural/
sexual selection. These advantages are discussed throughout the monograph, but
especially in Chapter 7.
For example, each step in the progression from one-word stage (no syntax), to
small clause stage (paratactic two-slot syntax), to hierarchical TP stage accrues
clear incremental communicative benets. Small clauses (or half-clauses), with only
one layer of structure, would have been immensely useful to our ancestors when
they rst started using syntax.
23
A half-clause is still useful, even in expressing
propositional contentmuch more useful than having no syntax at all (one-word
stage), and much less useful than having more articulated hierarchical syntax of the
specic functional category stage. This is exactly the scenario upon which evolution/
selection can operate.
According to Pinker and Bloom (1990), based on Darwins work, the only way to
evolve a truly complex design that serves a particular purpose is through a sequence
of mutations/changes with small effects, and through intermediate stages, with each
change/stage useful enough to trigger natural selection. This monograph explores
exactly that kind of scenario for the evolution of syntax. As pointed out by Pinker
and Bloom, it is impossible to make sense of the structure of the eye without
acknowledgingthatitevolvedforthepurpose of seeing; evolution is the only
physical process that can create an eye because it is the only physical process in
which the criterion of being good at seeing can play a causal role. The same can be
applied to language: evolution can create a system as complex as language because
selectional pressures operate thus presentsa moving targetfor natural selection. However, in a commentary
to this article, Fitch (2008) counters that the same issue of a rapidly changing environment also arises with
uncontroversially adaptive biological processes, and calls for more sophisticated models of co-evolution
between ontogeny, phylogeny, and language change in an attempt to understand the nature of language.
23
The reference to half-clauses (in Progovacs2008a paper titled What use is half a clause?) is meant
to mimic the typical objections to Darwins adaptationist approach in general, in the form of what use is
half an eye?
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Can natural/sexual selection be relevant for syntax? 15
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
evolution is the physical process in which the criterion of being good at language/
communication can play a causal role.
Moreover, not all linguistic innovations need have begun with a genetic change.
The Baldwin Effect postulates that learning and culture can guide evolution, given
that individuals using innovative features can set up a pressure for the evolution of
neural mechanisms that would make decoding such innovative features of language
automatic and undistracted by irrelevant factors, triggering conventional Darwinian
evolution (Hinton and Nowlan 1987; Pinker and Bloom 1990; Deacon 2003), as
discussed further in Chapter 7.
Chapter 7summarizes the advantages that each postulated stage brings with it, and
considers one concrete hypothetical scenario for progressing from one stage to the
next, invoking sexual selection. For example, as shown in Chapter 6, exocentric VN
compounds are fossil structures which specialize for derogatory reference (e.g. turn-
coat,kill-joy,cry-baby,hunch-back), and which provide evidence not only of most
rudimentary syntax, but also of ritual insult/sexual selection for such simple syntax
(see Progovac and Locke 2009; Progovac 2012). Selecting for the ability to quickly
produce (and interpret) such (often humorous and vivid) compounds on the spot
would have gone a long way toward not only solidifying the capacity to use paratactic
grammars, the foundation for more complex grammars, but also the capacity for
building (abstract) vocabulary.
The abundance of examples from various languages offered in Chapter 6makes it
clear that these compounds combine basic, concrete words, often denoting body
parts and functions, in order to create vivid and memorable abstract concepts. Thus,
sexual selection for the capacity to produce and interpret such compounds could
have been one of the factors facilitating the progression from the one-word stage to
the two-word paratactic stage. There is no doubt that many other factors would have
also contributed to solidifying this foundational syntactic strategy, given that having
simple syntax, as opposed to having no syntax at all, accrues a host of communica-
tive advantages.
As pointed out above, transitioning from the paratactic stage to the specic
functional category stage may have proceeded through a linker/proto-conjunction
stage in some cases, where the linker initially served only to solidify proto-Merge, as
will be discussed in detail in Chapter 4. Perhaps the initial meaningless linker
occurring between a subject and a predicate of a small clause gradually became a
Tense particle which can now automatically express reference to past and future
events, but also build a TP, and with it hierarchical structure. The grammaticalization
of the functional projection such as TP renders automatic and undistracted the
expression of the temporal and modal properties, allowing the speakers to break
away from the here-and-now much more easily than is possible with paratactic small
clause grammars (see Chapter 2for the data showing that TP-less root small clauses
are typically grounded in the here-and-now).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
16 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Breaking away from the here-and-now, and from the prison of pragmatics in
general, may have been one dimension along which language evolved.
24
As will be
discussed in Chapter 3, two-slot proto-grammars do not distinguish between subjects
and objects, and it is typically pragmatics that determines the meaning of sentences
created by such grammars. The same certainly holds of one-word utterances. So,
imagine encountering the following one-word (8) and two-word (9) utterance
sequences in a proto-syntax stage:
(8) Apple ...Eat ...John ...Go ...
(9) Apple eat. John go.
These kinds of utterances are much less precise (i.e. more vague) than a correspond-
ing TP sentence such as (10) below, and can receive many interpretations in addition
to the one in (10):
(10) John will (go and) eat the apple.
However, the meaning that does not readily come to mind with respect to (8) and (9)
is the one expressed in (11), but that reading does not come to mind because of its
pragmatic oddness, and not because there is anything in the structure of (8)or(9)
that excludes it. In contrast, this reading is excluded by the structure of the sentence
in (10), and it is the only reading that the structure in (11) allows.
(11) The apple will (go and) eat John.
This suggests that pragmatically odd (or impossible) propositions are harder to express
without complex syntax, given that underspecied structures, resulting in vague
interpretations, are in close alliance with the pragmatics of the situation; in this
sense, such structures are prisoners of pragmatics. Adding the transitive vP and/or
the TP layer to the small clause structure would have yielded more precise grammars,
with subjects and objects more clearly differentiated, making it much easier to describe
odd or pragmatically impossible events (11). Thisis so because with such grammars one
can now unambiguously make the applethe subject of eating a human being. But one
may wonder what good it does to be able to talk about apples eating humans.
First, it is important to keep in mind that language (and syntax) are not just used to
express propositions and exchange information, but that they are also often used for
playful purposes and in order to impress (see references in Progovac and Locke
24
Displacement, roughly characterizable as the capability of language to communicate about things
that are not present, is commonly thought to be one of the design features of human language, and
moreover one of the features that arguably distinguishes human language from animal communication
systems (see e.g. Hockett 1960; Hockett and Altmann 1968). This is the sense in which I am using the term
displacementin this book. The reader should note that the same term is also used to refer to a completely
different phenomenon, to the rearrangement of constituents within a sentence, as a result of the syntactic
operation Move.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Can natural/sexual selection be relevant for syntax? 17
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
2009), something we formal linguists often forget.
25
Thus, if an ancient language user
wanted to draw attention to himself by using language in a funny and surprising way,
he would have had a much harder time doing so with structures such as (8)or(9),
than with the structure such as (11), which relies on hierarchical syntax. This is just
one way in which transitivity, and hierarchical structure more generally, would have
been adaptive. Of course, the precision in expressing the argument structure (who
did what to whom) would have been adaptive in so many other ways as well,
including in gossip and story-telling, both of which rely on displacement.
In other words, the capacity for displacement, a key design feature of human
language, is facilitated by hierarchical syntax. As will be discussed in Chapter 4,
hierarchical syntax also enables Move and recursion, making it possible e.g. to
embed one point of view within another. Therefore, once the innovation that was
hierarchical syntax appeared on the evolutionary scene, there would have been
multiple types of pressures to select for it.
This is not to claim that every single phenomenon of syntax, such as every single
functional projection, or every single construction, has been selected; certain syntac-
tic phenomena seem to be bundled together, and it may be enough for one of them to
emerge to make the others possible. Likewise, just as is the case with the evolution of
other aspects of living organisms, there will surely be phenomena in syntax that serve
no particular purpose, and that can be seen as spandrels (i.e. by-products of some
other adaptations), or which perhaps developed through drift (variation due to
chance).
26
However, the existence of such phenomena should not distract one
from identifying those aspects of language that responded to selection pressures,
and from devising methods to test such hypotheses.
Finally, the third objection to the gradualist approach to language evolution is that
there was not enough evolutionary time for the selection to take place. Pinker and
Bloom (1990) propose that language evolved gradually, subject to the Baldwin Effect,
the process whereby environmentally-induced responses set up selection pressures
for such responses to become innate, triggering conventional Darwinian evolution
(see also Deacon 1997; Hinton and Nowlan 1987). Deacon (2003) puts emphasis on
learning, rather than innateness, in his adoption of the Baldwin Effect. He considers
that masking and unmasking of preadaptationsplays an important role in this
process. As an innovative tool (e.g. language) became more and more essential to
25
In this respect, Dunbar, Duncan, and Marriot (1997) report that only about 1020% of conversation
time is devoted to practical and technical topics, while the rest is devoted to social concerns (see also
Tallerman 2013b).
26
For example, the availability of Move may be inextricably linked to the availability of functional
layers, such as TP and CP, which Move serves to connect (Section 4.4.5). Recursion itself may be a
by-product of the emergence of specialized functional projections, such as CP for clausal subordination
(Chapter 4). As argued at length in Chapter 5, Subjacency should be seen as a by-product of other
adaptations, and not a principle in its own right.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
18 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
successful reproduction, novel selection pressures unmasked selection on previously
neutralvariants and created advantages for certain classes of mutations that might
not otherwise have been favored(934). At the same time, this innovative tool
masked selection on traits made less vital by being supplementedby the innovative
tool, such as perhaps the inventory and specicity of human calls (94). As claried in
Chapter 7, where I return to this topic, this approach ultimately reduces to Darwinian
natural selection.
Tiny selective advantages are sufcient for evolutionary change; according to
Haldane (1927), a variant that produces on average 1% more offspring than its
alternative allele would increase in frequency from 0.1%to99.9% of the population
in just over 4,000 generations. This would still leave plenty of time for language to
have evolved: 3.5to 5million years, if early Australopithecines were the rst talkers,
or, as an absolute minimum, several hundred thousand years (Stringer and Andrews
1988), in the event that early H. sapiens were the rst.
27
Moreover, xations of
different genes can go in parallel, and sexual selection can signicantly speed up
any of these processes. The speed of the spread depends on how high the tness of
these individuals was relative to the competitors. According to e.g. Stone and Lurquin
(2007), if relative tness is high, it can take just a few dozen generations for the
variant frequency to increase tenfold.
28
The initial arguments for the saltationist views, such as the postulation of the
Middle to Upper Paleolithic revolution, as well as the dating of the FOXP2gene, have
now been mostly reconsidered (see Chapter 7for more discussion on this). It was
initially reported by Enard et al.(2002) that FOXP2gene mutation in humans
occurred at some point in the last 200,000 years, which could have then coincided
with the emergence of syntax. However, it has since been found that the same
mutation characterizes Neanderthals (Krause et al.2007), which pushes the mutation
back to at least the common ancestor, about half a million years ago (see e.g. Piattelli-
Palmarini and Uriagereka 2011 for discussion).
Another type of evidence that has been invoked in favor of the saltationist view has
to do with the postulation of the Middle to Upper Paleolithic transition/revolution.
Based on archeological ndings, Mellars (2002) and others have initially suggested
that there was a major cultural and cognitive transition/revolution around 4335,000
Before Present (BP). These archeological ndings were often interpreted to mean that
syntax (or language) in its entirety arose at this juncture, through one single event,
such as a mutation (e.g. Bickerton 1995; Chomsky 2002,2005). However, the more
recent ndings suggest that there was no human revolution, at least not at this
27
Berwick et al.(2013) maintain that the capacity for language evolved about 100,000 years ago.
28
As one example, the tness of lactose tolerance is 23% higher in dairy areas. It took about
5,00010,000 years to reach the current rates of lactose tolerance among northern Europeans, which is
close to 100% with some populations.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Can natural/sexual selection be relevant for syntax? 19
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
particular juncture (see e.g. McBrearty and Brooks 2000; McBrearty 2007; and
Mellars himself (2007:3), as further discussed in Chapter 7).
In short, there is no real obstacle to studying syntax in a gradualist evolutionary
framework. The recurring theme of this monograph is that there is evidence of
evolutionary tinkering in the language design itself, consistent with the view that
the complexity of syntax emerged gradually, through evolutionary tinkering. As a
result, modern clauses are quirky and redundant (rather than optimal and perfect).
29
In this evolutionary perspective, rather than a system designed from scratch in an
optimal way, syntax is seen as a patchwork of structures incorporating various stages
of its evolution, and thus exhibiting a variety of quirky phenomena, many of which
are discussed in this monograph.
30
1.5Corroboration and testing
The gradualist evolutionary scenario for syntax, as outlined in this monograph, nds
corroboration in practically every domain relevant for language, in addition to the
fossil proto-structures found in modern languages. As discussed in various chapters
in this monograph, in children, as well as in adults acquiring a second language,
language clearly emerges gradually, through stages, arguably starting with the para-
tactic (small clause) stage, and it can also be partly lost in e.g. agrammatic aphasia
and speech language disorders.
When it comes to neuroscience, there is converging evidence in the literature
showing that increased syntactic complexity corresponds to increased neural activa-
tion in certain specic areas of the brain (see e.g. Caplan 2001; Indefrey, Hagoort et al.
2001; Just et al.1996; Pallier, Devauchelle, and Dehaene 2011; Brennan et al.2012). The
experiments performed by Pallier, Devauchelle, and Dehaene (2011) and Brennan
et al.(2012) have found a positive correlation between the levels of hierarchical
embedding and the degree of activation in the brain, even when keeping the number
of words constant. This is consistent with the proposal in this monograph that the
complexity of syntax is graded, and that it evolved gradually. The proposals in this
monograph are also specic and concrete enough that they themselves can be
subjected to neuroscientic testing, as summarized in the Appendix to this book,
which proposes specic experimental design.
29
A reviewer suggests that while syntactic representations may be quirky and redundant, the syntactic
operations, such as Merge, may be optimal and perfect. Again, in order for these claims to be falsiable, one
will need to dene what optimaland perfectshould mean in this respect (see Footnote 6). Besides, my
argument in this monograph is that the crucial properties of syntax, including the operations such as
Merge, have precursors (e.g. Conjoin), and that they, too, arose through evolutionary tinkering. In this
view, the reason why syntactic representations show quirkiness today is because they often incorporate
structures created by different types of operations, including by the precursors to Merge.
30
The quirkiness of a variety of syntactic constructions is recognized in e.g. Culicover (1999) and
Culicover and Jackendoff (2005), who refer to some such constructions as syntactic nuts.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
20 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
It is also signicant that the framework explored here can serve as a point of
contact, an intermediary, between the elds of neuro-linguistics and genetics. To take
one example, some recent experiments suggest that a specically human FOXP2
mutation is responsible for increased synaptic plasticity, establishing better connect-
ivity among the neurons in the brain (e.g. Vernes et al.2007; Enard et al.2009; see
Section 2.5.4).
31
If better synaptic plasticity is what facilitates the processing of more
complex syntax, then one can hypothesize that the pressures to evolve the capacity
for a more complex syntax could have contributed to the spread of the human
mutation of e.g. the FOXP2gene. Even at this preliminary level, one can appreciate
the potential for synergy among the elds which can shed light on the evolution of
human language: syntactic theory, neuroscience, and genetics. It is the evolutionary
considerations like this that can provide the point of contact.
32
1.6A brief comparison with Jackendoff s (and other) approaches
The work of Ray Jackendoff (e.g. 1999,2002) on the evolution of syntax, in particular
his characterization of syntactic fossils,provided an important component of the
proposal that I am exploring in this book. This short section is in no way meant to be
an overview of his approach, or to do justice to various aspects of his approach, but
merely to indicate where my proposal converges with his, and where it diverges.
Generally speaking, I would say that Jackendoff s approach is in broad strokes, with
wider implications (including some discussion of phonology and morphology), while
mine is narrowly focused only on the evolution of the layers of clausal structure, as
postulated in the syntactic theory associated with Minimalism.
Also, as per the distinction drawn in Heine and Kuteva (2007), Jackendoff s
approach is integrative, considering data from various domains, including language
acquisition, pidgin languages, and aphasia, while mine is discipline-based, following,
perhaps doggedly, a reconstruction method based on a syntactic theory, while the
evidence from the other domains is only considered as secondary, corroborating evi-
dence. Even though it seems plausible and insightful in many respects, Jackendoff s
31
FOXP2is just one of several genes that are implicated in language and speech (disorders), and are
thus of potential relevance for language evolution (see e.g. Vernes et al.2007; Newbury and Monaco 2010,
for FOXP1). Two other potentially relevant genes are CNTNAP2and ASPM (see e.g. Dediu and Ladd 2007;
Fitch 2010:291; Diller and Cann 2012). The exact contribution of FOXP2and the other genes remains to be
determined, as rightly pointed out by a reviewer, but I do not think this can be determined without some
concrete input by linguists, and without some specic, testable hypotheses about language evolution. If
these genes were even partly selected for some specic language abilities then, without hypothesizing what
these specic abilities might have been, we will not be able to nd out.
32
There is no doubt that the researchers in each of these elds will notice that there are other possible
takes and interpretations of the analyses and data presented here, and that there are many more
complexities involved with each eld than this approach can do justice to. Still, if this is one of the ways
that all these elds can be brought together, then it is at least worth exploring.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
A brief comparison with Jackendoff s (and other) approaches 21
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(1999,2002) approach does not easily lend itself to specic hypotheses that can be tested.
Botha (2006:135), among others, has pointed out that such windows into the evolution of
language need to be accompanied by insightful theories.
My intent in this book is to show that following a narrowly focused and discipline-
based approach leads to greater depth, and to some surprising novel insights, which
in turn make it possible to formulate specic hypotheses and predictions, as well as to
reveal clear communicative advantages that come with each stage. There is both a
virtue and a curse in following this kind of simple and precise reconstruction method.
The virtue is that you can be fairly condent in your reconstruction. The curse is that
it does not tell you about other things.
The idea of syntactic fossils advocated by Jackendoff is very powerful, as is the
idea that one can reconstruct the stages of language evolution by looking at the
nature of language itself. I believe that my approach strengthens these ideas
further by proposing that each new stage literally leans upon the structure of
the previous one, and cannot exist without it.
33
On my approach, not only are the
fossil structures used side by side with more complex structures (e.g. paratactic
(adjunct) structures alongside hierarchical structures), but these foundational
paratactic structures are literally built into the foundation of hierarchical struc-
tures. As will be shown, intransitive small clauses are built into vPs and TPs, and
exocentric compounds are built into hierarchical compounds. Thus, on my
approach, the fossil structures do not just provide cognitive scaffolding (i.e. increased
cognitive abilities) for advancing to hierarchical language (e.g. Jackendoff 2009);
the fossil structures also provide concrete syntactic scaffolding for hierarchical
structures to be built upon.
Jackendoff (2002) identies certain fossil principles of language, such as Agent
First (where the agent precedes the patient/theme: e.g. Bear chase boy); Grouping
(where modiers are grouped next to the words they modify: e.g. Brown bear chase
boy); Topic First (where the topic of the sentence appears before the comment);
Focus Last; etc. These are still not syntactic principles, although they can be seen
as precursors to such principles, especially the connection between the linear word
order and the semantic/thematic role. These also relate to what Givón (1979)has
called the pragmatic mode of language, which preceded the syntactic mode. In this
respect, Hurford (2012) suggests that the rst proto-sentences involved a topic-
comment dichotomy, from which even the categories of nouns and verbs emerged.
According to Hurford, the rst proto-sentences consisted of two words juxta-
posed, always in the topic-comment word order (653). It would be only at a later
33
While Jackendoff (1999,2002) has identied some fossils of the postulated one-word stageproto-
words which are not combinable with other words, such as ouch, wow, shhh, etc.I have identied some
rigid small clause structures in English (e.g. Case closed) and Serbian (Pala karta Card played), which also
seem to be syntactic isolates in the sense that they cannot combine further (Chapters 24).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
22 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
stage that topics would give rise to subjects, and comments would give rise to
predicates.
34
While all these ideas can in principle be plausible, without having a theory that
organizes these proposed principles, as well as illuminating the transition from one
stage to the next, it is hard to know what kind of evidence bears on these hypotheses.
It is also not clear from such a characterization what selection pressures, and what
communicative advantages, led to the transition from the topic-comment based, or
Agent-First based, language to the subject-predicate based language. For example, as
Jackendoff s Agent-First protolanguage is already capable of communicating who
does what to whom, and it already allows more than one argument per verb, it is not
clear why there would have existed selection pressures to transition to the (transitive)
subject-predicate grammars. In contrast, on my approach, which starts from an
intransitive absolutive-like foundation, the communicative advantages of developing
transitivity can be characterized clearly and precisely. In addition, this reconstruction
down to the intransitive absolutive-like layer allows me to connect this proposal
meaningfully to the typological variation across languages, as well as to the hominin
timeline (Chapter 7).
More generally, Jackendoff (2002:238) considers that protolanguage consisted of
the following separable components: use of symbols; concatenation of symbols; use
of open-class symbols; and use of word order to convey semantic relations. The
hierarchical stage then adds to the protolanguage the following: symbols encoding
abstract semantic relations, as well as grammatical categories and grammatical
functions, including subject vs. object. This is the sense in which, for Jackendoff,
the hierarchical stage subsumes protolanguage. However, as pointed out above, it is
not clear how and why, and in what manageable, incremental steps, one proceeds
from the concatenation of symbols with Agent First to a hierarchical transitive
sentence with a subject and object. My approach puts emphasis on this incremental
progression through stages, as well as on the specic communicative advantages
gained with each incremental step.
Bickertons(1990,1998)inuential work is also relevant here, as he has proposed
that pidgin languages are indicative of our ability to tap into the proto-linguistic
mode. However, in his view, pidgin languages (or child language) have no syntax,
which leads him to a saltationist view of the emergence of syntax, from no syntax at
all, to full-blown hierarchical syntax. Bickertons main reason for considering proto-
language to be without any syntax is his observation that the arguments routinely go
34
However, see Casielles and Progovac (2010,2012) for the idea that the so-called thetic statements are
evolutionarily primary, and that they preceded categorical statements, those which feature such topic-
comment diachotomies. Some examples of thetic statements include e.g. English It rained, and Serbian Pao
sneg (Fell snow), which do not involve a clear diachotomy between a topic and a comment, or between a
subject and a predicate, but rather describe an event as a whole. Such thetic statements also typically do not
have agents, and often overlap with unaccusative constructions (see Section 3.3).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
A brief comparison with Jackendoff s (and other) approaches 23
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
missing in these systems, and that syntactic language must obligatorily realize all the
arguments of the verb. For Bickerton, these asyntactic systems do not even involve
true language. Notice that Givón (1979:296) has also proposed that there was a pre-
syntactic, pragmatic mode of discourse, which had a low noun to verb ratio.
My approach has elevated the stage characterized by intransitivity (one argument
per verb) not only to the level of language, but also to the level of (simpler) syntax.
Given the logic behind the two-slot syntax, one is not dealing with missing argu-
ments here, but rather with a coherent syntax which can accommodate only one
argument per verb. Not only is this kind of proto-syntax syntactic and language-like,
but such fossil structures are still available across various constructions and lan-
guages, including in English. In my analysis, the proto-syntactic stages clearly show
continuity with the more innovative stages of syntax.
As pointed out above, Jackendoff (2002) advocates that word order in the proto-
language stage followed the semantic ordering of Agent First. In contrast, my
argument is that the initial stages were absolutive-like, with agent and patient not
being structurally differentiated at all. However, notice that Agent First may be
relevant after all, even in my approach, although in a somewhat roundabout way.
As discussed throughout the book (e.g. Section 3.4; Chapter 4), the paratactic small
clause combinations of the kind attested in Nicaraguan Sign Language (e.g.
WOMAN PUSH MAN FALL) may have provided precursors to accusative-type
transitivity (e.g. Senghas et al.1997). We notice here that WOMAN is interpreted as
an agent, and MAN as a patient, but this is not directly related to the Agent-First
principle, given that one is dealing with two clauses here. Instead, this may ultimately
reduce to Cause First principle, which is operative in a much wider array of paratactic
combinations, including e.g. Easy come, easy go;Nothing ventured, nothing gained.In
other words, given that the rst clause (e.g. WOMAN PUSH; Easy come) is inter-
preted, roughly speaking, as Cause of the second clause (MAN FALL; Easy go), then
WOMAN will be seen as the agent/causer. This will be discussed further, especially in
Chapters 3and 4.
While Jackendoff s work, as well as Bickertons, is more about characterizing the
fancy properties of modern syntax, which they list and illustrate, my approach is
more about envisioning and illustrating what the initial, early syntax was like, in its
own right, and its own logic. I offer a lot of data from present-day languages which
arguably approximate these early stages, emphasizing the symmetry and atness of
proto-syntax, as opposed to asymmetry and hierarchy of modern syntax. Interest-
ingly, if my approach is correct, it suggests that syntax was autonomous in this very
early stage: while thoughts can be uid, with many participants associated with one
verb or event, the proto-syntactic mold only allowed one such participant to occur
with the verb. In other words, the syntactic form did not just follow from the
semantic principles, or from the properties of events, but it imposed its own logic
and constraints.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
24 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The fossil structures discussed in Jackendoff (1999,2002) also include English
noun-noun (NN) compounds, such as snowman, doghouse, housedog. However, even
though seemingly simple, these compounds, at least in present-day English, are
headed and recursive, which may suggest more complex structure. Interestingly,
this kind of NN compounding process is not productive, and certainly not recursive,
in e.g. Serbian (see Snyder 2014 for other languages in this respect). Still, if there was a
proto-syntax stage with verb-like and noun-like proto-words (as per Heine and
Kutevas2007 reconstruction), then it would stand to reason that one should have
been able to combine not just verbs with nouns, but also nouns with nouns, and verbs
with verbs, as pointed out by a reviewer. However, the method of reconstruction that
I follow, and the fossil evidence that I have gathered, do not lead to a clear conclusion
in this respect, and I thus leave NN compounds for future research.
As for the verb-verb (VV) combinations, the discussion above suggests that at
least some serial verb constructions across languages probably have a complex
clausal origin, rather than just being plain VV compounds or concatenations (see
Section 3.4.1for more discussion on this). However, one does nd an occasional
VV compound which can be of evolutionary signicance, such as Macedonian
veži-dreši(tie-untie an ignorant person), consisting of two imperative forms
strung together (Olga Tomić,p.c.,2006); see especially Section 6.4for the relevance
of imperative morphology in compounds. Possibly of interest are also English tie-
dye and French passe-passe (sleight of hand).
Finally, a reviewer wonders if my approach cannot be somehow reconciled with
the saltationist views (e.g. Chomsky 2005; Berwick and Chomsky 2011), if one can
interpret their position to be that one single mutation occurred at a point when
protolanguage in Bickertons sense was already in place, in which case this one single
mutation would have brought about hierarchical syntax. First of all, there are clear
claims in Berwick and Chomsky (2011:2931) and elsewhere in this line of work to the
effect that there is no room in this picture for any precursors to languagesay a
language-like system with only short sentences,as quoted in full in Section 1.1.
Bickerton (1990,1998) shares this view. Some saltationists (e.g. Piattelli-Palmarini
2010:160) go even further to propose that even unstructured protolanguage in
Bickertons sense could not have existed (see also Section 4.2.2).
Crucially, my approach has isolated a coherent two-slot, at stage in the evolu-
tion of syntax, which provides a clear transition/intermediate stage between one-
word protolanguage and hierarchical syntax. Not only that, but my approach
identies specic kinds of (paratactic) precursors to all the hierarchical phenomena
discussed in the book, showing that the incremental, scaffolding approach is on the
right track. In this respect, my approach differs sharply not only from Berwick and
Chomskys approach, but also from Jackendoff s and all the other approaches to
language evolution (see Chapter 7for more discussion on this). Importantly, one
cannot object here that what I have reconstructed is not real language or real syntax.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
A brief comparison with Jackendoff s (and other) approaches 25
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
As will be shown, such structures are found, in some form or another, all over
present-day languages.
1.7Syntactic theory
As an inuential approach to syntax for an extended period of time, Minimalism (e.g.
Chomsky 1995) and its predecessors (the frameworks leading to it, such as Govern-
ment and Binding and Principles and Parameters), have accrued many insightful
generalizations and analyses which provide important tools for analyzing structure.
However, Minimalism has been in ux, and it would be unwise to base a whole
evolutionary framework on one particular version of Minimalism. My solution to
that is to rely only on well-established theoretical postulates: those which have
withstood the test of time and empirical scrutiny within this framework, and which
date back to the predecessors of Minimalism, as well as surviving into various later
versions. In this section, I will thus present only some of those stable postulates, in
particular those that will be useful for further discussion. For a fuller picture of the
framework that I am adopting here, the reader is referred to e.g. Adger (2003) and
Chomsky (1995). The discussion of Minimalist (and other theoretical) notions in this
monograph will be made accessible to a non-expert, and only those postulates will be
discussed that are relevant for further discussion.
As pointed out in Section 1.2.2, the theory of clause/sentence structure adopted in
Minimalism (e.g. Chomsky 1995) and its predecessors involves a hierarchy of func-
tional projections, which includes at least the following projections (several more
projections have been postulated, but these are the ones that are largely agreed upon):
(12) CP > TP > vP > VP/SC
The structure is built bottom up, so that the inner VP/SC layer is formed rst, to
accommodate the verb/predicate and one argument.
35
The next layer, vP, accom-
modates an additional argument, such as agent in transitive structures. TP (Tense
Phrase) accommodates the expression of tense and niteness, while CP (Comple-
mentizer Phrase) accommodates e.g. subordination/embedding, and wh-movement,
as discussed below.
The following derivation illustrates how one constructs a transitive sentence (TP)
in this manner, starting from a small clause.
(13) Maria will roll the ball.
35
Sometimes the initial combination of a verb and a noun is referred to as a VP (Verb Phrase), and
other times as a SC (Small Clause). Even though it is a bit clumsy, I will use the label VP/SC here in
order to reect that reality, as well as because vP is a label for the light verb phrase, which is considered
to be an additional layer of verb phrase. The layer of the vP structure on top of the VP is referred to as a
vP/VP shell.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
26 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(14)a.[
SC/VP
roll the ball] !
b. [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll the ball]] !
c. [
TP
Maria will [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll the ball]]]
[The strike-out notation is used to represent the original (pre-Move) copy of the
moved constituent.]
In deriving the sentence in (13), one starts with the basic, small clause layer in (14a).
At this point, one cannot know if the ball will be the subject or the object of the
sentence (see 16 below). Then, the agent (Maria) is merged in the higher vP layer
(14b), which is now responsible not only for accommodating this additional argu-
ment, but also for assigning (abstract) accusative case to the object (the ball). Finally,
the TP layer is projected on top of the vP layer, and Maria,the highest argument,
moves to become the subject of the TP (14c).
36
It is of note here that a corresponding intransitive sentence (15) can be derived
without the vP layer, simply by moving the argument of the small clause to the TP
layer (see e.g. Kratzer 1996,2000; Chomsky 1995:214 for unaccusatives):
(15) The ball will roll.
(16)a.[
SC/VP
roll the ball] !
b. [
TP
The ball will [
SC/VP
roll the ball]]
It is of note here that the two derivations above illustrate the uid, relative nature of
subjecthood. While the ballin (13) is the object, in (15) it is the subject, even though
its semantic role with respect to the event of rolling seems to be the same. This will be
relevant for the later discussion of proto-syntactic structures, especially those involv-
ing absolutive-like roles in Chapter 3.
What is of relevance here is that the modern syntactic theory associated with the
Minimalist Program (e.g. Chomsky 1995,2001) analyzes every clause/sentence as
initially a small clause (SC) which gets transformed into a full TP only upon
subsequent Merge of tense, and subsequent Move of the subject to TP in English.
This kind of analysis was originally proposed in Stowell (1981,1983); Burzio (1981);
Kitagawa (1985,1986); and further solidied in the work of Koopman and Sportiche
(1991); Chomsky (1995); and many others. This is thus one of those solid postulates in
this framework that has withstood the test of time and empirical scrutiny.
The import of this incremental structure building for the evolutionary proposal in
this book will become clearer in Chapters 2and 3. The signicance of the operation
Move from the evolutionary standpoint will be discussed in Sections 2.22.4and
36
In fact, there is an additional Move operation postulated in this structure, that is, Move of the verb in
V to the position of the light verb in v, but this operation is not directly relevant to the considerations in
this book, except to characterize Move as a force whose more general purpose may be to connect the layers
of structure, as per Section 4.4.5.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Syntactic theory 27
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
4.4.5. Further, Section 5.2discusses wh-movement in the context of Subjacency,
showing where wh-movement is possible, and where it is not.
Moving up the hierarchy in (12), wh-movement in e.g. English utilizes the CP layer
of structure, which is constructed on top of a TP:
(17) What will Maria roll?
(18)a.[
SC/VP
roll what] !
b. [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll what]] !
c. [
TP
Maria will [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll what]]]
d. [
CP
What will [
TP
Maria will [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll what]]]]
What happens in step (d) is that the wh-word what Moves to the CP layer, and so
does the auxiliary verb will, as indicated by the strike-out notation. Many more
instances of wh-movement are to be found in Section 5.2.
There are many complexities involved in characterizing Merge and Move, includ-
ing the motivation for Move, the availability of landing sites for Move, and the
restrictions on Move, including Subjacency, the latter discussed at length in
Chapter 5. Minimalism typically relies on various grammatical features to implement
Merge and Move, that is, to predict when these operations will take place and when
they will not. The reader is referred to e.g. Adger (2003) for one detailed implemen-
tation of the feature checking theory.
Embedded sentences, introduced by the subordinator/complementizer such as
that or whether, also rely on the CP layer, as illustrated below:
(19) (I believe) that Maria will roll the ball.
(20)a.[
SC/VP
roll the ball] !
b. [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll the ball]] !
c. [
TP
Maria will [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll the ball]]]
d. [
CP
that [
TP
Maria will [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll the ball]]]]
As discussed in Section 4.4, the CP layer may be instrumental in facilitating recursion
when it comes to clausal embedding. The following example illustrates how CPs can
be recursively embedded one within another:
(21) I believe [
CP
that John suspects [
CP
that Sue will acknowledge
[
CP
that Maria will roll the ball.]]]
As pointed out in Footnote 21, recursion in linguistics is typically characterized as one
type of category (in this case CP) embedding within another category of the same
type (another CP), potentially ad innitum (see Section 4.4for much more discussion
on recursion).
Just like functional projections are postulated on top of verb phrases, they are also
postulated on top of noun phrases, although there is less agreement among syntacticians
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
28 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
regarding the nature and number ofsuch projections when it comes to the noun phrase.
One such functional projection postulated for English is a Determiner Phrase (DP)
projection (e.g. Abney 1987), as in:
(22)[
DP
the [
NP
book on recursion]]
(23)[
DP
Peters[
NP
book on recursion]]
In other words, a similar kind of hierarchical layering of structure seen with clauses
also seems to characterize noun phrases. In this respect, it should be pointed out that
nouns and verbs are considered to be lexical (content) categories, and NP and VP
lexical projections of nouns and verbs, respectively. On the other hand, vP, TP, CP,
and DP are all considered to be functional projections, as they are not direct
projections of lexical categories.
Section 4.4.3returns to DP structures in the context of the discussion of DP
recursion in English and other languages. DP recursion is characterized in English
by a repeated embedding of one possessive DP within another, as illustrated below:
(24)[
DP
[
DP
[
DP
Peters] friends] book on recursion]
Section 4.4.3discusses languages and constructions in which recursion is not pos-
sible, as well as the evolutionary signicance of that.
What this section provides is a mere skeleton of the theory of structure building
that is adopted in this book, to help the reader follow the discussion in the subsequent
chapters better. Various other details of this theory will be discussed only when and if
they become relevant.
1.8Chapter-by-chapter overview
Chapter 2focuses on TP-less (root) small clauses, mostly in English and Serbian, and
shows that such clauses are measurably simpler than nite TP counterparts, and that
they can be considered as (living) fossils of the small clause stage in the evolution of
syntax. These clauses lack nite verbs, structural case, the ability to question or move
constituents, and the ability to embed and show recursion.
37
These are exactly the
characteristics postulated for the initial (paratactic) stage in the evolution of syntax.
Many among the root small clauses in both Serbian and English are now marginal,
formulaic expressions, although Serbian also has a type of small clause with a VN
order, which is used productively in parallel with its TP counterparts, as a true living
fossil. One nds corroborating evidence for the primacy of small clauses, and their
37
It follows from the considerations in this monograph that (unbounded) recursion only becomes
possible in the later stages of the evolution of language, more precisely when specialized functional
categories emerge, as discussed at length in Chapter 4.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Chapter-by-chapter overview 29
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
continuity with TP equivalents, in rst language acquisition, second language acqui-
sition, and agrammatism, and potential testing grounds in the elds of neuroscience
and genetics.
Chapter 3builds on the small clause analysis of Chapter 2, and takes it further to
the conclusion that only intransitive small clauses, those that license only one
argument, can be considered as true fossils of the initial stage of syntactic evolution.
One arrives at the intransitive small clause stage via the method of internal recon-
struction by removing the outer layers of functional structure, in this case the TP and
the vP layers, the latter being responsible for transitivity and accusative case. The
chapter goes even further to claim that this stage was characterized by an absolutive-
like grammar, that is, an intransitive grammar in which the distinction between
subjects and objects is not syntactically expressed.
38
Fossils of such an absolutive-like grammar are arguably found in all languages, and
include absolutives, unaccusatives, certain nominals, and exocentrics (e.g. exocentric
compounds).
39
Consistent with the gradualist evolutionary proposal for the expres-
sion of transitivity, one also nds various types of intermediate structures, including
the so-called middles,which straddle the boundary between transitivity and
intransitivity, and between subjecthood and objecthood. Corroborating evidence
for an intransitive absolutive-like stage comes from child language acquisition, as
well as from the initial stages of spontaneously emerging sign languages. Finally,
neuroscience provides fertile testing grounds for this proposal.
Chapter 4is concerned with the nature of the bond between the merged elements
in these proto-syntactic constructs, as well as with how the syntactic bond evolved
over time. In this respect, I identify three rough stages in the evolution of the syntactic
bond: (i) the Paratactic Stage; (ii) the Proto-Coordination Stage; and (iii) the Specic
Functional Category Stage (hierarchical stage), as outlined in Section 1.3. These
syntactic stages follow a hypothesized one-word stage. This progression is meant to
shed light on the gradual/incremental emergence of hierarchical syntax and recur-
sion, as well as on the existence of various transitional, ambivalent structures that
straddle the stage boundaries in modern languages.
In addition to a variety of living fossils of these stages found in modern languages,
this progression of stages nds corroboration in the studies of language acquisition,
agrammatism, grammaticalization, neuroscience, and animal communication. The
corroborating evidence is more robust for the paratactic stage than it is for the proto-
coordination stage, and this can be attributed to parataxis serving as the ultimate
38
According to many authors, the notions of subjecthood and objecthood, which are descriptive terms
particularly suited for nominative-accusative patterns, are not useful distinctions to make when it comes to
ergative/absolutive patterns (e.g. Authier and Haude 2012; Blake 1976; Mithun 1994:247; Shibatani 1998:
120; Tchekhoff 1973). This will be explained in detail in Chapter 3.
39
These terms will be explained and illustrated in Chapter 3.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
30 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
foundation for both coordination and subordination. The chapter identies some
concrete communicative advantages that each stage brings with it, making it possible
to invoke natural/sexual selection in evolving hierarchical grammars (that yield
recursion).
Chapter 5on islandhood (Subjacency) is a good example of how evolutionary
considerations of this kind can shed light on the very nature of language design, by
explaining certain phenomena observed in modern syntax, which otherwise remain
unaccounted for. Despite the sustained effort of syntactic theory for over forty years
to account for the islandhood effects, that is, for the existence of constructions that
prohibit Move, to date there has been no principled account. It is also signicant that
the postulated arbitrariness of Subjacency, the principle that is supposed to capture
islandhood effects, has been used to argue that syntax could not have evolved
gradually: one does not see why evolution would target a grammar with Subjacency,
when its contribution to grammar is not clear, let alone its contribution to survival.
As put in Lightfoot (1991), Subjacency has many virtues, but ...it could not have
increased the chances of having fruitful sex.
However, the approach explored here stands this argument on its head and shows
that subjecting syntax to a gradualist evolutionary scenario can in fact explain the
existence of islandhood effects. In this view, Subjacency is not a principle of syntax, or
a principle of any kind, but rather just an epiphenomenon of evolutionary tinkering.
Subjacency or islandhood can be seen as the default, primary state of language, due to
the evolutionary beginnings of language which had no Move. This default state can
be overridden in certain, evolutionarily novel, fancy constructions, such as hierarch-
ical CPs. To put it differently, given that proto-syntactic (paratactic and proto-
coordination stages) did not have Move (Chapter 4), the survivors of these stages,
adjuncts and conjuncts, continue to show islandhood effects.
Chapter 6considers in detail what may be the best fossils we can access today of
the paratactic absolutive-like stage in the evolution of human grammar: the exocen-
tric VN compounds (e.g. turn-coat,cry-baby,hunch-back,pick-pocket,kill-joy,spoil-
sport). These fossils consist of just one verb and one noun, with the noun in the
absolutive-like role. Structurally speaking, these compounds are exactly what the
postulated paratactic stage would have looked like: a rigid combination of only two
elements, a verb and a noun, with no subject/object distinction, and with no Move or
recursion available. What is even more striking about these compounds is that they
specialize for derogatory reference (insult) when they refer to humans, in language
after language, which makes it plausible that comparable creations in the ancient past
could have been used for ritual insult, and could have thus contributed to the sexual
selection of this simplest type of syntax (Progovac and Locke 2009). Some corrob-
oration for the primary nature of VN compounds comes from language acquisition
and neuroscience, the latter in connection to the often obscene nature of these
compounds.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Chapter-by-chapter overview 31
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Chapter 7considers the communicative advantages gained by each new stage, and
how the progression through each stage would have been guided by evolutionary
pressures. This chapter looks in detail at one concrete evolutionary scenario that
would have solidied the paratactic stage by way of sexual selection (see also
Section 1.4). The approach explored in this chapter thus offers a reconstruction of
how communicative benets may have been involved in shaping the formal design of
human language. Finally, given that the postulated stages of the evolution of human
language are consistent only with certain hypotheses regarding human prehistory,
this approach can also help choose among some competing hypotheses about the
origins of the human species.
Chapter 8summarizes and concludes, as well as considering future prospects and
promises.
The Appendix, written jointly with neuroscientist Noa Ofen, considers how the
main claims advanced in this monograph can be subjected to neuroimaging testing.
There is already reasonable evidence from neuro-linguistics establishing that
increased syntactic complexity correlates with the increased neuronal activation in
the specic areas of the brain. The Appendix builds on that and proposes an
experimental design for how specic hypotheses advanced in this monograph can
be tested. To take one example, one can compare and contrast the processing of
TP-less and vP-less small clauses/compounds with the processing of their hierarch-
ical counterparts, which use the same vocabulary, and only differ with respect to tiny
grammatical pieces, making hardly any difference in meaning in controlled contexts.
While the processing of full hierarchical structures is expected to show clear
lateralization in the left hemisphere, with extensive activation of some specic
Brocas areas, the proto-structures, including root small clauses and VN compounds,
are expected to show less lateralization, and less involvement of Brocas area, but
more reliance on both hemispheres, as well as, possibly, more reliance on the
subcortical structures of the brain.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
32 Introduction
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
2
The small (clause) beginnings
2.1Introduction
My proposal in this chapter is based on very specic claims, whose feasibility can be
evaluated and tested both in the theory of syntax and in neuroimaging experiments,
as well as corroborated by the ndings in several other elds. Specically, the
proposal is that the rst sentenceswere paratactic (not hierarchical, not headed)
combinations of a verb and just one argument, akin to present-day intransitive
small clauses (see e.g. Progovac 2006,2008a,b, 2009a,b). The claim is that such
structures are still found across various constructions in present-day languages,
living fossilsof this stage of grammar (see Jackendoff 1999,2002 for the idea of
living fossils in syntax). A living fossil in syntax can be characterized as a measurably
simpler syntactic construct which nonetheless shows continuity with more complex
counterparts, and which can be reconstructed back to a time when such complex
counterparts were not available.
1
My take on small clauses as living fossils is that they
have been preserved within modern sentences, rather than have been replaced by
them.
2
Many have proposed a simpler stage of syntax in the evolution of human language
involving concatenation (e.g. Givón 1979; Dwyer 1986; Bickerton 1990; Jackendoff
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
1
I believe that the term living fossil is appropriate to use in the context of my analysis, even though the
rigor of proof may not be identical to what one nds in biology. As pointed out in Chapter 1, biologists
consider lungsh to be a living fossil because it has changed little from its evolutionary past. In the case
of lungsh, actual fossils, identical to modern Queensland lungsh, have been found and dated at over
100 million years, proving that lungsh is a living fossil (the term rst used by Charles Darwin).
First of all, this suggests that living fossils in principle are possible, and that they can survive millions of
years, living side-by-side more modern species. Second, even if biologists had not discovered the actual
fossils, lungsh would still be a living fossil, and perhaps there would be some other, less direct way to
prove this, or at least to hypothesize this. In other words, what I hypothesize to be living fossils of language
evolution are not identical to, but are closely comparable to what is considered to be living fossils in
biology. Clearly, the proposal that I am exploring here requires a different kind of proof.
2
As pointed out in Chapter 1, the fossils as discussed in this monograph can only be seen as
approximations of the structures once used in the deep evolutionary past. Such fossils in present-day
languages may show morphological markings and other complexities which were not there in proto-
syntax. These structures count as fossils in some relevant respect under consideration, for example, in their
lack of a TP, but not in all their properties.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
1999,2002; Culicover and Jackendoff 2005; Deutscher 2005; Burling 2005; Hurford
2007,2012; Tallerman 2007,2013a, b, 2014a, b). Progovac (2006,2008a,b, 2009a,b;
2013b, 2014a) has connected this idea to the well-known construct in syntax, small
clauses.According to her proposal, small clauses used in isolation lack (at least) the
TP (Tense Phrase) layer of structure, typically associated with modern sentences in
Minimalism, and can be reduced to a single layer of structure. My argument is that
comparable small clauses served as precursors to more complex sentences (TPs),
given that they are syntactically measurably simpler (shorter by one or more layers of
structure), and given that they provide a foundation for building TPs. Crosslinguisti-
cally, small clauses (SCs) are both pervasive and robust syntactic constructs, occurring
in root contexts (as RootSCs), as embedded small clauses, as loosely attached adjuncts
or conjuncts, and, most importantly, they also serve as foundation for building full
sentences, according to Minimalism (e.g. Chomsky 1995, and subsequent work) and
predecessors to Minimalism (see Section 1.7).
The argument for the proposed progression from a small clause to a TP stage has
three prongs to it: (i) providing evidence of tinkeringwith the language design, in
the sense that older structures (i.e. small clauses) get built into more complex
structures (i.e. TPs); (ii) identifying living fossilsof the small clause stage in modern
languages; and (iii) identifying existing or potential corroborating evidence and
testing grounds, from language acquisition, agrammatism, genetics, and neurosci-
ence. Moreover, the goal is to show that each identied stage accrues concrete and
tangible advantages over the previous stage(s), advantages that were signicant
enough to be targeted by natural/sexual selection.
The method for hypothesizing previous stages of syntax can be roughly charac-
terized as internal reconstruction, based on the syntactic theory of structure building
adopted in e.g. Minimalism (e.g. Chomsky 1995). My proposal is that a structure X is
considered to be primary relative to a structure Y if X can be composed independently
of Y, but Y can only be built upon the foundation of X. While small clauses can be
composed without the TP layer, TPs must be built on the foundation of a small clause,
providing syntactic proof that small clauses are more primary than TPs (see Section 1.2.2
for the denition of the term primaryas used in the context of a reconstruction).
2.2Root small clauses in English
Consider the following three types of (marginal) RootSCs (i.e. small clauses used in
root/unembedded contexts): the so-called Mad Magazine/incredulity clauses in (1)
(Akmajian 1984); imperative/optative clauses in (3); and RootSCs involving past
participles in (5).
3
While (2), (4), and (6) can be considered their respective full
3
The examples of small clauses offered in this chapter are all intransitive, consistent with my proposal
that transitivity is a later evolutionary development in clause building, as well as with the syntactic analysis
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
34 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
sentential counterparts, no sentential paraphrase completely captures the expressive
power of RootSCs, which seem to convey a sense of urgency and immediacy. This is
just one indication that RootSCs are not simply elliptical versions of full sentences.
(1) Him retire!? John a doctor?! Sheila happy?!
Me in Rome?!
(2) Is he going to retire? Is John a doctor? Is Sheila happy?
Am I in Rome?
(3)Merst! Family rst! Everybody out!
(4) I want to be rst! Family should be rst! Everybody must
go out!
(5) Problem solved. Case closed. Point taken. Crisis averted.
Mission accomplished. Lesson learned.
(6) The problem has been solved. The case is closed. The point is
taken. The crisis has been averted. The mission has been
accomplished. The lesson has been learned.
The clauses in (1,3,5) combine a noun/pronoun with a predicate (typically verb),
resulting in a predication structure, arguably without functional projections, at the
very least without a TP.
4
While root small clauses are typically not discussed in syntactic literature, being
delegated to the periphery (but see Progovac 2006), embedded small clauses, such as
the bracketed clauses in (7) below, have received a lot of attention.
(7) I wanted [the problem solved].
I imagined [Sheila happy].
There are competing analyses of embedded small clauses, including some that ascribe
quite complex structure to them (see e.g. Cardinaletti and Guasti 1995; Dubinsky et al.
2000).
5
However, the tendency is still, overwhelmingly, to label them as SCs,
according to which transitivity involves an extra syntactic layer, a vP shell, as disussed in Chapter 3.
I assume here that passive-looking clauses in (5) do not involve a vP shell or Move(ment). Although I do
not provide a specic analysis for these clauses, my approach allows for them to be treated as middle-like
constructions, as discussed in Chapter 3.
4
The syntactic analysis of this kind of nonsententialspeech is based on Barton (1990), Barton and
Progovac (2005), and Progovac (2006,2013a) (see also Tang 2005). Fortin (2007), who embeds her analysis
in the phase framework of Minimalism (e.g. Chomsky 2001), also argues for the nonsentential analysis of
certain syntactic phrases, such as adverbials, vocatives, and bare unergative verbs, but she specically
argues against such an analysis of any propositional constructs, as are small clauses in (1,3,5), which are the
focus of this chapter.
5
One inuential early analysis is Stowell (1981), which treats such clauses, at least in the embedded
contexts, as headed structures, that is, as Adjective Phrases (APs) (Me rst!), Verb Phrases (VPs) (Him
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Root small clauses in English 35
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
suggesting hesitance to commit to an analysis that renders them projections of their
predicate, or of something else. In fact, the simplest among them may just be
paratactic creations, in which the subject and the predicate combine by the operation
Conjoin, which is akin to the operation Adjoin used in syntactic theory to account for
the attachment of various adjuncts (e.g. adverbials) (for details, see Chapter 4).
Conjoin here is to be understood in the simple sense join together, unite, combine,
rather than in the sense of using a conjunction. Chapter 4returns to the character-
ization of Conjoin, and paratactic attachment in general (Section 4.2). Sufce it to say
here that Conjoin does not create headedness or hierarchy, but rather creates
structures which can be characterized as at, and not asymmetrical.
Uriagereka (2008) looks at the embedded SCs such as the ones in (7), and
concludes that their structure is rather basic, and may involve the simplest type of
syntax in Chomsky Hierarchy (Chomsky 1956; for characterization and detailed
discussion of the Hierarchy, see e.g. Hurford 2012). One of the arguments Uriagereka
invokes for the basic nature of (embedded) small clauses is the long-noted observa-
tion that these clauses do not have an internal source of abstract (structural) Case for
their subjects, which are instead assigned Case by clause-external elements, such as
the verbs want or imagine in (7).
According to Progovac (2006), RootSCs likewise do not have a structural mech-
anism for assigning case to their subjects, providing another argument that they are
comparable to embedded SCs. Since with RootSCs there is no external source of case
either (they are not embedded under a verb), their subjects surface with what can be
characterized as default case (in the sense of e.g. Schütze 2001)witness the accusa-
tive case on the pronominal subjects in (1,3).
6
The evolutionary perspective sheds
worry?!), Prepositional Phrases (PPs) (Everybody out!), etc., based on the category of the predicate. Such
clauses, however, have properties that suggest that they form a natural class, which would not be captured if
they were labeled differently. For example, all of them can embed under a verb like want or imagine (i),
even though these verbs cannot otherwise take APs or PPs as their complements (ii).
(i) He imagined [everybody out]/[the problem solved]/[me happy].
(ii) *He imagined [very happy]/[out of there].
[The *marks an ungrammatical structure.]
That is one reason why the label small clause (SC) still persists, tacitly acknowledging that we do not know
what heads these structures, if anything at all.
6
As noted in Progovac (2006), small clauses found in isolation (e.g. Problem solved. Case closed) are even
smallerthan corresponding embedded small clauses, which require a determiner in the following examples:
(i) I consider the problem solved. / *I consider problem solved.
(ii) I consider the case closed. / *I consider case closed.
Essentially, some kind of grammatical relationship or functional projection is needed for syntactic
embedding/subordination (see Section 4.4), and for that reason bare small clauses, such as the ones
found in isolation, cannot embed (see also further discussion in the text).
The presence of the determiner the in embedded clauses instantiates the DP (Determiner Phrase) layer,
which, according to e.g. Longobardi (1994), is necessary to establish a case-checking relationship between the
higher verb and the subject of the small clause in English (Progovac 2006 has more discussion on this). This
relationship seems to provide sufcient grammatical gluetoallow embedding in this case (see also Section 4.4).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
36 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
light on the existence of both embedded SCs and RootSCsboth can be seen as
living fossilsof a proto-syntactic stage in which, presumably, clauses were put
together by an operation akin to adjunction (i.e. Conjoin), and in which there were
no functional categories or projections to facilitate grammatical relationships.
In any event, small clauses do not have the functional power to assign their
subjects a structural (nominative) case. In Minimalism, structural nominative case
is associated with the projection of TP, providing another argument that root small
clauses are not TPs. The next chapter will establish that absolutive-type fossils show a
comparable property of not having the functional power to assign structural (accusa-
tive) case to their objects.
As established in Section 1.7, the modern syntactic theory associated with Minim-
alism analyzes every clause/sentence as initially a small clause (SC) (examples below
in (a)), which gets transformed into a full TP only upon subsequent Merge of tense
(examples in (b)), and subsequent Move of the subject to TP in English (examples in
(c)). In other words, according to this inuential analysis, the layer of TP is super-
imposed upon the layer of small clause:
7
(8) a. Small clause: [
SC
Sheila happy]
b. [
TP
is [
SC/AP
Sheila happy]]
c. Sentence: [
TP
Sheila [
T
is [
SC/AP
Sheila happy]]]
(9) a. Small clause: [
SC
Peter retire]
b. [
TP
will [
SC/VP
Peter retire]]
c. Sentence: [
TP
Peter [
T
will [
SC/VP
Peter retire]]]
(10) a. Small clause: [
SC
(the) problem solved]
b. [
TP
is [
SC/VP
(the) problem solved]]
c. Sentence:
[
TP
The problem [
T
is [
SC/VP
(the) problem solved]]]
The (a) examples above involve only one clausal projection/layer, which can be
uniformly characterized as a SC (small clause). The full nite clauses in (c) have at
least two layers of clausal structure: the inner SC layer, and the outer TP layer, clearly
creating hierarchical structure. In other words, small clauses morph/transform into
TPs, as if the building of the modern sentence (TP) retraces its evolutionary steps.
The kind of derivation (from SC to TP) illustrated in (8-10) is the commonly
accepted postulate in Minimalism and predecessors, dating back to the early 1980s. In
7
I do not use the vP shells of Minimalism here because I only discuss intransitive clauses, for which the
vP shell is arguably not necessary. Chapter 3discusses this issue in greater detail and actually proposes that
the vP shell should be seen as a later evolutionary innovation, an additional layer of functional structure
superimposed over the foundational VP layer, introducing agency and transitivity. In this view, original
small clauses did not have vP shells.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Root small clauses in English 37
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
fact, this is one of the most stable postulates in this approach, which has survived
many changes of analysis and focus. In general, I base my proposal on the discoveries
and claims which are reasonably uncontroversial within this approach, and which
both predate Minimalism and survive into many later versions. Such stable postu-
lates include not only the derivation of the sentence from the underlying small clause,
but also the layering of sentential structure (e.g. CP>TP>vP>SC/VP), as established
in Chapter 1.
Recall from Chapter 1that my proposal relies on an internal syntactic reconstruc-
tion to arrive at the intransitive small clause proto-syntax:
Internal reconstruction of clause structure
A structure X is considered to be (evolutionarily) primary relative to a structure
Y if X can be composed independently of Y, but Y can only be created upon the
foundation of X.
This reconstruction claims that there was a point in time when only the primary
structures X were available, but not the structures Y, as explained in Section 1.2.2.
While small clauses (and VPs) can be composed without the vP or TP layers, vPs and
TPs need to be built upon the foundation of a small clause/VP.
The ambivalence as to how to analyze small clause structures is the reason behind
the persistence of the vague label SC.While the syntactic theory postulates that
every category (head) projects a phrase (e.g. a noun projects a noun phrase; a verb
projects a verb phrase; and a tense projects a tense phrase), and every phrase is a
projection of a head, the label SC dees this very important postulate, as it is not clear
at all what heads small clauses. One way to deal with this situation is to concede that
small clauses are not modern hierarchical formations, but rather fossils of a paratac-
tic proto-syntax stage, whose formations were neither headed nor hierarchical.
Kinsella (2009:44) raises the question of why one should have Move in the
syntactic theory, in addition to Merge, given that even in the Minimalist Program
Move is sometimes considered to be more costlythan Merge.
8
This question is
related to the question of why every sentence should begin as a small clause in the
rst place. But if the small clause core of the sentence can be seen as the rst step in
building sentential structure, as the paratactic scaffolding, then Move can be seen as a
force which connects different layers of sentential derivation, created by evolutionary
tinkering.
9
In other words, the building of the sentence bottom up, from small clause
to TP, may be seen, metaphorically, as retracing the steps of the evolutionary
development of the sentence. Neither bottom-up sentence building, nor small clausal
8
Kinsella (2009) is a published version of Parker (2006).
9
But see e.g. McDaniel (2005) for a different view of Move, as discussed in Section 4.4.5. See also
Hurford (2012) who considers that the initial impetus for Move may have been pragmatically driven, e.g.
for focalizing or topicalizing purposes.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
38 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
beginnings of the sentence, nor Move, would then need to be considered as concep-
tual necessities, but rather as just epiphenomena of evolutionary tinkering.
10
In support of the claim that modern clauses have (at least) two layers of structure,
notice that they can have two subject positions: one in which the subject is rst
Merged in the small clause, and the other in which the subject actually surfaces, after
Move (8-10). In certain sentences, both subject positions can be overtly lled, as
underlined below (see e.g. Koopman and Sportiche 1991):
(11)[
TP
The jurors [
T
will [
SC/VP
all rise]]].
The root counterpart of the small clause in (4) is also in use:
(12) All rise!
In this sense, then, a SC is indeed a half-clause in comparison to the corresponding
TP, with a substantial overlap between the two layers, as will become even more
obvious when we consider unaccusative small clauses in Serbian in the next section.
There is also some division of labor between root small clauses and their full
sentential counterparts: while full TPs specialize for indicative mood and assertion,
root small clauses tend to exhibit elsewhere, non-indicative, irrealisfunctions,
ranging over expressions of incredulity, commands, wishes, etc. Root small clauses
in general also specialize for the here-and-now, as further discussed in the following
section. It is important to point out that overlap, and partial specialization, are
hallmarks of evolutionary tinkering, but not of optimal design. According to e.g.
Carroll (2005:1701), evolving multiple means to the same end creates the oppor-
tunity for the evolution of specialization through the division of labor.
11
In the evolutionary perspective, if there was a stage of proto-syntax characterized
by root small clauses, then in that stage such clauses were probably able to express
assertions as well, there not yet having arisen the opportunity for the division of
labor.
12
The emergence of Tense/TP would have created such an opportunity for
specialization between small clauses and full TPs.
A similar scenario, which can illustrate how the emergence of a more
specialized category can lead to division of labor, has been reported for the
grammaticalization of tense and indicative mood in more recent, historical times, in
pre-Indo-European (pre-IE).
13
Many Indo-Europeanists converge on the conclusion
10
At a more abstract level, the theoretical construct Move can be seen as a metaphor for interpreting
one and the same constituent as somehow present/relevant in more than one position in a sentence. In fact,
regardless of the metaphor used, having a gap in one place which needs to be linked to a constituent in
another place in a sentence is a powerful mechanism of syntactic cohesion.
11
Carroll (2005) shows that extra limbs/appendages of various kinds, with various species, demonstrate
such specializations. In this respect, they also mention the specialization of human hands vs. legs.
12
Serbian unaccusative RootSCs are still used to express assertions, as shown in the next section. They
show specialization with respect to full TPs in other respects.
13
While Kiparsky (1968) estimates that Proto-Indo-European was spoken around 3,700 BC, Renfrew
(1987) dates it back to 7,000 BC, and Gray and Atkinson (2003), using a computational model, to around
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Root small clauses in English 39
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
that Proto-Indo-European (PIE), as well as early IE languages, had an unaugmented
verb form, theinjunctive, which was not marked for tense or mood (see e.g. Thurneysen
1883;Kuryłowicz 1925/1927; Gonda 1956; Kiparsky 1968).
14
As discussed in Kiparsky
(1968), this unmarked injunctive form, upon the grammaticalization of tense, began to
specialize for non-indicative/irrealis moods.
15
Child language acquisition seems to
proceed in a comparable fashion, from small clauses to TPs (Section 2.5), providing,
at the very least, corroborating evidence for the syntactic simplicity/primacy of small
clauses relative to tensed sentences (TPs).
2.3(Unaccusative) Root small clauses in Serbian
Serbian has the same types of root small clauses illustrated in the previous section for
English, but I will not discuss those here as they do not add anything new to the
arguments already presented in the previous section. However, Serbian has another
type of root small clause, the unaccusative root small clause, which makes an even
stronger argument for half(TP-less) syntax, and for the gradual integration of the
small clause into a nite TP. Moreover, this type of clause is quite productive in
expressing assertions, making an even stronger case for living fossils.
Serbian has (at least) two ways of expressing propositions/assertions with unac-
cusative verbs: as VS (verb-subject) small clauses, arguably without the TP layer (13),
and as full TPs with free word order (14) (for details, see Progovac 2008a,b, 2013b):
16
(13) a. Stigla pošta. (cf.
??
Pošta stigla.)
arrive.
PART
mail
The mail has (just) arrived.
10,000 years ago. Yet others have indicated that we simply do not know, and that Proto-Indo-European
could be pushed back even further (Dixon 1997:49).
14
Such tenseless/moodless forms occur in other families as well, e.g. in Bantu languages. Tswana, as
described in Cole (1955:445), has neutral tense forms which are used in coordinate structures, but also in
complements, where modern IE languages mostly use innitives. Cole refers to them as subjunctive forms.
Such neutral tenses are also found in other African languages, including Herero, Duala (where the form is
called aorist), and Swahili (Meinhof 1948).
15
In this injunctive stage of pre-IE, according to Kiparsky (1968), it was possible to express time by
temporal adverbials, which, unlike grammaticalized tense, were neither obligatory nor associated with a
specic functional projection, and which can best be described as adjuncts. In fact, in Greek and Sanskrit,
verbs are commonly put into (what looks like) present tense when modied by adverbs denoting past time
(Kiparsky 1968:47), and this is considered to be a vestige of the PIE injunctive. It is highly likely that
temporal adverbs preceded the grammaticalization of tense in the evolution of syntax.
According to Kuryłowicz (1964:21), the injunctive, a tenseless verbal form, was the only mood in earliest
PIE. Gonda (1956:367) points out that any attempt exactly to translate the injunctive categories into a
modern Western idiom is doomed to fail, given the vagueness in meaning and the great, and in the eyes of
modern man astonishing, variety of its functions.As pointed out in Chapter 6, some of these functions
were optative and imperative, which seem to have been preserved in VN compounds in some languages.
16
PART
in the glosses stands for a perfective participle form of the verb, which marks perfective/
completed aspect, but not tense. The form is equivalent to English gonein expressions such as All gone.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
40 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
b. Pala vlada. (cf.
??
Vlada pala.)
fall.
PART
government
The government has (just) collapsed.
c. Umro Petar. (cf.
??
Petar umro.)
die.
PART
Peter
Peter just died.
d. Pao sneg/mrak. (cf.
??
Sneg/Mrak pao.)
fall.
PART
snow/darkness
It has just snowed./It got dark.
Among such SCs, many are formulaic/rigid/non-compositional in meaning, and
with these the rigidity of VS word order is more obvious:
e. Pala karta. (cf.
?*
Karta pala.)
fall.
PART
card
Card laid, card played.
f. Prošo voz. (cf.
??
Voz prošo.)
gone train
The opportunity has passed.
g. Pukla tikva. (cf.
?*
Tikva pukla.)
burst.
PART
squash
The friendship/alliance has ended.
The full (TP) counterparts feature the nite (past tense) auxiliary je, as well as free(er)
word order (14a-d). In addition, formulaic readings typically do not survive expan-
sion into full clauses, as shown in (14e-g), which are interpreted literally.
(14)a.Pošta je stigla. / Stigla je pošta.
mail is arrived arrived is mail
The mail (has) arrived.
b. Vlada je pala. / Pala je vlada.
The government (has) collapsed.
c. Petar je umro. / Umro je Petar.
Peter died.
d. Sneg je pao. / Pao je sneg. Mrak je pao. / Pao je mrak.
It snowed.’‘It got dark.
e. Karta je pala. / Pala je karta.
The card fell.
f. Voz je prošao. / Prošao je voz.
The train is gone.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
(Unaccusative) Root small clauses in Serbian 41
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
g. Tikva je pukla. / Pukla je tikva.
The squash has burst.
Unaccusatives can be roughly characterized as intransitive structures which blur the
boundary between subjects and objects in the sense that their only argument is not an
agent, but typically theme, showing some properties of objects. Consequently, un-
accusative verbs (e.g. arrive, fall, come, appear) are analyzed crosslinguistically as
Merging their sole arguments as objects, rather than as subjects (e.g. Perlmutter 1978;
Burzio 1981,1986). In Serbian, there is a preference even in the surface structure for
unaccusative subjects to follow the verb, the position typically associated with objects.
With unaccusative SCs in (13) this preference becomes more rigid, imposing the
otherwise non-canonical VS order (see Progovac 2008a,b, 2013b, for details).
17
Given this widely accepted analysis of unaccusatives, full/nite unaccusative
clauses in Serbian and English are derived as follows:
18
(15) a. Small clause: [
sc
pala vlada]
b. [
tp
je [
sc
pala vlada]]
c. TP Sentence: [
tp
vlada [
t’
je [
sc
pala vlada]]]
(16)a.[
sc
spill the milk]
b. [
tp
will [
sc
spill the milk]]
c. [
tp
the milk [
t’
will [
sc
spill the milk]]]
Here, the milkcan be considered object-like also in the sense that if there is an
agent added, as in John spilled the milk, then the milkwould clearly emerge as an
object (for further discussion of this, see Chapter 3).
In the paper entitled What use is half a clause?Progovac (2008a) argues that root
small clauses are half-clausesin comparison to the TP counterparts, which have an
additional (TP) layer of structure. The clause in (15a) is a half-clause in comparison to
the clause/sentence (15c), which has two layers of structure, SC and TP, and two
subject positions, as also discussed below. Frequent arguments against Darwins
theory of evolution have been of the kind: what use is half an eye? Since similar
arguments have been raised against a gradualist approach to the evolution of syntax,
17
The closest English equivalents to rigid VS unaccusatives occur in fossilized expressions such as
Come winter, she will travel to Rome; cf. *Winter come, she will travel to Rome). Another example, Come
one, come all, is found among the fossilized small clause combinations, as discussed in Section 2.4. Just as in
Serbian, the word order in these expressions is VS, even though the word order in English is otherwise
SVO, and Serbian typically shows a freedom of word order, with SVO being the default order.
18
As shown in the examples in the text, Serbian TPs can also retain the unaccusative VS order, in which
case the tense particle je has to follow the verb (see example (14) in the text). Since je is a clitic, it has to
observe the Clitic-Second requirement in Serbian, and that is why it cannot appear rst in (14). There are
many different approaches to the placement of clitics in Serbian, but for my purposes here I will assume
that the SV examples in (14) are syntactically more complex than the VS counterparts, involving more
movement operations, most notably subject raising to the specier of TP.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
42 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
it is instructive to wonder about whether such half-clauses would have been useful to
our ancestors when they rst stumbled upon syntax.
19
As it turns out, such half-clauses are used productively in Serbian even today
(13), alongside with the full TP counterparts illustrated in (14)(Section2.4). As is
the case with English root small clauses discussed in the previous section, Serbian
unaccusative half-clauses also specialize for the here-and-now, reporting on an
event that has just manifested itself. Consequently, these clauses cannot be modi-
ed by adverbs denoting remote past, such as three years ago(?*Stigla pošta pre
tri godine,arrived mail before three years), leading again to a division of labor.
Moreover, some formulaic unaccusative clauses (13e, repeated below) are only
possible as half-clauses, and not as full clauses, when used to perform a speech-
act in the context of a card game:
(13e) Pala karta. (cf.
?*
Karta pala. /
?*
Karta je pala.)
fall.
PART
card
Card laid, card playedyou cannot take it back now.
These clauses rst of all provide a forceful argument that half-clause syntax is real:
the VS word order in these clauses can only be explained if the widely-adopted
unaccusative hypothesis is coupled with the small-clause analysis. The awkwardness
of the (otherwise default) SV order (13) makes it clear that they are not just
abbreviated/elliptical versions of some nite counterparts, such as those given in
(14). Rather, these half-clauses, as well as the ones illustrated for English in the
previous section, demonstrate consistent and systematic properties of a different,
simpler clausal syntax, a syntax that involves one (less) layer of clausal structure, the
basic (underived) word order (no Move), non-nite verb forms, and default case (for
more details, see Progovac 2006,2008b).
From the evolutionary standpoint, it is signicant that half-clauses (13) to some
extent overlap in function with their full equivalents (14), even though they show a
degree of specialization as well, as elaborated in the repeated example below.
(14) a. Stigla je pošta.
arrive.
PERF.PART.F.SG
is.
3SG
mail.
F.SG
The mail has (just) arrived.
19
As put in Carroll (2005:1701), the erroneous notion . . . has been that the intermediate stages in the
evolution of structures must be uselessthe old saw of What use is half a leg or half an eye?’” Such
expressions of disbelief were partly due to the inability to imagine, based on the structure of the modern
eye, how it could have been broken down into stages, and moreover stages that would have provided
incremental advantages. The arguments against a gradualist approach to the evolution of syntax are of a
comparable kind: given how we view/understand modern syntax today, we cannot imagine how it could
have evolved through stages, and moreover how each new stage could have provided incremental
advantages.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
(Unaccusative) Root small clauses in Serbian 43
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
While the perfective participles in half-clauses contribute to the perfective aspect (but
have no tense or TP), the full counterparts mark both perfective aspect (with the
participle) and (past) tense (with the auxiliary je). This expression of tense/aspect
must be redundant at least to some extent (especially for the here-and-now situ-
ations), given that only past tense auxiliaries in this case are compatible with these
perfective participle forms.
Agreement properties of these clauses exhibit redundancy and overlap even more
obviously. As indicated in the glosses in (14), the participle form agrees with the
subject in number and gender, but not in person, the type of agreement that also
characterizes adjectives in Serbian. On the other hand, the auxiliary verb agrees with
the subject in person and number (but not in gender). It is as though both layers
of the clause have their own subject position (see previous section, examples 1112),
their own separate agreement properties, which partly overlap, and their own ways of
encoding time/aspect, which again partly overlap. This provides evidence of tinker-
ing with clausal structure, rather than evidence of optimal design.
20
My proposal in this respect is that a layer of TP (or a comparable functional
projection) was at one point in evolution superimposed upon the layer of a small
clause (half-clause), the proto-syntactic construct which already was able to express
some basic clausal properties: predication and some temporal/aspectual properties.
21
If so, then half-clauses would have been useful to our ancestors. A half-clause is still
useful, even in expressing propositional contentmuch more useful than having no
clausal syntax at all, and less useful than articulated nite syntax. This is exactly the
scenario upon which evolution/selection can operate.
2.4Small clause syntax is rigid (no Move, no recursion)
In addition to the obvious morpho-syntactic hallmarks of the discussed root small
clauses in English and Serbian (absence of a nite verbal form, absence of nominative
case checking in English, absence of subject raising with Serbian unaccusative SCs
(resulting in strong preference for VS order), these clauses are also characterized by
20
The argument here is that root small clauses both in English and in Serbian are approximations of a
proto-syntax stage in the evolution of human language, and that the superimposition of a TP over the small
clause layer works basically in the same way in both languages. A reviewer wonders if these data may not
just be properties of particular languages, but not a design feature for the capacity for language. First of all,
Minimalism and predecessors analyze every sentence/clause as starting as a small clause, and the intent for
this analysis is to hold universally, in all languages. The English and Serbian data discussed here are thus
just illustrations of this otherwise universal phenomenon. What I am claiming here is that this property of
language, recognized in syntactic theory, reects an imperfection, evidence of tinkering, rather than
optimal design.
21
Finally, the reviewers wonder how one can distinguish between historical change and language
evolution in this case. While historical language change is typically considered to be a change which
does not have any genetic consequences, language evolution (and evolution in general) is typically
associated with genetic changes. I address this issue in Section 7.3.5.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
44 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
the following surprising properties: they do not tolerate movement of any kind
(1718); they cannot embed (one within another), and thus do not show recursion
(1920); their interpretation is typically conned to the here-and-now (2123); and
many among them are (semi-)formulaic. For all these reasons, these clauses cannot
be analyzed as identical in structure or complexity to their full nite counterparts,
nor can they be reduced to elliptical versions of the full counterparts.
The following (a) examples illustrate that small clause syntax does not exhibit (wh-)
movement, in sharp contrast to the full sentences (b).
22
(17) a. *Who(m) worry?!
*Where everybody?!
b. Who worries?
Where is everybody?
(18) a. *Kada stigla pošta?
when arrived mail
b. Kada je stigla pošta?
The examples below illustrate that a small clause of this type cannot embed into
another clause, and thus does not show recursion. Recall from Chapter 1that
recursion is dened in this book, as per the traditional view, as a category of a certain
type being embedded within another category of the same type. In this respect, what
we see in (19) is a (failed) attempt to embed one SC within another SC.
(19) a. *Him worry [me rst]?
b. *Him worry [problem solved]?
(20) a. *Ja mislim [(da) stigla pošta].
I think (that) arrived mail
b. cf. Ja mislim [da je stigla pošta].
At rst sight, it may seem that the clauses in (20) should be able to embed if the
complementizer da is used, given that complementizers are supposed to provide
the specic functional glue necessary for subordination, as per the discussion in
Chapter 4. However, in syntactic theory it is considered that there is a hierarchy
22
Interestingly, as the reviewers of this manuscript have pointed out, some types of questions seem
possible with subsentential structures, and I have no good explanation for that. While (i) seems to be a xed
expression, an unanalyzed unit, (ii) illustrates that why can freely combine with various categories.
Interestingly, however, neither of them can combine with a small clause (iv). The example in (iii) may
be an echo question, that is, a question echoing what somebody else has said before.
(i) How come?
(ii) Why worry? Why now? Why Mary?
(iii) Solve what?
(iv) *Why Mary worry? *How come Mary worry?
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Small clause syntax is rigid (no Move, no recursion) 45
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
of functional projections such that each functional category selects the next (e.g.
Abney 1987; Adger 2003; but see e.g. Grimshaw 2000, who does not adopt this view
of the hierarchy). Recall that this is the theoretical postulate on which my recon-
struction method rests, making use of the hierarchy of functional projections:
CP>TP>vP>SC/VP.
In this concrete case, a CP (Complementizer Phrase) needs to select a TP (Tense
Phrase). This would mean that if a clause does not have a TP to begin with, it cannot
build a CP or use a nite complementizer/subordinator. Serbian data illustrated in
(20) conform to this pattern rather dramatically. The subordinate clauses with the
tense auxiliary can be introduced by the complementizer, and are fully recursive
(20b), while the clauses without the tense auxiliary cannot take a complementizer and
cannot embed at all (20a).
23
Finally, the following data illustrate that small clauses are typically conned to the
here-and-now, rejecting modication by adverbials denoting distant past.
(21) a. *Stigla pošta pre tri godine.
three years ago
b. *Pala karta pre tri godine.
(22) a. *Case closed three years ago.
b. *Me rst three years ago!
Clearly, we are dealing with two distinct types of grammar here: the simpler, rigid,
TP-less small clause grammar, arguably approximating the ancient proto-syntax
stage, and the more complex TP grammar, which subsumes the former in that a
TP is projected upon the small clause foundation.
24
TPs have at least one more layer
of structure than root small clauses (or half-clauses). Superimposing one layer (e.g.
TP) over another (SC) creates hierarchy, as well as additional syntactic space for
Move to target as it connects multiple layers of structure. Due to the wiring of the
brain in this particular way throughout human evolution, it is entirely possible that
the only way we humans can build sentences is by starting with the small clause, even
if one can certainly envision more direct and more optimal derivations.
23
A reviewer wonders about the English example in (i) in this respect:
(i) [
CP
For [
TP
John [
T
to have left]]] would make sense.
The bracketed clause is still typically analyzed as having a C (for) which selects a TP headed by to. But the
reviewer is correct to point out that sometimes the heads of TP or CP are allowed to be non-overt in this
theory, which makes it harder to see how the hierarchy works.
24
It is worth pointing out here that the rigid small clauses considered here seem to be syntactic isolates,
in the sense that they cannot be easily embedded or modied, and in this sense they do not show recursion
even in the Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitchs(2002) weak sense of the term, which seems to reduce to the
possibility to reapply Merge. Recursion is discussed in much more detail in Chapter 4.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
46 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Quite clearly, these data cannot be attributed to any cognitive restrictions: the ability
to embed examples in (20b), but not those in (20a), depends solely on the structural
properties of these two types of clauses. The signicance of this for the evolutionary
argument is that one may in principle be capable of recursive thought, but cannot
express it through language via subordination if the structural properties of language
are limited in this way.
25
Given these data and analyses, one can reconstruct a
gradualist progression from proto-syntax to the development of recursion, as discussed
in Chapter 4.
Notice that Move and recursion, reducible to Merge, are considered to be universal
and dening properties of human language among most Minimalist researchers (see
e.g. Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch 2002; Chomsky 2005; Moro 2008). While Hauser,
Chomsky, and Fitch (2002) do not dene it, what seems to be meant by recursion by
them is the ability to apply and then re-apply Merge, so perhaps this sense of
recursion can be characterized as recombinability (see e.g. Tomalin 2011 for some
useful discussion). In other words, the operation Merge can apply repeatedly. The
ability to recombine/re-Merge in this way yields hierarchy, but not necessarily what is
typically considered to be recursion by linguists, that is, the ability to embed one
category (e.g. CP) within another category of the same type, in an unlimited fashion
(see Chapter 4for more discussion on this).
If considerations in this book are on the right track, then Move and recursion
cannot be the dening properties of human language, not even recursion in the weak
sense of recombinability. Nor can they be reduced to Merge. Rather, both Move and
recursion should be seen as relatively recent, fragile innovations, which emerged with
the hierarchical stage (as discussed at length in Chapter 4).
The TP/CP grammar allows for embedded recursion (23) and for the expression of
a variety of nuanced meanings with respect to the temporal/aspectual/modal prop-
erties of the clause (24):
(23) He worries [that I think [that the problem has been solved]].
(24) The problem has been/may have been/will be solved.
I will be/should be/better be rst.
The small clause grammar, on the other hand, allows for at concatenation of two
clauses, of the type illustrated in (2534), once again often resulting in (semi-)formulaic
expressions, not subject to questioning or recursion (see Progovac 2010a):
26
25
A reviewer has wondered how recursive thought is related to recursive syntax. As my goal in this
monograph is to conne my claims to what my reconstruction and my fossil data lead me to, this question
falls outside the scope of this monograph. Still, for what it is worth, I believe that, as in art, the medium
partly shapes not only what you can express, but also what occurs to you to express.
26
The reader will notice that not all of these clausesinvolve a noun-verb combination, but that there
are other possibilities as well. Most of them involve an interesting AB-AC pattern, although in the Serbian
examples the As are not identical, only similar (correlated) in some sense. In spite of the differences among
them, they all seem to exhibit a characteristic rhythm and symmetry.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Small clause syntax is rigid (no Move, no recursion) 47
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(25) Nothing ventured, nothing gained.
(26) Easy come, easy go.
(27) First come, rst serve.
(28) Monkey see, monkey do.
(29) Come one, come all.
(30) Like father, like son.
(31) So far, so good.
(32) Preko preče, naokolo bliže. (Serbian)
Across shorter, around closer.
(33)Što na umu, to na drumu.
what on mind that on road
What one thinks, one says.
(34) Duga kosa, kratka pamet.
long hair short intelligence
Who wears long hair has little intelligence.
(35) Wo dua wo twa. (Twi)
27
you sow you reap
(36)Wo hwehwea wo hu.
you seek you nd
As discussed in Chapter 4, the glue that holdsthese small clause combinations together
is paratactic, resulting in a non-hierarchical, symmetric bond, arguably created by the
same operation Conjoin which joins the subject and the predicate in at small clauses
(Section 2.2). Let me represent the paratactic process Conjoin with the symbol #:
(35) [sc Monkey # see] # [
SC
monkey # do]
In fact, if musical protolanguage was an episode in the evolution of human language
(see e.g. Darwin 1874; Fitch 2010:475), then it would have been most useful right here,
in this paratactic stage, in which the rhythm and melody would have served to hold
together not only two-word clauses, but also binary combinations of such clauses.
However, unlike in Fitchs proposal in which a musical stage preceded words
(criticized by Tallerman 2013a), the use of melody/prosody here would have been
compositional, used to combine words into larger utterances (see also Section 4.2).
27
Twi is spoken in Ghana. Thanks to Kingsley Okai (p.c. 2011) for supplying the data.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
48 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The best evidence of rigid syntax is typically found among intransitive constructions,
specically among unaccusative and absolutive-like constructions. This observation is
taken up in the next chapter, which postulates an intransitive, absolutive-like stage in
the evolution of syntax, and which discusses its many modern manifestations. The next
section considers corroborating evidence and testing grounds for the small clause
proposal explored in this chapter.
2.5Corroborating evidence and testing grounds
There exists abundant corroborating evidence for the small clause beginnings of
language, which comes from the gradual emergence of syntax in child language
acquisition and second language acquisition (Section 2.5.1) and from agrammatism
(2.5.2). In addition, neuroscience (2.5.3) and genetics (2.5.4) constitute possible testing
grounds for this hypothesis. Section 2.5.5considers various other stratication-based
approaches to evolutionary progression, adding to the plausibility of the proposal
explored in this monograph.
2.5.1Language acquisition
When it comes to rst language acquisition, it has been argued by many that children
go through a root small clause/root innitive stage (e.g. Radford 1988,1990; Lebeaux
1989; Platzak 1990; Ouhalla 1991; Guilfoyle and Noonan 1992; Rizzi 1994; Jordens 2002;
Potts and Roeper 2006; but see e.g. Guasti 2002; Pinker 1996, for opposing views). Of
course, this stage follows the well-known one-word stage in which single words are
used often to express full propositions (e.g. Bloom 1970). According to Radford (1990),
children enter the one-word stage at about ten months of age, start sequencing single
words at around fteen months, and start using something comparable to small clauses
around two years of age. This sequencing represents a plausible transition from one-
word stage to a small clause stage in evolution as well (Chapter 4).
Below are some examples from child English, using root small clauses, based on
Guasti (2002):
(37) Marie go. Me go.
Eve gone.
Kitty hiding.
You nice.
These data are obviously missing markers of niteness, and can thus be analyzed as
TP-less small clauses, as they are in e.g. Radfords work. It is also obvious that these
data are directly comparable to the root small clauses in adult speech, as introduced
in the previous sections, which also consist of a noun/pronoun and a predicate, either
involving a non-nite verb (innitive or participle), or some other predicate, such as
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 49
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
adjective. If these are essentially the same kinds of root small clauses, used by both
adults and children, then it is not surprising that childrens initial stages of language
development do not show embedding/subordination or Move, both reported to be
rather late developments in children (e.g. Radford 1990; Lebeaux 1989; Ouhalla 1991;
Platzak 1990; Potts and Roeper 2006; Hollebrandse and Roeper 2007). The claim in
this monograph is that Move and recursion are unavailable to paratactic (small
clause) grammars. As shown in Section 2.4, adult root small clauses, taken to be
fossils of the paratactic small clause stage in language evolution, also show no Move
or recursion. Given the small clause data in adult speech and in language acquisition,
one can conclude that a small clause stage in language evolution was not only
possible, but highly probable.
Early stages of second language acquisition have been analyzed in a similar light.
According to e.g. Klein and Purdues(1997)inuential work, second language
acquisition can stabilize/fossilize at the stage of the so-called Basic Variety, which
is, according to them, a well-structured, simple, and efcient form of language. The
Basic Variety also does without most functional categories, complex hierarchical
structure, Move, and subordination.
A reviewer has wondered why language acquisition would be relevant for the
considerations of language evolution. First, I should remind the reader that my
proposal is based on syntactic reconstruction, as well as on the availability of
syntactic fossils, and I use language acquisition only as corroborating evidence for
the proposal, and not as main evidence. Having said that, let me also point out that in
my proposal language evolved through scaffolding/layering, in such a way that the
lowest layers served as necessary foundation for the higher layers. The prediction of
this proposal is that child language, to the extent that it emerges in stages, has to
observe the same scaffolding. So, even without any ontogeny/phylogeny connections
ever established in biology, child language acquisition would still be relevant for
language evolution considerations, at least for the approach that I am pursuing in this
monograph.
In biological texts (e.g. Ridley 1993:551; also Strickberger 2000:4934), the rela-
tionship between ontogeny and phylogeny is considered to be a classic topic in
evolutionary studies, despite much controversy surrounding it. In my work, I do
not consider that ontogeny literally recapitulates phylogeny, but only that it can be
used as secondary, corroborating support for a proposal that is independently
established. This is in line with e.g. Studdert-Kennedy (1991); Rolfe (1996); Locke
(2009); Locke and Bogin (2006), who suggest that present-day views warrant the use
of ontogeny to corroborate hypotheses about phylogeny.
When it comes to the studies of the evolution of language, Burling (2005,174)
makes use of the phylogeny/ontogeny connection, and so does Lieberman (e.g. 2000)
in his discussion of the descent of larynx. In his work on Riau Indonesian, Gil (2005)
also invokes the phylogeny-ontogeny connection. In particular, he argues that Riau
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
50 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
comes close to being a perfect example of an IMA (IsolatingMonocategorial
Associational) language, a language whose syntax can be characterized as exhibiting
a simple combinatorial operation (call it Conjoin), the semantic effect of which is a
loose associational relationship. According to Gil, IMA language may constitute a
stage both in language acquisition and language evolution.
On the other hand, as a reviewer points out, Yang (2013) argues that there is no
connection between phylogeny and ontogeny when it comes to language, and con-
cludes from there that gradualist approaches to language evolution are not feasible.
However, in the nal analysis, this article cannot reach both of these conclusions at the
same time. That is, one cannot claim that the connection between ontogeny and
phylogeny is irrelevant, and then use it (i.e. use the supposed lack of correspondence
between the two) to make an argument that there was no gradual evolution of
language. I thus interpret this article to be actually using the (lack of) ontogeny/
phylogeny connection in a certain domain to make an argument against a gradualist
approach to the evolution of syntax. This paper is discussed further in Section 4.5.1.3.
The reviewer also wonders if there is enough evidence for a two-word stage in rst
language acquisition. It has been reported by various researchers that there typically
is such a stage, a stage where utterances of more than two words are very rare (e.g.
Bloom 1970; Bloom 1994). Of course, a two-word stage does not eradicate the one-
word stage, as I discuss in this monograph, and thus this stage would encompass both
one-word and two-word utterances. It is worth mentioning in this respect that the
level of language prociency in children is typically measured by the mean length of
their utterances (MLU), characterized as the number of words/morphemes per
utterance. It is well-known that MLU increases gradually with age, and it is often
used as an indicator of the acquisition stage. I return to this issue in Section 3.5, where
I discuss the absolutive-like nature of childrens two-word utterances.
However, an inuential theory of language acquisition, the Continuity Hypothesis,
has proposed that in spite of appearances, childrens grammars, from the very start,
are full-blown adult grammars, where the functional categories are only supercially
missing (see e.g. Guasti 2002 and references there; Pinker 1996; see also the quote
from Berwick and Chomsky 2011 in Section 1.1). The rationale behind the Continuity
Hypothesis is that without assuming it, there is a discontinuity between child
grammars and adult grammars, and it would be a difcult task to explain how
children then advance to adult grammars (see also Section 3.5for more discussion
on this). Interestingly, comparable arguments have been advanced against the grad-
ualist approach to the evolution of syntax.
When it comes to the continuity of syntax, Progovac et al.(2006) have proposed in
the Epilogue that continuity lies in small clause/paratactic grammars, rather than in
full nite grammars. As pointed out above, both children and adults use small clause
grammars, and, moreover, small clauses are built into the very foundation of nite
sentences. For agrammatic patients (see following subsection), even when they lose
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 51
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
the ability to consistently produce full sentences, they are often capable of producing
small clauses. According to Kolks (e.g. 2006) study of Dutch and German, normal
adults produced 10% non-nite root clauses, aphasics produced about 60%, and in
children the overuse of non-nite root clauses decreases with age: from 83% in the
two-year-olds, to 60% in the two-and-a-half-year-olds, to 40% in the three-year-olds.
There is thus continuity and common ground in the use of small clause/non-nite
grammars across all these groups.
Clearly, if small clause grammars are the foundational structures, upon which
everything else rests, then they are expected to emerge rst for that reason alone.
Given that adults use small clause grammars as well, both in root and embedded
contexts, children are exposed to simpler grammars, and the continuity of language is
not disrupted.
2.5.2Agrammatism
Agrammatism offers another source of corroborating evidence for the primacy of
simpler, paratactic grammars. When it comes to aphasia, Kolk (2006; also Kolk 1995;
Kolk, van Grunsven, and Keyser 1985) has argued that the preventive adaptation
results in a bias to select simpler types of constructions, often sub-sentential, includ-
ing root small clauses and root innitives (see also Friedmann and Grodzinsky 1997).
The argument is that the impaired system reorganizes to exploit alternative routes to
the same goal.
(38) Kofe drinken.
coffee drink-
INF
(39) Portemonnaie verloren.
wallet lost-
PAST.PART
(40)iedereen naar buiten
Everybody out
Just as with the English small clause data, the data above illustrate clauses with non-
nite verb forms, in particular the innitive (38) and the past participle (39), as well as
clauses without a verb (40). The use of non-nite clauses in Dutch and German is
signicant not only because they occur so frequently in agrammatism, but also because
they involve morphology and word order that are distinct from what is found in the
corresponding nite clauses. Just as with the Serbian data discussed in sections 2.3and
2.4, this again indicates that one is dealing with a distinct, simpler type of grammar,
which cannot be reduced to elliptical versions of full nite sentences.
2.5.3Neuroimaging
Neuroimaging can provide a fertile testing ground for various evolutionary claims,
including the hypotheses explored in this chapter. My suggestion is that one can use
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
52 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
the subtraction and other neuro-linguistic methods to determine how paratactic
small clause structures are processed in comparison to their more complex (TP)
counterparts, in an attempt to identify neuro-biological correlates of TP layering and
niteness (see Progovac 2010b).
For the reasons given in the Appendix, while the processing of full TPs is expected
to show clear lateralization in the left hemisphere, with extensive activation of
specic Brocas areas, the proto-syntactic structures, including root small clauses,
are expected to show less lateralization, and less involvement of Brocas areas, but
more reliance on both hemispheres, as well as, possibly, more reliance on the
subcortical structures of the brain. This can be tested given the availability of
minimally contrasting pairs in English and Serbian discussed in this chapter, such
as Case closed vs. The case is closed;Pao sneg vs. Sneg je pao (1314). A detailed
proposal to this effect can be found in the Appendix. If syntax evolved gradually,
through several stages, then it is plausible to expect that modern syntactic structures
and operations decompose into evolutionary primitives. If so, this will be measurable
in the activation of the brain.
If the brain co-evolved with language/syntax, then the pressures to use ever more
complex syntax contributed to the strengthening of necessary neural connections,
and with it some specic processing strategies. According to Deacon (2003:867), if
language structure arose in a drawn-out coevolutionary process in which both brain
and language structures would have exerted selection pressures on one another, then
we should expect to nd that human brains exhibit species-unique modications
that tend to tthe unique processing demands imposed by language learning and
use.As noted by many, including Deacon (1997) and Diller and Cann (2013), not all
parts of the brain increased at the same rate, but Brocas areas and other language
processing areas increased more than proportionately. According to Diller and Cann
(2013:253), in biology we expect form and function to evolve together.In other
words, if certain processing strategies evolved more recently in order to support e.g.
layered syntax, then it is expected that such strategies would exhibit a particularly
good t for the function of processing such syntactic structures.
2.5.4Genetics and the FOXP2 gene
Genetics is another area of great interest to the evolutionary considerations. A gene
has recently been identied, the FOXP2gene, which is taken to play a role not only in
articulation, but also in the processing of (morpho-)syntax. The symptoms of the
affected members of the KE family (those who have a mutation) include simplied
morpho-syntax (e.g. Gopnik and Crago 1991), potentially implicating problems with
building functional categories and projections, including tense and TP (see also
Piattelli-Palmarini and Uriagereka 2011; also some discussion in Tallerman 2013a).
The specic symptoms involve subject drop and the nonsystematic use of plural
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 53
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
forms and tense (Gopnik and Crago 1991, and references cited there). While Diller
and Cann (2012:171) consider that it would seem likely that FOXP2is more
important for . . . vocalized speech than for something as complex as grammar,
they add that speech and certain aspects of grammar . . . are closely related to each
other from the standpoint of human neural function,and that the KE family . . . has
a disruption of both speech and certain aspects of grammar.
This may suggest that the affected KE family members experience difculties
establishing neural connections necessary for connecting multiple layers of structure,
in a manner similar to agrammatic speakers (Section 2.5.2); see also the discussion
below. In an fMRI experiment (Liégeois et al.2003), the unaffected KE family
members showed a typical left-dominant distribution of activation involving Broca's
area, whereas the affected members showed a more posterior and more extensively
bilateral pattern of activation, as well as signicant underactivation in Brocasarea
and its right homologue. This may suggest that they are relying on alternative
processing strategies, possibly those better suited for processing paratactic language.
According to Enard et al.(2002), there is evidence for positive selection of the gene
by humans, which would render this discovery of relevance for the evolution of
language. Diller and Cann (2009;2012:171) estimate that the FOXP2mutation dates
back to 1.8to 1.9mya (million years ago), approximately the time when Homo (Homo
habilis, H. ergaster, and H. erectus) emerged, and when the hominin brains began to
triple in size. According to Diller and Cann (2012:171), this would be consistent with
symbolic speech, grammatical language, and the spectacular brain growth evolving
together.
FOXP2is just one of several genes that are implicated in language and speech
(disorders), and are thus of potential relevance for language evolution (see e.g.
Newbury and Monaco 2010). Two other potentially relevant genes are CNTNAP2
and ASPM (Diller and Cann 2012; see Dediu and Ladd 2007 for ASPM and Micro-
cephalin).
28
In order to actively engage this and any other relevant future ndings in
genetics, we linguists will have to come up with some concrete linguistically-based
hypotheses about how language evolved. Without that, these remarkable ndings in
genetics will go untapped.
To suggest just one possible track, some recent experiments indicate that the
specically human FOXP2mutations are responsible for increasing synaptic plasti-
city and for establishing better connectivity among neurons in the brain (e.g. Vernes
28
According to Christiansen and Chater (2008), human genome-wide scans have revealed evidence of
recent positive selection for more than 250 genes (Voight, Kudaravalli, Wen, and Pritchard 2006), making
it very possible that genetic adaptations for language would have continued in this scenario. According to
Hurford and Dediu (2009:179), there is genetic diversity across the human species and each gene has a
different history.See also Levinson and Dediu (2013). Fitch (2010:503) observes that if widespread allelic
variations turn out to correlate with subtle linguistic differences, as suggested by Dediu and Ladd (2007),
genetic data may help resolve such debates in the coming decades.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
54 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
et al.2007; Enard et al.2009:968). This contributes to the enhanced capability of
cortico-basal ganglia circuits in the human brain that regulate critical aspects of
language, cognition, and motor control (Lieberman 2009). One can thus hypothesize
that the FOXP2mutation was selected, in part, in order to facilitate the processing
of syntax.
2.5.5Stratication accounts elsewhere
The proposal in this chapter considers that the complexity in clausal structure arose
through the imposition of one layer of structure upon another, that is, by superim-
posing a layer of TP over the layer of a small clause. It is worth pointing out that
stratication accounts have also been proposed for brain evolution in general, where
newly emerged patterns are considered to become dominant and rework/subor-
dinate older patterns into conformity with them (e.g. Rolfe 1996; Vygotsky 1979).
Vygotsky (1556) states that brain development proceeds in accordance with the
laws of stratication of construction of new levels on old ones . . . Instinct is not
destroyed, but copiedin conditioned reexes as a function of the ancient brain,
which is now to be found in the new one.
29
A repeated theme in Piagets work is the
inclusion of attainments of earlier stages in the structures of later stages (Gruber and
Vonèche 1977: xxiii). From this perspective, small clause structures can be seen as the
older/lower structures, which are retained in, and subordinated to, the newer/higher
sentential TP structures.
30
The notion of the triune brain also invokes the idea of evolutionary layering and
subordination. According to Isaacson (1982:1,240), following Broca (e.g. 1878), the
inner lobe of the brain is organized into two layers: the inner and phyletically oldest
ring (allocortex) and the outer limbic ring (transitional cortex). The lowest, proto-
reptilian brain involves ancestral learning and memories, which are subjugated by the
higher limbic brain, thus allowing forgetfulness and suppression of the protoreptilian
habitual way of responding (MacLean 1949:2402,247). In turn, rational decision
making is associated with the prefrontal cortex, or yet-higher brain (Strickberger
2000:506).
In his characterization of symbolic reference, Deacon (1997:300) argues that each
higher-order form of a representational relationship must be constructed from, or
decomposed into, lower levels of representation, in such a way that indexical reference
depends upon iconic reference, and symbolic reference in turn depends upon indexical
29
As put in Bickerton (1998:353)the creation of a new neural pathway in no way entails the extinction of
the previous one. The fact that weremain capable offunctioning in the protolinguistic mode. . .indicates the
persistence of the older link.
30
A rather concrete example of evolutionary layering and recency dominance comes from the adap-
tation that led to black coloration in leopards, which still preserves the previous layer of orange spots
(Carroll 2005). Metaphorically speaking, the small clause grammar can be seen as orange spots still lurking
through the layer of the more recent, dominant black coloration of sentential/TP speech.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 55
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
reference. Deacon (453) concludes that a failure to appreciate the constitutive role of
lower forms leads to a perspective that kicks the ladder away after climbing up to the
symbolic realm and then imagines that there never was a ladder in the rst place.
2.6Conclusion
In the evolutionary proposal given in this chapter, Tense and TP (and higher projec-
tions, such as CP) did not emerge from scratch, but were superimposed upon what was
already therethe small clause layerallowing small clauses to survive, but only in
marginalized, subordinated roles. This kind of incremental building of clausal structure
is arguably also evident in language acquisition (Section 2.5.1). The above established
quirky (rather than optimal) properties of modern clauses, attested crosslinguistically,
begin to make sense if they are seen as by-products of evolutionary tinkering.
Relying on the stable postulates of syntax, that TPs are built upon the foundation
of small clauses, one naturally arrives at the small clause stage in language evolution
by a method of internal reconstruction. By removing the TP layer of the clause, one
can get down to the SC layer. This same method of reconstruction will be used again
in the next chapter to reconstruct an intransitive stage in the evolution of syntax, by
peeling away the vP layer, associated with agents and transitivity. The proposal in the
next chapter also sheds light on various other puzzling properties of language design,
including unaccusativity and ergativity. Chapter 7demonstrates how the property of
displacement, a design feature of human language, is supported by more complex
grammars.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
56 The small (clause) beginnings
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
3
The intransitive two-word stage:
Absolutives, unaccusatives, and
middles as precursors to transitivity
3.1Introduction: The two-word stage
The previous chapter discussed (root) small clauses, which were argued to be
evolutionary precursors to more complex (TP) counterparts, with both still in use
to varied degrees in present-day languages. It is of note that all the small clause data
included in Chapter 2involved intransitive clauses, that is, clauses with a subject but
no object. While small clauses in present-day languages can denitely be transitive,
my argument is that the proto-grammars in the paratactic (non-hierarchical) stage
were intransitive.
1
There are many reasons to postulate that proto-syntax started intransitive. First of
all, childrens language acquisition proceeds through a two-word stage, as noted by
many (e.g. Bloom 1970); a two-word stage can accommodate a predicate with only
one argument, and thus cannot be transitive, at least not without positing various
null categories in order to bridge the gap between adult grammars and early child
grammars.
2
Similarly, early stages of sign languages constructed from scratch also
seem to show a two-word, intransitive stage, as discussed below. Next, many fossils of
proto-grammars are intransitive two-word structures, including certain compounds
and unaccusative and passive-like small clauses (see also Chapter 2).
1
The following example of a TP-less incredulity small clause is transitive, containing both a subject
(him) and the object (his wife). Just like the intransitive small clauses from the previous chapter, this
example lacks tense, agreement, and structural nominative case, as well as shows the other properties of
small clause syntax:
(i) Him leave his wife?! (That is not possible!)
On the other hand, the unaccusative data from Serbian, as well as the passive-like (Problem solved)and
verbless (Me rst!)small clauses from English, are necessarily intransitive in the sensethat only one argument
can be structurally realized.
2
Section 2.5.1in Chapter 2offers some discussion of the so-called Continuity Hypothesis, which posits
that all the relevant categories in adult language are also there in child language, but are just null or covert.
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In addition, paratactic combinations of (small) clauses are almost always binary,
merging only two clauses at a time (12). Thus, two-word grammars creating a
(small) clause are paralleled by two-clausegrammars:
(1) Nothing ventured, nothing gained.
(2) Come one, come all.
Combining more than two paratactic phrases/clauses typically leads to a processing
quagmire, as the following example helps illustrate:
(3) No come, no money, no shelter.
This example is an expanded version of attested binary examples from pidgin
languages, such as No mani, no komfrom Hawaiian Pidgin English (Winford
2006). Unlike the relatively clear message behind No money, no come,it is hard to
know how to interpret (3). Is it that if you do not come, then you cannot get paid, or
get any shelter? Or does it mean that if you do not come with the money, then you
will not get any shelter? Or is it a prediction or a threat that you wont come, wont
get the money, and wont get any shelter either? The grammar on its own cannot
decide among these options.
This is not just an example involving the familiar kind of ambiguity, as found in
e.g. He saw the man with the binoculars,where language users typically reach for
one interpretation and do not even consider the other(s). With the one in (3), we are
at a loss right away. It seems that our brains are just not prepared to readily assign
meanings to paratactic ternary structures such as (3). But we can handle binary
structures.
In Minimalism (e.g. Chomsky 1995) and predecessors, the central combinatorial
operation Merge is widely considered to be binary, that is, it is considered that Merge
can combine only two elements at a time (see e.g. Kayne 1984). The same assumption
holds for the operation Adjoin, which is akin to paratactic attachment (see
Chapter 4).
3
As a consequence of binary Merge, it is considered in Minimalism
and predecessors that binary branching is a syntactic universal, characteristic of all
languages. To be more accurate here, because it was empirically determined/dis-
covered that the vast majority of syntactic structures across languages can be
analyzed as involving binary branching, the operation Merge was hypothesized to
only be able to combine two words/phrases at a time.
3
Very roughly speaking, operation Merge creates a headed structure, given that one of the merged
elements determines the category of the newly-created constitutent. For example, in merging a Tense
element and a verb phrase, one creates a Tense Phrase, with Tense acting as the syntactic head. In contrast,
with operation Adjoin, which serves to attach e.g. adverbials, neither of the merged elements is treated as a
syntactic head (for discussion, see e.g. Adger 2003). For example, an adverb such as quickly can attach to a
vP, expanding that vP, but not creating a new headed structure. I return to the distinction between the two
operations in Chapter 4.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
58 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
If so, then the initial proto-syntax, characterized by parataxis, could not have been
transitive in the modern sense of the word, given that transitivity involves three
obligatory constituents (subject, verb, object), and accommodating three such con-
stituents structurally would require hierarchical syntax.
4
At least this is the claim in
Minimalism: on top of the small clause (or VP layer) in transitive structures one must
project another verbal layer, the layer of vP, as discussed later in the chapter. If, as
I argue, proto-syntax did not have hierarchical capabilities, then it could not have had
true transitivity.
But, can there be languages without transitivity? How would one express the basic
notions such as who does what to whomin such languages? At rst glance, such
grammars might seem impossible to imagine. However, as will be shown in this
chapter, there are many constructions in present-day languages that exhibit exactly
such non-transitive properties.
A good initial illustration is provided by the emergence of Nicaraguan Sign Lan-
guage (NSL) by deaf children in the 1970sand1980s, to be discussed further in
Section 3.5(see also Aronoff et al.2008 for Al-Sayyid Bedouin Sign Language, which
exhibits similar properties). According to Kegl, Senghas, and Coppola (1999:21617),
the earliest stages of NSL, with the rst generation of speakers, do not utilize transitive
N V N constructions, such as (4), at least not when both nouns are animate (Senghas
et al.1997). Instead, the speakers resort to a sequence of two intransitive clauses, an
NVN V sequence (56), clearly resembling the paratactic structures in (12):
(4) *WOMAN PUSH MAN.
(5) WOMAN PUSHMAN REACT.
(6) WOMAN PUSHMAN FALL.
Focusing on (6), one can say that the sign for WOMAN is the subject of PUSH, but
the sign for MAN here is not the object of PUSH, but instead the subject of FALL. In
this kind of grammar, there are no structural objects, as these structures are intransi-
tive.
5
Similar considerations hold for Homesign syntax, as reported in e.g. Goldin-
Meadow (2005), to be discussed in Section 3.5. But, one can argue, this may just be a
phenomenon of early stages of sign languages, and nothing like that is possible in
spoken languages.
6
4
This property of language, that its structures are necessarily binary-branching, may partly be a
consequence of the paratactic beginnings of language, and the processing constraints to which such
paratactic grammars seem to be subjected (see the discussion regarding the example in (3)).
5
One must also appreciate the relativity of the notions subject and object, to be discussed further in this
chapter: whether MAN/WOMAN in the above examples is subject-like or object-like depends on the
choice of the verb.
6
A reviewer has wondered why the acquisition of these sign languages is relevant for language
evolution. As pointed out for the same question raised for language acquisition in general (Section 2.5.1),
my approach postulates that the foundational layers of syntax need to be in place before one can build more
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Introduction: The two-word stage 59
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
However, this chapter will go over a variety of present-day structures which blur
the subject/object distinction in this same way. One example of this kind of grammar
is the so-called exocentric VN compounds, which necessarily consist only of two
words (i.e. two free morphemes), a verb and a noun, resembling small clauses (see
Section 3.3.2for more details). If Givóns(1971) well-known slogan todays morph-
ology is yesterdays syntaxhas some truth to it, then it provides additional support
for the claim that the mold these compounds are poured into may be just fossilized
syntax of an earlier era. One more recent example of a compound which preserves a
stage of English syntax is the name for the plant forget-me-not. While English
speakers no longer use this kind of syntax in sentences (e.g. *You forgot me not), it
is preserved in this particular compound.
7
In the underlined compounds in (7) the noun is subject-like, while in the rest of the
compounds it is object-like, as discussed below.
(7) scare-crow, kill-joy, pick-pocket, cry-baby, cut-purse, busy-body,
spoil-sport, turn-coat, rattle-snake, hunch-back, dare-devil,
wag-tail, tattle-tale, saw-bones, cut-throat, Burn-house, Love-joy,
Pinch-penny (miser), sink-hole, turn-table
Even though these compounds contain a verb, and the verb takes one argument (the
noun), which is typically object-like, it would be wrong to analyze such compounds
as transitive. First of all, clearly, there is no second argument in these compounds,
which would count as a subject. Also, the noun is not necessarily object-like, but can
also be subject-like, as is the case with the underlined compounds. While a scarecrow
is somebody who scares crows (crow is object-like), a rattlesnake is a snake that
rattles (thus subject-like), and a cry-baby is a baby (or somebody) who cries (again
subject-like). But the nouns in both of these cases appear in exactly the same position
and the same form in the compound, following the verb, and thus there is no formal
differentiation between object-like and subject-like arguments in this sense. This is
quite comparable to the clauses characterizing early stages of Nicaraguan Sign
Language, as illustrated above in (56). The VN compounds in other languages,
complex layers. If the acquisition of a sign language proceeds in stages, then these stages are expected to be
consistent with the postulated scaffolding.
7
According to a reviewer, Givóns slogan is controversial. However, my approach does not use Givóns
slogan as a reconstruction method, but rather just to give an extra dimension to the claim that (verbal)
compounds may have preserved a very old stage of syntax. In this respect, Anderson (1988) discusses
Givóns slogan and concludes that while it is impossible to identify all of todays morphology with
yesterdays syntax(338), there is every reason to believe that much morphology does in fact represent
the reanalysis of earlier syntactic complexity(340), even though the relation between the two is not simple
and direct (see also Lightfoot 1979). According to Lightfoot (1979:160), the morphology is notoriously
slow to adapt to changing syntaxand may reect syntactic patterns of great antiquity. If true, then this can
be helpful for my proposal, which attempts to reconstruct the earliest stages of human syntax.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
60 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
including Serbian, show exactly the same properties in this respect, as discussed in
detail in Chapter 6.
Furthermore, the intransitive constructions in some modern ergative languages
share this property as well. In these languages, the subject of the intransitive clause is
structurally not distinguishable from the object, both appearing in the so-called
absolutive case, as illustrated in the following example from Tongan (Austronesian
language spoken in Tonga; Tchekhoff 1979:409):
8
(8)oku kai ae iká.
PRES
eat the.
ABS
sh
The sh eats.
The sh is eaten.
As the two distinct translations indicate, the only argument (the sh) can be
interpreted here as either the subject or the object of eating, once again illustrating
an intransitive grammar which does not make a formal distinction between subjects
and objects. As pointed out in Tchekhoff (1973), as well as by other researchers (e.g.
Authier and Haude 2012; Blake 1976; Mithun 1994:247; Shibatani 1998:120), the
subject/object distinction does not play a role in such ergative/absolutive patterns,
especially those which are both syntactically and morphologically ergative, as will be
explained below. In addition to these, several other absolutive-like constructions
found in present-day languages, in fact languages classied as nominative-accusative,
will be considered in this chapter, including unaccusatives, nominals, and middles.
The main proposal in this chapter is that the initial paratactic (non-hierarchical)
grammars were intransitive grammars, whose clauses consisted of just two (proto-)
words. In this proposal, transitivity is seen as an innovation brought about by
superimposing an additional layer of structure (perhaps the vP layer of Minimalism)
upon the foundational (absolutive) layer, with some intermediate middleconstruc-
tions paving the way toward transitivity. Not only can this approach shed light on the
ergative-absolutive and nominative-accusative dichotomy found across todays lan-
guages, but it can also explain the availability of the foundational absolutive-like
patterns in various guises in primarily nominative-accusative languages. The recur-
ring theme of this monograph is that each stage preserves, and builds upon, the
8
While
ABS
does not appear in the gloss in the original, I have added it here because this would be
typically considered as absolutive case. Tchekhoff calls it the rst modier,as opposed to the second
modier,which corresponds to an agent (ergative case).
Interestingly, as reported by Haiyong Liu (p.c. 2013), Chinese shows similar vagueness of expression,
especially when the perfective particle le is used (see also Section 3.3.3for comparable data from Riau
Indonesian).
(i) Ji chi le.
chicken eat PERF
The chicken(s) have/has nished eating.
The chicken was eaten.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Introduction: The two-word stage 61
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
achievements of the previous stage(s). In this case, the proposal is that transitive
structures (vP shells), as well as middles, are built upon the foundation of intransitive
(absolutive-like) VPs (or small clauses), shedding light on a host of quirky phenom-
ena across languages.
As was the case with the small clause proposal in Chapter 2, this proposal also
involves an internal reconstruction based on the theoretical postulates within Min-
imalism. Just as one can peel the TP layer off a modern sentence (Chapter 2), one can
also peel off the vP layer, resulting in intransitive small clauses. Recall that the
reconstruction method used in this book is based on the hierarchy of functional
projections which allows a SC/VP to be composed without a TP or vP, but does not
allow either a vP or a TP to be composed without a VP/SC. This renders the proposed
progression of stages theoretically plausible.
In the process of evolving transitivity, i.e. grammaticalizing the syntactic positions
of more than one argument, I propose that there are/were various types of inter-
mediate steps, as discussed in Section 3.4. The evidence for these intermediate stages
includes various middleconstructions, which straddle the boundary between
transitivity and intransitivity, passives and actives, as well as neutralize the distinc-
tion between subjects and objects. I exemplify this with se middle constructions to be
introduced below, where se is analyzed as a meaningless proto-transitive marker.
As with the analysis of small clauses in Chapter 2, the argument for the proposed
progression through stages (absolutive, to middle, to transitive) has three prongs to it:
(i) evidence of tinkeringwith the language design, so that fossils of one stage
provide foundation for the next, possibly through intermediate steps; (ii) identifying
living fossilsof each stage in modern languages; (iii) existing or potential corrob-
orating evidence. Moreover, the goal is to show that each identied stage accrues
concrete and tangible advantages over the previous stage(s), advantages that are
signicant enough to be targeted by natural/sexual selection.
In this respect, Section 3.2shows how intransitive absolutive-like structures get built
into the transitive (vP) structures, thus providing evidence of evolutionary tinkering
with the language design. Section 3.3introduces further living fossils of the postulated
absolutive-like stage in the evolution of syntax. Section 3.4considers middle construc-
tions and serial verb constructions, both of which straddle the boundary between
intransitivity and transitivity. There is also some corroborating evidence for an
intransitive stage, as well as potential testing grounds, as discussed in Section 3.5.
3.2Intransitive absolutives
This chapter postulates a stage in the evolution of syntax in which only intransitive
absolutive-like patterns were available, i.e. patterns in which a verb takes only one
argument, and in which the distinction between subjects and objects is neutralized, in
fact, irrelevant. This is the sense in which I am using the term absolutive-likein this
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
62 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
context, just to indicate that an intransitive structure does not distinguish subjects
from objects grammatically. This is not to imply in any way that there was a special
marking of an ergative argument, to contrast with the absolutive one. My proposal is
that this intransitive proto stage could only have one argument per clause. From
there, one can see how ergative and nominative languages would have diverged in the
way they express additional arguments in sentences. Ergative languages would have
kept the absolutive pattern for intransitive sentences, but added ergative arguments
to this absolutive structure in order to express transitive patterns. On the other hand,
nominative-accusative languages would have developed a special, accusative case
only for the lower argument, establishing a category of the object. It could be that
certain middle constructions in the latter languages paved the way toward developing
the accusative case, as discussed in Section 3.4.2.
It should be pointed out that this is a very different view from the one that would
advocate missing or null arguments. In this analysis, one is dealing with a two-slot
grammar with only one argument slot, and there is nothing missing or null syntac-
tically speaking.
9
This is a perfectly coherent grammar, even if simpler than e.g.
transitive grammars. Developing such a grammar would have constituted an enor-
mous advantage over no grammar at all, but this kind of grammar has less expressive
power than a fully transitive grammar, exactly the kind of scenario that would allow
evolutionary forces such as natural selection to operate (see Chapters 2,4, and 7).
Pressure to accommodate additional arguments would have been a powerful driving
force behind the evolution of more complex (transitive) patterns.
This proposal is entirely consistent with the analysis of transitivity in e.g. Minim-
alism, where transitivity is considered to involve an additional layer of verb structure,
a vP shell (e.g. Chomsky 1995). In this analysis, the internal (lower argument) is
generated in the VP (or SC), and the external argument (e.g. agent) in the vP (910),
as discussed in Section 1.7.
(9) Maria will roll the ball.
(10)a.[
SC/VP
roll the ball]
b. [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll the ball]]
c. [
TP
: Maria will [
vP
Maria [
SC/VP
roll the ball]]]
In deriving the sentence in (9), one starts with the basic, small clause layer in (10a).
Then, the agent (Maria) is merged in the higher vP layer (10b), which is responsible
9
Bickerton (1990,1998) discusses pidgin languages, as well as child language, in the light of language
evolution, and concludes that these systems are not real languages. One of the reasons why these systems
are not treated as reallanguage in Bickertons work is that they do not realize all the arguments that seem
to be obligatory in adult speech (see the discussion in Section 1.6). However, given that constructions with
missingarguments are also prevalent in adult languages, one cannot really conclude that this is not real
language. Instead, my argument is that languages are composites encompassing structures of various
degrees of syntactic layering, reecting different stages in the evolution of human language.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Intransitive absolutives 63
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
not only for accommodating this additional argument, but also for assigning
(abstract) accusative case to the object (the ball). Finally, the TP layer is projected
on top of the vP layer, and Maria,the highest argument, moves to become the
subject of the TP (10c).
Thus, just as is the case with the small clause vs. TP distinction discussed in
Chapter 2, here as well we have a layer of structure (vP) superimposed upon the
foundational, absolutive (small clause) layer. In both cases, the small clause with one
argument is the foundation. In more elaborate grammars, full transitive sentences
will have all three layers, arranged in a hierarchy of projections (see e.g. Abney 1987):
(11) TP > vP > SC/VP.
Assuming this kind of structure building in Minimalism, my proposal in fact does an
internal reconstruction to arrive at the intransitive small clause proto-syntax, as
proposed in Chapters 1and 2, and repeated below:
Internal reconstruction of clause structure (based on Minimalism)
A structure X is considered to be (evolutionary) primary relative to a structure Y if
X can be composed independently of Y, but Y can only be built upon the foundation of X.
This hierarchy of functional projections is an inuential theoretical construct, with
good empirical foundation, and it is signicant that it can be used to reconstruct
proto-syntax.
While Chapter 2provided evidence for living fossil structures without a TP, my
focus in this chapter is on the fossil structures without vPs. In fact, intransitives,
especially unaccusatives (see Section 3.3.1), can be accommodated without the vP
layer (1213), as discussed in Section 1.7. In other words, the vP layer is optional.
10
(12) The ball will roll.
(13)a.[
SC/VP
roll the ball]
b. [
TP
: The ball will [
SC/VP
roll the ball]]
Given that there is no agent, and no accusative case either, the vP shell need not
project in (13a). In English, the object-like argument (the ball) has to move to the TP
projection and become a structural subject (13b).
11
10
Recognizing that vP is an optional layer means that the hierarchy TP > vP > SC/VP has to be seen in
the following way. The SC/VP serves as necessary foundation for all clausal constructions. Transitivity (vP)
must have a SC/VP as its foundation. TP, on the other hand, must have either the SC/VP or the vP as its
foundation. If both vP and TP are present, then the TP will dominate vP. Because vP is considered to be
just a shell, another layer of the verb phrase, then a unied generalization for TP is that it has to be built
upon the foundation of a verbal layer.
11
One exception in English are fossil structures such as the underlined small clause in (i), in which the
subject does not move, and which closely parallels the structure of the unaccusative small clauses in
Serbian, discussed below in the text (see also Chapter 2).
(i) Come winter, he will go to Florida.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
64 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The verbs like roll, which participate in both transitive and intransitive patterns,
clearly show uidity in the expression of subjecthood (see also Sections 1.7and 3.4).
Observe that (9) and (12) start with exactly the same foundation, the small clauses in
(10a) and (13a), respectively. Whether the ball will be the object or the subject of the
sentence depends on whether or not there is an additional argument. What counts as
a subject is thus relative to the number of arguments expressed.
12
Recall from Chapter 2that in the absence of the TP layer in unaccusative small
clauses in Serbian of the kind in (14), only one layer of structure is available, the
[SC/VP] layer:
(14)[
SC/VP
Pala vlada.]
fell government
In conjunction with the examples above, we see a gradual progression toward more
syntactic complexity, from one single layer of structure in (14), to two layers of
structure in English tensed unaccusatives (13), to three layers of structure with
English tensed transitive clauses (10c), abstracting away from some other functional
projections that may be there. Crucially, this gradual increase in complexity is arrived
at not through impressionistic means, but by a precise method of internal recon-
struction based on theoretical considerations.
Grammaticalizing transitivity in e.g. nominative-accusative languages, with a
structural accusative case and the vP/VP shell, would not have precluded some
other structures (e.g. unaccusatives, se clauses, nominals, compounds) from retaining
the absolutive-like avor. If these simpler grammars are easier to process, then their
retention at least in some constructions is to be expected.
This section has shown that intransitive (absolutive-like) structures get built into
the transitive vP shells, providing the necessary foundation for transitivity, thus
offering evidence of evolutionary tinkering with the language design. The following
section introduces further types of living fossils of the postulated absolutive-like stage
in the evolution of syntax.
3.3More on living fossils: What is it that unaccusatives, exocentrics,
and absolutives have in common?
In this section I consider in more detail the following living fossilsof the postulated
absolutive-like stage in the evolution of human language: unaccusatives (Section 3.3.1),
exocentric VN compounds (Section 3.3.2), absolutives in ergative-absolutive languages
12
Of note is also that Borers(1994) fully congurational approach to argument linking assumes that
the arguments within the VP are hierarchically unordered, and that there is no lexical distinction between
subjects and objects inside the VP. Such distinctions can only be made with the help of the functional
projections, such as vP. This is consistent with the proposal in this monograph that the foundational small
clause layer of structure is non-hierarchical and absolutive-like.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
More on living fossils 65
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(Section 3.3.3), as well as (other) absolutive-like constructions found in nominative-
accusative languages, including nominals and dative subject clauses (Section 3.3.4).
3.3.1Unaccusatives
Unaccusative small clauses were introduced in Chapter 2, where the focus was to
establish that such clauses are structures without a TP layer, showing neither Move
nor subordination. What is relevant about them in this chapter is that they are
intransitive structures which can be generated without projecting the vP layer either.
This kind of grammar is a good approximation of the hypothetical two-word stage, as
discussed in Section 3.1, as well as in Chapter 2. Moreover, this kind of grammar is
reminiscent of the grammar found in exocentric VN compounds, as discussed
further in Section 3.3.2, as well as in Chapter 6.
As pointed out in Section 3.2, unaccusatives can be accommodated without
projecting the vP layer:
(15)[
TP
: The ball will [
SC/VP
roll/fall the ball]]
Recall that vP is projected primarily in order to accommodate an additional argu-
ment, typically the agent, as well as the accusative case, but unaccusative structures
have only one argument and no accusative case (hence their name). Unaccusatives
can be roughly characterized as intransitive structures whose sole argument is
typically a theme, showing some object-like properties, including the postverbal
position in some cases (see e.g. Perlmutter 1978; Burzio 1981; Levin and Rappaport
Hovav 1995, for crosslinguistic manifestations and characterizations).
In Serbian, for example, there is a clear preference for unaccusative subjectsto
follow the verb, the position typically associated with objects. If these unaccusatives
are at the same time TP-less small clauses (e.g. 16), this preference becomes more
rigid, with strong preference for the otherwise non-canonical VS order (see Progovac
2008a,b for details):
(16) a. Pala vlada.
fall.
PART
government
The government has (just) collapsed.
b. Prošo voz.
gone.
PART
train
The opportunity has passed.
This provides support for the unaccusative analysis under which the subjectsof the
unaccusative verbs (e.g. arrive, fall, come, appear) Merge as objectsof the small
clause (e.g. Burzio 1981).
Recall that unaccusative small clauses in Serbian are analyzed as involving one
single layer of structure, (SC/VP) layer, and that their subjects thus have no syntactic
position into which to move (Chapter 2; see also Section 3.3):
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
66 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(17)[
SC/VP
Pala vlada]
Without a vP or TP layer, these are just rigid and at two-word structures, reasonably
good approximations of the postulated two-word stage.
13
Given this proposal, the unaccusativity phenomenon can be seen as an option to
retain (elements of) absolutive-type grammars in constructions which can be sup-
ported by such grammars, e.g. intransitive constructions with a single (internal)
argument (Casielles and Progovac 2010,2012).
14
To put it another way, if proto-
syntax involves less grammatical burden, and is less costly to process, then one can
expect to nd it in constructions in which more complex grammars do not confer
much advantage. Transitive constructions, as well as intransitive constructions
involving agents in some languages, may need extra syntactic space, e.g. a vP shell,
and thus cannot be expressed as readily with this type of grammar.
Intransitive absolutive constructions in ergative languages, as discussed in
Section 3.3.3, as well as various absolutive-like constructions elsewhere, are again struc-
tures which blur the distinction between subjecthood and objecthood in the sense that
their only argument has characteristics of both.
15
The only difference seems to be that
unaccusatives tend not to encompass agents, and this may be due to the special status
agents have acquired in nominative-accusative languages, possibly by being associated
with their own functional projection, such as vP in Minimalism. In other words, even if
there is an association of the role of agent with the vP in some modern languages today
13
A reviewer wonders why this stage could not have had a noun phrase in lieu of the noun, combining
with the verb, resulting in a multiple-word stage. Perhaps this kind of complexity, involving modication,
arose only later, as it would have created an asymmetrical structure. Also, the typical modiers of nouns,
adjectives, would have evolved in a later stage, given Heine and Kutevas(2007) reconstruction, and
considering that not all languages distinguish the category of adjectives.
14
As pointed out in Section 1.6, Casielles and Progovac (2010,2012) explore the connection between
unaccusatives and thetic statements. According to e.g. Marty (1918), categorical judgments (also referred to
as double judgments) involve two successive acts (choosing an entity and making a statement about it) and
are expressed by the traditional subject-predicate sentences (Vlada je pala (the) government has col-
lapsed). In contrast, thetic statements or simple judgments merely assert a state of affairs where a new
situation is presented as a whole. In these statements the entity involved in the event forms a unit with it
(Pao sneg Fell snow). There is a lot of overlap between thetic and unaccusative grammars. It would stand
to reason that grammars which generate thetic statements are evolutionarily more primary, as well as
simpler. In this respect, Gil (2012) has proposed that predication is a composite emergent entity, rather
than a primitive.
15
Comrie (1978) has made an argument that subjecthood across languages is not a rigid notion, but a
notion on a continuum. This can be accommodated within the evolutionary scenario explored here,
according to which this distinction was not there at all in the rst stages of proto-syntax.
In Minimalism, subjecthood is characterized structurally/mechanically, based on the position of the
phrase, as well as on its agreement properties. Thus, very roughly speaking, if a phrase (in English) occupies
a certain syntactic position (e.g. a specier position of a TP), and/or if it agrees with the Tense element,
then it is considered to be the subject, descriptively speaking. But in fact whether or not we call this phrase a
subject matters very little in this syntactic theory. Thus, the uidity of the concept of subjecthood does not
seem to pose a problem for this theory. Where the problems lie is in the attempt to rigidly associate specic
thematic roles with specic syntactic positions, as addressed from this perspective in Progovac (2014b).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
More on living fossils 67
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(but see Progovac 2014b), this association was certainly not there in the two-word
grammar stage. What the two phenomena have in common, absolutives and unaccusa-
tives, is the unavailability of the accusative case, that is, the structural case which is
reserved only for objects.
16
3.3.2Exocentric compounds
Another phenomenon that is difcult to explain given the postulates of modern
morpho-syntax are exocentric VN compounds of the kind illustrated in (1819)
below for English and Serbian. However, their shape makes sense if they are seen
as fossils closely approximating a two-word absolutive-like (intransitive) stage in the
evolution of human language (see Progovac and Locke 2009; Progovac 2009a, 2012).
(18) scare-crow, kill-joy, pick-pocket, cry-baby, spoil-sport, turn-coat,
rattle-snake, hunch-back, dare-devil, wag-tail, tattle-tale,
drynk-pany (drink-penny; miser (a surname)), pinch-penny
(miser), sink-hole, turn-table, busy-body
(19) ispi-čutura (drink.up-askdrunkard), guli-koža (peel-skinwho
rips you off), cepi-dlaka (split-hairwho splits hairs), muti-voda
(muddy-watertrouble-maker), jebi-vetar (screw-wind
charlatan), vrti-guz (spin-buttdget), tuži-baba (whine-
old.woman; tattletale), pali-drvce (ignite-stick, matches)
The grammar behind these compounds is quite simple: it is a two-place mold that
can t exactly one verb and one noun, whether the verb is semantically monovalent
or bivalent. Moreover the thematic role of the noun is underspecied. While the
noun in these compounds is often interpreted as an internal argument, correspond-
ing to an object in a sentence, it can also be external, corresponding to a subject in a
sentence, as is the case with the underlined compounds in both languages. As pointed
out in Section 3.1, the noun in crybaby is subject-like, while the noun in scarecrow is
object-like.
Once again, the grammar behind these compounds provides no morpho-syntactic
differentiation between subjecthood and objecthood, leaving room for vagueness.
For example, a rattlesnake is conventionally interpreted as a snake that rattles, but
one can imagine this word also used for somebody who routinely rattles snakes, on
16
It follows from this proposal that proto-clauses did not have structural case, whether accusative or
nominative, as discussed in Chapter 2. In Minimalism, structural nominative case is associated with the
functional projection of TP, and structural (accusative) case with the projection of vP. While nominative
and accusative noun phrases can have different morphological manifestations (e.g. he/who vs. him/whom
in English), the syntactic theory considers that even without such overt manifestations, there are abstract
case relationships between Tense (TP) and nominative, and between the light verb (vP) and the object in
the accusative-type languages.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
68 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
analogy with e.g. pick-pocket.
17
Notice that a more complex compound, snake-rattler,
which has a transitivity layer, is no longer vague in this way, and can only be
interpreted as somebody who rattles snakes.
Perhaps a better way to make this point would be to consider a contrast between a
turn-coat and a turn-table. Conventionally, a turncoat is somebody who turns his
coat/skin inside out (traitor), with the coat being object-like. On the other hand, a
turntable is a table that turns, where the table is subject-like. But if a turntable can be
a table that turns, then, in principle, grammatically speaking, a turncoat could be a
coat that turns, perhaps a coat that is reversible. Likewise, if a turncoat can be
somebody who turns his coat, then, in principle, a turntable could be someone
who (routinely) turns tables upside down, perhaps a rowdy regular in a bar. Again,
this exibility is not there with syntactically more elaborated compounds, such as
table-turner, which cannot mean, not even in principle, a table that turns.
Exocentric VN compounds can thus be seen as absolutive-like constructions
which blur the distinction between subjecthood and objecthood, and which also
lack accusative case, the properties these compounds share with unaccusatives and
(other) absolutives.
It is of interest that exocentric VN compounds across languages seem to specialize
for derogatory reference when referring to humans, possibly implicating their ori-
ginal use in ritual insult. Chapter 6explores the proposal that the ability to create
such compounds in the distant evolutionary past may have been sexually selected,
contributing to the consolidation of proto-syntax, as well as to vocabulary building.
As pointed out by a reviewer, there are many other compound types in English,
combining other categories, such as an adjective and a noun (blackbird), a noun and
a noun (snowman), a noun and an adjective (sky-blue). There are several reasons why
they are not considered in this monograph, although future research might reveal
relevance of some of these for evolutionary considerations, perhaps compounds of
the egghead type. First of all, even though N-N compounds in English may seem
simple and straightforward at rst sight, they are typically not only headed (the
second element is the syntactic and semantic head of the whole compound), but
they are also recursive, producing: styrofoam snowman,orpolicy committee decision
17
Some compounds can even be simultaneously doubly interpreted in this respect: Serbian pali-drvce
(ignite-stick, matches) is at the same time a stick that ignites and a stick that gets ignited. In this case, the
vagueness is quite expressive and appropriate. Precision is not always desirable, and this can provide partial
explanation for the persistence of vague expressions. One example where vagueness is desirable involves
suppressing the agent of the action in passives, as in (i). In English, passive constructions serve this purpose
particularly well, while in other languages, such as Serbian, middles are used for this purpose as well
(Section 3.4).
(i) The policeman was wounded.
The point here is that one does not always want or care to express precisely who did what to whom, but just
to express that something happened.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
More on living fossils 69
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
process. While it may seem that such combinations of nouns directly reect our
cognitive abilities for headed Merge and recursion, it is worth pointing out that not
all languages in fact use such compounds, and especially not recursively (see
Section 1.6; Chapter 6; also Snyder 2014).
In contrast, as will be discussed in Chapter 6, VN compounds are typically neither
headed (hence the name exocentric) nor recursive. Moreover, they are relevant for
the purposes of this book because they are combinations of a verb and a noun, typical
building blocks of clauses/sentences, and the rst categories to emerge and be
differentiated (e.g. Heine and Kuteva 2007). Finally, these VN compounds reveal
evidence of ritual insult, rendering them of particular interest for evolutionary
considerations for that reason as well. Chapter 6offers additional reasons for their
evolutionary signicance.
3.3.3Absolutives
The vagueness attested in exocentric VN compounds is also characteristic of intransi-
tive absolutives in some ergative-absolutive languages. Consider another example
from Tongan featuring an intransitive sentence with the absolutive case (Tchekhoff
1973:283):
18
(20) Oku ui a Mele
PRES
call
ABS
Mary
Mary calls.
Mary is called.
In this intransitive sentence, Mary can be interpreted either as the agent of the action, or
the patient/theme. But, as pointed out in Tchekhoff (1973), this sentence means neither
Mary callsnor Mary is calledin Tongan, these being just two different translations
of one single underdetermined/underspecied structure in Tongan. In other words,
these translations reect our nominative/accusative bias. Instead, all this sentence
means is that there is calling, and that Mary is implied in the process (Tchekhoff 1973:
284). This is also the essence of Gils analysis of vague sentences in Riau (Footnote 18), as
well as my proposal for middles in Serbian, and the idea of a proto-role (Section 3.4.2).
18
See also Gil (2005) for an extensive discussion of comparable vague clauses in Riau Indonesian:
(i) Ayam makan
chicken eat
The chicken is eating.
Somebody is eating the chicken.
Etc.
While Gil does not analyze Riau as an ergative/absolutive language, this may be simply because it does not
have a special ergative case marking, which would then contrast with an absolutive case. But, for all relevant
purposes, the structure in (i) above can be considered absolutive-like, as it exhibits the same properties
found in intransitive constructions in ergative-absolutive languages such as Tongan.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
70 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In ergative-absolutive patterns, the subject of an intransitive predicate is morpho-
syntactically equivalent to the object, both characterized as absolutive arguments (e.g.
Comrie 1978; Dixon 1994). Only agents of transitive verbs are marked distinctly, with
ergative case.
19
It is only after the addition of the external ergative argument (e.g.
John below) that the role of Mary disambiguates and is necessarily patient/theme
(Tchekhoff 1973:283). In other words, the addition of the external argument forces
the inner absolutive layer to distinguish itself from the external argument, resulting
in more precision.
20
(21) Oku ui e Sione a Mele
PRES
call
ERG
John
ABS
Mary
John calls Mary.
The examples in (2021) illustrate quite clearly how the ergative argument (John)is
inserted into the basic absolutive layer. They also illustrate something that has been
noted repeatedly in the typological literature, that the ergative-absolutive structures
resemble passive structures in nominative-accusative languages, in which the agent is
introduced as an oblique argument, e.g. as a by-phrase in English passives, as
discussed further below (see e.g. Hale 1970). These similarities extend to the nominal
domain as well, as discussed in the following section.
Dyirbal (Australian language spoken in northeast Queensland) is another ergative
language which, like Tongan (see also Dukes 1998), exhibits syntactic ergativity, in
the sense that the absolutive role even in transitive constructions continues to behave
in a subject-like fashion, as illustrated with a coordinated structure below (Dixon
1994:155):
(22) nguma yabu-nggu buran banagan
y
u
father.
ABS
mother-
ERG
saw return
Mother saw father and (father) returned.
This clearly contrasts with English (23) below, in which a comparable coordinated
structure yields the opposite result for the missing argument:
(23) Mother saw father and (mother) returned home.
In fact, if we were to coordinate a passive sentence and an active sentence in English,
we would get the pattern comparable to the one in (22) from Dyirbal:
(24) Father was seen by mother, and (father) returned home.
19
To put it slightly differently, as is often done in the literature on ergativity, the ergative alignment
involves formal singling out of the agent of transitive verbs in contrast to the patient of transitive verbs and
the single argument of intransitive verbs (e.g. Authier and Haude 2012; see also Comrie 1978; Dixon 1994).
20
Notice that the addition of -er in VN compounds has a comparable effect, as pointed out above.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
More on living fossils 71
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
This is the sense in which the ergative phrase can be likened to the passive by-phrase.
The by-phrase here, just like the ergative phrase in (22), is not the true, structural
subject, but only the logicalsubject, as will also be discussed with respect to the
noun phrases in Section 3.3.4.1. This is also the reason behind the proposals in Nash
(1996) and Alexiadou (2001) that ergative phrases may be attached by adjunction, in a
way similar to the attachment of the passive by-phrase in English.
While Tongan and Dyirbal are analyzed as syntactically ergative languages, in the
sense that they exhibit both morphological and syntactic ergativity, there are many
ergative languages spoken today which exhibit only morphological ergativity, pat-
terning with English with respect to e.g. coordination (see Aldridge 2008 for an
overview and discussion; thanks also to Robert Henderson, p.c. 2013, for a discussion
on this). Likewise, ergative-absolutive languages typically show the so-called split-
ergativity, in the sense that they are ergative with some nouns/pronouns, but accusa-
tive with other nouns/prounouns, as discussed in Section 7.3.3. Tongan has also
developed certain morphological constructions that can be analyzed as accusative
patterns (see e.g. Tchekhoff 1973). It may well be that every language has some ergative
and some accusative patterns, and it is only a matter of which patterns prevail.
Assuming that there was an intransitive absolutive-like (proto-syntactic) stage in
the evolution of human language, one can envision the subsequent development of
the two basic language types, primarily nominative-accusative and primarily erga-
tive-absolutive. Lehman (1985:245) points to the gradient nature of the distinction
between the ergative and accusative types: a language is never wholly and exclusively
either ergative or active or accusative, in all its grammatical patterns.As pointed out
in this section and in the following sections, there are many absolutive-like construc-
tions in nominative-accusative languages. Likewise, so-called ergative languages
often develop nominative-accusative patterns in some domains, e.g. in the domain
of personal pronouns (which are higher on the animacy hierarchy), resulting in so-
called split ergativity (e.g. Trask 1979 and references there; see Chapter 7for more
discussion). This overlap is what one would expect under the evolutionary approach
explored here.
Bringing unaccusativity and ergativity under the same umbrella, Bok-Bennema
(1991:169) points out that ergativity and unaccusativity are both characterized by the
inability of transitive verbs to assign structural case to their deep objects. To put it
another way, neither ergative nor unaccusative structures can have true (syntactic)
objects, that is, objects distinguished from subjects by means of a specic structural
case (see Footnote 16). According to e.g. Alexiadou (2001:18; also Hale 1970; Nash
1995), ergative/absolutive patterns are reexes of a passive/unaccusative system.
Therefore, what all these phenomena have in common (absolutives, exocentric VN
compounds, unaccusatives, and passives) is that the verb is unable to assign struc-
tural case to its deep object. Given that the object does not receive a distinct
(accusative) marking, the distinction between subjecthood and objecthood is blurred.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
72 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
These phenomena begin to make sense if they are seen as survivors from a two-
word proto-syntax stage, which could only accommodate one argument per verb,
and which did not have the means to distinguish between subjects and objects. As
pointed out above, it is perfectly plausible to expect that the absolutive-like patterns
will be preserved in some constructions, especially those in which subject/object
differentiation is not important. It is also conceivable under this approach that the
foundational absolutive-like patterns will be found in some guise or another in
nominative-accusative languages as well, as explored further in the following section.
Languages may vary considerably with respect to the degree to which they rely on the
foundational absolutive-like patterns, but my argument is that every language has at
least some constructions which are absolutive-like in nature, providing continuity
and common ground between the two language types.
3.3.4More absolutive-like patterns in nominative/accusative languages
As noted in e.g. Authier and Haude (2012:2)some notoriously accusativelan-
guages such as Latin, French, and in fact many Indo-European languages may have
some hints of ergativity(see also Bauman 1979:430; Lehman 1985). Such hints of
ergativity have already been introduced in this chapter for English and Serbian
exocentric compounds, as well as for unaccusatives. This section considers additional
constructions that can be seen in a similar light, including nominals (Section 3.3.4.1),
dative subjects (Section 3.3.4.2), and clausal complements (Section 3.3.4.3).
3.3.4.1Nominals This section is there to show that even in English one nds, in
productive use, these absolutive-like structures which do not distinguish subjects
from objects, resulting in vagueness. According to e.g. Alexiadou (2001), nominals
across various languages are intransitive, as well as absolutive-like (passive-like). In
other words, all nominals, whether passive or not, have an intransitive base (see also
Picallo 1991; Bottari 1992; Alexiadou and Stavrou 1998). In passive nominals the agent
appears as an adjunct, as in (25) from Alexiadou (2001:78).
21
(25) the destruction of the city by the barbarians
In this analysis, by-phrases in derived nominals can only be interpreted as affectors
(agents, instruments, creators), rendering examples such as (26) not fully grammatical.
22
21
Comrie (1978) suggests that nominalizations constitute a possible source for ergativity. Or perhaps it
is the other way around.
22
One reviewer does not nd (26) completely ungrammatical. A native speaker I consulted likewise
nds this example marginal/awkward, but not fully ungrammatical. On the other hand, (25) is fully
grammatical, indicating that there exists some contrast here, although perhaps subtler than perceived in
Alexiadou (2001). Interestingly, a similar contrast is offered in Pesetsky and Block (1990:751) in order to
challenge Pinker and Bloom (1990), as discussed in Section 7.4:
(i) the citys destruction by the enemy
(ii) ?*the citys sight by the enemy
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
More on living fossils 73
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
According to the authors, unlike with the verbal domain, there is no structural external
argument in nominalizations, generated in a vP (or an nP, the nominal equivalent of a
vP), and the presence of the by-phrase seems to be lexically licensed. In that sense, the
external argument in the by-phrase resembles ergative case, which is also often analyzed
as lexical/prepositional case, rather than structural case (see above).
23
(26) ??the receipt of the package by John
This is consistent with the proposal in this chapter that the intransitive, absolutive-
like/passive-like patterns provided a foundation for evolving transitive structures,
with ergativity and accusativity being different solutions to the same problem of
accommodating an additional, external argument.
3.3.4.2Dative subjects Consider next dative subjectsin Serbian, which co-occur
with nominative objectsin what certainly looks like an ergative/absolutive pattern:
(27) Meni se pije kafa.
me.
DAT SE
drinks coffee.
NOM
I feel like drinking coffee.
Nominative on the objectis like absolutive, being also the case of intransitive
subjects, while dative adds an external argument, akin to an ergative (see e.g.
Alexiadou 2001; Nash 1996, for an adjunction analysis of the ergative argument). As
pointed out in e.g. Trask (1979:398), the ergative case is often identical to the genitive,
dative, or locative. According to Nash (1996:171), ergative subjects, like dative subjects,
cannot co-occur with structural accusative, but instead appear with absolutive/nom-
inative objects.This is yet another construction in which the verb fails to assign
structural (accusative case) to what would be its object.
It is also of signicance here that dative subjects in Serbian typically co-occur with
the (middle) pronoun se. As per the proposal in Section 3.4.2,se is associated with the
ancient absolutive-like pattern.
3.3.4.3Clausal complements The clausal complements of the so-called raising
predicates, such as seem, appear, likely, as well as of predicates such as obvious,
are also absolutive-like/unaccusative-like in nature. While they are generated as
23
For additional references claiming that ergative is an inherent case, see e.g. Woolford (1997,2006);
Legate (2008); Massam (2000,2001). There are alternative analyses of ergative arguments. For example,
Otsuka (2011) treats ergative as structural, rather than inherent case, based on the analysis proposed by
Levin and Massam (1985), and further developed by Bobaljik (1993) and Laka (1993). According to that
analysis, both ergative and absolutive are structural cases, and the difference between accusative and
ergative languages is taken to be the choice of primary case between the two core structural cases, one
assigned by T and the other assigned by v. These references also suggest that the absolutive case is licensed
by v, which would not work with my analysis, according to which vP is not projected in intransitive
absolutive constructions.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
74 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
complements of the verb, they do not receive accusative case, and there is no external
argument either, which is reminiscent of the unaccusative grammars.
(28) It seems/appears/is likely that John is in jail.
(29) It is obvious/surprising that John is in jail.
For purely grammatical purposes, the subject position of these sentences hosts an
expletive (meaningless) pronoun it, but this pronoun is certainly not an argument of
the verb. In fact, what looks like an external argument can optionally be added, as in:
(30) It seems to me that John is in jail.
(31) It is obvious to me that John is in jail.
Intriguingly, when it comes to comparable predicates in Serbian, their external
argument, if expressed, would appear as a dative subject:
(32)Čini mi se da je Jovan u zatvoru.
seems me.
DAT SE
that is John in jail
Both Serbian mi and English to me can be seen as a type of ergative case, added to the
otherwise absolutive foundation. This just shows that various quirky and exotic-looking
phenomena across languages can be understood in this evolutionary framework.
3.4Precursors to transitivity
3.4.1Serial verb constructions
As a reviewer rightly points out, also of relevance to this discussion are the so-called
serial verb constructions, widespread in Creole languages, in the languages of West
Africa, Southeast Asia, Amazonia, Oceania, and New Guinea. Serial verb construc-
tions can be characterized as sequences of verbs which act together as a single
predicate, without any overt marker of coordination, subordination, or syntactic
dependency of any other sort,describing what is conceptualized to be a single event
(e.g. Aikhenvald 2005:1). What one observes in these examples again is that there is
one argument per verb, and the relationship of that argument to the verb seems
absolutive-like. According to Givón (1979:220), serial verb constructions involve a
concatenation of small propositions in which, roughly, a one-to-one correlation is
maintained between verbs and nominal arguments.
Aikhenvald further states that these constructions are monoclausal, and that their
intonational properties are the same as those of a monoverbal clause, sharing just one
tense, aspect, and polarity value. Importantly, she also mentions that serial verbs do
not necessarily have to be next to each other, as they are in (34), but can also be
separated by other constituents, as in (33).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Precursors to transitivity 75
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Anyi-Sanvi (Kwa family, Niger-Congo: Van Leynseele 1975:1912)
(33) cùá c`i ákO´
!
dog catch.
HAB
chicken eat
The dog eats (lit. catch-eat) a chicken
Igbo (Igboid, Benue-Congo, Niger-Congo; Lord 1975:27)
(34) ó tì-wà-rà ètèrè á
he hit-split.open-
TENSE
plate the
He shattered the plate.
It is of note here that (33) in essence has an N VN V structure, comparable to the
structures attested in Nicaraguan Sign Language (e.g. WOMAN PUSH MAN
FALL) (see e.g. Section 1.6). Intriguingly, Senghas et al.(1997:558) claim that the
NVN V structures of the rst generation of NSL signers tend to become N VV
N (WOMAN PUSH FALL MAN), or N N VV (WOMAN MAN PUSH FALL)
combinations, with the second generation. In other words, the second generation is
grouping the two verbs so that they are adjacent to each other, as is typically the case
with serial verb constructions. As Senghas et al.(560) conclude in the article, the next
stage may be a stage where transitivity emerges, with only one verb remaining to
support both nouns. This is essentially the path of grammaticalization envisioned in
e.g. Givón (1979:220).
While I would like to leave a more detailed investigation of serial verb construc-
tions from this perspective for future research, it is worth pointing out that devel-
oping an intricate system of such constructions may have been yet another route
toward transitivity, by embracing the dual-verb structures. If so, it is signicant that
the intransitive foundation (one absolutive-like argument per verb) provides the
common ground for such a wide range of strategies for expressing transitivity.
24
In
fact, this astonishing variety of strategies for expressing transitivity across languages
and constructions seems to have nothing in common except for this paratactic,
absolutive-like foundation. If true, this provides signicant support for the recon-
struction explored in this chapter, and for the gradualist approach to the evolution of
syntax more generally.
3.4.2The middleground
According to e.g. Kemmer (1994:181), the reexive and the middle can be situated
as semantic categories intermediate in transitivity between one-participant and
24
If this is the origin of at least some serial verb constructions, then at least they should not be analyzed
on a par with compounds, or as some kind of freely Merged V-V combinations (as per the discussion in
Section 1.6). Instead, they should be seen as a by-product of, or as one kind of solution to, the emergence of
transitivity from paratactic combinations of intransitive small clauses.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
76 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
two-participant events.
25
Here I consider just one representative example: se con-
structions in Serbian that can be characterized as middles as they straddle the
boundary between the passive and active voice. In addition to dative subject clauses
introduced in the previous sections (3.3.4.2and 3.3.4.3), se is also used in a wide
variety of other constructions in Serbian, and may well be one of the most frequently
used words in the language.
Where pragmatics allows, se constructions in Serbian exhibit astounding vague-
ness of meaning, and se clearly cannot be analyzed as a reexive pronoun, reexivity
being only one of the available interpretations, and not even a preferred one, as the
following examples illustrate:
(35) Deca se tuku.
children
SE
hit
The children are hitting each other/?themselves.
The children are hitting somebody else.
One hits/spanks children.
(36) Pas se ujeda.
dog
SE
bites
The dog bites (someone).
?The dog is biting itself.
?One bites dogs.
(37)Marko se udara loptom!
Marko
SE
hits ball.
INST
Marko is hitting me with a ball.
Marko is hitting somebody with a ball.
?Marko is hitting himself with a ball.
?One is supposed to hit Marko with a ball.
If (37) is uttered with a sense of urgency, the most probable interpretation will involve
the most salient discourse participant, the speaker, even though there is no word or
morpheme corresponding to the rst person at all! Even though (38) below offers an
unambiguous way of expressing the rst reading of (37), (38) is much less likely to be
used in the heat of the moment, suggesting that se constructions are easier to process
than regular transitives:
(38) Marko me udara loptom!
Marko me hits ball.
INST
25
Kemmer (1994:184) points out that middle systems are quite widespread, being found in a large
number of genetically and areally divergent languages. According to Arce-Arenales, Axelrod, and Fox
(1994:23), the middle diathesisis marked in all nom-acc languages, and many constructions which have
traditionally been analyzed in terms of passive voice could be better understood as middle diathesis.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Precursors to transitivity 77
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
It is signicant that the vagueness in se clauses illustrated above is comparable to that
found with Tongan absolutives (20) and Riau intransitives (Footnote 18), as well as with
exocentric compounds. In (36), as apparent from the translations, Marko can be either
the subject (agent), or the object (patient), or both at the same time, the latter option
yielding the reexive interpretation. This kind of ambivalence can only be a result of
underspecication, that is, of simple, unarticulated syntax and semantics.
26
Given this,
the meaning of (37)and(38) can be roughly characterized in the following way:
(37) There is an event of hitting with a ball, and Marko is a participant
in that event.
Logical formula: e [H(e) Participant (Marko, e)]
(38) There is an event of hitting with a ball, and Marko is the agent of
that event, and the speaker is the patient of that event.
Logical formula: e [H(e) Agent (Marko, e) Patient (Me, e)]
It is probably more accurate to characterize (38)as(38’’) below, building directly on
the middle pattern in (37):
(38’’) There is an event of hitting with a ball, and Marko is the agent of
that event, and the speaker is the participant of that event.
Logical formula: e [H(e) Agent (Marko, e) Participant
(Me, e)]
This would essentially mean, as discussed in this chapter, that the basic absolutive
layer is still preserved even in (38), and that it is by virtue of superimposing a higher
argument that the initial participant is now interpreted as a non-agent, in this case as
patient/theme. This is exactly what we see with the Dyirbal data in Section 3.3.3.
Interestingly, Dowty (1991) also questions the rigidity and descreteness of theta
roles, and proposes that they can instead be seen as prototypes, or proto-roles, such
as proto-agent and proto-theme roles (thanks to a reviewer for leading me in this
direction). The participant role that I am using here can then be seen as an even more
underspecied role, just a proto-role. This is then how one can characterize proto-
predication as involving a verb (predicate) and just one argument, with a proto-role
of a participant.
The presence of se simply implies that there is one more participant involved in the
event, in addition to the one surfacing, and typically its role can be inferred from
pragmatic context (e.g. 37). But the role of the expressed argument (e.g. Deca,Pas,or
Marko above) still remains absolutive-like, not grammatically specied as either
subject or object, giving rise to massive ambiguities (Progovac 2005a, 2013b, 2014a,b).
26
Recall that VN compounds, which are also analyzed as absolutive-like, are likewise vague in this
respect, with the noun acting either as an object, or as a subject, or as both at the same time in some cases.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
78 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The constructions in (3536) once again illustrate a two-word grammar at work (this
time enhanced by the particle se). Even though, pragmatically speaking, one is
dealing here with an event with two participants, this kind of fossil syntax cannot
express both arguments, nor can it specify whether the only expressed argument is
subject or object.
27
Comparable vagueness may also be found with cognate se constructions in other
Slavic languages, but also in Spanish (Arce-Arenales, Axelrod, and Fox 1994:5),
clearly indicating that the phenomenon illustrated above is not just a quirk of
Serbian:
28
(39) Juan se mató.
Juan
SE
killed
Juan got killed.
Juan killed himself.
Serbian se is analyzed in Franks (1995) and Progovac (2005a) as an expletive (mean-
ingless) pronoun, absorbingaccusative case. Another way to look at it is to say that
se in these constructions is a proto-transitive/proto-accusative marker imposed upon
an ancient absolutive pattern, but being stuck in this intermediate stage between
absolutivity and transitivity. As pointed out by Maggie Tallerman (p.c. 2014), these se
constructions, as well as other constructions which I consider transitionalin this
framework, are not transitional in the sense that they are unstable or in the process of
changing they can only be transitional in the sense that they straddle the boundary
between transitivity and intransitivity.
It is hard to be sure how to analyze these se constructions by using the tools of
Minimalism, and the derivation in (40) is just a suggestion:
(40)[
TP
Deca [
FP
se [
SC/VP
deca tuku]]]
children
SE
children hit
Again, the idea is that the noun and the verb are rst Merged in a SC/VP (Section 1.7).
Next, a proto-transitive functional word se is Merged with the SC/VP to create some
27
It is interesting to note in this respect that Otsuka (2011) analyzes some of the Tongan constructions
as involving a null SE anaphor, even though, as he mentions, Tongan does not have any overt anaphors!
The way I see it, the author is simply noticing a connection between absolutivity and se middles.
28
Consider also the vagueness of the English example below:
(i) The children got dressed.
As argued in e.g. Alexiadou (2012), these get-passive constructions should be analyzed as middles, that is,
constructions which have only one structural argument. In this respect, get-passives are non-canonical
passives, given that canonical passives are taken to have two structural arguments. Middles in English also
include examples such as (ii-iii), among others:
(ii) These apples sell well.
(iii) The glass cuts easily.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Precursors to transitivity 79
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
kind of functional projection, whose head is se, and which can be labeled as FP.
29
Finally, assume that the TP is created, and the noun deca Moves to the specier of the
TP. FP is still not a vP, as it does not introduce an agent, nor does it disambiguate the
role of the absolutive-type argument in the SC/VP, but it can be considered as a
precursor to vP. The next step(s) in developing vP-type transitivity in accusative
languages would be to associate this FP with an additional, external argument, such
as agent, and to associate the internal argument with the special (accusative) case.
Interestingly, without se, the absolutive pattern vanishes, and the only argument
has to be interpreted as subject/agent performing an action on an unspecied object,
as is also the case with English translations in (41) and (42), a familiar consequence of
accusative grammars:
(41) Deca tuku.
The children are hitting (somebody).
(42) Pas ujeda.
The dog bites (someone).
This suggests that the fossil absolutive-like structures in Serbian are only preserved
under the wing of se (as further explored in Progovac 2014b).
It seems, then, that the distinctions between subjecthood and objecthood, transi-
tivity and intransitivity, passive and active, can be neutralized, and can have a middle
ground. One way to make sense out of this is to postulate an intransitive absolutive-
like stage in the evolution of human language, a stage which provides a foundation
for any subsequent elaboration of argument structure.
Importantly, however, introducing transitivity with a structural accusative case
(vP/VP shell) to a language does not preclude some other constructions (e.g.
unaccusative small clauses, nominals, se constructions, compounds) from remaining
absolutive-like. What is also important to emphasize is that many of these founda-
tional structures still live inside/within the more complex structures. For example,
absolutives generated in small clauses/VPs arguably live inside nominals, se con-
structions, and transitives, and small clauses in general live inside TPs, as commonly
assumed in syntactic theory (Chapter 2). This reinforces the claim in this monograph
that small clauses and intransitive absolutives constitute the foundation, the platform
on top of which one can build (or not) more complex syntax, namely TPs and
transitivity, perhaps in the form of vP shells.
Transitivity in syntax thus need not be seen as conceptual necessity, but rather as an
evolutionary innovation; it can be seen as an additional layer of structure superimposed
upon the foundational (absolutive) layer, leading to a variety of crosslinguistic strategies
29
Se could have even started out as some kind of linker in the sense of Chapter 4.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
80 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
for marking case relations, and reected in the postulation of two verbal layers in
Minimalism (two vP shells). This renders syntax a quirky system, a product of tinker-
ing, rather than a system optimally designed from scratch. As was the case with the
small clause/TP distinction discussed in Chapter 2, the hypotheses explored in this
chapter are testable/falsiable, as well as corroborated by evidence from other elds, as
discussed in the following section.
3.5Corroborating evidence and testing grounds
The strongest corroborating evidence for the proposal in this chapter comes from
language acquisition, both involving sign languages and spoken languages. Neuro-
imaging would, once again, provide a good testing ground for the hypotheses
proposed in this chapter.
As pointed out in Section 3.1, the emergence of NSL provides excellent corrobor-
ation for the proposal. According to Kegl, Senghas, and Coppola (1999:21617), the
earliest stages of NSL, observed with the rst generation of speakers, do not exhibit
transitive N V N constructions, such as (43) below, at least not when two animate
nouns are involved (Senghas et al.1997). Instead, one nds what look like sequences
of two clauses of the kind (N VNV)(4445):
(43) *WOMAN PUSH MAN.
(44) WOMAN PUSHMAN REACT.
(45) WOMAN PUSHMAN FALL.
Aronoff et al.(2008, and references there) found a similar pattern for another sign
language that emerged spontaneously about 70 years ago, Al-Sayyid Bedouin Sign
Language (ABSL). They also report that there is a tendency toward one argument per
predicate, where e.g. transitive events involving two animate referents are rendered
by two or even three clauses.
These sequences can be analyzed as paratactic/symmetric combinations of two
intransitive (small) clauses, which are interpreted as the rst one causing the sec-
ond.
30
In this sense, this grammar is absolutive-like, and resembles the grammar
behind serial verb constructions and other absolutive-like constructions discussed in
this chapter, in that only intransitive structures are available, that is, each verb can
have only one argument.
30
This is not necessarily how the authors of the article would analyse these data. My personal
communication with Ann Senghas and Marie Coppola (p.c. 2014) revealed that they are revisiting those
early analyses, and that there are complexities involved. But, as far as I understand, the claim still stands
that in the earliest stages of NSL one nds these N V N V types of constructions, in lieu of N V
N transitive constructions, when both Ns are animate. When one of the nouns is inanimate, then
apparently transitive structures are possible.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 81
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
It is perhaps of interest to mention here that the overwhelming majority of the
world languages are classied as either Subject-Verb-Object (SVO) or Subject-
Object-Verb (SOV). Both types can be derived easily from a binary N V NV
pattern, comparable to the paratactic patterns in (4445). If one starts with an N V
N V sequence, and assigns the role of S (subject) to the rst noun, and the role of
O (object) to the second noun, one can easily derive the two word orders above
by dropping one of the verbs (the dropped verb could then be grammaticalized as a
null light verb (v), as per the syntactic theory). There is another symmetric paratactic
possibility: V N V N, the verb initial order being attested in e.g. unaccusatives
and VN compounds. If, again, the rst noun is associated with S, and the second
noun with O (as per the Cause First principle discussed in e.g. Section 1.6), this
underlying pattern can easily yield the SVO order again, but also another possible
word order across languages, VSO. The other logically possible word orders are
extremely rare across languages. Needless to say, this is a rather speculative observation.
According to Goldin-Meadow (2005), the syntax of Homesign languages, self-
styled gestural communication systems spontaneously developed by deaf children
not exposed to sign language, also appears to be absolutive-like. In Homesign, both
patients/themes and intransitive agents tend to precede verbs, once again neutraliz-
ing the distinction between subjects and objects. Also, patients are more likely to be
expressed than agents, as is also the case with exocentric compounds and nominals
discussed in the previous sections. As Goldin-Meadow notes, both American and
Chinese deaf children are more likely to produce the sign for the eaten than for the
eater. In Zheng and Goldin-Meadows(2002:1712) study, the Chinese children
showed a bias to omit only the subjects of caused motions (agents), not the subjects
of spontaneous motions. Subjects of spontaneous motions were produced as often as
objects.
Considering that early stages of NSL, ABSL, and Homesign are languages arguably
constructed from scratch, the patterns of intransitivity and ergativity observed in
their creation are of evolutionary signicance (see Section 2.5.1for much more
discussion regarding the reasons why language acquisition can be relevant for
language evolution studies). At the very least, these considerations demonstrate
that there is a simpler way to break into syntax, starting with intransitive clauses
and blurring the distinction between subjecthood and objecthood.
Moreover, children acquiring spoken languages also go through a two-word stage
(Bloom 1970) which seems to be characterized by similar proto-syntactic patterns. It
is often claimed for child language acquisition that children deletearguments in
their speech, that is, that they do not express all the arguments that would typically be
required in the adult grammar.
31
According to Zheng and Goldin-Meadow (2002:
31
As pointed out in Section 1.6, Bickerton (1990,1998) takes this frequent omission of arguments to
indicate that children at this stage do not have reallanguage.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
82 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
1712), such deletionsare not random, but rather follow an ergative pattern. If
children in these cases are using absolutive-type intransitive grammars, as per the
proposal in this chapter, then they are not deleting anything, but rather just using the
syntactic mold in which there is room for expressing only one single argument.
Similar patterns in language acquisition of spoken languages have been reported
by other authors. For example, when hearing children are exposed to Korean (Clancy
1993) or Samoan (Ochs 1982), they too follow the deaf childrens patternthey omit
transitive subjects and produce intransitive subjects and objects, exhibiting essen-
tially an absolutive pattern. Indeed, the same pattern has been observed for English
language acquisition (Goldin-Meadow and Mylander 1983:63). As Zheng and
Goldin-Meadow (2002:1712) conclude, the ergative pattern is more robust, consid-
ering that the omission pattern found in all of these hearing children and the deaf
children is reminiscent of the alignment found in ergative languages. This ties in well
with the approach explored in this chapter.
As pointed out by a reviewer, the preferred discourse pattern in a variety of
languages is the pattern in which only one argument is given in full, while the
other arguments are either omitted altogether or occur in a reduced (afx) form
(see e.g. Newmeyer 2005:1323, and references there). For example, Du Bois (1985:
3479) found that in Sacapultec, a Mayan language of Guatemala, most clauses in the
discourse contain only one full noun phrase, with zero noun phrases also very
common. The full NP that commonly occurs is the absolutive, consistently following
the verb, while the ergative full noun phrases are infrequent.
In addition, Du Bois (1987) has noted that the pattern in which the grown is
expressed more readily than the grower is common in the adult languages of the
world, as attested with the intransitive constructions in (b) from English:
(46) a. John grew tomatoes. b. John grew.
(47)a. John shook Bill. b. John shook.
While the transitive pattern in (a) necessarily takes John to be an agent, the
intransitive counterparts in (b) favor the interpretation in which John is undergoing
the action, as a theme/patient. In other words, there is avoidance of agents/external
arguments in these cases (see also Casielles and Progovac (2010,2012) for the
signicance of this phenomenon for language evolution, and in particular for the
Agent-First hypothesis).
Interestingly, the bonobo Kanzi has been reported to have mastered a VS (two-
word) syntax in his use of lexigrams and gestures, based on the description in
Greeneld and Savage-Rumbaugh (1990:161), as well as Heine and Kuteva (2007:
1457). First of all, Kanzi only uses two-word combinations, including creations with
one verb and just one argument, in a way that does not distinguish agents/subjects
from patients/objects, with both following the verb. While Kanzis initial combinations
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 83
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(during the rst month) show free word order (hide peanut, peanut hide), the later
combinations seem to converge on the productive VS order, even when the noun is the
agent, in the sense that the verb is followed by an agent gesture.
32
There is a lot of controversy surrounding the interpretation of these and other
reports on primate communication, and it is not my intention to engage with these
controversies in this book. For now, sufce it to say that, if Kanzi is in principle
capable of (sporadic) two-word (intransitive) combinations, then it is conceivable
that at least some individuals of our common ancestor with bonobos were too. This
would have been enough to allow the process of natural selection for language.
Last but not least, as pointed out in Chapter 2, neuroimaging can provide a fertile
testing ground for the hypotheses explored in this chapter. The suggestion is that one
can use the subtraction and other neuro-linguistic methods to determine how proto-
syntactic structures are processed in comparison to their more complex counterparts,
in the hope of nding neuro-biological correlates of, for example, vP shells and
transitivity (see Progovac 2010b).
For the reasons given in the Appendix, while the processing of transitives with vP
shells is expected to show clear lateralization in the left hemisphere, with extensive
activation of specic Brocas areas, the proto-syntactic structures, such as absolutive-
type constructions, as well as middle se constructions, are expected to show less
lateralization, and less involvement of Brocas area, but more reliance on both
hemispheres, as well as, possibly, more reliance on the subcortical structures of the
brain.To take just one concrete example (not discussed in the Appendix), it follows
from the analysis presented in this chapter that se constructions (and middles in
general) are easier to process than regular transitives, given that they involve simpler,
less articulated syntax. This can be tested given the availability of minimally con-
trasting pairs in Serbian involving se constructions (48) vs. true transitive counter-
parts (49), as suggested in Progovac (2014a,b):
(48) Marko se udara!
Marko
SE
hits
(49) Marko me udara!
Marko me hits
If syntax evolved gradually, through several stages, then it is plausible to expect
that modern syntactic structures and operations decompose into evolutionary
32
As pointed out by e.g. Tallerman (2012:453), human syntax is far more than regularities in word
order, concluding that at most we can agree that Kanzi has learned a productive proto-grammar.
Tallerman (2012:454) further elaborates that certain properties that we might call proto-syntactic are
attested in animal language research. Words can be meaningfully combined, especially in novel ways . . .
This is where the reconstruction of syntax in this book should be helpful. It decomposes syntax all the way
down to the simplest syntactic strategy, which in turn allows one to nd some continuity, however tenuous
it may be, with animal communication systems.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
84 The intransitive two-word stage
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
primitives. If so, this will not only be measurable in the activation of the brain, but
without these evolutionary considerations it may not be possible to achieve a true
breakthrough in the eld of neuro-linguistics (see Section 2.5.3).
3.6Conclusion
This chapter builds on the arguments of Chapter 2, and reconstructs a stage in the
evolution of human language which is characterized by intransitive small clauses,
lacking vP and TP structure, and allowing only one proto-argument per clause, that
is, an argument whose thematic role is underspecied. This stage is arrived at by
internal reconstruction based on the syntactic hierarchy of functional projections.
Peeling off the outer clausal layers, TP and then vP, one arrives at the basic
predication structure of an intransitive small clause. As with the proposal in
Chapter 2, there are three prongs to this argument. First, the absolutive-like pattern
is shown to provide a foundation upon which transitive structures are built. Second,
there is a variety of absolutive-like foundational structures even in nominative-
accusative languages. And, third, there is good corroborating evidence and promising
testing grounds for this proposal. Furthermore, postulating an intransitive absolu-
tive-like stage allows one to clearly identify the kinds of evolutionary pressures that
would have led to the rise of transitivity, as explored in Chapter 7.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Conclusion 85
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
4
Parataxis and coordination as
precursors to hierarchy: Evolving
recursive grammars
4.1Hypothesized evolutionary stages of syntax
The goal of this chapter is to show that syntax can be decomposed into evolutionary
primitives/layers at an even more abstract level than explored in the previous
chapters, and that such decomposition can not only help identify the stages of
evolutionary progression of syntax, but also shed light on its very design. The intent
is also to show that the progression through such stages makes evolutionary sense,
i.e., that each new stage brings some concrete advantage(s) over the previous stage(s),
and that such advantage(s) could have been subject to natural selection.
Considering some present-day constructions, as well as the trends in grammat-
icalization processes, I propose the following three rough stages in the evolution of
syntax (iiii), following a hypothetical non-syntactic one-word stage (0). My working
assumption, the simplest possible, and the least stipulative, is that any combination of
words/phrases into a single utterance involves syntax.
(0) One-word stage (no combinatorial power)
1
It has been postulated thatchildren go through a one-word stage as they acquire language
(e.g. Bloom 1970), but adult speech also sometimes involves single words meant as
complete utterances (as in e.g. Snake!Run!Out!) Since the one-word stage does not
involve syntax, it will not be discussed here, except to show why it would be benecial to
advance from this stage to a proto-syntactic stage, as characterized in (i) below.
(i) Paratactic stage (proto-syntax), where prosody/supra-segmentals provide the only
glue for (proto-)Merge. In other words, in this stage there is prosodic evidence, but
not any segmental evidence, that the words/constituents are Merged. The paratactic
1
See Section 4.2.2for some discussion regarding the issue of valence in a one-word stage.
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
syntax of this stage can be characterized by an operation Conjoin, rather than Merge
proper. As explained below, Conjoin is an operation not distinct from Adjoin, as used
in e.g. Adger (2003) for the attachment of adjuncts. Unlike Merge proper, Conjoin
does not create headedness or hierarchy.
(ii) Proto-coordination stage, where, in addition to prosody, the conjunction/linker
provides all-purpose segmental glue to hold the utterance together. In this stage, the
evidence for (proto-)Merge is more robust, as it retains the prosodic evidence (the
only type of evidence available in the previous stage), and adds to it segmental
evidence (the linker), even though in this stage the linker does not add much more
than that to the interpretation. This stage is arguably still syntactically at/non-
hierarchical.
(iii) Specic functional category stage (hierarchical/subordination stage), where, in
addition to prosody and to segmental glue, specic functional categories emerge,
providing specialized syntactic glue for constituent cohesion, including tense par-
ticles (copulas) and subordinators/complementizers. In other words, this stage
includes all the achievements of the previous stages, and adds another, which is to
use the segmental piece (linker) also to identify the type of constituent created by
Merge. To take just one example, a meaningless linker of the proto-coordination
stage, connecting the subject and its predicate, becomes a meaningful tense particle,
which can now build its own Tense Phrase (TP). I argue that it is only at this stage
that hierarchical structure, Move, and recursion become available, considering that
adjunction and coordination structures, characterizing the previous two stages, are
typically islands for Move (Chapter 5), and do not show true recursion.
2
This is a progression from least syntactically elaborated (parataxis), to more elabor-
ated (coordination), to most elaborated (specialized functional categories/projec-
tions). I consider that each of these grammars can operate both clause-internally,
e.g. to combine a subject and a predicate (into a small clause Me rst!), and clause-
externally, to combine two such clauses into a single utterance (e.g. Nothing ventured,
nothing gained).
2
I should clarify here that I do not consider Move to be subsumable under Merge, the so-called Internal
Merge, as is typically assumed in the Minimalist Program today. Instead, the considerations in this book
lead me to conclude that Merge is just a necessary condition for realizing Move, but that Move requires
additional conditions to be met, as discussed below, as well as in Section 4.4.5. So does recursion.
As will be discussed in Section 4.3, the coordination stage and the subordination stage may not have
shown a clear chronological ordering in the evolution of human language, as they may have been
intertwined, just as they seem to be in todays languages. Still, they can be ordered in terms of relative
complexity, as per the proposal in this book. I hope that future research will shed brighter light on this
issue.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Hypothesized evolutionary stages of syntax 87
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
As pointed out in the previous chapters, the argument for each proposed progres-
sion through stages has three prongs to it: (i) identifying living fossilsof each stage
in modern languages; (ii) providing evidence of tinkeringwith the language design,
so that fossils of one stage can be shown to be integrated into the next, leading also to
composite structures incorporating constructions of various stages; (iii) identifying
existing or potential corroborating evidence from grammaticalization, language
acquisition, agrammatism, animal communication, neuroscience, and genetics.
Moreover, the goal is to show that each identied stage accrues concrete and tangible
advantages over the previous stage(s), advantages specic enough to be targeted by
natural/sexual selection.
One of the themes of this monograph is that the advent of a new stage does not
replace the previous stage(s), but rather that the older stages continue to co-exist,
often in specialized or marginalized roles, in addition to being built into the very
foundation of more complex structures (see Chapters 2and 3). Evolution is known
not to throw a good thing away, but to build upon it, which is why one should expect
to nd constructions of previous stages (fossils) in the later stages.
Prosody and intonation are of course still in use everywhere not only to signal
constituent cohesion, but also to signal grammatical function, such as interrogative
mood in (1). When they are used in conjunction with syntactic operations such as
Move (subjectauxiliary inversion), the result is redundancy and robustness, hall-
marks of evolutionary tinkering.
(1) Mary is already at home?
(2) Is Mary already at home?
There is also experimental evidence to show that prosody signals syntactic cohesion.
For example, Tyler and Warren (1987) have performed an experiment to see how
comprehension is affected by disrupting either syntactic or prosodic structure. Their
conclusion is that a disruption in prosody has a serious adverse effect on compre-
hension, suggesting that prosody even today plays a crucial role in achieving syntactic
cohesion. Tyler and Warren conclude that prosody does not play the poor sister to
syntax, with prosodic information only used when there are syntactic options, such
as syntactically ambiguous phrases. Rather, prosodic information seems to be an
integral part of the comprehension process(656). This is also consistent with
Deacons(1997) characterization of the role of prosody, as discussed in Section 4.5.1.3.
The progression of stages proposed above is consistent with what one nds with
the grammaticalization processes observed in the present times. The grammatical-
ization of e.g. nite subordination typically takes parataxis as a starting point and
possibly proceeds through a(n intermediate) coordination stage, as discussed in
Section 4.5. Here I extend this progression of stages even to clause-internal level,
suggesting that predication may have also gone through a similar progression in its
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
88 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
evolutionary trajectory: (i) root small clause (SC) stage (created by parataxis/prosody
alone); (ii) proto-coordination stage (with a linking/conjunction-like element con-
necting the subject and the predicate); and (iii) a specic functional category stage,
i.e. a hierarchical stage involving a specic functional category superimposing one
layer of structure (e.g. TP) over another (SC).
As will be discussed further below, while the evidence for a paratactic stage is
overwhelming, evidence for a coordination stage is not that robust. This may be
because the paratactic structures provide the necessary foundation for building both
coordination and subordination, while coordination may serve as an intermediate
stage only optionally, in some circumstances.
The following subsections explore each of the postulated stages of syntax, as well as
point to the possible communicative advantages of each. The following section will
consider some of the same data introduced in the previous two chapters to illustrate
the paratactic stage, namely intransitive small clauses and compounds, but the focus
in this chapter is on the nature of the bond between merged elements, as well as on
how that bond changes with the progression to the subsequent two stages, both
clause-internally and clause-externally.
4.2Paratactic proto-syntax stage
4.2.1Operation Conjoin: Clause-internally and clause-externally
As argued in Chapter 2, as well as in Chapter 3, the following types of small clauses
(34), clause combinations (5), and compounds (6) are reasonably good approxima-
tions of what the operation Conjoin (proto-Merge) could accomplish in the para-
tactic proto-syntactic stage. Recall that Conjoin can be characterized as an operation
which joins/unites two elements into a single utterance, but in so doing it does not
create headedness or hierarchy. What holds the bond together is only intonation/
prosody (i.e. supra-segmentals).
(3)Merst! Everybody out! Him apologize?! Me worry?!
(4) Case closed. Problem solved. Point taken. Mission accomplished.
Crisis averted.
(5) Nothing ventured, nothing gained. Monkey see, monkey do. Come
one, come all.
(6) pick-pocket, turn-coat, hunch-back, cry-baby, busy-body, rattle-snake
Of note here is also that certain root small clause types, in particular the clauses
illustrated in (3), are characterized by exaggerated intonation, possibly compensating
for the lack of functional categories or linkers, and thus tapping into the proto-
linguistic ability to use prosody/intonation for the purposes of conjoining. Given this,
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic proto-syntax stage 89
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
it is not implausible to suggest that in this stage of proto-syntax prosody may have
been exaggerated, or perhaps even musical, in the sense of prosodic protolanguage
discussed in Fitch (2010:475, and references there). However, Fitchs proposal that
this kind of prosodic or musical protolanguage preceded words in the evolution of
language, and was devoid of propositional meaning, sort of like birdsong, was rightly
criticized by Tallerman (2013a). On the approach explored here, if there was such a
musical episode in the evolution of language, then it would have been most useful at
this (paratactic) juncture, where prosody/melody would have had a very specic
compositional function to hold the (proto-)words and utterances together (see also
Section 2.4).
Notice that adjunction, used abundantly in present-day languages, is taken to
involve a comparable kind of at/non-hierarchical structure, essentially parataxis. In
(7) below, the adverb is traditionally analyzed as adjoining to the verbal projection
(but see Cinque 1999 for a specialized functional category approach to the attachment
of adverbs). Similarly, the adverbial clause in (8) is traditionally analyzed as adjoining
to the main clause. This kind of attachment does not create a new (functional)
category or layer, but rather loosely attaches to an already projected layer, expanding
it, as shown below.
(7) She [
vP
[
vP
worked] feverishly].
(8)[
TP
After considering all the options,[
TP
she ventured out.]]
This is what prompted Jackendoff (1999,2002) to propose that adjunction structures
have proto-linguistic avor, and that they can be seen as evolutionary fossils
(Section 1.6).
While it may look as if adjunction is creating an additional layer of structure in
(78), this is just an artifact of the lack of appropriate notation. The intent of the vP/
TP repetition in these examples is to capture the idea that the existing layer is only
expanded/stretched, not that a new layer is created. Just like conjuncts, adjuncts seem
to be in a different dimension, and have been seen as merging in a different plane
(e.g. Chomsky 2001; also Chomsky 2004; Citko 2011). It is for this reason that I do not
consider that the structures in (78) involve true recursion, in the sense that one
syntactic category is embedded/inserted within another, as its integral part. What we
have here instead is an adverb phrase loosely adjoining to a vP (7), and a clause
loosely adjoining to another clause (8). In the sense of Kinsella (2009), this should be
seen as iteration, rather than true recursion, as discussed further in Section 4.4.
It has been repeatedly noted in the syntactic literature that clausal adjuncts such as
the one in (8) are not fully integrated into syntactic fabric. As put in An (2007), these
adjuncts sit in semi-integrated, non-canonicalsyntactic positions (see also Selkirk
1978; Stowell 1981; Nespor and Vogel 1986; Zec and Inkelas 1990 for the prosodic
properties of adjuncts). Whatever the analysis, it highlights the exceptional and
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
90 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
peripheral nature of the adjunction process. Chomsky (2004:117) acknowledges that
there has never [ . . . ] been a satisfactory theory of adjunction.An evolutionary
approach provides a rationale: adjunction is not some well-designed (engineered)
property of human language, which stands in clear differentiation from all other
syntactic processes and operations, but it is rather just a fossil of the paratactic stage
in language evolution, which is thus neither the same as the more modern structures,
nor sharply differentiated from them.
In this sense, the operation Conjoin characterized above subsumes the operation
Adjoin, operative in modern languages (see e.g. Adger 2003). What they share is the
paratactic, non-hierarchical, non-headed nature of attachment. However, Conjoin, as
intended here, is a broader term than Adjoin. When it comes to modern adjuncts, by
denition, they are peripheral structures attached to the core structures, such as
adverbs attaching to the verb phrases. On the other hand, the operation Conjoin, in
the sense in which I am using it here, can also join two elements of equal status,
where neither element is subordinated to the other, resulting in symmetrical attach-
ment, which is often described as parataxis, or even as (asyndetic) coordination.
Consider the following examples from Kaqchikel (Mayan), spoken in Guatemala.
3
(9) a. ru-te', ru-tata'
his-mother, his-father
his parents
b. tiwila' i-juyub'al i-taq'ajal.
nd your-mountains your-valleys
(Maxwell and Hill 2006:30).
Harris and Campbell (1995:283) also struggle with the distinction, and characterize
parataxis as either asyndetic joining, or loose (imprecise) joining, or both at the
same time. Asyndetic joining is simply joining without a conjunction.
4
3
Thanks to Robert Henderson (p.c. 2013) for leading me to the Kaqchikel (Mayan) data. According to
Maxwell and Hill (2006:25), Maya writings have long shown parallelism in structure. The Mayan Codices
are replete with repetition. A set of registers may show one gure, a Chac (Rain Deity), in a variety of poses.
The accompanying texts will share a syntactic form, varying perhaps one content word, a noun or a verb.
But the substitute words will have all the same inection as the originals. Such close parallelism appears in
modern spoken language in most formal genres, particularly public prayer. As the formality of speech
decreases, so does the strictness of the parallel structure.
4
It is of note here that Givóns(1979) pragmatic (asyntactic) mode of communication is characterized
by what he calls loose conjunction or parataxis (2223). In addition, Gil (2005 and elsewhere) has in fact
argued that simple sentences in Riau Indonesian (i) are put together by an instance of coordination.
(i) Makan ayam
eat chicken
In the analysis pursued in this monograph, this would fall under operation Conjoin, which is meant to
capture the common ground between coordination and adjunction.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic proto-syntax stage 91
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In clauses such as Me rst! (see (3) repeated below), arguably created by Conjoin, it
is not clear what counts as the head (center), the pronoun or the adjective, or
something else, and that is precisely why these structures are still referred to as
small clauses, i.e. as syntactically undened constituents (see Chapter 2for compet-
ing analyses of embedded small clauses). Similarly, exocentric compounds (6), which
are also arguably created by Conjoin, are traditionally considered to be headlessin
fact, the lack of headedness in these compounds is so salient that it is responsible for
their name, exocentric,that is, without a center/head (see Chapter 6for details of
their analysis). Moreover, the paratactic combination of two clauses in (5) is also
headless, and is arguably also a product of Conjoin. It is obvious here that the two
clauses are on an equal footing structurally, neither one being structurally embedded
within the other. In fact, the nature of the link in the correlative constructions more
generally can be considered fossil-like in this respect, given that it involves parallel,
symmetric attachment, as discussed later in the text.
(3)Merst! Everybody out! Him apologize?! Me worry?
(5) Nothing ventured, nothing gained. Monkey see, monkey do.
Come one, come all.
(6) pick-pocket, turn-coat, cry-baby, busy-body, hunch-back, rattle-snake
In other words, unlike Merge proper, which is considered to create headedness and
hierarchy, Conjoin, subsuming Adjoin, can be seen as an operation creating at,
exocentric (non-headed) structures. In this respect, Conjoin can be seen as creating
both conjoined constituents of equal status (parataxis/asyndetic coordination) and
conjoined constituents of unequal status (adjunction).
5
Some syntacticians consider that modern Merge can be decomposed into two
operations: Concatenate and Label (e.g. Chomsky 1995; Hornstein 2009; but see Citko
2011). Given this idea, Conjoin can be taken to involve just Concatenate, but not
Label, while Merge proper can be considered to involve both. This would be in line
with the suggestion in Clark (2013) that labeling might be a later evolutionary
development. Labeling itself would be responsible for selecting one of the combined
elements to be the head/center of the whole composition, creating headedness and
asymmetry. For example, in a combination run marathons, the verb and the noun
5
According to e.g. Haspelmath (2004:34), coordinating constructions can be identied on the basis of
their symmetry, and he includes here both paratactic constructions, without a coordinator, and those with
a coordinator. He also struggles with a differentiation between coordination in this sense, and subordin-
ation, which involves asymmetry, concluding that there are many constructions showing mixtures of
both, and we are only at the beginning of understanding what constraints there might be on such mixtures
(37). As discussed throughout this chapter, the evolutionary approach explored here predicts that there
would be such overlap between stages, and that in fact a clear differentiation will never be possible. As
noted by a reviewer, these may pose a challenge for the Minimalist Program.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
92 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
combine (by Concatenate/Conjoin), but then labeling renders the whole combin-
ation a verb phrase, with the verb being selected as the head/center of the whole
composition. While this may be a promising direction to explore, here I stick with the
more traditional terminology in order to avoid the undesirable assumptions associ-
ated with Merge in e.g. Hornsteins(2009) view, including its inseparability from
Move and recursion.
The choice of the term Conjoin may seem unfortunate at rst sight, given that it can
be confused with coordination structures, which are also referred to as conjunction
structures. Here the term is used in its lay sense of joining together, or uniting. But this
term is often used in linguistic literature not only for structures involving conjunctions
(e.g. and), but also for paratactic structures without any conjunction, especially if these
structures are on equal footing, that is, symmetrical. Are these uses of linguistic terms
confusing? Yes, but there is a good reason whyit is not possible to clearly delineate and
differentiate conjunction from adjunction/parataxis. If my proposal is on the right
track, then the initial paratactic Conjoin stage, without any coordinating words,
gradually integrated into the proto-coordination stage, in which proto-conjunctions
or linkers were used, for the sole purpose of solidifying the operation Conjoin, without
much difference in meaning. That is why the terms coordination/conjoin/parataxis are
often used interchangeably in linguistic literature. The overlap in terminology is the
result of the overlap in constructions: there is no clear differentiation among these
processes in present-day languages, as discussed further in Section 4.3. This is as
expected under the evolutionary approach explored here.
Recall from Chapter 2that the paratactic small clauses discussed above cannot be
manipulated by Move (10), and that they are not subject to embedding/subordination
either (11):
6
(10) a. *Where everybody?
b. *To whom him apologize?
c. *What solved?
d. *What ventured, nothing gained?
(11) a. *Him worry [me rst].
b. *Sheila happy [problem solved].
If root small clauses found in present-day languages are indeed approximations of
proto-syntactic structures, then this is consistent with my claim that paratactic proto-
syntax was rigid, and that it did not have the operation Move, or the ability to embed
one clause within another. Arguably, both of these processes are facilitated by specic
functional categories, which provide a stronger bond between constituents.
6
The reader is referred to Section 2.4for some discussion of questions such as Why worry ? and How
come?
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic proto-syntax stage 93
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Clearly, given their behavior illustrated above, root small clauses instantiate a
distinct, simpler grammar, which cannot be reduced to supercial omissions of
functional categories. In any event, this paratactic grammar is exocentric and at,
rather than hierarchical, and it lacks functional categories such as TP and CP, as well
as Move and subordination/recursion.
The clauses investigated in this chapter, as well as in the previous chapters,
typically consist of two words, a noun-like element and a verb-like element, which
I consider to be in a proto-predication relationship.
7
As pointed out in Chapter 3, it is entirely conceivable that the rst syntactic
combinations were two-word utterances, that is, that Conjoin could only combine
two elements at a time. In fact, all the evidence from present-day grammars points to
that conclusion. First of all, the central operation of modern grammars, Merge, is
widely considered to be binary, that is, that it can combine only two elements at a
time. If Conjoin was a precursor to Merge, then Merge retained this important
property of Conjoin. The same assumption holds for the principle Adjoin, which
I consider to be just one facet of the paratactic principle Conjoin. In e.g. Minimalism,
binary branching (i.e. binary Merge) is considered to be a syntactic universal,
operative in all languages. Also, as discussed in Section 2.5.1, children typically
proceed from a one-word stage to a two-word stage, before they start combining
more than two words into single utterances.
Furthermore, even observationally speaking, the overwhelming majority of con-
ventionalized compounds across languages are binary, consisting of only two free
morphemes.
8
In addition, where clauses are clearly combined paratactically (e.g. 12),
the number of clauses that combine is again typically just two. Combining more than
two clauses in this way becomes cumbersome to process, as discussed in Chapter 3):
(12) Nothing ventured, nothing gained. Easy come, easy go.
This adds plausibility to the argument that the initial clauses were two-word
(intransitive) combinations, and that only two such clauses could combine paratac-
tically into a conjoined union (see also the examples in 1519 below).
9
7
Hurford (2012) considers that the rst two-word utterances were of the topic-comment kind, and that
they only later grew into subject-predicate structures (see some discussion in Section 1.6).
8
Here, I am not considering recursive compound processes, such as English (i), but rather compounds
that are likely to be stored in the speakerslexicons, and found in the dictionaries, such as (ii).
(i) policy committee proposal discussion
(ii) bedroom, toothbrush, heartbeat
Moreover, in cases where the compound process is not recursive, only two words can combine by default,
and this is the case with e.g. English and Serbian VN excocentric compounds, as well as Serbian
compounds in general, as discussed further in Chapter 6(see also Section 1.6).
9
Additionally,itisworthpointingoutthatthestructure of ideophones, which can also be considered as
linguistic fossils, is paratactic and binary, suggesting that this kind of grammarmight be working across
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
94 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In sum, what I propose in this chapter is that both clausal combinations in (5) and
predicateargument combinations in (34) can be created by the same type of
grammarparatactic grammar, which is characterized by the operation Conjoin.
This parallelism between clause-internal and clause-external processes nds further
support in the consideration of the proto-coordination stage, which reveals that the
same proto-coordinator/linker can sometimes be used to connect both (Section 4.3).
4.2.2Paratactic grammar vs. separate utterances
As pointed out in Section 4.1, each new stage should accrue some advantages over the
previous stage(s) in order to justify its evolutionary usefulness. In this respect,
consider (13) as a report from a business trip, with falling intonation rendering
these two clauses two separate utterances, not connected by Conjoin:
(13) Nothing ventured . . . Nothing gained.
The interpretation in (13) is that nothing was ventured, and that nothing was gained.
Crosslinguistically, falling intonation implies assertion/certainty/completion, while
rising intonation signals uncertainty/incompleteness (e.g. Burling 2005,170 and
references there). In contrast, in (14), Conjoin combines the two clauses into a single
utterance, using rising intonation as only glue. This invokes an interpretation that
assigns a (causal/conditional) connection to the utterance.
(14) Nothing ventured, nothing gained.
In the absence of specic functional glue of the hierarchical stage (e.g. If nothing is
ventured, then nothing is gained), concatenations such as (14) typically rely on
iconicity of word order to express temporal and/or causal relations (see
Section 4.2.3). While structurally neither of the clauses in (14) is embedded within
the other, pragmatically they are interpreted in such a way that the rst clause serves
as a condition for the second, mainclause.
Such parallel, symmetric concatenations occur crosslinguistically, and are typically
preserved in formulaic, proverb-like sayings:
10
linguistic modules. What is also of interest when it comes to ideophones is that the pr ototypical examples among
them are often iconic in the sense that they imitate the sounds (tick-tock)orthesights(zig-zag)innature.
(i) tick-tock; zig-zag; ip-op; willy-nilly (English)
(ii) tika-taka; cik-cak; trte-mrte (aha, you are scared!); (Serbian)
apa-drapa (unruly, disorderly); kuku-riku (roosters call)
(iii) (mosquitoes buzzing); (Hmong)
plĩ-plo
ˇn (empty bottle submerged in water lling up)
The Hmong data are from Ratliff (2013; see also Ratliff 2010). Some languages, such as Korean, Japanese,
and Hmong, make a much more extensive use of ideophones than e.g. English or Serbian, and the speakers
of these ideophone-rich languages can create such expressives on the spot.
10
Comparable concatenations are quite prevalent in pidgin languages as well (e.g. No money, no come,
Winford 2006).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic proto-syntax stage 95
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(15) a. Easy come, easy go.
b. Monkey see, monkey do.
c. Card laid, card played.
d. Come one, come all.
e. Like father, like son.
f. So far, so good.
(16) a. Na psu rana, na psu i zarasla.
on dog wound on dog and healed
No big deal!(Serbian)
b. Preko preče, naokolo bliže.
across shorter around closer
Shortcuts are not always best.
c. Koliko para, toliko i muzike.
how-much money, that-much and music
How much you pay, is how much you can enjoy.
d. Duga kosa, kratka pamet.
long hair, short intelligence
(17) a. Wo dua, wo twa. (Twi)
11
you sow you reap
b. Wo hwehwea, wo hu.
you seek you nd
(18) a. Bene diagnoscitur, bene curatur. (Latin)
well diagnosed well cared-for
b. Cito maturum, cito putridum.
early ripe, early rotten
c. Qualis rex, talis grex.
like king, like people
d. Ubi fumus, ibi ignis.
Where there is smoke, there is re.
(19)a.
ua noj ua haus (Hmong)
12
make eat make drink
to earn a living
11
Twi is spoken in Ghana, and the examples were kindly provided by Kingsley Okai (p.c. 2011).
12
Hmong is spoken in southern China and northern Southeast Asia, and the data are taken from
Mottin (1978) and Johns and Strecker (1982). Thanks to Martha Ratliff (p.c. 2013) for leading me to the
Hmong data, as well as for providing the background for understanding them. Hmong has thousands of
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
96 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
b. kav teb kav chaw
rule land rule place
to rule a county
c. cua daj cua dub
wind yellow wind black
a storm
d. ua tsov ua rog
make tiger make war
make war
e. kev tshaib kev nqhis
way hunger way thirst
famine
It is clear how paratactic Conjoin brings about an advantage over no combinatorial
capabilities: the emergence of the paratactic syntactic stage (e.g. 14) does not eradicate
the possibility in (13) to use the clauses as separate utterances. Rather, with two
possibilities now available, to Conjoin and not to Conjoin, we can now more easily
distinguish between two unrelated propositions (13), and utterances that introduce
two propositions in a causal/temporal relationship (14). If so, then Conjoin affords a
concrete expressive advantage which could have been targeted by natural selection.
Still, without specialized functional elements, this paratactic grammar cannot be fully
explicit about the nature of the relations between clauses. Instead, such relations
seem to be inferred iconically. Iconicity here is reected in the requirement to express
the condition/cause before the outcome, as will be discussed further below. Deutscher
(2000) argues that the development of nite subordination had an adaptive advan-
tage in that it broke away from such iconicity.
A comparable kind of advantage is brought about clause-internally. While one can
express a variety of thoughts with one-word utterances (20), bringing two words
together by Conjoin into a single utterance (21) begins to create tighter connections,
paving the way toward (proto-)predication.
(20) Fall. Snow.
such creative binary paratactic creations. Even though the Hmong examples seem to create complex
vocabulary items as opposed to conditionals, their structure is parallel to the examples from English and
Twi, in that they are of the AB AC form. Some of these are frozen expressions (the one for storm,for
example) and are passed down from generation to generation, but good speakers will make up new ones
that are easily interpretable. Just 6070 years ago Hmong was a totally unwritten language, so for millennia
language skill equaled oral skill, and making up new, good ones was highly valued (Martha Ratliff, p.c. 2013).
That Hmong speakers use these AB AC structures productively is shown by Mortensen (2014), who
considers a 17 million-word corpus based on Hmong text from the soc.culture.hmong Usenet group. The
corpus yielded 16,106 valid tokens and 3,253 types of AB AC expressions.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic proto-syntax stage 97
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(21) Fall snow.
While the two separate utterances in (20) can express that there is somebody or
something that fell, perhaps because of the snow, or perhaps the snow fell, the small
clause in (21), created by Conjoin, is more likely to be interpreted as snow being
directly involved in the act of falling. Here, again, Conjoin provides an additional
expressive capability, which contrasts with the more vague possibility in (20), which
still remains available.
However, as pointed out by a reviewer, some syntacticians claim that words cannot
exist in isolation, as words have valence, that is, they are taken from the lexicon
(mental dictionary) with various grammatical features which dictate that they com-
bine with certain other words. In this particular case, the idea would be that the word
fall must combine with a subject (e.g. snow), as well as with Tense, in order to express
an assertion. In this view, neither (20) nor (21) can make assertions. For example,
Piattelli-Palmarini (2010:160) considers that words themselves are syntactic entities
and that it is illusoryto think that as such words can exist outside of full-blown
syntax, or that any protolanguage can be reconstructed in which words are used, but
not full-blown syntax.
On the other hand, Bickerton (2014:89) points out that these early words could
have been different from modern words; perhaps they were mere lexical shells,
without grammatical features. It is also important to point out that even present-
day adult speakers often use one-word utterances (e.g. Me!Fire!), which need not
be analyzed as elliptical, that is, as derived from full sentences by ellipsis (see
Progovac 2013a for an overview of this issue and for references). It is well-known
that words sometimes have a special form when used in isolation, and such forms
have been analyzed as default forms (see e.g. Schütze 2001; Section 2.2), that is, as
forms with unspecied grammatical features. These default forms are used
exactly in those situations in which syntactic rules cannot reach them, including
in isolation. In other words, Piattelli-Palmarinis claim is not necessary even
for present-day languages, as even present-day languages allow words to be
used in isolation. This leaves the door wide open for a one-word stage in language
evolution.
The usefulness of paratactic grammars is also very obvious with exocentric VN
compounds. Progovac (2009a, 2012) and Progovac and Locke (2009) argue that the
ability to use the kind of paratactic grammar characterizing exocentric compounds
may have been sexually selected, and that some modern languages may still preserve
evidence of such selection. As discussed in much detail in Chapter 6, these com-
pounds seem to be the only well-dened morpho-syntactic construction that spe-
cializes for derogatory reference/insult. It is also the construction that most neatly
falls under the umbrella of a paratactic, exocentric, intransitive, absolutive-like
grammar (see Chapter 3and Chapter 6).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
98 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(22) scare-crow, kill-joy, pick-pocket, cry-baby, spoil-sport, turn-coat,
rattle-snake, hunch-back, dare-devil, wag-tail, tattle-tale,
Drynk-pany (miser), Pinch-penny (miser), busy-body
(23) ispi-čutura (drink.up-askdrunkard), guli-koža (peel-skinwho
rips you off), cepi-dlaka (split-hairwho splits hairs), muti-voda
(muddy-watertrouble-maker), jebi-vetar (screw-wind
charlatan), vrti-guz (spin-buttdget), tuži-baba (whine-
old.woman; tattletale) (Serbian)
The argument is that one can create much more colorful and creative (ritual) insults
with two-word concatenations than one can ever do with just single words. The
reader can try to nd one-word (non-compound) equivalents to the concepts
expressed with the metaphorical compounds above. The chances are that either the
alternatives of that kind do not exist, or if they do, that they are too dry or abstract,
and not likely to have existed in the initial stages of language. On the other hand, one
should notice that the pieces of exocentric compounds (e.g. wind, cry, rattle, wag,
peel) tend to be rather concrete concepts, much more likely to have existed at the
early stages of language evolution. It is fascinating to observe how the simplest
combinations of these most basic pieces are able to yield truly complex and abstract
concepts, which can serve amazingly well as insults. But such combinations can also
be useful for providing more precise descriptions of animals, as is the case with
e.g. rattlesnake. Paratactic grammar in this particular domain would have thus
constituted a true breakthrough in human expressive capabilities, clearly something
that could have, and would have, been subject to selection, as discussed in Chapter 6,
as well as in Chapter 7.
4.2.3Absolutes and correlatives: More on Conjoin
As established in the previous section, when two small clauses combine paratactic-
ally, they appear to be on an equal footingwith respect to each other as far as syntax
is concerned, and their relationship is then interpreted as one of temporal ordering
and/or causation, expressed iconically by the relative ordering of the two clauses.
On the other hand, when a bare small clause attaches paratactically to a nite
sentence/TP, in an unequal act of union (24 below), such a small clause is perceived
as an adverbial/adjunct, which again usually receives temporal/causal, or some other
modier-like interpretation. In his detailed consideration of absolute constructions
(not to be confused with absolutives), such as the underlined clause in (24), which
can also be characterized as involving operation Conjoin, Stump (1985:302) con-
cludes that the logical relation between the absolute and its superordinate clause is
often determined inferentially. He denes inferenceas anything which is not part
of the literal meaning of some expression but which language users judge to be part of
the intended meaning of that expression(304).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic proto-syntax stage 99
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(24) She clapped her hands like a child, her lucid eyes sparkling.
(Stump 1985:332)
Jackendoff (2002) also considers similar small clause attachments in (25) and (26),
suggesting a possible pre-TP stage in the evolution of human language:
(25) [Us having left], he reverted to his old ways.
(26) [Him having gone to Rome], I can now focus on my work.
As opposed to the symmetric parataxis illustrated in (1519), the interpretation in this
case is no longer determined by the relative ordering of the two clauses, but is at least
partly determined by their unequal grammatical status, again iconically: the nite
clause serves as the main clause because it is grammatically the fuller one, and the
small clause just provides some temporal and/or causal modication of the main
clause. Even if the ordering is reversed in (2728), the interpretation remains the
same. This is in contrast to symmetric clause combinations, which are directly
affected by such reversals of order (29):
(27) He reverted to his old ways, [us having left].
(28) I can now focus on my work, [him having gone to Rome].
(29) ?Nothing gained, nothing ventured.
?Easy go, easy come.
?Monkey do, monkey see.
?Come all, come one.
The analysis of (1519) as simple concatenation/parataxis may be called into question
by some recent analyses of correlative constructions of the type illustrated in (30)
below:
(30) The more you read, the less you understand.
Culicover and Jackendoff (2005:508) argue that such correlative constructions
involve a paratactic (quasi-coordinate) syntax with conditional semantics. However,
den Dikken (2005:503) responds that their approach condone(s) a mismatch
between syntax and semanticsand proposes a syntactically more complex deriv-
ation (see also Smith 2010 and Citko 2011 for an overview of various approaches). The
conditional semantics, however, does not follow even from den Dikkens treatment
of correlatives, as he himself acknowledges. But, at any rate, this same friction
between syntax and semantics seems to carry over to my examples in (1519).
First of all, at least in the case of examples such as (1519), one is not dealing with a
mismatch, but rather with underspecication/vagueness, just as one is not dealing
with a mismatch in the case of absolutive constructions. The paratactic attachment
only signals that there is a relationship between the events in the two clauses, but it
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
100 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
does not specify the nature of that relationship. According to Culicover and
Jackendoff (2005:528), parataxis is grammatically the most primitive way to com-
bine linguistic elements, one that leaves the semantic relations among the elements to
be determined by their inherent semantic possibilities or by pragmatic consider-
ations.As pointed out above, concatenations such as (1519) typically rely on
iconicity of word order to express temporal and/or causal relations, rather than on
any syntactic devices (see also Stump 1985:307; Deutscher 2000).
This is also the case with constructions akin to serial verb constructions, as
discussed in Chapter 3, Section 3.4.1. One example is the concatenation of two
intransitive clauses (e.g. WOMAN PUSH, MAN FALL), meant to express a transitive
event in Nicaraguan Sign Language. Comparable to the examples in (1519), such
combinations are also interpreted iconically, in the sense that the rst clause acts as
the cause for the second (and the order is not reversible). If transitive constructions
ultimately derive from such paratactic sequences, then this would explain the over-
whelming tendency in world languages for agents (which are typically causers) to
precede patients/objects in transitive constructions. Perhaps this could even obviate
the need for a separate Agent-First principle, as discussed in Section 1.6.
Furthermore, the correlative structures in (30) are clearly more complex than the
paratactic attachment of small clauses in e.g. (15), both clause-internally and clause-
externally (see especially Smith 2010). Internally, both clauses in (30) are nite,
showing tense and agreement, as well as a left-peripheral position before the subject,
which may implicate Move, or at least a(n additional) functional projection above
TP. In contrast, the small clauses in (15) are just thatsmall clauses which show no
tense, no agreement, and no Move. Externally, each of the small clauses in (15) can be
a root construct on its own, not requiring another clause to complete it (e.g., Nothing
ventured!) This is not the case with the correlative constructions in (30), whose
individual clauses are clearly dependent (*The more you read), possibly suggesting
some additional external mechanism of clause cohesion, not available in (15).
This is not to deny the obvious similarities between the constructions in (15) and
the correlatives in (30). The correlatives in (30) may represent modern complications
of ancient correlatives, the latter more closely approximated by the examples in (15),
but the examples in (30) still showing some elements of proto-syntax. Citko (2011)
also concludes that correlative structures are somewhere between parataxis and
hypotaxis. Notice that such clauses still depend iconically on the relative ordering:
(31) The less you understand, the more you read.
(31) is interpreted very differently from (30). This is in contrast to clearly subordin-
ated structures (32) below, which do not depend on relative ordering:
(32) If you read more, you understand less.
You understand less if you read more.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic proto-syntax stage 101
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The issue of vagueness and underspecication deserves special attention in an
evolutionary framework (see also Chapter 3). If language evolved gradually, then it
is to be expected that not all the grammatical tools that we use today to express
various relations with some precision were available in the previous stages of
grammar. This should not have prevented our ancestors from speaking in however
imprecise and vague ways. It is also important to keep in mind that, however precise
we may believe that our language is today, it is still extremely underspecied with
respect to so many distinctions that could in principle be made, and which are made
in some languages, but not in others (see e.g. Gil 2014).
The ever-increasing precision in what we can express with language, and the
increasing match between syntax and semantics, may have marked one of the
directions in which language evolved. But there is no reason to believe that a perfect
syntaxsemantics match will ever be achieved (see e.g. Francis and Michaelis (2003)
which focuses on various incongruities of this kind), or that it is even desirable to
achieve (see e.g. Bouchard 2013). As pointed out throughout the book, even when
more precise means are available in languages, speakers often resort to simpler,
vaguer expressions, such as middles in Serbian. In languages like English, which
does not have comparable middles, one often uses passive forms, whose end result is
the suppression of the agent, that is, less precision in characterizing the argument
structure.
In conclusion, postulating a paratactic stage in the evolution of syntax is supported
by the living fossilsof this stage found in abundance in modern languages (e.g. root
small clauses, their paratactic combinations, and exocentric compounds). In add-
ition, Section 4.5identies corroborating evidence from ancient languages, gram-
maticalization processes, language acquisition, comparative animal studies, and
neurological studies, including the processing of intonation and prosody. It is of
note that paratactic grammars cannot be manipulated by Move. This feeds into my
proposal in Chapter 5on Subjacency that Move is a later evolutionary innovation,
which arguably emerged together with hierarchy (also Section 4.4.5). The following
subsections, 4.3and 4.4, consider how paratactic constructions provide a foundation,
a scaffolding, for the coordination and subordination structures.
4.3The proto-coordination stage
As pointed out in the previous section, paratactic combinations rely solely on
prosodic, supra-segmental information to provide evidence of proto-Merge (Con-
join). If the advent of proto-Merge, that is, the beginning of proto-syntax, was a
particularly advantageous development in the evolution of human language, then
one can see how providing more robust and unambiguous evidence of such an
operation would have been benecial. The proposal here is that proto-conjunctions,
the all-purpose linking categories, evolved as a result of the pressures to consolidate
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
102 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
proto-Merge/Conjoin. Such proto-conjunctions/linkers added all-purpose segmental
glue to the already available prosodic glue characteristic of the paratactic stage,
providing now two indicators of proto-Merge, both segmental and prosodic. Two
mechanisms will necessarily yield more robust evidence for Merge than just one of
them alone (it is also possible that segmental glue (conjunction/linker) by itself
provides a more salient cohesive mechanism than prosody). It may have been only
later that such proto-coordinators/linkers differentiated into specic functional
categories, such as aspect markers, tense markers, or complementizers, as discussed
in Section 4.4.
There may have been other advantages to the emergence of (proto-)conjunctions,
such as the ability to use different types of conjunctions, not just the neutralconnective
and. As pointed out in Payne (1985:9) and references cited there, in languages such as
Vietnamese and Japanese, a coordinator is used for the adversative conjunction
comparable to English but, even though in non-adversatives the strategy involves
simple juxtaposition (parataxis) of the conjuncts,with no intervening conjunction.
13
This highlights the continuity/uidity between parataxis and coordination, as already
discussed in Section 4.2.
14
According to Payne, the paratactic strategy, where the conjunctsare simply
juxtaposed, with no additional markers of conjunction, is probably available to all
languages. This would be expected under the evolutionary scenario explored in this
book, according to which parataxis preceded, and provided the necessary scaffolding
for, both coordination and subordination structures. In many languages, such as for
example Turkish, parataxis is a normal alternative to coordination, existing side by
side with other strategies. The classical languages, including Sanskrit and Latin, also
widely use the juxtaposition (parataxis) strategy at the expense of coordination
(Payne 1985:25). The two strategies are obviously in competition, and are not at all
clearly demarcated, exactly the kind of overlap expected under an evolutionary
scenario outlined in this book.
Just a cursory look at some very common data in English can illustrate the
ambivalence and overlap between the two processes:
(33) a. The tall, elegant lady carried a heavy suitcase.
b. The tall and elegant lady carried a heavy suitcase.
13
One also nds combinations of both the neutral conjunction (and) and an adversative conjunction in
e.g. English and yet and Standard Arabic wa lakin and but,as noted in Payne (1985:15), suggesting that
the neutral coordinator can serve as a mere connector/linker, without a specied meaning.
14
There are also numerous examples across languages which seem to straddle the boundary between
parataxis and subordination/complemention. One example is serialization/complementation in Hmong
(Martha Ratliff, p.c 2013). According to Jarkey (2006:129), complementation in Hmong involves a serial-
like construction, a step along a continuum between serialization and complementation in terms of the
closeness of the juncture.Serial verbs are discussed in more detail in Section 3.4.1.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The proto-coordination stage 103
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(34) a. He read the book quickly.
b. He read the book, and quickly.
(35) a. She visited many cities, including Prague, Paris, Rome,
Trieste, Vienna.
b. She visited many cities, including Prague, Paris, Rome,
Trieste, and Vienna.
(36) a. She is tall, elegant, and ambitious.
b. She is tall and elegant and ambitious.
Such examples show that there are contexts in which one can either use a conjunction
or not, in constructions that are typically characterized as coordination (see Progovac
2003 and references there for an extensive discussion of the phenomenon). Payne and
others refer to this as a paratactic strategy for coordination, again suggesting a lack of
clear differentiation between the two. Similar ambivalence is encountered when one
tries to distinguish between coordination and subordination in some cases, as
pointed out in the next section. This would be surprising if syntax were a perfect
and optimal system, engineered from scratch, with adjunction, coordination, and
subordination each having their own specic functions. On the other hand, this
ambivalence and overlap are exactly what one expects from evolutionary tinkering, if
parataxis gradually integrated into coordination, and coordination and parataxis
gradually integrated into subordination.
Clausal conjuncts (e.g. John is here, and Mary is gone), just like adjuncts (e.g. John
is here because Mary is gone), have been repeatedly noted in current syntactic
literature not to be fully integrated into syntactic fabric (Selkirk 1978; Stowell 1981;
Nespor and Vogel 1986; Zec and Inkelas 1990). This is consistent with them sitting in
semi-integrated, non-canonical,syntactic positions, as put in An (2007). Next,
conjuncts have been analyzed in syntax as sitting on parallel planes, that is, in a
different dimension (e.g. Goodall 1987), even though this analysis is not widely
accepted (see an overview of these issues in Progovac 2003; see also Crysmann
2006 and Citko 2011).
Moreover, c-command, the central postulate of syntax, does not seem to extend
into conjuncts or adjuncts in all cases (see Progovac 2003). As discussed in
Section 4.4.5, Move targets a hierarchically higher (c-commanding) position,
so that the Moved element can structurally command/identify its trace/gap.
C-command also regulates other structural relationships, such as the one between
noun phrases and co-referring pronouns (Footnote 15), and negation and
co-dependent negative polarity items (i.e. items that must be licensed by negation,
e.g. ever). It is thus of interest that c-command does not extend seamlessly into
conjuncts and adjuncts, suggesting that conjuncts and adjuncts are not fully inte-
grated into the layers of syntax. To take one example, while it is possible to license the
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
104 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
negative polarity item ever in an embedded subordinate clause (37), it is not possible
to do so in a conjunct clause (38) or an adjunct clause (39):
15
(37) Mary did not say [that she ever met Peter]. Subordination
(38) *Mary did not say it, [but she ever met Peter]. Coordination
(cf. Mary did not say it but she never met Peter.)
(39)*Mary did not say it, [after she ever met Peter]. Adjunction
It is of note that Bruening (2014) has proposed that the principle of precedence is
relevant even for sentential grammars (see Footnote 15), and that instead of a purely
syntactic principle of c-command, one needs a conjunction of two principles:
Precede and Command. While he treats Precede as a syntactic principle, the fact
that it extends across sentence boundaries (Footnote 15) suggests that this principle
has a pragmatic source. Could it be that an ancient, pragmatic principle of prece-
dence got grammaticalized into a structural relation of c-command, whose effects are
fully observable only in the hierarchical, subordination stage? Interestingly, Bruening
proposes that this decomposition of c-command allows one to treat coordination
structures as symmetrical (352, fn. 7). According to him, what gives an effect of
asymmetry in coordinated structures is the precedence, rather than hierarchical
asymmetry of conjuncts.
In addition, several theoretical accounts invoke adjunction as an integral part of
the analysis of coordination, and/or liken it to subordination (e.g. Munn 1993;
Johannessen 1993; Kayne 1994).
16
These analyses are technical, and would take us
too far aeld to introduce them here, but the reader is referred to Progovac (2003) for
a lengthy overview of various analyses of coordination. Sufce it to say here that
theoretical analyses of coordination are not able to draw clear distinctions among
the three categories under discussion: adjunction, coordination, subordination. In
15
In a similar fashion, Principle C effects, clearly visible with subordination (i), do not seem to extend
into conjuncts (ii): while she and Mary cannot co-refer in (i), such co-reference is possible in (ii). The
judgment is less clear with an adjoined clause in (iii). To me, as well as a native speaker I consulted, it seems
that (iii) is slightly better than (i).
(i) *She
i
never mentioned [that Mary
i
is a bartender]. Subordination
(ii) She
i
never mentioned it, [but Mary
i
is a bartender]. Coordination
(iii)
?
*She
i
never mentioned it, [after Mary
i
became a bartender]. Adjunction
To complicate matters further, some Principle C effects seem to overlap with the effects of the pragmatic
precedence principle, which operates across independent sentences (iv), and can thus not be reduced to
c-command, which is a sentence-internal principle (see Progovac 2003 for discussion):
(iv)
?*
He
i
nally arrived. John
i
s cousin accompanied him.
Given this, it is not clear if it is syntactic c-command or precedence that excludes co-reference in
e.g. (i). Clearly, this issue deserves further investigation. It may be that the grammaticality status of the
examples introduced above reects a curious interplay of more than one factor, including syntactic
command and pragmatic precedence, whose domains seem to partly overlap.
16
See also Schwartz (1989a,b) for the comitative/asymmetric conjuncts.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The proto-coordination stage 105
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
several other respects as well, the conjunction is a category unlike other functional
categories, straddling the boundary between adjunction and subordination. Conside-
rations like this give credence to the gradualist evolutionary approach, for they
provide evidence of continuity and overlap among adjunction/parataxis, coordin-
ation, and subordination.
Section 4.2established that the operation Conjoin, which creates paratactic/exo-
centric structures, applies both clause-internally and between clauses. I would like to
extend this same idea to coordination, and tentatively suggest that even predication
may have, at least in some circumstances, passed through a proto-coordination
(linker) stage in the evolution of human language. The fossils of such processes are
not as easy to nd as they are for clausal combinations, but there are some construc-
tions that can be considered as such fossils. For example, German incredulity root
small clauses take an optional conjunction (see Potts and Roeper 2006; also Progovac
2006,2009b):
(40) Ich (und) Angst haben? (German)
I (and) fear have.
INF
Me afraid?!
The German small clause above seems to preserve both the paratactic option
(without a coordinator) and the coordination option, the latter just adding a mean-
ingless coordinator/linker to solidify the connection between the subject and the
predicate. In a similar fashion, Akkadian, a Semitic language spoken between c. 2,500
and 500 BC, used the coordinative particle ma in predicative functions (41), as
reported in Deutscher (2000:33f.). The absence of a verbal copula suggests the use of
root small clauses:
(41)napišti māt-im eql-um-ma
soul.of land.gen eld.nom.conj
The soul of the land is the eld.
In addition, Bowers (1993) analyzes English as as a realization of the head of
Predication Phrase, whose purpose again is merely to link the subject with the
predicate:
(42) She regards [
sc
Mary as a fool/crazy.]
Of note here is that English as (as well as Akkadian ma) can serve as glue for both
predication (interclausally, as in (41,42)) and to connect clauses (extraclausally, as in
English (43)):
17
17
It is also reported in Mous (2004:121) that Alagwa (Cushitic language spoken in Tanzania) uses the
same morpheme for both conjunctive functions and as a copula. See also Newman and Newman (1977:
212) for the in Hausa, a Chadic language spoken in Africa; also Gil (2004) for various functions of sama
in Riau Indonesian.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
106 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(43) a. Peter will be late, as will John.
b. The door opened as she was approaching.
Note also that as is used to solidify/cement predication only in small clauses, where,
arguably, there are no specied functional projections, such as TP, which can serve
the purpose. It is also worth pointing out that as in (43) seems to straddle the
boundary between a coordinator and subordinator.
In descriptions of various linguistic phenomena one nds reference to linking
words or morphemes, which do not seem to have any specic meaning. To take just
one recent example, den Dikken (2006:245) devotes his whole book Relators and
Linkers to such meaningless elements (meaningless in the sense of having no
semantic load) that play an essential role in the establishment and syntactic manipu-
lation of predication relationships.As he puts it, relators and linkers are the vital
syntactic cement of predication relationships(249). He goes on to say that all
subject-predicate relationships are mediated by such relators, whether overt or
covert.
Little words like as in English can also be seen as a kind of linker, whether it is used
to link a subject and its predicate (42), or to link two clauses (43). In its former
function it can be likened to a copula, while in the latter function it can be likened to a
conjunction, or subordinator, but the claim here is that this is a reex of a pattern
in which such distinctions were not made.
18
Moreover, as argued in e.g. Vossen
(2010:47), there is a linkerain Central Khoisan, Kalahari branch of Khoe, spoken
in southern Africa, which, at least at the synchronic level has no recognizable
meaning nor does it reveal a denite grammatical function.
19
This is so because it
is found linkingvarious kinds of grammatical elements (all-purpose linker),
including the verbal base to the following tense-aspect marker; or a verb and the
dative argument (Daniel Ross, p.c. 2013).
(44)a.xũú-wá-hã
kill-
LINKER-PRETERITE
b. gòm-á-mà
smoke-
LINKER-DATIVE
to smoke for
Heine (1986) has argued that the linker (or juncture, as it is sometimes referred to) is
a grammaticalized copula, which still exists as such in most Kalahari Khoe languages.
18
Also, the copular verb be appearing between the subject and a non-verbal predicate, as in English
John is happy, is traditionally referred to as a linking verb.This kind of verbal linker is typically absent
from small clauses (e.g. I consider John happy), and is also not used in all languages, or with all tenses in a
given language, as discussed in Chapter 7.
19
Another example of a linker is the (in)famous particle de in Chinese, as described in e.g. Cheng
(1986).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The proto-coordination stage 107
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
At the same time, Elderkin (1986) has argued that the linker derives historically from
a conjunction. Even though these two proposals seemingly compete with each other,
my approach suggests that they can both be correct: the linker was at one point the
proto-coordinator, used both to connect the subject and the predicate (copular use),
and to connect other constituents.
According to Schneider-Zioga (2013), the Bantu language Kinande, spoken in
Congo, has a linker which occurs between internal arguments (e.g. direct and indirect
objects), and sometimes between adjuncts or between an internal argument and an
adjunct. She shows that the function of this linker cannot be reduced either to a case
marker or to the distinctness condition, but rather remains just a copula, or rather a
linker, as copula is the term usually reserved for the linker between the subjects and
predicates. What these data show is that other constituents in a sentence, including
objects and adjuncts, can also be linked to the rest of the sentence via linkers/
specialized copulas.
The proposal of this chapter is that those kinds of all-purpose proto-linkers can
grammaticalize into more specialized functions, and moreover different functions in
different languages. The most prototypical of these linkers is arguably the conjunc-
tion such as and in English, which is still characterized by a signicant amount of
promiscuity and possibly by the lack of meaning above and beyond mere linking. If
one can now imagine a grammar where this kind of linker is even more promiscuous
and devoid of meaning, and which can link any two constituents, including the
subject and the predicate, then this would be the all-purpose proto-conjunction
hypothesized in this chapter. The main reason to refer to these linkers as proto-
conjunctions is that, in modern languages, conjunctions are used in more linking
functions than other (functional) words, approximating the proto-conjunction
markers better than other words.
Likewise, one nds a variety of so-called linking morphemes in compounds across
languages (e.g. linking oin speed-o-meter;Graec-o-Roman;palat-o-alveolar
in English; kiš-o-bran (rain-o-guard, umbrella); kamen-o-rezac (stone-o-carver) in
Serbian; linking sin Germanic compounds, e.g. tabak-s-rook (tobacco smell) in
Dutch; Himmel-s-tor (heavens door) in German; hunt-s-man in English. Linking o
is very common across Slavic, as well as in Greek. It is also found in Romance
languages. All these constructions may be frozen somewhere at an intermediate
proto-coordination stage, some place between parataxis and a specialized functional
category stage. Recall that the VN compounds such as pick-pocket, discussed in
Section 4.2, have no linking morphemes, and are characterized as paratactic, which
in my analysis renders them simpler, more primary than the compounds involving
linkers.
In sum, this section hypothesizes that (proto-)conjunctions/linkers may have been
among the rst functional categories to emerge, for the primary function of solidi-
fying Merge, that is, of providing more robust evidence of Merge than just prosody
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
108 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(supra-segmentals) can do. Finally, if the emergence of parataxis already proved
advantageous to our ancestors as they advanced to the rst syntactic stage, then
providing more robust and unmistakable evidence of such (proto-)syntax, by intro-
ducing linkers (coordination stage), would have constituted a clear and concrete
benet, which could have been subject to natural selection.
Section 4.5considers some corroborating evidence for a proto-coordination stage,
mostly based on language acquisition. Evidence for a proto-coordination stage at the
level of predication is not as robust as evidence for a paratactic stage. It may be that
the proto-coordination stage at the predication level was a brief, eeting stage, which
quickly led to the appearance of specic functional categories. It is also probable that
this stage was optional, that is, that not all languages/constructions needed to proceed
through this stage, as it should be possible to evolve a specic functional category
without rst evolving a conjunction-type linker (see Section 4.5). In contrast, the
paratactic stage is the foundational stage, upon which everything rests, and the
evidence for parataxis providing a scaffolding for other structures is overwhelming.
4.4The specic functional category stage
4.4.1From linkers to specic functional categories
Finally, certain categories, including linkers/conjunctions of the proto-coordination
stage, would have grammaticalized into specic functional categories, such as predi-
cation head or tense or subordinator/complementizeranother syntactic break-
through and the beginning of modern, hierarchical syntax, which can now not
only use functional words as glue to connect words/phrases/clauses, but which can
also use them to build specialized, hierarchical functional projections, such as TP and
CP. A modern functional category such as a copular verb (head of TP), or a
complementizer (head of CP), can be seen as providing not only segmental evidence
of Merge (interclausally with TPs and extraclausally with CPs), but also, simultan-
eously, an expanded structural space, which can now accommodate Move.
These specialized functional projections not only provide landing sites for Move, but
also motivation for Move. Recall from Chapters 2and 3that the subject of the clause
Moves out of the SC layer only after the TP layer is projected on top of the SC. In other
words, the SC layer by itself does not exhibit the Move of the subject. In this case at
least, syntactic theory considers that Move is driven by the need of the higher layer, TP,
to have its own subject. In some very abstract sense, then, Move serves to connect the
layers of structure, and such layers only become available in the hierarchical stage.
Another example would be the Move of the verb (V) into the light verb (v) position,
and in some languages and some circumstances the verb is taken to Move even higher,
to T or to C (see Section 4.4.5for more discussion). Likewise, the CP position is
typically the target of wh-movement, as discussed at length in Chapter 5.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The specic functional category stage 109
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
For concreteness, suppose that a linker comparable to as was used as all-purpose glue
in the proto-coordination stage, both to connect words into clauses, and to connect
clauses, as the following repeated examples from the previous section illustrate.
(45) She regards [
sc
Mary as a fool/crazy.]
(46) Peter will be late, as will John.
(47)As
she was approaching, the door opened.
In (45)as acts as a linker between a subject and its predicate; in (46)as is akin to a
conjunction, connecting two clauses; and in (47)as is more like a subordinator/
complementizer, even though the latter two functions are not clearly distinguished.
20
Now, the function (as well as the phonological shape) of this linker could have
diverged in these different positions to specialize either for predication/tense/aspect
marking, or for clause cohesion, the developments which would now signify the
beginning of the subordination stage, i.e. specic functional category stage. In this
stage, the linkers are not only there to provide segmental glue, but also to illuminate
the nature of the link (e.g. predication vs. clause combination), and to provide more
specic information about the link, such as information about present vs. past tense
in the case of predication, or causation vs. temporal event ordering in the case of
clause combination.
To appreciate the three stages, also reported in the processes of grammaticalization
of subordination in e.g. Traugott and Heine (1991) and Deutscher (2000), consider
the following examples which seem to range from least syntactically integrated (48,
parataxis), to most integrated (50, subordination), with coordination (49) straddling
the boundary between the two:
21
(48) Marc is a linguist(as) you know. Parataxis
(49) Marc is a linguist, and you know it. Coordination
(50)You know that Marc is a linguist. Subordination
20
Potts (2002) analyzes as clauses such as (i) below as syntactically quite complex, involving movement
and CP integration. In fact, he treats as in such clauses as a preposition, which selects a CP.
(i) As the FBI eventually discovered, Ames was a spy.
In contrast, others have analyzed parentheticals in general as involving a loose concatenation of two
independent sentences, which is how parataxis is often understood (e.g. Emonds 1976:523; Haegeman,
Shaer, and Frey 2009). Asher (2000) also discusses as parentheticals in this light. Resolving this issue is
beyond the scope of this book. The purpose here is only to illustrate how certain words in todays languages
might approximate multi-functional linkers, rather than to provide an in-depth analysis of English as.
21
The following example may also be seen as involving parataxis, but in a clause-internal position:
(i) Marc, (as) you know, is a linguist.
Notice that as in (48) is itself an intermediate category bridging the gap between true parataxis (without as)
and true coordination (49).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
110 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In these combinations of only two clauses, the three different syntactic strategies
for clause union result in roughly the same interpretations. This is not surprising
under the evolutionary tinkeringscenario explored in this monograph, in which
conjunctions/linkers emerge just to provide additional (segmental) evidence of
union, on top of the prosodic evidence which already characterizes parataxis.
The specied functional categories then arise, characterized by a more specic
meaning/function.
Such tinkering would have left us with multiple possibilities which partly overlap in
function, that is, with redundant means for expressing similar meanings (4850). One
wonders, then, what concrete communicative advantages might have been gained by
the subordination stage (50) over the two previous stages (48,49). The following
sections discuss this issue in relation to CP recursion (4.4.2) and DP recursion
(4.4.3), to shed light on the question of what it takes to realize recursion in syntax.
4.4.2CP and recursion
Recall from Chapter 1that I adopt the traditional characterization of recursion, also
adopted in Kinsella (2009), according to which recursion is dened as the embedding
of a constituent of a certain syntactic category (e.g. a clause/CP) within another
constitutent of the same category (another clause/CP). Traditionally, this operation is
taken to automatically apply in an unlimited fashion, given that one embedded CP
can always feature another embeded CP inside it, and so on, as in (53) below. This
was the traditional way to provethe existence of innite recursion. In other words,
recursion in this characterization has two components to it: the same category
embedding, and the unlimited reapplication of this kind of embedding. This char-
acterization coincides with what Heine and Kuteva (1987) call productive recursion,
as will be discussed in Section 4.4.3.
As it turns out, in addition to facilitating Move, including Move across clause
boundaries (see Chapter 5; Section 4.4.5), the subordination stage also provides a
recursive mechanism for embedding multiple viewpoints within one another, unavail-
able with either coordination or parataxis/adjunction, privileging in this respect (53)
over (5152).
(51) a. ?Marc is a linguist[you know,] [Mary knows].
b. Marc is a linguist[you know it,] [Mary knows it].
(52) Marc is a linguist, [and you know it,] [and Mary knows it].
(53) Mary knows [that you know [that Marc is a linguist]].
Only (53) allows one to report on one persons knowledge about another persons
knowledge, unambiguously and recursively.
As the bracketing notation indicates, while in (53) each embedded clause is an
integral part (complement/object) of the higher clause, showing subordination
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The specic functional category stage 111
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(hypotaxis), in (51) and (52) the clauses are strung next to each other (parataxis).
Kinsella (2009) discusses the distinction between iteration, characteristic of coord-
ination, and true embedded recursion. As she puts it, the difference between
iteration and recursion is this: the former involves mere repetition of an action or
object, each repetition being a separate act that can exist in its entirety apart from the
other repetitions, while the latter involves the embedding of an action or object inside
another action or object of the same type, each embedding being dependent in some
way on the action/object it is embedded inside(115).
22
In this sense, (5152) should
be analyzed as involving iteration, rather than true recursion.
However, a reviewer points out that, with some elaboration, coordination may
allow for multiple embedding of one viewpoint within another, as in the following
example, which places prosodic prominence on that:
23
(54)
?
Marc is a linguist, and you know it, and Mary knows that.
So, at least with coordination, one can nd a way to tinker with the utterance until it
expresses two levels of embedding, with the help of prosody and the alternation
between it and that referring to the main clause, as per Footnote 23.
24
But even with these tools, rst of all, the sequence in (54) does not guarantee the
interpretation in (53), as other interpretations are possible, too. Second of all, the lack
of syntactic precision becomes even more obvious when one attempts recursion
beyond the two levels. Let us show this by attempting two more levels of embedding,
contrasting the coordination strategy in (55), with the subordination strategy in (56):
(55)
?
Marc is a linguist, and you suspect it, and Mary knows that, and
Steven really believes that, and Peter wonders about that.
(56) Peter wonders [
CP
if Steven really believes [
CP
that Mary knows
[
CP
that you suspect [
CP
that Marc is a linguist]]]].
22
Kinsella further notes that, unlike iteration, embedded recursion involves keeping track or adding to
memory using a stack (116). In other words, tracking recursive structures poses a challenge to our
processing abilities the way that iteration does not, to be discussed further below in the text. This is why
it is so helpful to have a designated functional projection such as CP, which unambiguously tracks an
embedded recursive process.
23
What makes this possible in (54), but much less so in (52), is the alternation between it and that, both
of which can refer to a clause. Using the same pronoun (it) suggests that one is referring to the same main
clause (Marc is a linguist) in both cases. On the other hand, alternating it and that, and placing special
emphasis on that in the second coordinated clause, suggests that whatever it refers to, that contrasts with it,
and refers to something else. This something else can then be a combination of the rst two clauses,
although it need not, and other possibilities for the interpretation of that are certainly also available. This is
another example of an underspeciced structure, subject to vagueness.
24
To the extent to which there is a contrast in acceptability between (54) in the text and (i) below, it
might suggest that coordination is a bit more exible than plain parataxis in this respect:
(i)
??
Marc is a linguist, you know it, Mary knows that.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
112 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The more levels of embedding, the more clear it becomes that (55) is not a great
strategy for embedding multiple viewpoints one within another, while (56) is spe-
cialized to do just that, in an unambiguous and streamlined way. Whatever (55)
means, it is hard to see how it would be used successfully to express the meaning
in (56). (55) does not exhibit true recursion in the sense above.
In the same vein, in the paratactic example in (48), the two clauses should be
analyzed as occurring next to each other, loosely conjoined, in the sense of iteration,
rather than true recursion. The nature of the semantic link between the two clauses
will then be gured out pragmatically. However, if there are multiple links to gure
out, that is, multiple clauses strung together, then this becomes a processing game of
guessing, familiar from Section 3.1with examples such as No come, no money, no
shelter. In that sense, a specialized, designated functional projection such as CP,
whose processing is streamlined, can circumvent the more scattered processing
strategies associated with Conjoin (see also Section 7.3.4).
Sufce it to say here that this is exactly what evolutionary forces can operate on:
there is already a precursor to recursion, that is, a precursor to the ability to embed
one viewpoint within another, but it is only good for one or two levels of such
embedding, and it is never unambiguous. In contrast, CP subordination, which
specializes for this kind of embedding, gives rise to innite recursion, exactly because
it can circumvent the imprecise processing strategies based on Conjoin. This is the
sense in which gradual, step-by-step evolution should be understood: a new stage
does not bring about something totally new, but something just a bit more stream-
lined. The following section explores recursion associated with the Determiner
Phrase (DP).
4.4.3DP and recursion
In addition to recursion associated with CP embedding, recursion is also often
illustrated for English with possessive structures, such as:
(57) a) Peters brother
b) Peters brothers cat
c) Peters brothers cats toy
Here, one DP (Peters) is embedded within another DP (Peters brother), which in
turn is embedded within another DP (Peters brothers cat), and so on, illustrating a
true recursive process that can keep going. It exhibits both of the elements of the
traditional characterization of recursion: the same category condition, and the
potential for unlimited reapplicability. And from the point of view of an English
speaker, this may seem like no big dealof course you can keep embedding one
possessive within another, and why not conclude from there that this is just
unbounded, recursive Merge at work? And why not also conclude that the recursive
Merge here reects our recursive cognitive abilities?
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The specic functional category stage 113
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Interestingly, however, Heine and Kuteva (2007) introduce a distinction between
productive recursion, as attested with English possessives (57), which can apply
multiple times, and one-level recursion (simple recursion), which can only apply
once, which they illustrate with German possessives (58):
(58) a) Peters Bruder
b) *Peters Bruders Auto
Despite great surface similarities between the two languages, German possessive
structures of this kind cannot be repeatedly embedded one within the other, and
the question is why not?Given the characterization of recursion I am adopting, the
German example does not in fact involve recursion: one of the two conditions is
clearly not met: the unbounded nature of recursion.
This in itself should be enough to illustrate that just having Merge is not enough to
guarantee recursion, and that there is crosslinguistic variation even between closely
related languages in this respect. It must be that English and German are using
different syntactic strategies to the same end: one happens to be recursive, and the
other is not. While determining exactly what these different syntactic strategies are is
an ongoing topic in syntactic theory, the discussion in the previous section suggests
that what Heine and Kuteva (2007) call simple recursion may be a symptom of a
paratactic (iterative) strategy, rather than true embedded recursion (see also
Section 4.5.1.1for parataxis which can be mistaken for subordination in PIE).
To complicate matters further, Serbian, just like German, does not show recursion
of possessives (59), even though it is possible to express one level of possession (60):
(59) *Milenina mamina knjiga. / *moja mamina knjiga.
Milenas mothers book my mothers book
(60)a.
Milenina mama moja mama
Milenas mother my mother
b. mamina knjiga moja knjiga
mothers book my book
In line with the idea that recursion needs to be facilitated by specic functional
projections, Bošković(2008, and subsequent work) has proposed that Serbian does
not have a DP, which correlates with the lack of denite articles such as the in
Serbian. This analysis is controversial, but if true, then Serbian cannot use the same
DP-within-DP strategy that is used in English for possessives. Instead, Bošković
analyzes the possessive in Serbian as an adjective adjoined to an NP. This would
then render the possessive attachment close to the Conjoin/Adjoin strategy, i.e. to the
iterative strategy in the sense of Kinsella (2009).
According to Bošković(2008), the reason why Milenina mamina cannot form an
Adjective Phrase (AP) which adjoins to the NP is because adjectives cannot modify
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
114 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
other adjectives. In other words, Milenina is not interpreted as being inside the
phrase headed by mamina in (61), but rather as being next to it, and can thus not
yield true recursion, in contrast to English (62):
(61)*[
NP
[
?
Milenina mamina [
NP
knjiga]]] (Serbian)
(62)[
DP
[
DP
[
DP
Peters] brothers] [
NP
car]] (English)
Even though German has denite articles, and is thus analyzable as a DP language, it
is possible that German uses a similar adjectival strategy for possessives, and treats
them as adjoined to an NP.
(63)*[
DP
[
NP
[
?
Peters Bruders] [
NP
Auto]]] (German)
One can see that the structure in (62) is truly recursive, as far as syntax is concerned,
because it involves a repeated insertion of one DP within another. However, the
structures in (61) and (63) are not recursive in this way, as they do not involve one DP
embedded within another DP, but an adjective adjoined to an NP, a paratactic
strategy.
It seems that all hierarchical phenomena considered so far have an alternate,
paratactic route, including CP subordination and DP possessive expression. As
pointed out in Chapter 3with respect to serial verb constructions (Section 3.4.1),
even transitivity can be expressed with an alternative, paratactic strategy (as opposed
to a hierarchical strategy). This is consistent with the proposal in this book that
parataxis provided, and continues to provide, a foundation and a precursor for
building hierarchical structures. The emergence of transitivity and TP layering will
be futher discussed in Chapter 7.
4.4.4Benets of subordination
As discussed in the previous subsections, recursive syntactic mechanisms have two
basic advantages over parataxis and coordination: (i) they allow more levels of
(recursive) embedding, and (ii) they provide a more precise, unambiguous mechan-
ism for expressing recursive thoughts. Of course, the hierarchical stage in general has
many additional advantages, including the ability to streamline the expression of
transitivity and tense marking, as further discussed in Chapter 7.
The subordination stage, a hierarchical, specic functional category stage, can thus
be characterized as a stage that facilitates Move, as well as provides a mechanism for
true recursion. As pointed out above, at an abstract level, one important function of
Move is to connect the layers of hierarchical structure (Section 4.4.5). However, it is
important to keep in mind that only those constructions that have reached this
hierarchical level can be recursive and subject to Move. Recall the proposal that
sentences in modern languages are composite structures, potentially incorporating
constructions of all three stages:
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The specic functional category stage 115
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(64) As you may recall, her having left, Peter decided that he wanted
to buy a new house, but not in California.
Preceding the main clause (Peter decided . . . ), there is an adjoined full TP/CP
adjunct/parenthetical (as you may recall), followed by an adjoined small clause
adjunct (her having left), both attached paratactically by Adjoin/Conjoin. The main
clause contains a fully subordinated clause (CP), which moreover features coordin-
ation inside it (that he wants to buy a new house, but not in California). As discussed
in Chapter 5, Move is typically not possible out of adjuncts and conjuncts, adjunction
and coordination being the most notorious islands for movement. In Chapter 5
I argue that these island/Subjacency effects are epiphenomena of evolutionary tin-
kering, more precisely, of having such rigid, Move-less structures co-exist side by side
more modern structures.
It is also worth pointing out here that the lack of recursion cannot be attributed to
cognitive capabilities, or rather to the lack thereof. Just as it was pointed out with
respect to the lack of recursion with small clauses, the inability to express true
recursion with parataxis and coordination has nothing to do with the speakers
cognitive abilities, and everything to do with the structure of these constructions.
The claim in this monograph is that the kind of functional structure which enables
recursion evolved gradually in the evolution of human language, although it did not
emerge with every single construction in every single language (see also Heine and
Kuteva 2007).
In this respect, both German and Serbian speakers must be cognitively capable of
recursive thought, given that they make use of recursion elsewhere, and yet their
possessive structures, as discussed in Section 4.4.3are not recursive. It cannot be that
language is just a passive reection of thought, equipped with an unbounded Merge,
so that, if you can only think an unbounded thought, it will allow you to express it
through recursive syntactic means. Instead, language is patched together from
various bits and pieces to rst allow paratactic precursors to recursion, and then, in
some special cases, unlimited recursion.
25
This shows that a language can have
hierarchical syntax and Merge in the sense of Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch (2002),
but there is still some tinkering to do before recursion in the traditional sense can
emerge.
Also consistent with the considerations in this chapter are reports that some
modern languages do not make use of nite subordination (e.g. Dixon 1994 for
Dyirbal; Mithun 1984,2010 for various Native American languages). Most recently,
Everett (2005) has argued that Pirahã lacks recursion both in the domain of CP
25
It is, of course, misleading to talk here about precursors to recursion, as if German and Serbian and
Pirahã (see below) strategies are somehow unstable and awaiting recursion. It is only from the point of view
of how recursion comes about that these strategies can be seen as precursors.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
116 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
subordination and in the domain of possessive recursion, the conclusion also echoed
in Sakel and Staperts work (e.g. 2010); see also Piantadosi et al.2012).
26
Newmeyer
(2005:1701) also leaves the door open for languages to lack subordination, suggest-
ing that this may be correlated with the lack of literacy, considering that CP
subordination is mostly used in written texts, and very rarely in everyday conversa-
tion. This can serve as a partial answer to a reviewers question concerning why a
human language would not have CP or clausal embedding, if human brains are
capable of it.
27
4.4.5Possible precursors to Move
As established so far, the proposed fossils of the paratactic (non-hierarchical) stage
are not subject to Move. This is not at all surprising given that Move in the theoretical
framework associated with Minimalism has to take a constitutent in a certain
syntactic position and raise it to a hierarchically higher (c-commanding) position,
so that the raised constituent can hierarchically dominate its trace or copy left in the
original position. To put it slightly differently, in order to posit that there is a gap (left
by Move) in a certain syntactic position, there has to be an automatic, grammatical-
ized way to identify the position and nature of the gap by a higher constitutent, and
this kind of command relationship (c-command) is only relevant for hierarchical
grammars (see also Section 4.3). Nonetheless, there might be precursors to Move in
this paratactic stage, or rather structures that can provide the basis for Move.
One relatively straightforward case would involve a transition from a hypothetical
paratactic serial verb sequence (Section 3.4.1) of the kind in (65), to vP transitivity of
the accusative type, such as (66).
28
(65)a)[
SC
Woman push], [
SC
man fall]
b) [
SC
Girl roll], [
SC
ball roll]
26
The analysis of Pirahã, as proposed in Everett (2005), has been contested by e.g. Nevins, Pesetsky, and
Rodrigues (2009) and references there, and is, in general, surrounded by a lot of unpleasant controversy
(see e.g. the characterization by Pullum 2012, and the comments there).
27
In this respect, it is important to keep in mind that, whether in evolution in general or in language
change, an innovation is typically due to chance, and is not predetermined or predestined. While human
beings are capable in principle of inventing a wheel, not all cultures have done that, and certainly not all
individuals. We often pose these negative questions, such as how come this language or person does not
have this? Or why do certain constructions lack Move? Or, why do certain constructions lack recursive
subordination? Or why do some languages lack DP? In fact, on this evolutionary approach, the questions to
be posed are of the opposite kind: why is it that certain constructions have Move (Chapter 5), and why is it,
and what kind of circumstances needed to be met, for some constructions to become recursive, and for
languages to acquire a DP? And what does it take to invent a wheel? For the absence of such rather bizarre
phenomena as far as nature is concerned is much easier to understand than their existence.
28
As pointed out in Footnote 25, these can be considered as precursors only from the point of view of
the vP accusative structures, which needed that foundation. But these structures are supported by coherent
grammars, which can be stable.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The specic functional category stage 117
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(66)a)[
vP
Woman push [
VP/ SC
man push]]
b) [
vP
Girl roll [
VP/ SC
ball roll]]
The second small clause in the vP structure (66) is now inserted into the higher
clause, rather than being next to it (65), which is what creates hierarchy and
subordination. In the syntactic theory I am following, the idea is that the lower
verb Moves from the position of V into the higher verb position, light v, leaving
behind a gap, which is now identied by the higher verb. In this case, the postulated
Move accompanies the building of hierarchical structure, whereby the Moved ele-
ment travels through the layers of structure, providing cohesion among them. This
kind of Move seems purely grammatical, without leading to a different semantic or
pragmatic interpretation.
Another instance of purely grammatical Move would be the Move of the subject of
the SC into the layer of TP in English, as discussed in Chapter 2. Suppose that we start
with a hypothetical paratactic sequence in (67), to arrive at the hierarchical structure
in (68), in which the initial verb go has been grammaticalized into a future tense
particle, a common occurrence in grammaticalization. Here, the repeated instance of
boy can be interpreted as a trace/copy of Move, and thus deleted.
(67)[
SC
Boy go], [
SC
boy hunt]
(68)[
TP
Boy go [
VP/SC
boy hunt]]
As pointed out before, what seems to be captured by Move is the observation that
some word or phrase is relevant/interpreted in more than one position in a sentence.
In some sense, then, Move is an epiphenomenon of the modest, two-word beginnings
of syntax, which could not accommodate all the arguments, or the temporal infor-
mation, into a single clause. Instead, these types of information can only be provided
in separate layers, and Move is that kind of operation which can, metaphorically
speaking, run through all these layers, providing syntactic cohesion.
Syntactic theory also postulates Move in cases where the motivation for Move
seems to be pragmatic, for the purposes of foregrounding or backgrounding. To take
just one example, consider the case of topicalization:
(69) Mary, I dont like Mary.
Here, Mary is taken to have Moved from its original object position to the left
periphery of the clause (possibly to CP) in order to serve as a topic of the sentence.
It is possible that such topicalization structures also have paratactic precursors, which
do not involve Move, such as (70) below, typically referred to as left-dislocation:
(70) Mary, I dont like her.
The attachment of Mary in (70) could be by adjunction or parataxis (see e.g.
Haegeman, Shaer, and Frey 2009). What is important here is that the position of
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
118 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Mary in (70) is typically not analyzed as a result of Move, given that there is no gap in
the rest of the sentence, but rather there is a (resumptive) pronoun her, which refers
back to Mary. In any event, the kind of Move postulated for (69) can only charac-
terize the stage of hierarchical syntax in which there is at least a TP, but possibly also
a CP, to provide a hierarchically higher landing site for Move.
When it comes to Move, McDaniel (2005) considers that protohumans initially
produced long, uent, unstructured strings of words (e.g. 71), essentially Bickertons
(1990) protolanguage, but more uent. According to McDaniel, when syntax xed
the order (72), it was no longer possible to topicalize an object (e.g. baby), but this
becomes possible again if Move is introduced (73). The repetition of arguments
characteristic of protolanguage can be reinterpreted as copies of Move, and thus
provide a precursor for Move (see also the discussion in Bickerton 2012; Tallerman
2014b).
(71) baby tree leopard baby baby kill
(72) leopard tree kill baby
(73) baby [leopard tree kill baby]
At least given the theoretical framework associated with Minimalism, two conditions
would need to be met in order for (73) to constitute Move: rst, as McDaniel suggests,
there would be deletion of the lower copy (avoidance of repetition); and, second,
hierarchical structure would already have to be in place in order to be possible to
syntactically identify the gap, as per the discussion above. For example, in order to
postulate a gap in the object position in (73), one needs to be certain that this is in fact
a transitive (vP) structure in the rst place, given that an intransitive absolutive-like
structure would not have an object position. Likewise, in order for baby to be able to
c-command the gap in the object position, this already would have to be hierarchical
syntax, with baby appearing in the highest layer.
In this respect, it is also important to point out that any permutations of word
order in the two-word stage (e.g. Ball roll vs. Roll ball) cannot be considered as Move
in the technical sense of Move, as discussed above. Instead, these kinds of permuta-
tions would need to be considered as just instances of a single application of the
operation Conjoin, which does not impose linear ordering on the constituents.
29
In
this sense as well, Conjoin is like Adjoin in that it can exhibit different word
orderings without implicating syntactic Move (e.g. Adger 2003). Thus, the adverbs
29
As such, different orderings could be used for different discourse purposes of backgrounding or
foregrounding, but they could not be considered to instantiate Move. In this respect, Hurford (2012)
considers that Move is driven by the desire to change the information structure, for example to express
topicalization, new vs. old information, questions, etc. Given my approach, Move can serve these purposes
only at a much later stage, necessarily hierarchical, as per the discussion in the text.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The specic functional category stage 119
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
below are not analyzed as involving Move, but rather just attachment in different
syntactic positions.
(74) a) Unfortunately, they will have to retire.
b) They will have to retire, unfortunately.
(75) a) They quickly extinguished the re.
b) They extinguished the re quickly.
In other words, not every permutation of constituents is analyzed as syntactic
Move, but only those instances in which a constituent travels upwards through
(c-commanding) hierarchical layers.
4.4.6Transitions and overlaps
Given this gradualist view, one can expect to nd transitional constructions, those
straddling the boundary between coordination and subordination, and such con-
structions are not difcult to nd (see Section 4.3for the overlap between parataxis
and coordination). In addition to as illustrated there, there are other words that are
difcult to classify as either coordinators or subordinators. In the examples below,
but is analyzed as a coordinator, and although as a subordinator. Notice, however,
that although introduces an adjunct clause, rather than a clause truly subordinated
into the matrix clause, once again showing a curious interplay among adjunction,
coordination, and subordination.
(76) He wants to get married again, but this time not in Las Vegas.
(77) He wants to get married again, although this time not in Las Vegas.
To take another example, the most neutral, prototypical of conjunctions, and, can
sometimes express subordinating relationships, as discussed in e.g. Culicover and
Jackendoff (2005).
(78) a. Give him an inch, and he will take an ell.
(Oxford English Dictionary)
b. Speak one word, and you are a dead man!
(Oxford English Dictionary)
c. One more can of beer and I am leaving.
(Culicover and Jackendoff 2005:474)
In (78) above, the relationship between the two clauses is best paraphrased as
involving a conditional, ifthen relationship. Culicover and Jackendoff (2005:474)
call this use of and left-subordinating and.In this use, and can be seen as a pure
linker/proto-conjunction, linking two clauses. Recall from Section 4.2that paratactic
clause combinations without any linkers (e.g. Nothing ventured, nothing gained) also
get interpreted as involving causal or conditional relations.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
120 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
More recently, Ross (2013) has argued that English and has undergone a grammat-
icalization process froma conjunction to a subordinator/complementizer in e.g. the try
and type of constructions (I will try and do that). He ties this with comparable
processes of grammaticalization observed in e.g. !Xun (southern African Khoisan
language), in which conjunctions become subordinators (Heine and Kuteva 2002:44):
(79) /oa tcí ta a #èhi
he neg come and he
PROG
be.sick
He doesnt come (because) he is sick.
A similar process has been observed in Tok Pisin, English-based Creole spoken in Papua
New Guinea (Verhaar 1995), as illustrated in the following example from Ross (2013):
(80) Em (i) tra-im na help-im mi.
He
PRED
try-
TRANS
and help-
TRANS
me
He tries/tried to help me.
Even within the subordination stage, one nds a variety of clausal subordination
types, with differing degrees of cohesion between clauses. These types of clausal
subordination range from those that involve most syntactic structure, nite subor-
dination with a CP (Complementizer Phrase) (8182), to those which involve the
least structure, a small clause (8384), abstracting away from intermediate cases, such
as innitive clauses (see Progovac 2009c, 2010a).
(81) Mary believes [that he fell off his motorcycle].
(82) Mary believes [that John knows [that the neighbors noticed [that he
fell off his motorcycle]]].
(83) Let [it rain].
Peter saw [Mike fall].
I consider [the problem solved].
(84) ?I will let [John imagine [Peter see [Mike fall off his
motorcycle]]].
In contrast to nite (CP) subordination, which is fully recursive in the sense that one
clause can be embedded inside another, potentially ad innitum (82), small clause
recursion seems to be somewhat more limited in this sense, as the marginal status of
(84) suggests. Of note is that the subjects of embedded SCs have a structural (case)
relationship with the matrix verb, the so-called ECM case, suggested by the required
adjacency with the verb (no intervening adverbials) (85), and by the required
determiner (86).
30
30
The label ECM (Exceptional Case Marking) is due to the observation that the verb here assigns
structural case to a noun phrase which is not its object. Structural case is a grammatical case assigned to a
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The specic functional category stage 121
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(85) * Peter saw yesterday [Mike fall].
*I consider crucially [the problem solved].
(86) I consider [*(the) problem solved].
I consider [*(the) class in session].
Both types of embedding exploit some functional glue to cementthe relationship
between the two clauses: complementizers/subordinators (82) or structural case (84).
Complementizer glue is more specialized (only used for nite subordination), while
structural case is used for other purposes as well. This may be one reason why
recursion is freer with nite subordination (see also Deutscher 2000). In other
words, it may be that nite subordination allows recursion more freely because it is
more unambiguously marked for embedding than are ECM small clauses (see also
discussion in Section 4.4.2).
Thus, it seems that recursion itself is not an all-or-nothing phenomenon. Very
roughly speaking, extrapolating from the discussion in this section, as well as
previous chapters, recursion is structurally impossible without hierarchical func-
tional structure; it can be limitless with highly specialized functional categories
such as nite complementizers; and it is possible, although not limitless, with other
types of structures, such as ECM.
The conclusion emerges that recursion is not just a ubiquitous omnipresent
phenomenon, which comes to language free with Merge, but rather it is a conse-
quence of fairly elaborate syntactic structure, which may be present in some, but not
other, language constructions. As pointed out in the previous sections, the absence
of recursion with a particular structure in a particular language is not an indicator
of a general cognitive (in)ability, but rather just an indicator of the less elaborated
syntax.
Finally, the functional category stage introduced in this section may have wit-
nessed more ne-grained sub-stages. Perhaps there was a stage in which aspect was
grammaticalized, but not yet tense (see also the discussion of PIE in the following
section; also Progovac 2008a,b for Serbian small clauses). Perhaps there was a stage in
which TP could be built, but not yet CP (see also Chapters 3and 7for the vP
projection and transitivity). Perhaps gender/number agreement (e.g. on participles)
emerged before person agreement (see Progovac 2008a,b). In this respect, Boeckx
(2008:119) suggests that the Minimalist operation Agree may have emerged after
Merge. But my primary focus in this chapter is on the three rough syntactic stages, as
well as on envisioning what proto-grammars looked like in the initial stages, as well
as how these initial stages may have penetrated into the subsequent stages gradually
noun phrase (or DP) by e.g. a verb or a preposition in a certain syntactic conguration, often requiring
adjacency. DP is considered to be required for structural case in e.g. English and Italian (Longobardi 1994;
see also Chapter 2), which helps explain why the articles are obligatory in (86). For an elaborate argument
with regard to small clauses in this respect, see Progovac (2006).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
122 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
paving the way toward layered/hierarchical and recursive syntax. My purpose was
also to show how postulating these stages can shed light on the quirks and complex-
ities of present-day syntax (see also Chapter 5on Subjacency).
4.5Corroborating evidence
4.5.1Corroborating evidence for the paratactic stage
There is abundance of corroborating evidence for a paratactic stage in the evolution
of human language, coming from e.g. ancient languages (4.5.1.1), grammaticalization
processes (4.5.1.2), animal communication (4.5.1.3), agrammatism (4.5.1.4), neurosci-
ence (4.5.1.5), and language acquisition (4.5.1.6).
4.5.1.1Ancient languages While ancient languages are typically considered to be
full modern languages in the sense of language evolution, I consider them separately
here rst because they are no longer spoken, and second because they just might have
preserved more syntactic fossils than present-day languages. Here I merely list some
of these fossil properties reported in the literature, leaving their evolutionary signi-
cance for future research.
Kiparsky (1968) has argued convincingly that PIE syntax was characterized by
optional adverbial temporal particles, which did not build TPs. Such adverbs may
have been attached by Conjoin (or Adjoin). Similarly, when it comes to clause
combination in PIE, according to Kiparsky (1995:155) (see also Hale 1987; Watkins
1976; Hock 1989), a major characteristic, best preserved in Sanskrit, Hittite, and
Old Latin, was that nite subordinateclauses were not embedded but adjoined.
Kiparsky further argues that IE protolanguage lacked the category of complementizer
and had no CP or any syntactically embedded sentences. What looked like nite
subordinate clauses, including relative clauses and sentential complements, were
syntactically adjoined to the main clause, still exhibiting main clause properties, such
as topicalization of constituents to clause-initial position. Kiparsky (1995:145) calls
these adjoined nite clauses embedded root clauses,for they exhibit properties of
root clauses, and yet seem to be interpreted as embedded. According to Kiparskys
analysis, these correspond to the paratactic attachment, which does not yield recursion.
Kiparsky further claims that the introduction of complementizers coincided with
the shift from adjunction to subordination, which is in line with Kaynes(1982) claim
that only CPs can function as true sentential arguments, i.e. as embedded clauses (see
also Holmberg 1986; Taraldsen 1986). If true, then ancient languages, such as PIE, as
well as Akkadian, as discussed in the previous section, can provide additional access
to evolutionary fossils of language.
4.5.1.2Grammaticalization
31
As already pointed out, the outlined progression of
stages is consistent with the grammaticalization processes observed in recent times:
31
Section 7.3.5discusses why historical change may be of interest to evolutionary considerations.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence 123
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
e.g. transitions from paratactic to subordinate relationships are observed even in
present-day languages. According to e.g. Deutscher (2000) and Traugott and Heine
(1991), the grammaticalization of nite subordination typically takes parataxis as a
starting point. Mithun (2010) offers several examples from a variety of languages,
illustrating the uidityof recursion, in the sense that not all languages exhibit it in
all possible constructions. Her ndings support the idea that subordination often
arises from parataxis, and that parataxis is still used in some languages as the main
strategy for clause combination, utilizing intonation as the primary glue. The fol-
lowing example from Mohawk illustrates two independent clauses used in a
sequence, but pronounced as a single intonational contour, beginning with a high
pitch reset and descending to a nal fall only at the end of the second clause
(Mithun 2010:24):
32
(87) Iah kithe: tehoterièn:tarenaa:wenne.
not in.fact at.all did he know (it) so it happened
In fact, he did not know it. It so happened.
In English, a preferred way to express this would be by using subordination, as in (88)
below. But the use of parataxis in English is still widely attested, as the example in
(89) shows.
(88) In fact, he did not know [what happened].
(89) You know that. Marc is a linguist.
Such paratactic combinations of independent sentences into a single intonation unit
often result in the grammaticalization of demonstratives into complementizers. All
that needs to happen in (89) is for the demonstrative that to be reanalyzed as
introducing the following clause (90), rather than ending the previous clause, and
this is in fact a very frequent source of complementizers/subordinators, according to
e.g. Heine and Kuteva (2007) and references there:
(90) You know [that Marc is a linguist].
If this kind of progression from parataxis to subordination is a natural process that
occurs even in present times, then this is certainly not an implausible scenario for the
evolution of human language.
4.5.1.3Comparative studies: Animal communication Given that parataxis involves
no markers of Merge other than intonation/prosody, it is also of interest here that
32
It is in fact a traditional view in historical linguistics that subordination (hypotaxis) develops from
parataxis (juxtaposition, coordination), advocated in e.g. Schlegel (1808), Bauer (1833), Delbrück (18931900),
among many others (see e.g. Harrisand Campbell 1995 for criticism of this view, as well asfor many additional
references). Harris and Campbell conclude, however, that subordinate clauses originated in relatively recent
times (308).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
124 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
intonation and prosody, which are modulated analogically, rather than discretely,
have been proposed by many to have been available before syntax proper, given that
they seem to have analogs in other species (see e.g. Deacon 1997; Piattelli-Palmarini
and Uriagereka 2004; Burling 2005), and given that prosody emerges early in
language acquisition (Section 4.5.1.6)
33
According to Deacon (1997), speech prosody
is essentially a mode of communication that provides a parallel channel to speech; it
is recruited from ancestral call functions.
34
Like these systems, prosodic features are
primarily produced by the larynx and lungs, and not articulated by the mouth and
tongue. But unlike calls of other species, prosodic vocal modication is continuous
and highly correlated with the speech process (Deacon 1997:418).
35
The human
larynx must be controlled from higher brain systems involved in skeletal muscle
control, not just visceral control (243).
According to Deacon, it is as though we have not so much shifted control from
visceral to voluntary means but superimposed intentional cortical motor behaviors
over autonomous subcortical vocal behaviors. If this is on the right track, then this
would be another scenario consistent with the theme of this monograph, which is
that older strategies got integrated into more recent ones, rather than got replaced by
them, resulting in composite structures.
There have also been numerous reports that primates can combine two signs into a
meaningful utterance, even though, as pointed out by reviewers, the interpretations
of these ndings are controversial. The problem seems to be that primates usually
produce a stream of signs without much evidence for cohesion (e.g. Kanzi, a bonobo,
as reported in Savage-Rumbaugh and Lewin 1994). The question then is whether
there are at least some sporadic attempts to put some of these signs together into
meaningful units. It has been reported that Washoe, a chimpanzee who learned how
to use signs of American Sign Language, combined the signs for water and bird to
describe a duck (Gardner, Gardner, and van Cantfort 1989). Kanzi has been reported
to be able to combine a lexigram and a gesture into a meaningful unit (Greeneld and
Savage-Rumbaugh 1990:161), as discussed in Section 3.5.
Washoes and Kanzis ability to combine two elements into a meaningful unit
should not be taken to mean that they are using compounds or small clauses in the
same productive way that humans do today. Clearly, the use of such combinations by
non-humans is rare and sporadic. The relevant question here is not whether Washoe
reached a two-word or hierarchical stage of language, but rather whether our
33
In addition, intonation and prosody may remain intact even in cases of various kinds of aphasia (e.g.
Brain and Bannister 1992; Pulvermüller 2002; and references cited there).
34
Affective prosody has been reported to be strikingly similar in humans and other primates so that
human subjects having no previous experience with monkeys correctly identify the emotional content of
their screams (Linnankoski et al.1994; Kotchoubey 2005:136; see also Hurford 2007:282).
35
This is also consistent with Tyler and Warrens(1987) experimental nding that comprehension is
affected by disrupting either syntactic or prosodic structure (Section 4.1).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence 125
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
common ancestors were in principle capable of combining two signs. This kind of
basic ability, if it was there at the relevant juncture, would have greatly facilitated the
transition from the one-word stage to the two-word stage. In order for the selection
process to get off the ground, at least some of our common ancestors should have
been capable of producing and understanding such combinations. Those who were
just a bit better at it would have been the ones whose genes were passed on in the line
of descent leading to humans. It is important to point out that any continuity with
other primates is not to be sought in the most advanced features of human syntax,
such as recursive CPs or DPs, but rather in the most rudimentary of syntactic
structures, such as two-word paratactic combinations.
One important consequence of the syntactic reconstruction offered in this book is
that it decomposes syntax down to its most modest beginnings, revealing where
continuity with the abilities of non-humans is likely to be found. In this respect,
consider Yangs(2013) study discussed in Section 2.5.1. It compares childrens com-
binations of articles (aand the) and nouns, with the sign combinations by non-
human primates, of the kind give X,ormore X. It is not clear to me how these
structures are comparable, given that articles are highly abstract functional categories
(associated with DPs), late to emerge in children (e.g. Radford 1990), as well as in the
grammaticalization processes (e.g. Heine and Kuteva 2007). Recall also from
Section 4.4.3that articles are not even available in all human languages. In any
event, this monograph suggests that continuity can only be expected with the most
rudimentary of syntactic structures. But even there, as pointed out above, one does
not expect human-like uency with two-word combinationsnot at all. After all,
humans had millions of years to undergo selection for language since the common
ancestor with chimpanzees. All one can hope to nd in this respect is a precursor to
the ability to combine signs.
4.5.1.4Agrammatism As discussed in Chapter 2, agrammatism offers another
source of corroborating evidence for small clause grammars, which are arguably
paratactic grammars. Consistent with the conclusion that agrammatic patients often
resort to small clause grammars, one expects them also to have difculties with
embedding and recursion.
As found in e.g. Friedmann and Grodzinsky (1997), the use of subordination/CP is
also affected in the speech production of agrammatic aphasia, which typically
involves a lesion in the left inferior frontal gyrus (see also Friedmann 2002). While
the speakers in their study could produce simple sentences, they failed to produce
embedded sentences in sentence repetition and sentence elicitation tasks, as well as in
spontaneous speech. The study concludes that these agrammatics cannot project
their syntactic trees up to the CP node (their Tree-Pruning Hypothesis). This is
expected if agrammatics often resort to paratactic small clause grammars, with as few
functional projections as possible.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
126 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In addition, a recent neuroimaging study found that sentences with CPs involve
more activation in multiple loci, including Brocas area, in comparison to those
without a CP (Shetreet, Friedmann, and Hadar 2009). The authors concluded that
the generation of syntactic layers is cognitively costly, which is fully compatible with
the proposal explored in this monograph.
4.5.1.5Neuroscience Recent computational and brain-imaging work is consistent
with the notions explored in this book. To take one example, a PET study by
Indefrey, Brown et al.(2001) indicates that non-nite clauses do indeed require less
grammatical work. These authors presented German-speaking participants with
pictures of simple colored objects (squares, circles, and ellipses) in different spatial
congurations. The task of the participants was to describe the pictures, using one of
three different sentence formats. In the full-sentence condition, they had to produce a
full grammatical sentence, containing all relevant information (e.g. Das rote Viereck
stößt die blaue Ellipse weg the red square pushes the blue ellipse away). In the noun
phrase condition, they were required to use a non-nite phrase and to leave out the
determiner (e.g. Rotes Viereck, blaue Ellipse, wegstoßen red square, blue ellipse,
pushing away). In the word condition, participants were also required to produce
sub-sentential forms, but this time they needed to omit the inection of the adjective
and put the adjective after the noun (e.g. Viereck rot, Ellipse blau, wegstoßen square
red, ellipse blue, pushing away). The latter two strategies involve paratactic attach-
ment, and not fully integrated syntax. The blood ow response varied as expected
between these conditions in the left operculum, a region just behind Brocas area:
maximal response in the full-sentence condition, less strong in the noun phrase
condition, and less strong still in the word condition.
It is also of some interest that the data introduced in this monograph, the living
fossilsof the paratactic stage, are characteristically formulaic/stereotypical expres-
sions (e.g. Case closed; Me rst; Nothing ventured, nothing gained). According to e.g.
Code (2005:317), non-propositional, stereotypical/formulaic uses of language might
represent fossilized clues to the evolutionary origins of human communication, given
that their processing involves more ancient processing patterns, including more
involvement of the basal ganglia, thalamus, limbic structures, and the right hemi-
sphere (see e.g. Lieberman 2000 for an extensive argument that subcortical struc-
tures, basal ganglia in particular, play a crucial role in syntax). According to Ullman
(2006:4801), Brocas area is part of a larger circuit that involves the basal ganglia,
with the two parts of the brain densely interconnected. Basal-limbic structures are
phylogentically old and the aspects of human communication associated with them
are considered to be ancient too (van Lancker and Cummings 1999; Bradshaw 2001).
The Appendix returns to this discussion.
Moreover, the proposals in this monograph are vulnerable to empirical verica-
tion. Neuroimaging experiments can be devised in such a way as to distinguish
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence 127
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
between paratactic (small clause) structures and hierarchical structures, as explored
in the Appendix (see also Chapter 2).
4.5.1.6Acquisition As discussed in Chapter 2, syntax in language acquisition seems
to begin with a root small clause stage (or root innitive stage), arguably a two-word
paratactic stage. Early stages of second language acquisition have been analyzed in a
similar fashion (see e.g. Klein and Purdues1997 Basic Variety). Also, as shown in e.g.
Hua and Dodd (2000), prosody emerges early in language acquisition. On the other
hand, subordination, as well as Move, are rather late developments in children, as
reported in numerous references (e.g. Radford 1990; Lebeaux 1989; Ouhalla 1991;
Platzak 1990; Potts and Roeper 2006; Hollebrandse and Roeper 2007). This is
consistent with the claim in this monograph that subordination and Move are
unavailable in the paratactic stage.
4.5.2Corroborating evidence for a proto-coordination stage
Evidence for a proto-coordination stage is not nearly as robust as evidence for a
paratactic stage. It is entirely possible that the proto-coordination stage was a brief
stage, which quickly led to grammaticalization of specic functional categories. This
stage also must have been optional in the sense that not all languages/constructions
had to pass through it. Recall from Section 4.5.1.2that subordinators often gram-
maticalize from demonstratives and verbs like say, rather than from pure linkers (see
e.g. Heine and Kuteva 2007). The coordination stage may have been only a detour, a
direction taken only in some circumstances.
One piece of corroborating evidence for a coordination stage may come from
instances where grammaticalization of e.g. nite subordination proceeds through a
(n intermediate) coordination stage (see e.g. Deutscher 2000; Traugott and Heine
1991; and references cited there). While the references above often speak of coordi-
nation even where there is no overt coordinator, there are some concrete proposals
according to which an overt coordinator grammaticalizes into a subordinator.
36
For
example, according to Harris and Campbell (1995:290), conditional marker da in
Mingrelian, language spoken in Western Georgia, comes from the conjunction and.
Likewise, it is frequently reported in language acquisition literature that some
children use llersin places where one would expect functional categories. While
researchers sometimes attribute the presence of such llers to the presence of specic
functional categories, a more conservative approach is that these are just connectors
(proto-conjunctions or linkers), serving to connect words into phrases/clauses (see
e.g. Peters 1999; Peters and Menn 1993; Veneziano and Sinclair 2000; and references
36
As discussed in detail in this chapter, various languages and constructions do not mark with
conjunctions what can be considered as coordination, resulting in structures which straddle the boundary
between parataxis/adjunction and coordination.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
128 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
cited there). Such llers in English are often a syllabic nasal [m] or a schwa [@], as the
following example illustrates (Peters and Menn 1993):
(91) [m] pick [@]owers. (English learning boy, age 1;6)
According to the above authors, the llers are vocalizations that do not correspond to
particular words/morphemes, and that initially seem to range over various kinds of
functional categories/positions.
Such llers can thus be seen as proto-conjunctions, as per the proposal in this
chapter. It is only later that they transition into specic functional categories,
resulting in hierarchical structure. If this is on the right track, it can be seen as a
progression from a proto-coordination stage to a specic functional category stage.
In addition, Pérez-Leroux et al.(2012) found that young children in their study
frequently avoided producing recursive nominals with three nouns, such as Elmos
sisters ball, which crucially rely on recursive hierarchical structure, and possibly on
the presence of a DP (Determiner Phrase) projection (see Section 4.4). In contrast, the
same children demonstrated facility integrating three nouns into coordinated struc-
tures, suggesting that coordination involves less syntactic complexity than embedded
recursion, consistent with the proposal in this chapter (see especially Section 4.4for the
distinction between true recursion and iteration, as per Kinsella 2009).
Also, Jordens (2002) argues that there is a stage in the acquisition of Dutch where
all constituents are attached by adjunction/parataxis, but where certain modal verbs
and negation serve as proto-functional categories. These proto-functional categories,
according to Jordens, are linking elements between the topic and the predicate (74 4),
certainly analyzable as proto-conjunctions/linkers in the sense of this chapter. In the
next, nite-linking stage,these linkers are grammaticalized into auxiliaries, which
now serve as heads of hierarchical structures (750). This progression of stages ts well
with the proposal of this chapter, showing transitions from the adjunction/parataxis
stage to the proto-coordination and the specic functional category stages.
4.6Concluding remarks
This chapter has proposed the following progression of syntactic stages in the
evolution of human language:
0.One-word stage (non-syntactic stage)
(i) Paratactic proto-syntax stage (at, non-hierarchical stage), where prosody/supra-
segmentals provide the only glue for (proto-)Merge (Conjoin)
(ii) Proto-coordination stage, where, in addition to prosody, the (proto-)conjunction/
linker provides all-purpose segmental glue to hold the utterance together. It is only at
this stage that Move and recursion become available
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Concluding remarks 129
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(iii) Specic functional category stage (hierarchical stage), where, in addition to
prosody and to segmental glue, specic functional categories also provide specialized
syntactic glue for constituent cohesion, including tense elements and subordinators/
complementizers.
The progression of stages along these lines is being proposed both for predication
(clause-internally) and for clause combination. It is shown that each new stage offers
clear and concrete communicative advantages over the previous stage(s), and more-
over advantages specic enough to be responsive to natural selection. Signicantly, in
their modern incarnations, the constructions of the three stages also overlap a great
deal, which is expected under a gradualist evolutionary scenario.
In Chapters 2and 3I argued that the capacity for two-word paratactic grammars
evolved due to natural selection, including sexual selection. As the reviewers point
out, the question now arises whether the capacity for hierarchical syntax evolved
through biological selection as well, or whether it just developed through the gram-
maticalization processes, once the paratactic stage was in place. My hypothesis here is
that the capacity to use hierarchical grammars evolved through biological processes
as well, although I am certainly not claiming that each specic functional projection
had to evolve that way. This will be further discussed in Chapter 7.
The following chapter on Subjacency builds directly on the proposals in this
chapter to explain why adjuncts and conjuncts constitute islands for Move.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
130 Parataxis and coordination as precursors to hierarchy
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
5
Islandhood (Subjacency) as an
epiphenomenon of evolutionary
tinkering
5.1Introductory note
This chapter builds directly on Chapter 4in that it proposes to treat islandhood/
Subjacency as an epiphenomenon of the progression through the three evolutionary
stages, as outlined in that chapter. In particular, the proposal of the previous chapter
is that adjunction/parataxis and proto-coordination stages of syntax do not show full
syntactic integration and thus do not allow movement or subordination. This
approach not only directly captures the islandhood of adjunction and coordination,
but it can also shed light on some other island effects. In this view, Subjacency or
islandhood can be seen as the default, primary state of language, due to an evolu-
tionary base of language which was without Move. This default state can be overrid-
den in certain evolutionarily novel, fancy constructions, arising in the hierarchical
(subordination) stage(s). The constructions that allow Move form a natural class, and
can be characterized syntactically, while the constructions that do not allow Move
(islands) do not form a natural class at all. My conclusion is that Subjacency is not a
principle of syntax, but rather an epiphenomenon of the evolutionary trajectory of
syntax.
5.2What is islandhood/subjacency?
Move(ment) plays a central role in Minimalism (e.g. Chomsky 1995) and its prede-
cessors. So, for example, wh-question formation in English is considered to involve
movement of the wh-word or phrase from its thematic (underlying) position to the
left periphery of the sentence. The following examples illustrate this:
(1) What do penguins eat what?
(2) What does Peter think [
cp
penguins eat what]?
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(3) Who(m) did Peter walk with who(m)?
(4) Who(m) did you say [
cp
Peter walked with who(m)]?
In (1)(2) it is assumed that the wh-word what originates after eat as a complement/
object of eat (cf. echo questions such as Penguins eat what?), and that it subsequently
moves to the front of the sentence, to the position of the specier of CP. (The
strikeout notation is used here to represent the original, pre-Move, copy of the
wh-word.) Similar considerations hold of the wh-word who(m) in the examples
(3)(4). It is important to note here that wh-movement conceived in this way can
cross clausal (CP) boundaries, as is the case in (2) and (4).
In his seminal work, Ross (1967) noted that there are many types of syntactic
islands, that is, constructions out of which it is not possible to apply Move.
1
One such
island is coordinationas illustrated with the minimal pairs below, while it is
possible to move a wh-word out of a Prepositional Phrase (PP) (5,7), it is not possible
to move a wh-word out of a conjunct (6,8):
(5) What did Peter eat ham with what?
(6) *What did Peter eat ham and what?
(7) Who did Peter see Richard with who(m)?
(8) *Who did Peter see Richard and who(m)?
Notice that the echo versions below are grammatical, suggesting that the problem
lies with the movement itself, rather than with the semantics.
(9) Peter ate ham and what?
(10) Peter saw Richard and who(m)?
Movement is also prohibited out of adjunct clauses, which are also considered to be
islands:
2
(11)
?
*What did Peter retire [
cp
after Mary said what?]
[cf. echo question: Peter retired after Mary said what?]
Likewise, movement out of subjects (12) is less acceptable than movement out of
objects (13), and subjects are for that reason also regarded as islands:
1
We say that a phrase is an islandif it is immune to the application of rules that relate its parts to a
position outside of the island(Chomsky 1980:194).
2
As pointed out by a reviewer, there are some apparent exceptions to this observation in certain well-
dened contexts, as reported in Borgonovo and Neelman (2000:199200):
(i) What did John arrive whistling what?
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
132 Islandhood (Subjacency) as an epiphenomenon of evolutionary tinkering
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(12)
??
Who did [
np
your loyalty to who(m)] appeal to Mary?
[cf. echo question: Your loyalty to who(m) appealed to Mary?]
(13) Who(m) did Bill question [
np
your loyalty to who(m)]?
[cf. echo question: Bill questioned your loyalty to who(m)?]
The following examples introduce two additional islands: Wh-Islands, where
wh-extraction is prohibited out of another wh-clause (14), and Complex NP Islands,
where Move is prohibited out of a noun phrase which includes a clause, either a
nominal complement clause (15), or a relative clause (16):
(14)
?
*Which book did you ask John [
cp
where Bill bought which
book]?
(15) *What did Bill reject [
np
the accusation [
cp
that John stole what]]?
(16) *Which book did Bill visit [
np
the store [
cp
that had which book in
stock]]?
Interestingly, there are languages (e.g. Japanese and Chinese) which keep their
wh-phrases in situ (i.e., not moved), and it is still an open theoretical question how to
analyze wh-questions in these languages. One line of research considers that wh-words
in fact do undergo Move even in these languages, but covertly/invisibly so (e.g. Huang
1982). However, just as is the case with English echo questions (910), wh-words in situ
in these languages do not show island effects, at least not when in argument positions.
This prompted e.g. Huang (1982) to propose that Subjacency does not hold for covert
wh-movement. In contrast, Tsai (1994) and Hagstrom (1998) rejected the idea that wh-
words themselves move covertly, but instead proposed a different strategy of deriving
such wh-questions. According to the proposal in Fukui (1986), the lack of wh-movement
in Japanese can be correlated with the lack of CP in the language.
While it is beyond the scope of this book to engage with the issue of covert
movement, sufce it to say here that approaches which do not invoke such move-
ment of wh-phrases are fully compatible with the evolutionary approach I am
adopting here. This is so because these approaches identify a different strategy for
expressing wh-questions, a strategy which does not require a CP layer, or Move.
3
The
approach explored here highlights the existence of multiple routes to the same goal.
One of the central goals of syntactic theory has been to determine what differen-
tiates constructions that allow Move from those that do not. Overwhelmingly, the
assumption among syntacticians is that islandhood, that is, restrictions on Move, is
the marked case, in need of explanation. This assumption has led to the expectation
that there is some (abstract) principle of syntax, such as Subjacency, which accounts
3
As proposed in Radford (1990), a similar kind of strategy is needed to capture wh-questions in
child English, prior to the emergence of CP.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
What is islandhood/subjacency? 133
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
for all or most of the island effects. Research has thus concentrated on characterizing
and dening the principles that are taken to constrain Move, including Subjacency.
4
Almost fty years after Rossdissertation, no real progress has been made on this
frontthere is still no principled characterization of islandhood.
5
Most accounts stipulate which syntactic nodes (S, NP, CP, DP, etc.), and/or which
combination of nodes, and/or nodes in which syntactic positions, constitute obstacles
to Move (barriers/bounding nodes/phases). The classic accounts are Huang (1982);
Lasnik and Saito (1984); and Chomsky (1986). To take one example, very roughly
speaking, one can account for the Complex NP constraint (15)(16) by assuming that
the NP is an obstacle to Move, to use neutral terminology. But the NP proves an
obstacle only in conjunction with a clause, given that movement is otherwise possible
either out of a clause as in (2) and (4), or out of an NP as in (13). Very roughly
speaking again, one needs to assume that clauses and NPs are both obstacles, but that
the wh-phrase can jump over one obstacle (at a time), even though not over two. So
far, so good. But then this analysis does not really carry over to other islands. When it
comes to the Subject Island, how does one explain why movement out of the subject
NP is illicit, while movement out of a comparable object NP is licit? In both cases, the
wh-phrases seem to be crossing the same number of obstacles. According to Huang
(1982), this is because the subjects (and adjuncts) are not properly governed,while
objects are. In Chomskys(1986) version, this is because subjects (and adjuncts)
are not L-marked, while objects are. The appeal to either proper government or
L-marking only stipulates that objects/complements are special/privileged in this
respect, implicating the importance of the structural position, in addition to the
nature and number of nodes crossed. But there is now no real unication of the
Complex NP Island, on the one hand, and subject or adjunct islands, on the other.
6
4
Some more recent accounts (e.g. Boeckx 2008) adopt a pluralistic view of islandhood, that is, a view
that islandhood is a result of the application of various principles, not just one unied principle such as
Subjacency. Under this view, a unication of all islandhood is not pursued or expected. In fact, Boeckx
considers that the result of each Merge is an island, although typically not an absolute island. For him,
islandhood results if too much checking affects a single item. If features to be checked can be distributed
over more than one item, such as may be the case with movement leaving a resumptive pronoun, then
islandhood is voided or weakened (208). In other words, the islands are relativized to the amount of
checking relations established and their congurations. Boeckx (2008) does acknowledge, however, that
adjoined structures have a freezing effecton movement (233), as well as that the islandhood of
coordination is not captured by his, or any other syntactic theory (237).
5
This is not meant, in any way, to denigrate the quality of research done within this approach. For even
when one follows an ill-fated hypothesis, one gathers invaluable data and insights along the way. But
however ne and ingenious this research may have been otherwise, and however great its contributions, in
my view, it has not yielded progress on this particular front, that is, it has not provided a principled account
of islandhood, suggesting that a different angle is needed.
6
And this is looking at islandhood in only one language: English. There is variation in this respect
across languages, too (see e.g. Sprouse and Hornstein 2014:4). To take just one example, Italian does not
seem to show wh-island effects. To account for this, Rizzi (1982) proposed that in Italian the obstacles for
movement are NPs and CPs, as opposed to NPs and IPs (i.e. TPs) in English. Also, as mentioned above, in
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
134 Islandhood (Subjacency) as an epiphenomenon of evolutionary tinkering
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
And the problems multiply as one considers additional islands, such as coordination
(see e.g. Postal 1997,1998).
7
Within the Minimalist Program, in which proper government and L-marking of
the previous frameworks are not available as theoretical postulates, Chomsky (2001,
2008) attempts to capture some of the island effects by invoking new Minimalist
constructs, phases (impenetrable domains), again stipulating that CPs and DPs
(former NPs) are phases. As Boeckx and Grohmann (2007:216) observe, these
most recent phase-based approaches to islandhood do not improve upon the previ-
ous approaches, and phases are in many ways reincarnations of bounding nodes and
barriers.Belletti and Rizzi (2000) report an interview with Chomsky, in which he
concludes that there is no really principled account of many island conditions.
5.3Why there is no principled account of islandhood
The persistent view of islandhood/Subjacency (in Minimalism and predecessors)
considers Move to be the default option, while Subjacency (and other restrictions on
Move) are treated as a marked option, in need of explanation (Ross 1967; Huang 1982;
Lasnik and Saito 1984; Chomsky 1986,2001; Stepanov 2007; Sprouse and Hornstein
2014). To be more accurate, Move in Minimalism is never completely free, as it is
taken to apply only if motivated by a need to check certain (strong uninterpretable)
features. But once such features are present in the derivation, it is considered that
Move applies freely, in the sense that it applies unless blocked by some specic
principle like Subjacency.
Signicantly, this view fuels the inuential language evolution hypothesis, accord-
ing to which Merge (which subsumes Move) was the only evolutionary breakthrough
for syntax: once it emerged, it was able to apply freely and recursively, automatically
yielding Move and subordination (Berwick 1998; Chomsky 2005; Berwick and
Chomsky 2011). In an early attempt to reconcile this view with a gradualist approach
to syntax, Newmeyer (1991) proposes that a grammar with Subjacency was specic-
ally targeted by natural/sexual selection, over a previous stage of grammar, which
presumably had no Subjacency. This implies that this previous stage was character-
ized by a much freer Move, and that the ungrammatical examples discussed in
Section 5.2would have been grammatical in this stage. However, Lightfoot (1991:69)
some languages wh-phrases do not show overt movement at all, and this introduces further complications
for the characterization of Subjacency.
7
In fact, coordination and adjunction seem to be the most difcult islands to capture. For example,
Napoli (1993:401,409) notes that while Subjacency accounts for the Complex NP Constraint, [ ...] the
Subject Condition, and the wh-islands, it cannot account for the ungrammaticality of movement out of
coordinate structures and out of adverbial clauses(see also Footnote 4). The islandhood of coordination
and adjunction is the central focus of this chapter, and it is proposed here that it follows from a looser
integration of adjuncts and conjuncts into the fabric of syntactic structure (see Chapter 4).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Why there is no principled account of islandhood 135
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
counters that Subjacencyhas manyvirtues, but [...] it could nothaveincreasedthe
chances of having fruitful sex.In other words, it is not clear how or why a grammar
with Subjacency would have been naturally/sexually selected over a grammar without
Subjacency.
It is exactly based on these considerations that Berwick (1998:3389) concluded
that there is no possibility of an intermediatesyntax between a non-combinatorial
one and full natural languageone either has Merge in all its generative glory, or one
has no combinatorial syntax at all(see also Bickerton 1990,1998,2007; Berwick and
Chomsky 2011; Chapter 1). This reasoning, which is reminiscent of the old saw
what use is half an eye,has led some syntacticians to believe that syntax is an
all-or-nothing package, which could not have evolved gradually, and which must
have been, in its entirety, a product of one single sudden event, possibly one single
mutation, which Berwick and Chomsky (2011:29) characterize as minor.
But there is no need for this drastic conclusion. In fact, there is an alternative
possibility to consider regarding Subjacency (mentioned in e.g. Cinque 1978;Postal
1997; Boeckx and Grohmann 2007; Progovac 2009b), that islandhood is the default
state of syntax. Given this view, permitting Move would bea special/marked option. In
fact, the constructions that prohibit Move are much more numerous and diverse than
those that allow it. Consider, again, the list of constructions which constitute islands
(for a long inventory of additional island constructions, see e.g. Postal 1997,1998):
Subject Islands
(17)
??
Who did [
np
your loyalty to who] appeal to Mary?
Wh-Islands
(18)
?
*Which book did you ask John [
cp
where Bill bought which
book]?
Complex NP Islands
(19) *What did Bill reject [
np
the accusation [
cp
that John stole what]]?
(20) *Which book did Bill visit [
np
the store [
cp
that had which book in
stock]]?
Adjunct Islands
(21)
?
*What did Peter retire [
cp
after Mary said what?]
Conjunct Islands
(22) *What did Peter retire and [
cp
Mary said what?]
Typically, Move is possible only out of (a subset of) complements/objects, for
example, verbal (non-wh-)complements, whether clausal (23) or nominal (24):
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
136 Islandhood (Subjacency) as an epiphenomenon of evolutionary tinkering
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(23) Which book did you tell John [
cp
that Bill bought which book]?
(24) Who did Bill question [
np
your loyalty to who]?
What this means is that constructions which disallow Move (islands) do not form a
natural class, while those that allow Move, seem to. If so, then any attempt to
characterize islandhood/Subjacency in unied terms is doomed to fail. On the
other hand, it should be possible to formulate a general characterization of non-
island constituents, as pointed out in Postal (1997). For example, in the case of
(2324), Move proceeds through the hierarchy of projections where each new layer
c-commands the previous one, and where there are no adjunct or conjunct clause
boundaries on the way. Recall from Chapter 4that c-command does not extend
seamlessly into adjuncts or conjuncts, and given that movement has to proceed to a
c-commanding position, any boundary that is not strictly hierarchical, subject to an
unbroken chain of c-command, can trip up Move.
Furthermore, there are additional cases where Move is illicit, and I list them here to
anticipate the discussion in subsequent sections. For example, Move does not occur
across sentential boundaries, as is well-known, but not discussed in the context of
Subjacency:
(25) *Who did Mary see the movie. It featured who?
The idea is that the principles of syntax do not extend across sentence boundaries,
but it is worth noting here that some sentence-internal boundaries, such as parataxis,
resemble sentential boundaries in this and other respects.
Move is also prohibited from paratactically (loosely) attached parallel small clauses
(26), as well as from small clauses adjoined to nite clauses (27), the latter example,
but not the former, subsumable under Adjunct Islandhood:
8
(26) a. *What nothing ventured, what gained?
(cf Nothing ventured, nothing gained.)
b. *How easy come, how go?
(cf Easy come, easy go.)
c. *Who monkey see, who do?
(cf Monkey see, monkey do.)
(27) *Where can her having retired from where,wenally relax?
(cf. Her having retired from where, we can nally relax.)
Both types of examples above feature a paratactic boundary across which the
wh-phrase would have to Move. If the paratactic glue is mainly intonational/prosodic
8
As pointed out by the reviewers, these examples do not seem to allow even echo questions:
(i)
??
Nothing ventured, what gained?
(ii) *Easy come, how go?
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Why there is no principled account of islandhood 137
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(Chapter 4), then the paratactic boundary is not unlike a sentence boundary. In
addition, if these are just small clauses, then they are not provided with the functional
categories and projections, such as CP, that would provide the landing sites for
wh-Move. It is typically considered that wh-movement targets the specier position
of CP, and that if this position is not there, or is lled with some other material,
wh-movement cannot take place (see also Section 4.4.5).
The same considerations hold for single root small clauses in (28) below, discussed in
chapters 2and 3. If these clauses are just bare argument-predicate concatenations, then
they also lack the relevant syntactic space for Move to take place, such as TP or CP.
(28) *When problem solved when? (cf. Problem solved.)
*Who(m) worry? (cf. Jeanne worry?!)
With these additional examples, it becomes even clearer that constructions that
prohibit Move (islands) have no syntactic property in common, that is, that these
constructions do not form a natural class. It is thus not surprising that in spite of all
the effort, to date, there has been no principled analysis of islandhood/Subjacency, as
pointed out in Section 5.1(see also Belletti and Rizzi 2000; Szabolcsi and den Dikken
2003; Boeckx and Grohmann 2007).
As mentioned in Footnote 4, yet another angle is possible, namely, to adopt a
pluralistic view in which islandhood is a result of several independent principles that
constrain Move (see e.g. Boeckx 2008). In addition to not being able to capture the
islandhood of coordination and adjunction, the central topics of this chapter, this
view is also not able to account for the generalization that non-islands seem to form a
natural class. Even though the correlation is not perfect, it still holds that if a
constituent is not a complement, then it is highly likely to be an island.
9
For all these reasons, it would be prudent to explore an alternative track, an
approach that takes islandhood to be the default state of syntax, and Move a special
option, available only in certain privileged constructions. In this view, the question is
no longer why Move is impossible out of islands, but rather why Move is possible out
of certain complements, and indeed why Move is possible at all. But, rst, before one
can pursue that question, it is important to establish the reason why No Move would
be the default state of syntax. The next section addresses that question.
9
There are many subtleties regarding islandhood, including distinguishing weak from strong islands,
which my approach does not address. I hope that future research will address this question within an
evolutionary framework, especially given that an evolutionary approach is well-equipped to deal with
graded grammaticality. In this respect, one would need to consider the three rough stages explored in this
monograph: Adjunction/Parataxis, Coordination, and Subordination, as just three idealized points in the
evolution of syntax, with a variety of transitional sub-stages certainly a possibility, as discussed in
Chapter 4. To the extent that the structures can be more or less syntactically integrated, the graded
judgments would then reect the extent of that integration, which can vary not only across constructions,
but also across languages.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
138 Islandhood (Subjacency) as an epiphenomenon of evolutionary tinkering
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
5.4Subjacency in the light of evolution
My proposal is that proto-syntax, characterized by one-word utterances, (root) small
clauses (29), and paratactic combinations of such small clauses (30), did not have Move
or subordination (Progovac 2008a,b, 2009b, 2013b, 2014a), as discussed in Chapters 24.
10
(29) a. Case closed. Problem solved. Point taken. Crisis averted.
Me rst! Everybody out! Him apologize?!
(30) a. Nothing ventured, nothing gained.
b. Easy come, easy go.
c. Monkey see, monkey do.
d. Come one, come all.
The examples above are arguably present-day approximations of this stage of syntax.
Even though these present-day incarnations must be a bit more complex than the
proto-structures, they still do not allow Move (2628), as established in the previous
sections, as well as in the previous chapters.
In this proposal, the kind of syntax illustrated in (29)(30) was primary and
foundational, while Move was an evolutionary innovation. In agreement with
Newmeyer (1991), this proposal advocates a gradualist approach to the evolution
of syntax; however, recall that Newmeyer proposed that the previous stage(s) of
grammar had no restrictions on Move, and that Subjacency was an innovation
(Section 5.2).
11
In my proposal, in contrast, the proto-stages of grammar were
characterized by islandhood, or lack of Move, with Move emerging only later, in
conjunction with layered, hierarchical syntax (Section 4.4.5), supported by special-
ized functional categories and projections, such as TP and CP. In Minimalism Move
is typically associated with functional projections. For example, Move of the under-
lying small clause subject targets the specier of a TP (Chapter 2; Section 4.4.5), while
wh-movement targets the specier of a CP, as illustrated in this chapter.
12
In a small
clause based grammar which has neither TPs nor CPs, one does not expect to
encounter this type of Move, especially considering that Move has to target a
hierarchically higher position, as explained in Section 4.4.5.
10
As pointed out by Boeckx (2008), syntactic theories of Subjacency, and locality in general, should be
compatible with ndings in neuroscience and evolutionary biology: Up to now, compatibility with neuro-
science and evolutionary biology has been a rather weak constraint on theory construction in linguistics
(Boeckx 2008:4).
11
A similar idea can be found in, for example, Boeckxs(2008:244) statement that bounding nodes are
solutions that the language faculty has developed to ensure that syntactic objects are unambiguous.
12
A reviewer wonders if all Move operations target functional projections. I would say here that at least
the uncontroversial cases of Move do involve functional projections, such as subject raising to TP,
wh-raising to CP, V movement to v, etc. In fact, even adjunction of adverbials is sometimes claimed to
target only functional projections (see e.g. Adger 2003).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 15/5/2015, SPi
Subjacency in the light of evolution 139
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Going back to islands, we can now envision an answer to the question of why some
constructions still disallow Move (e.g. coordination and adjunction), while others
facilitate it (e.g. subordination). My claim is that our grammars, courtesy of gradual
evolutionary development, show a range of constructions that fall between the
two opposites: (i) completely independent utterances/sentences and (ii) syntactically
fully integrated expressions. The intermediate possibility is to be loosely attached
(semi-integrated) into sentential fabric, and this is arguably the case with parataxis/
adjunction and conjunction.
13
Only the most integrated of constructions (e.g. com-
plements), which build a ladder, a scaffolding of functional projections, allow Move
to climb along this ladder.
14
The metaphor of climbing is appropriate here given
that syntactic theory assumes that movement is always to a structurally higher
(c-commanding) position. Clausal conjuncts and adjuncts have been repeatedly
noted in the literature not to be fully integrated into syntactic fabric, as discussed
in Chapter 4. An evolutionary approach can shed novel light on these phenomena.
This evolutionary account also helps explain why human grammars should avail
themselves of redundant means for expressing clause combinations, and moreover
such imperfectmeans, as are coordination and adjunction. Recall from Chapter 4
how clauses are combined in the postulated three rough stages: parataxis (adjunc-
tion) (31), coordination (32), and subordination (33):
(31) He is a linguist(as) you know. Parataxis
(32) He is a linguist, and you know it. Coordination
(33) You know that he is a linguist. Subordination
If comparable stages characterized language evolution, with adjunction and coord-
ination constituting intermediate steps between separate utterances (no syntactic
integration, no Move) and subordination (full integration, free(er) Move), then such
evolutionary tinkeringleft us with multiple possibilities which partly overlap in
function, that is, with redundant means for expressing similar meanings (31)(33).
15
13
Even though I will not discuss subject islands in this book, it is worth noting that syntactic theory
recognizes that subjects/speciers are less tightly integrated than objects/complements. While objects/
complements are merged directly with the verbs (First Merge), subjects/speciers are typically introduced
as sisters to intermediate projections (Second Merge). In addition, subjects typically undergo local Move
out of verbal projections, further contributing to their syntactic instability.
14
This is not to say that subordination was necessarily one big solid monolithic stageas pointed out
repeatedly in this chapter, as well as in Chapter 4, sub-stages and transitions may well have existed, and
may account for a number of present-day constructions which are ambivalent and difcult to categorize.
15
My claim here is not that a hierarchical stage automatically licenses Move. I am only saying that
hierarchy is a necessary condition for Move, not sufcient. This is not surprising given that Move is
typically assumed to target a c-commanding position, that is, a structurally higher position. Other
conditions clearly need to be met to allow Move, including the existence of the appropriate and available
landing sites for Move (e.g. CP for wh-movement). Given this, the fact that not all subordinate construc-
tions allow Move, but only a subset of them do, is not directly a problem for my analysis. The analysis
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
140 Islandhood (Subjacency) as an epiphenomenon of evolutionary tinkering
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
As pointed out in Chapter 1, evolution is taken not to throw a good thing away, but
to build upon it, or to add to it. So, if adjunction and conjunction proved to be useful
syntactic mechanisms in a proto-syntactic stage, the later stages did not have to
discard them, but could continue to use them in specialized functions. This is also
what happens in present times with grammaticalization of subordination, as well as
with grammaticalization processes in general (see e.g. Heine and Kuteva 2007).
Overlap and (partial) specialization are properties of evolutionary tinkering, rather
than of optimal design.
Grammaticalization is relevant for my approach because it shows that this type of
change is in principle possible (see also Fitch 2010). When processes of grammati-
calization happened for the rst time, they would have driven biological selection
toward developing brains that can support the processing of such abstract categories
and their projections. Once the processing mechanisms evolved to a certain point,
then grammaticalization processes could, in principle, operate without biological
evolution. However, as discussed in much more detail in Chapter 7, there is no
guarantee that any of these processes will not, for some reason and in certain
circumstances, trigger genetic selection.
As pointed out in Chapter 4, there are concrete and tangible advantages to each
postulated stage of syntax. The conjunction stage has an advantage over the adjunc-
tion stage in that it provides more robust evidence for proto-Merge, by including
the segmental glue. In addition to facilitating Move, the hierarchical, subordination
stage also provides a recursive mechanism for embedding multiple viewpoints one
within another, as discussed in detail in Chapter 4. Thus, if subordination (as well as
Move) is an innovation resulting from evolutionary tinkering, then subordination
would have signicantly increased the expressive power of language, in a concrete
manner, and thus, unlike Subjacency, constitutes a plausible target for natural/sexual
selection.
In this evolutionary perspective, rather than a system designed from scratch in an
optimal way, syntax is seen as a patchwork of structures incorporating various stages
of its evolution, giving an impression, or an illusion, of Subjacency. It follows from
this approach that Subjacency is not a principle of syntax, or a principle of any kind,
but rather just an epiphenomenon. Subjacency or islandhood can be seen as the
default, primary state of language, due to an evolutionary base of language which was
without Move. This default state can be overridden in certain evolutionarily novel
constructions, such as subordination.
proposed here posits a different question than the traditional analyses: the question here is not what non-
complements and complement islands have in common, the question pursued by Subjacency accounts, but
rather how complement islands differ from complement non-islands. Exploring this question further may
give new insights into the nature of Move, and language in general.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Subjacency in the light of evolution 141
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
5.5Conclusion
This chapter has pointed out that syntactic islands do not form a natural class, but
that non-islands do, and that, for this reason, there can never be a principled, unied
account of islandhood/Subjacency. My proposal is that Subjacency is not a specic
principle of syntax, but rather the default state of syntax, dating back in time to the
evolutionary beginnings of language, in which Move, and functional projections that
facilitate Move, were simply unavailable. I have hypothesized that two initial stages in
the evolution of syntax do not exhibit Move: the adjunction/parataxis stage, and the
coordination stage. In this analysis, Move and subordination are later innovations,
made possible by the emergence of specialized functional categories and their
projections, such as TP and CP. Present-day sentences can still include various fossil
constructs lacking Move, specically adjuncts and conjuncts, which are then seen as
islands.
My proposal reverses the direction of syntactic evolution hypothesized in
Newmeyer (1991), who also explores a gradualist approach to syntax. While New-
meyer assumes that the initial stages of syntax were characterized by Move free of
Subjacency, I propose exactly the opposite, that islandhood (or the state with no
Move) was the norm in the previous stages, and that Move was an innovation. This
reversal allows me to kill three birds with one stone. First, it provides some rationale
for characterizing islandhood/Subjacency as the default state of grammar, rather than
as a constraint on grammars. Second, this allows me to explain why various fossilized
expressions (arguably living fossilsof this proto-syntax stage) cannot be manipu-
lated by Move.
Third, and most importantly, this allows me to address the question of how or why
the progression took place from the proto-syntactic stages with no Move and no
subordination, to the stage(s) with Move and subordination. Instead of targeting the
abstract and obscure Subjacency by natural selection, as per Newmeyers(1991)
proposal, my proposal targets the emergence of subordination (Move emerging in
conjunction with it). In comparison to its more primary counterparts (adjunction
and coordination), subordination provides a clear and concrete advantage in the
expressive power of language. One such advantage is that subordination affords the
possibility to recursively and unambiguously embed/nest multiple viewpoints one
within another.
This chapter offers a hypothesis which is consistent with a lot of descriptive data,
with how grammaticalization processes work, as well as with many studies in
language acquisition and processing, as discussed in Chapter 4. Finally, an important
advantage of this proposal is that it does not force us into the conclusion that syntax
is all or nothing, and that the evolution of syntax as a whole had to have been a
sudden and passive event, passive in the sense that its evolution was parasitic on
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
142 Islandhood (Subjacency) as an epiphenomenon of evolutionary tinkering
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
some other event. For example, Gould (1987) and Chomsky (1988) have proposed
that syntax can just be a consequence of an increase in the size of the brain, or of
some general laws of growth. The approach explored here leaves open the possibility
that syntax played an active role in shaping human brains. Another important
advantage of this approach is that it reveals how the incremental nature of the
evolution of syntax can actually shed light on the very properties of its design.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Conclusion 143
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
6
Exocentric VN compounds:
The best fossils
6.1Introduction
This chapter looks at a host of surprising properties of VN compounds, such as pick-
pocket, turn-coat, spoil-sport, cry-baby, across a variety of languages, focusing pri-
marily on those found in English and Serbian. My argument is that the grammar
behind these exocentric compounds is a survivor (living fossil) of an early stage of
syntax in language evolution, and that by looking at their structure we can get a good
glimpse into the workings of proto-syntax. Jackendoff (1999,2002) has proposed that
the evolution of syntax might have preserved fossilsof previous stages in its later
stages (see also Bickerton 1990), mentioning in particular compounds (e.g. snowman)
as one such living fossil (see Section 1.6).
I have argued that specically exocentric VN compounds constitute the most
plausible candidate for a syntactic fossil featuring a verb (Progovac 2009a, 2012).
When it comes to their structure (or the lack thereof), my argument is that VN
compounds, at least in English and Serbian, are a clear product of the paratactic
proto-grammar, as introduced in Chapters 24. These compounds are best analyzed
as involving a single application of (proto-)Merge/Conjoin (of Chapter 4), to exactly
two words, a verb and a noun, where the noun stands as the verbs only (proto-)
argument. The thematic (theta) role of this noun, even though typically theme
(object-like), can be shown to be largely underdetermined, in fact absolutive-like,
corroborating the proposal that these compounds are at, paratactic structures,
rather than hierarchical structures equipped with null projections and null argu-
ments (Section 6.2). I will argue that the relationship between the verb and the noun
in these compounds is that of proto-predication (see e.g. Gil 2012), a precursor to true
predication (for the notion of a proto-role, see Section 3.4.2; also discussion below).
Section 6.3compares VN compounds with their more complex hierarchical coun-
terparts, bringing to light the sharp differences between them, but also continuity in
the sense that the former provide scaffolding for building the latter. Consistent with
the theme of this monograph, the structure of VN compounds integrates into the
structure of their more complex hierarchical counterparts.
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
It will also be shown that the verb in these compounds surfaces in what at least
synchronically appears to be the imperative form, the kind of imperative that is also
found in other (frozen) expressions. This is unmistakably the case with Serbian VN
compounds (Section 6.4), but the same has also been proposed for VN compounds in
other languages, including other Slavic and Romance languages (Section 6.5). As will
be shown, VN compounds across languages, not only Indo-European (IE), but also
non-IE, exhibit striking parallelisms both in form and in imagery (Section 6.5).
Exocentric VN compounds specialize for derogatory reference when they refer to
humans, providing a good glimpse into how comparable expressions might have
played a role in (ancient) ritual insults, which is why these fossils are of signicance
for sexual selection considerations (Progovac and Locke 2009), as addressed in
Section 6.6, as well as in Chapter 7. As pointed out in Chapter 1, the present-day
compounds, as well as all the other fossils discussed in this book, are only to be seen
as approximations of the structures once used by our ancestors. Some corroborating
evidence and testing grounds for the proposal in this chapter come from language
acquisition studies and language representation in the brain (Section 6.7). To the
extent that their structure and use can best be understood in an evolutionary
framework, these compounds constitute an argument for the gradualist approach
to the evolution of syntax, for the same reason that nding fossils elsewhere would.
6.2Paratactic grammar behind VN compounds
This section focuses on the type of (proto-)Merge that characterizes VN compounds
and concludes that the grammar behind these compounds, including their absolu-
tive-like and exocentric nature, begins to make sense only if seen as a fossil of the very
beginnings of syntax, capable of producing only at, paratactic structures.
1
This
would be the hypothesized paratactic proto-syntax stage of Chapters 24.InVN
compounds, the noun is the verbs only (proto-)argument, which is absolutive-like in
nature, as established in Section 6.2.1. The exocentric nature of VN compounds is
addressed in Section 6.2.2, where it is shown that absolutivity and exocentricity in this
case are just two sides of the same coin.
6.2.1Absolutive-like proto-predication
As proposed in Chapter 3, the simplest possible grammar involving predication is a
at, intransitive, absolutive-like grammar, the kind which licenses only one argument
per predicate, and which blurs the distinction between subjects and objects. If we
consider all the data involving VN compounds, it becomes obvious that the grammar
1
See Jackendoff (1999,2002) for the proposal that adjunction/parataxis in general is a protosyntactic
fossil; see Chapter 4of this volume for an extensive discussion of the reach of parataxis in proto-grammars
and modern grammars.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic grammar behind VN compounds 145
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
behind VN compounds is also absolutive-like in this sense. The noun in VN
compounds is not always the object or theme of the verb, as is typically assumed in
the literature. Consider the following data from English rst:
(1) pick-pocket, scare-crow, turn-coat, dare-devil, hunch-back,
wag-tail, tattle-tale, kill-joy, cut-purse, spoil-sport, saw-bones,
Shake-speare, Burn-house, Drink-water, Bere-water, Drynk-pany
(drink-penny, miser), Pinch-penny (miser)
(2) rattle-snake, catch-phrase, cry-baby, stink-bug, worry-wart, copy-
cat, tumble-weed, scape-goat, turn-table
While the nouns in the compounds in (1) are object-like, the nouns in (2) are subject-
like, occasionally involving agents (e.g cry-baby, copy-cat).
2
The situation is the same in Serbian. While the composing nouns in the com-
pounds in (3) are object-like, those in (4) are subject-like. Even though the data in
(4a) can be considered as unaccusative, with the nouns analyzable as themes, those in
(4b) involve agents. It follows that it is not possible to describe these compounds as
uniformly involving objects, or even themes, and that the only unied description is
the one that invokes absolutive-type roles.
(3) cepi-dlaka [split-hair = hairsplitter]
deri-koža [rip-skin = person who rips you off]
ispi-čutura [empty-ask = drunkard]
kljuj-drvo [archaic: peck-wood = wood-pecker]
kosi-noga [skew-leg = person who limps]
muti-voda [muddy-water = one who muddies waters]
(4) a. duri-baba
3
[sulk-old.woman=who sulks like an old
woman]
kaži-prst [show-nger=index nger]
smrdi-buba
2
The terms object-like and subject-like are used here in the sense that the noun arguments would
surface as objects or subjects, respectively, in a corresponding sentence. While the sentences A snake rattles,
or A baby cries, involve these nouns as subjects, the sentences He picks pockets or He kills joy involve these
nouns as objects. See Chapter 3for various additional constructions across languages which do not clearly
distinguish between subjects and objects.
A reviewer points out that some VN compounds feature nouns that are not clearly either subject-like or
object-like, such as scatter-brain and jump-rope. This may still be consistent with the proto-role charac-
terization of proto-predication (Section 3.4.2). The reviewer also brings up compounds created by merging
prepositions and verbs, such as input, hand-out, follow-through. If Heine and Kutevas(2007) reconstruc-
tion is correct, then the category of prepositions was a later evolutionary development, not characteristic of
the earliest proto-syntax stages.
3
As pointed out in Mihajlović(1992), baba is a difcult piece to translate since it involves layers of
meaning, including woman,”“old woman,and witch.In fact, many of these compounds are impossible
to translate accurately, given that they preserve older uses and meanings of morphemes, no longer
accessible to native speakers.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
146 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
[stink-bug=bug species that stinks; person
who stinks]
smrdi-vrana [stink-crow =a species of crow]
tresi-baba [shake-old.woman=who shakes/scares like
an old woman]
visi-baba [hang-old.woman=ower: snowdrop]
b. plači-drug [cry-friend=who commiserates with you]
plači-baba [cry-old.woman=cry-baby]
striži-buba [grate-bug=an insect which pecks trees]
tuži-baba [complain-old.woman=who complains like a
woman]
trči-laža [run-lie=one who spreads lies]
Recall from Chapter 3how absolutivity works in e.g. Tongan (Tchekhoff 1979:409).
When only one argument is present, an absolutive argument, it can be either subject-
like or object-like, resulting in vagueness:
(5)oku kai ae iká.
PRES
eat the.
ABS
sh
The sh eats.
The sh is eaten.
The lack of theta role specication on the noun is also noticable with compounds
such as turn-table and turn-coat, showing that, with one and the same verb, the noun
can be either subject-like or object-like (see Section 3.3.2). As discussed in Section 6.3,
hierarchical compounds, such as table-turner, show a precise thematic role assign-
ment, and the noun in such compounds can only be interpreted as object-like. In
other words, unlike with VN compounds, with -er compounds it is the grammar that
dictates that the noun must be interpreted as object-like, given that the -er piece is
associated with the role of agent.
The most expressive of VN compounds can in fact be doubly interpreted, allowing
the noun to play the role of the agent and theme at the same time, providing a strong
argument for the proto-linguistic character of these compounds. For example,
English dare-devil is the one who dares the devil, and can also be the one who is a
devil that dares.
4
In Serbian pali-drvce [ignite-stick, matches], drvce is interpreted
as both a theme and an agent (the stick is both ignited and igniting). Since both
4
According to e.g. the Online Etymology Dictionary, dare-devil consists of the verb dare and the noun
devil, and the devil might refer to the person, or the sense might be one who dares the devil (compare
scare-crow, pick-pocket, cut-throat).’” Interestingly, some native speakers believe that only the former
interpretation is behind this compound, while others believe that the latter interpretation is there; there is
disagreement even among the reviewers of this book.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic grammar behind VN compounds 147
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
interpretations are available at the same time, this has to be a matter of vagueness/
underspecication, rather than ambiguity (Progovac and Locke 2009; Progovac
2012). While vagueness is typically associated with paucity of structure, ambiguity
is typically ascribed to distinct structural possibilities (see e.g. Kempson 1977 for the
distinction).
My proposal is that an absolutive-like grammar underlies VN compounds, and
that all the compounds illustrated above (14) involve the same kind of composition.
It would be an error to treat (1) and (3) distinctly from (2) and (4). A unied
(absolutive-like) analysis of VN compounds would immediately capture their iden-
tical morphological make-up, including the imperative morphology in Serbian
(Section 6.4), as well as their shared (derogatory) semantics (Section 6.6).
5
As shown in Section 6.3, all the VN compounds in Serbian (3) and (4) types alike,
feature exactly the same morpho-syntactic frame, complete with an imperative form
of the verb, calling for a unied analysis. While in English the form of the verb is
unmarked, the similarity in structure and interpretation between e.g. English rattle-
snake and Serbian tresi-baba; English worry-wart and Serbian duri-baba, strongly
suggests that the English VN compounds also form a unied class. Section 6.2.2on
exocentricity provides further arguments for this unied analysis. In fact, the argu-
ments for the absolutive nature and for the exocentric nature of these compounds are
inextricably linked, and these compounds can only be understood if both of these
crucial properties are considered together, as they are two sides of the same coin.
In the spirit of Downing (1977), Gil (2005) suggests that root NN compounds (e.g.
toothbrush, snowman), as well as some other constructions in various languages,
involve an association operator semantically. On the other hand, the semantics of
VN compounds involve (a bit) more thanjust association; they involve a participant in
the event, and thus a relationship which can be characterized as a precursor to
predication, i.e., as proto-predication. In this respect, Gil (2012) has proposed that
predication is a composite emergent entity, rather than a primitive, and that it brings
together both thematic role assignment and headedness. In this light, VN compounds
exhibit a rudimentary thematic role assignment, involving just one participant, but
with no further theta-role specication, and with no headedness or hierarchy.
6
5
While Carstairs-McCarthy (1992:118) claims that the semantic relation between the noun and the verb
is free in VN compounds, and may include an internal argument (but need not), Ackema (1998:128), based
on Dutch, claims that there are two types of VN compounds, depending on whether the noun is a
complement or not. The considerations in this chapter strongly support the former view, i.e. a unied
analysis of VN compounds.
6
As pointed out in Section 3.4.2, Dowty (1991) proposes that theta roles are not discrete, but can instead
be seen as prototypes, including proto-agent and proto-theme roles. The participant role I am using here
can be seen as the ultimate proto-role.
Proto-predication does not assume valence in the modern sense of the term, that is, it does not assume
that the verbs in this stage necessarily require a certain number of arguments, the assumption which is also
necessary to make for the one-word stage, as discussed in Section 4.2.2.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
148 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
My conclusion is that the VN compounds in (14) are all instances of the same
paratactic, absolutive-like proto-strategy, where the nouns thematic role is not
structurally specied. While it is typically a theme, it can also be an agent, attesting
to the proto-predication character of the compounding process. The next section
gives further support to this view, considering how the exocentric nature of VN
compounds is closely tied to their absolutive-like nature.
6.2.2Exocentricity
It is typically reported in the linguistics literature, including textbooks, that VN
compounds of the kind illustrated in (1) are exceptional in that they are exocentric
(i.e. not headed), in contrast tothe compounds illustrated in e.g. (6), which are headed
by the second/rightmost element in the compound (e.g. Spencer 1991; Selkirk 1982):
(1) pick-pocket, scare-crow, turn-coat, dare-devil, hunch-back, wag-tail,
tattletale
(6) toothbrush, headboard, bedroom, blackboard, navy-blue
While a bedroom is a kind of room, and navy-blue is a kind of blue (with room and
blue acting as heads), a turncoat is neither a kind of coat nor a kind of turn. It is rather
a person who (metaphorically speaking) turns his coat (a traitor), even though there
is no morphological piece, at least not an overt one, contributing to the meaning
person.
And even though the compounds in (2)and(4) discussed in the previous section at
rst glance seem to pattern with those in (6), in the sense that a rattlesnake is a kind of
snake,andashow-nger is a kind of nger (cf. index nger in English), there is good
evidence for the view that they are in fact the same compound type as those in (1).
(2) rattle-snake, catch-phrase, cry-baby, stink-bug, worry-wart,
copy-cat, tumble-weed, scape-goat, turn-table
The clearest evidence is available in Serbian VN compounds, which feature the same
type of (imperative) morphology in both (3) and (4) type compounds, but never in
the compound type in (6). In fact, the compounds such as (6), considered to be root
compounds, consisting of just two roots, are practically non-existent in Serbian, as
mentioned in Section 1.6. Apart from very few creations, mostly borrowings, Serbian
cannot use the root compound strategy in (6) productively. For example, one cannot
create *krevet-soba (lit. bed-room), or *kafa-sto (lit. coffee-table) in Serbian. Instead,
one uses phrases of different kinds to express similar concepts, such as spavaća soba
(lit. sleeping room), or sto za kafu (lit. table for coffee). It is clear in Serbian that the
imperative compounds in (4) cannot be the product of the root compound strategy,
of the kind exemplied in English (6). Instead, this is the exact same strategy used to
form (imperative) compounds in (3).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic grammar behind VN compounds 149
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
To recapitulate, the argument for the absolutive-like, exocentric nature of VN
compounds is as follows. Given that Serbian does not really have root compounds,
and certainly not any root compounds with imperative morphology, and given that
compounds in (3) and (4) show completely identical morphological make-up,
including the imperative form of the verb, the conclusion must be that the com-
pounds in (3) and (4) in Serbian are a product of the same compounding strategy.
Given that some of these compounds involve object-like predication (3), and others
subject-like predication (4), the unied analysis of these compounds must invoke the
absolutive-like analysis. Even though in English there is no clear morphological
evidence to show if the compounds in (2) pattern with those in (1) or with those in
(6), I propose to extend the unied analysis to English VN compounds as well, for the
reasons mentioned below. However, if it turns out that the English data in (2) are just
(headed) root compounds, the data in Serbian still remain a clear absolutive-like
fossil.
I can offer the following reasons for treating all English VN compounds discussed
so far, including those in (2), as exocentric, absolutive-like creations. First of all,
unlike root compounds, which are extremely productive in English, the VN strategy,
both in (1) and (2), is highly restricted and unproductive.
7
Second, when they refer to
humans, the compounds in (2) tend to be pejorative, just like their counterparts in
(1), as is obvious from e.g. cry-baby, worry-wart, copy-cat. Furthermore, as discussed
in Section 6.5, the VN compounds across different languages involve very similar
images and concepts, typically combining simple, basic words. As pointed out in the
previous section, there are clear parallels in the interpretation and imagery of English
rattle-snake and Serbian tresi-baba; English worry-wart and Serbian duri-baba,
suggesting that VN compounds in English should receive the same unied analysis
that is inescapable in the case of Serbian VN compounds.
Exocentricity is a surprising property, given that all morpho-syntactic structure
(derived by Merge) is considered to be headed, headedness and hierarchy con-
stituting the hallmarks of Merge. According to e.g. Williams (1981), compounds
and afxation in morphology are also subject to headedness, more specically right-
hand headedness, with the rightmost morpheme serving as the head of the whole
compound/word. While Williams(1981) Righthand Headedness Rule seems applic-
able in describing the headed compounds in (6), it does not apply to the VN
compounds in (1). This is only one of several ways in which VN compounds are
nonconforming.
7
While these VN compounds are no longer productive in English, it is interesting that they are still
accessible to the brain. As pointed out to me by Ana Progovac (p.c. 2013), one can nd an online fantasy
name-generator for insults (http://www.rinkworks.com/namegen/), which generates a list of potential
derogatory names for characters and a lot of them are in fact VN compounds. Another example of a
recent creation is sell-sword, used in the sense of mercenary, which gures in the title of the trilogy of
fantasy novels The Sellswords, written by R. A. Salvatore.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
150 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The few references that address the structure of VN compounds of type (1)
typically attempt to make them more streamlined, more conforming to the pre-
sent-day accusative-style grammars, by endowing them with null elements and
covert structure. Marchand (1969) proposed that VN compounds, which he calls
pseudo-compounds,are derived by a null afx which serves as their head (see also
Rohrer 1977 for French and Lieber 1992).
8
More recently, Ferrari (2005), based on
Italian data, explores an analysis of VN compounds which posits a null head and an
Aspect Phrase inside these compounds, rendering them headed by a null afx.
I explore an approach to VN compounds, at least those found in English and Serbian,
which does not posit any covert structure or null elements, embracing the traditional
view of these compounds as exocentric (but see Section 6.5.2for Romance languages
possibly being an exception in this respect). This in turn leads to an absolutive-like
analysis. As this chapter will show, there are many reasons to adhere to this view.
In addition to the observed ambivalence in theta-role assignment, Serbian VN
compounds are also ambivalent when it comes to determining what counts as head
with respect to agreement possibilities. In some sense, the noun inside Serbian VN
compounds seems to act as a morphological head of the whole compound, inuen-
cing agreement possibilities, but in another sense, it does not, as illustrated in the
following table:
(7) Nominative Accusative
ta.
F
. /taj.
M
.(this) trči-laža.
F
tu.
F
/tog.
M
trči-laž-u.
F
ta/taj ispi-čutura.
F
tog/tu ispi-čutur-u.
F
taj jebi-vetar.
M
tog jebi-vetr-a.
M
Animate
taj vadi-čep.
M
taj vadi-čep.
M
Inanimate
to.
N
pali-drvce.
N
to.
N
pali-drvce.
N
For the F(eminine) noun čutura [ask], the compound is declined as a simple F noun
would be, as demonstrated by the characteristic F accusative ending u(čuturu). The
choice of the demonstrative is also inuenced, although not determined, by the
F form of the noun: if the noun is F, the demonstrative for the whole compound
can be either F or M(asculine), the latter choice probably available by default (see
Ferrari 2005 for an important role played by default M gender in compounds
and word formation in general.)
9
The M option suggests that the noun in a VN
8
The null afx can be seen as perhaps a null counterpart of the morpheme -man,or-er. Marchands
view is criticized in Langendoen (1971) and Ljung (1975), who favor the ellipsis approach (the term ellipsis is
also used in Jespersen 1954). Warren (1978:27) uses the term incomplete compoundfor a host of different
types of compounds, including compounds such as egghead, which she analyzes as missing the morpho-
logical piece corresponding to man.Egghead type compounds may also be of evolutionary signicance.
9
On the other hand, Ferrari (2005) reports that Italian VN compounds are uniformly M, suggesting
that they may have more morpho-syntactic structure, including possibly a null M sufx.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Paratactic grammar behind VN compounds 151
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
compound is not unambiguously its morphological head. Also, the F demonstrative
can be freely used with VN compounds even when they refer to males.
If the noun is inanimate M (vetar [wind]), and the compound human/animate, the
demonstrative must be M as well, but the whole compound in the accusative form
would follow an animate accusative pattern, with an ending in a(jebi-vetr-a),
suggesting again that the nal (inanimate) noun is not really the head of the
compound. On the other hand, if the compound as a whole refers to an instru-
ment/inanimate object (vadi-čep), and if, moreover, its noun is inanimate and M (čep
[cork]), then the demonstrative must be M, and the whole compound also follows the
accusative inanimate M pattern. When the noun is inanimate N(euter) (drvce
[stick]), and the whole compound is also inanimate, the demonstrative must be
N as well, and the accusative follows the inanimate pattern. These patterns point to
some unusual strategies and compromises in determining agreement, which would
be understandable if these compounds lack morpho-syntactic heads. The compari-
son between VN compounds and their hierarchical -er/-ac counterparts in the
following section reinforces the conclusions reached in this section.
6.3A comparison with the hierarchical verbal compounds
Recall that the proposed analysis of exocentric compounds involves a at, paratactic
combination of a verb and a noun, its only argument, making use of a single instance of
(proto)-Merge (or Conjoin in the sense of Chapter 4). Proto-Merge, creating non-
hierarchical, at structures, arguably coincides with rudimentary predicate-argument
semantics, as established in the previous sections. From an evolutionary perspective, the
structures created by proto-Merge, including VN compounds, can be seen not only as
precursors, but also as necessary foundation for building more elaborate, hierarchical
structures, including hierarchical verbal compounds discussed in this section.
Consider the following verbal (synthetic) compounds in English and Serbian, also
composed of a verb and a noun, but involving additional morphology and structure:
(8) truck-driver, meat-eater, brick-layer, story-teller, tax-payer, heart-
breaker
(9) kamen-o-rez-ac [stone-
O
-carve-
AGENT
, stone-carver]
srebr-o-ljub-ac [silver-
O
-love-
AGENT
, who admires
money]
žen-o-mrz-ac [woman-
O
-hate-
AGENT
, woman-hater,
misogynist]
ver-o-lom-ac [faith-
O
-break-
AGENT
, who converts]
brak-o-lom-ac [marriage-
O
-break-
AGENT
, who breaks
marriages]
rib-o-lov-ac [sh-
O
-hunt-
AGENT
,sherman]
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
152 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The two compound types, the exocentric VN strategy and the -er/-ac strategy illus-
trated in (89) are comparable given that both utilize the same free morphemes, a verb
and a noun, to express similar concepts, which is especially clear with the following
minimal pairs, one involving a VN compound, and the other an -er/-ac compound:
10
(10) a. der-i-koža [rip-
IMP
-skin, one who rips you off]
kož-o-der-ac [skin-
O
-rip-
AGENT
, skin-ripper, one who
rips you off]
b. liž-i-sahan [lick-
IMP
-basin, boot-licker]
čank-o-liz-ac [basin-
O
-lick-
AGENT
, boot-licker]
(11) kill-joy vs. joy-killer; Bere-water vs. water-bearer/carrier
The -er/-ac compounds not only have more morphological pieces than the VN
exocentric compounds, but they also show an obligatory rearrangement of the two
free morphemes, the verb and the noun. One approach to this is to take VN
compounds to reect the underlying, basic word order (e.g. Lieber 1992; Murray
2004) and the -er/-ac compounds to involve a rearrangement/Move of constituents,
as illustrated below.
According to e.g. Roeper (1999: Footnote 32) and Progovac (2005b), -er/-ac
compounds have an additional layer of structure, the transitivity layer, possibly vP,
where the agentive morpheme -er/-ac is generated, the way agents are in the
Minimalist Progam.
11
Recall from Chapter 3that transitive structures are analyzed
in Minimalism as involving a vP layer, while intransitive structures, especially
absolutive-like structures, need not have the vP layer. Given the at/non-hierarchical
(basically small clause (SC)) analysis of VN compounds explored in this chapter,
these compounds certainly lack the vP layer. In this respect, they contrast with -er/-ac
compounds, which have hierarchical structure, and possibly also involve Move/
incorporation of the internal argument into the verb (e.g. Baker 1988; see also Lees
1960; Roeper and Siegel 1978; Lieber 1992).
12
10
The two compounds in (10b), coming from two different dialects, clearly illustrate the distinction in
the use of the verb form: imperative in the VN compound (ližiin both dialects), and the root form in -ac
compounds (liz in both dialects). The imperative morphology in VN compounds will be discussed at
length in Section 6.4.
11
For my purposes, the label for this projection is not as important as the need to capture the layering/
shelling effect of these compounds; a nominal equivalent of vP, an nP shell, would do just as well (see e.g.
Ferrari 2005).
12
For postulating VP in nominalizations, see e.g. Lees (1960); Lieber (1992); Fu, Roeper, and Borer
(2001); van Hout and Roeper (1998); for movement/incorporation in word formation, see e.g. Fabb (1984);
Sproat (1985); Roeper (1999). For some more recent syntactic approaches to word formation, see also Halle
and Marantz (1993); Marantz (1997); Josefsson (2001); Julien (2002); Lacarme (2002); Pylkkänen (2002);
Ferrari (2005); Roeper (2005); and references cited there.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
A comparison with the hierarchical verbal compounds 153
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(12)a)[
SC
kill joy] [
vP
er [
SC
kill joy]] [joykiller]
b) [
SC
der[i] koža][
vP
-ac [
SC
der koža]] [kož-o-der-ac]
According to this analysis, just like the small clause in general provides the platform
for building the TP or vP (Chapters 2and 3), the VN conguration provides the
foundation for building the more complex compound. As shown in (12), the -er/-ac
attaches to the small clause, building the complex compound upon the foundation of
the simpler one. What I am proposing is that the simpler, paratactic structures
literally provide a concrete syntactic basis upon which the more complex structures
have to be built. As seen in Chapter 2, there is empirical evidence that the TP is
superimposed upon the SC. The question now arises if there is any such empirical
evidence that the paratactic VN foundation provides the scaffolding for the -er/-ac
compounds. This question can best be answered by considering an alternative
analysis, which does not assume this kind of scaffolding.
An alternative analysis of -er/-ac compounds would be to treat them as NN
compounds, truck + driver, where the second noun happens to be derived by the
sufx-er/-ac (e.g. Selkirk 1982; Spencer 1991). While this analysis may work for some
-er compounds, such as truck-driver in English, it does not work for many others.
Jespersen (1954:293) points out that derivations such as sound-sleeper cannot be
derived by combining the adjective with the noun sleeper, but rather by adding -er to
the foundational combination [sound sleep]. The following examples illustrate that
neither English nor Serbian -er/-ac compounds can be uniformly derived through an
NN compounding process, given that the second noun often does not have a
derivation independently of the compound (see also Warren 1984:233; Spencer
1991; Murray 2004):
13
(13) brick-lay-er (*layer as Agent)
story-tell-er (*teller as human Agent)
tax-payer (*payer)
(14) kamen-o-rez-ac stone-carver(*rezac)
srebr-o-ljub-ac silver-lover(*ljubac)
žen-o-mrz-ac woman-hater(*mrzac)
brak-o-lom-ac marriage-breaker(*lomac)
Once again, just as is the case with small clause derivations of sentences (TPs)
discussed in Chapter 2, the layering/scaffolding approach, which takes the (VN)
13
As pointed out by a reviewer, it is not impossible to say a layer of bricks,or a teller of tales.But
these nouns still differ from other nouns in that they require such of complements. In Serbian, even such
phrasal realizations are completely ungrammatical (*rezac kamena = carver of stone). In fact, Serbian -ac
specializes for attaching to the VN basis, and is only rarely found outside of compounds, that is, attached
directly to a verb. Instead, different derivational sufxes are used to derive nouns from just verbs, such as
-ačin pliv-ač(swimm-er).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
154 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
small clause to be the foundation (see (12)), sheds light on the otherwise unexpected
properties of these compounds.
It is also of note here that -ac compounds in Serbian necessarily feature a vowel -o,
which is often seen as a linking vowel (but see Progovac 2005b for the default
agreement analysis). What this means is that -ac compounds in Serbian have four
pieces of morphology, certainly more than VN compounds. Recall the proposal in
Chapter 4that the paratactic stage of grammar was followed by a proto-coordination
stage, characterized by linkers/coordinators, with little or no semantic import. An
interesting question then arises with respect to -ac compounds in Serbian: are they
created by the coordination/linker type of grammar, or by true hierarchical gram-
mar? Most likely, these compounds have elements of both, and represent fossilized
intermediate structures.
As an alternative to the derivation in (12), one can also consider an analysis
according to which -er/-ac sufx is an ergative sufx(12), added to the absolutive
compound base, and possibly attached by adjunction (see Chapter 3for discussion
and references on the attachment of ergative phrases.)
(12)a)[
SC
kill joy] [
SC
er [
SC
killjoy]]
b) [
SC
der[i] koža][
SC
ac [
SC
derkoža]]
The added precision in theta-role assignment in -er/-ac compounds would come
from this added agentive argument, the morpheme -er/-ac, whether it is an agent in
vP (12), or an ergative adjunct (12), necessitating that the lower (absolutive-like)
argument be a non-agent. In fact, the ergative analysis would have an added benet
of explaining why -ac in Serbian can only attach to compounds (Footnote 13):
ergative arguments are typically only added to structures which already contain an
absolutive argument. If so, then Serbian -ac compounds are yet another example of
ergative syntax at work in Serbian (see Chapter 3for more examples).
As pointed out in Section 6.2, the grammar of VN compounds resembles the
grammar of absolutive intransitives, as illustrated in Tongan (5). When only one
argument is present, the absolutive argument, it can be either the agent or the theme/
patient of the action. However, once a specically marked agent is introduced
(ergative), its very presence renders the absolutive argument as semantic patient/
theme (see Chapter 3for further examples and details). This is exactly what happens
with e.g. the compound dare-devil, which is less specied in comparison to devil-
darer. In other words, the one-argument proto-grammar is underspecied when it
comes to the nature of theta roles, but the addition of an external, agent argument
leads to more precision.
Even though one compound type can be shown to be more complex than the
other, it is signicant that there is continuity of structure between the two compound
types, where one type literally provides the (paratactic) scaffolding for the other, as
illustrated in (12) and (12) above. This is consistent with the main theme of this
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
A comparison with the hierarchical verbal compounds 155
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
monograph, which is that simpler syntactic structures integrate into more complex
ones, serving as their foundation (see e.g. Chapters 2and 3for small clauses and TPs/
vPs). Some corroborating evidence for the continuity between VN and -er com-
pounds comes from the way children acquire compounds, as discussed in Section 6.7.
The following section provides yet another reason for treating VN compounds as
evolutionary fossils.
6.4A surprising verb form: The imperative
Linguists and grammarians converge on the (surprising) conclusion that VN com-
pounds in Serbian consist of an imperative verb plus a noun (Stevanović1956;
Mihajlović1992; Maretić1899; Belić1949;Živanović1904; Progovac 2005b, 2010c).
This is signicant since it may push the ultimate analysis of this compound strategy
into the deep evolutionary past.
The imperative in Serbian has a characteristic i/j ending, as can be seen from the
examples below. Although there is an overlap with some verbs (marked as IMP/3SG)
below, those verbs which have distinct endings for the base 3SG form (third person
singular present) and for the imperative (IMP) unmistakably use the imperative form
in these compounds, whether these compounds involve object-like nouns (15a) or
subject-like nouns (15b) (see also Section 6.2).
14
(15) VN compounds as common nouns in Serbian
a) with object-like nouns
cepi-dlaka [split-hair = hairsplitter] IMP
15
deri-koža [rip-skin = person who rips you off] IMP
ispi-čutura [empty-ask = drunkard] IMP/3SG
jebi-vetar [screw-wind = charlatan] IMP
jedi-vek [eat-life = one who constantly annoys] IMP
kljuj-drvo [archaic: peck-wood = wood-pecker] IMP
liži-sahan [dialectal: lick-basin = boot-licker] IMP
kosi-noga [skew-leg = person who limps] IMP
mami-para [lure-money = money-grabber] IMP/3SG
muti-voda [muddy-water = one who muddies waters] IMP/3SG
pali-drvce [burn-stick = matches] IMP/3SG
pali-kuća [burn-house = one who burns houses] IMP/3SG
14
As pointed out in Section 1.6, there are VV compounds in Macedonian which involve two imperative
verbs strung together, as in veži-dreši(tie-untie an ignorant person) (Olga Tomić, p.c. 2006).
15
The example cepi-dlaka seems problematic at rst glance since the imperative form of cepati is cepaj,
and not cepi (the base, 3SG present tense form is cepa.) However, prexed perfective counterparts of
the verb cepati, such as pre-cepiti,ot-cepiti, have the respective imperative forms as pre-cepi and ot-cepi. The
compound probably preserves a now obsolete imperative form cepi.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
156 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
podvi-rep [fold-tail = someone who is crestfallen] IMP
priši-petlja [sow-loop = who clings onto another] IMP
probi-svet [break-world = wanderer] IMP
raspi-kuća [waste-house = who spends away property] IMP
razbi-briga [break-worry = game/entertainment] IMP
seci-kesa [cut-purse = pick-pocket] IMP
vadi-čep [extract-cork = corkscrew] IMP/3SG
vrti-guz [spin-butt = restless person, dget] IMP/3SG
vrti-rep [wag-tail = restless person, dget] IMP/3SG
vuci-batina [pull-whip = tramp, good-for-nothing] IMP
b) with subject-like nouns
kaži-prst [show-nger=index nger] IMP
tresi-baba [shake-old.woman=who shakes/scares like IMP
an old woman]
visi-baba [hang-old.woman=ower: snowdrop] IMP/3SG
plači-drug [cry-friend=who commiserates with you] IMP
plači-baba [cry-old.woman=cry-baby] IMP
striži-buba [grate-bug=an insect which pecks trees] IMP
tuži-baba [complain-old.woman=who complains like
a woman] IMP/3SG
In other words, all the compounds above marked as IMP can only be analyzed as
involving an imperative verb, while the compounds marked as IMP/3SG are ambigu-
ous between the two forms. Signicantly, there are no compounds whose verb can be
analyzed as 3SG, but not as IMP. To illustrate, in seci-kesa,seci is unambiguously
IMP, as opposed to sek.
ROOT
,seći.
INF
,seče.
3SG
.
PRES
. Likewise, plačiin plači-drug is
clearly IMP, as opposed to plakati.
INF
,plače.
3SG.PRES
,plak.
ROOT
. Any unied charac-
terization of the morphological make-up of Serbian VN compounds must therefore
refer to the imperative form:
(16) (Fossilized) imperative verb + noun (default case)
16
It is signicant to note that most of these compounds are derogatory when referring
to humans. The exception are compounds created in more recent times, for ofcial
16
All the compounds in the citation form have their nouns in the default nominative case (seci-
kesa.
NOM
), and not in the accusative case (seci-kesu.
ACC
), which would be required in a sentential
imperative counterpart (Seci kesu!/*Seci kesa!Cut the purse!). When these compounds are used in a
sentence, the noun gets inected for the appropriate case assigned to the position of the whole compound.
It is important to point out that these compounds in Serbian are not interpreted as involving commands
of any kind, whether their nouns are subject-like or object-like. Only the form here is imperative, and the
native speakers are typically not aware of this. I will give further arguments below for why this imperative
form should be analyzed as a fossilized imperative.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
A surprising verb form: The imperative 157
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
naming purposes, which are not derogatory, but in fact tend to express grand wishes
(see e.g. Yonge 1863:441).
(17) VN compounds as non-derogatory names in Serbian
Bodi-roga [pierce-horn?] IMP
Bori-voj [ght-war] IMP/3SG
Brani-mir [defend-world?] IMP/3SG
Budi-mir [be-world?] IMP
Budi-sava [be-?] (town) IMP
Deli-blato [divide-mud] (town) IMP/3SG
Jezdi-mir [ride-world] IMP/3SG
Kolji-vratić[cut-throat] IMP
Kruni-slav [crown-glory] IMP/3SG
Pali-lula [burn-pipe/straw?]
17
IMP/3SG
Popi-voda [drink-water] IMP
Rasti-slav [grow-glory] IMP/3SG
Stani-mir [stay-world] IMP
Stani-slav [stay-glory] IMP
Sveti-mir [bless-world] IMP/3SG
Trpi-mir [endure-world] IMP/3SG
Strati-mir [waste-world] IMP/3SG
Veli-mir [command world] IMP/3SG
Vladi-mir [rule-world] IMP/3SG
Zlati-bor [gild-pine] (mountain) IMP/3SG
Zlati-slav [gild-glory] IMP/3SG
As can be seen, these more recent creations also feature the imperative form of the
verb (see Appendix 2for more examples).
Even though English does not distinguish imperative from base and root forms,
according to e.g. Jespersen (1954:224),VN English compounds often seem to
originate in an ironical imperative.Following Darmesteter (1894,1934), Weekley
(1916) also analyzes English VN compounds as consisting of the imperative verb +
object, and sometimes an adverb (e.g. Go-lightly).
18
17
Mihajlović(1992:16,136) suggests that Pali-lula, a place name, derives from Pali-lila, meaning burn-
straw/hay,the ancient image dating back to a pre-Christian (Old Hittite) ritual. If so, then the present-day
form Pali-lula was derived by folk-etymology: lula means a (smokers) pipe, while lila has no meaning in
present-day Serbian.
18
These data include examples from Weekley (1916); Jespersen (1954:2234;34750); Lees (1960);
Marchand (1969:3802); Adams (1973); Groom (1937). For many more examples of English VN com-
pounds, the reader is referred to these references (see also Appendix 1of this Chapter).
A reviewer disagrees with Jespersens claim, noticing that there is no imperative interpretation in English
compounds. However, Serbian VN compounds are also not interpreted as imperative, even though the
form is unmistakably imperative. This imperative form will be analyzed below as a fossilized form, akin to
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
158 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(18) bang-straw (thresher), break-back, break-fast, break-neck, break-
vow, break-water, burn-bag, burst-cow (insect), carry-all, catch-y
(plant), catch-penny, cease-re, cover-shame (plant), cover-slut
(apron), cure-all, cut-nger (plant), cut-throat, cut-purse, cut-water,
do-nought, dread-nought (originally a person; later a battleship),
ll-belly (glutton), ll-pot, nd-fault, hang-dog (originally a
person who hangs stray dogs), hang-man, heal-all (plant), hunch-
back, kill-joy, kill-lamb (plant), kill-time, know-little, know-
nothing, lack-brain, lack-bread, lack-grace, lack-land, lack-love,
lack-luster, lack-wit, lick-box, lick-dish, lick-ladle, lick-platter,
lick-pot, lick-spit, lock-jaw, make-mirth, make-peace, pass-port,
pas-time, pick-lock, pick-purse, pick-thank, pinch-back (miser),
pinch-belly, pinch-gut, pinch-penny, rake-hell (scoundrel, rufan),
rake-shame, save-all, saw-bones, scape-gallows, scare-crow,
scatter-brain, scoff-law, scrape-gut (ddler), shear-water (bird),
shufe-wing (bird), skin-int (miser), sling-shot, spend-thrift
(miser), spit-re, spoil-sport, spurn-water, stay-stomach (snack),
stop-gap, sweep-stake, swish-tail (bird), tangle-foot (whiskey),
tear-thumb, tell-tale, toss-pot, tumble-dung (insect), turn-coat,
turn-key, turn-penny, turn-skin, turn-spit, turn-table, wag-tail (bird)
While it is hard to tell what all the English words in (18) mean, if one selects only
those for which the meaning is relatively clear, and which refer to humans as opposed
to plants or objects, the list includes the following:
(18) cut-throat, cut-purse, do-nought, dread-nought (originally a person;
later a battleship), ll-belly (glutton), hunch-back, kill-joy, know-
little, know-nothing, lack-brain, lack-grace, lack-land, lack-wit,
lick-spit, pick-thank, pinch-back (miser), pinch-penny, rake-hell
(scoundrel, rufan), saw-bones, scatter-brain, scoff-law, scrape-gut
(ddler), skin-int (miser), spend-thrift (miser), spoil-sport, tell-
tale, turn-coat
They all seem to be derogatory, but even if just the majority of them were, this would
still call for an explanation. This is in addition to previously introduced compounds,
such as tattle-tale, busy-body, cry-baby, crake-bone (crack-bone). I do not know of
any other morpho-syntactic process that has created so many pejorative terms.
English optative uses of verbs, as in Long Live the King, which show no agreement with the subject. As will
be shown, this same form is also used as Historical Imperative in some dialects of Serbian. This is then just
an ancient mood form that happens to coincide with the synchronic imperative morphology in Serbian.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
A surprising verb form: The imperative 159
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
As is obvious from Appendix 2, the older compounds in Serbian that refer to
humans are also derogatory, and there are many more like that in Mihajlovićs(1992)
book. The exception is the newly created class of names in Serbian, given in (17). It is
important, though, to focus on the compounds that refer to humans, for those that
describe instruments or animals would not be useful as insults. Even though in
medieval times these compounds sometimes showed unquotable coarseness,
Weekley maintains that this is a very expressive and convenient way of naming,
which ourished in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries. Most reference books do
not include these compounds due to their obscene nature, driving them to virtual
extinction, not only in English, but in other languages as well (see also Lloyd 1968;
Darmesteter 1934; Mihajlović1992).
Rolfe (1996) has hypothesized that humans initially used verbs to issue commands
(imperative), even in the one-word (pre-syntactic stage), and much before using
verbs to make statements. The imperative in general is among the rst productive
verbal forms used by children (e.g. Bar-Shalom and Snyder 1999) (see Section 6.7). It
also tends to be the least marked verbal form across languages, and/or to preserve
archaic patterns (see e.g. Dixon 1994:189; Kuryłowicz 1964:137).
Imperatives arguably also may provide some continuity with animal calls and
other communicative signals, in the sense that they are calls for action, typically in
the here-and-now. This would be consistent with e.g. Greeneld and Savage-
Rumbaughs(1990) and Tomasellos(2008) claims that non-human primates use
communicative signals, both vocalizations and gestures, almost exclusively for
imperative purposes. In addition, Millikan (2004) has argued that animal commu-
nicative signals are both indicative and imperative in force.
If the capacity to use the VN compound strategy emerged at an early stage of
language evolution, when one-word utterances and imperatives ruled, then it is
plausible that the compound-like names would have been put together using what
was already therethe imperative-like verbs.
19
But it is important to keep in mind
that one is dealing here with a proto-imperative form, not with what is meant by
imperative in present-day languages. This proto-imperative would have had a much
wider range of functions than the modern imperative has today. In this respect, the
quote by Speijer (1886:2713) regarding the imperative form in Sanskrit is useful:
Sanskrit imperativecomprises more than is conveyed by its European name. It is
not only the equivalent of what we are wont to understand by this mood, but it is also
expressive of wishes, benedictions, possibility, and doubt . . .
19
Mihajlović(1992:16,136) suggests that Pali-lula, a place name, derives from Pali-lila, meaning burn-
straw/hay,the ancient image dating back to a pre-Christian (Old Hittite) ritual. If so, then the present-day
form Pali-lula was derived by folk-etymology: lula means a (smokers) pipe, while lila has no meaning in
present-day Serbian.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
160 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In fact, this proto-imperative form is used in Serbian in other surprising functions
as well, all of which can be considered as fossils. For example, some petried optative/
subjunctive forms such as English (19) are rendered as imperative forms in Serbian
(20), the same forms that are found inside VN compounds:
20
(19) Long Live the King! God Forbid!
(20) a. Pomozi Bog!
Help.
IMP
God
b. Hvali Bog!
Praise.
IMP
God
Another example comes from the archaic Historical Imperative, which used to be
productive in narratives, but is now only used in some dialects of Serbian (Stevanović
1966:41213):
(21) A on ti skini motiku s ramena, zabij je u zemlju, ostavi fenjer kraj
sebe i sedi na ladju.
And he take off-
IMP
the spade from his shoulder, stick-
IMP
it
into the ground, leave-
IMP
the lantern by himself, and sit-
IMP
onto the boat.
It is prhaps relevant for these considerations that the Slavic imperative descended
from the optative mood expressing wishes (often indistinguishable from commands),
which in turn descended from the ancient PIE injunctive (e.g. Belić1960; Kiparsky
1968; Kerns and Schwartz 1972:23; Stevanović1974).
21
The injunctive was initially an
unmarked mood, but later specialized for non-indicative, irrealismoods, express-
ing wishes, commands, and/or exclamations).
22
It is possible that VN compounds
preserve approximations of this ancient mood morphology, which in Serbian hap-
pens to be rendered as imperative, via optative (see Progovac 2006,2010c).
It is also relevant in this respect that swearing in present-day languages often
involves verb forms which look like imperatives, but are not true imperatives in the
modern sense of the word. These include e.g. Damn (you)! Fuck (you)!), as discussed
in Dong (1971).
23
Such uses of verbs in swearing in fact resemble optatives in the
sense that they impose wishes/curses upon someone. In that sense, such swear
20
There is a name in Polish that has exactly the same make-up as (20b), as illustrated in (22)in
Section 6.5.1.
21
According to Kiparsky (1968:51), in Vedic, Greek, and Old Irish, injunctives are also a source of
historical present, equivalent to the Serbian Historical Imperative discussed in the text.
22
See Section 2.2for the discussion of (tenseless) injunctive mood in PIE in connection with small
clauses, which are arguably tenseless creations.
23
Dong is the pseudonym for linguist James McCawley. Notice that present-day imperatives necessarily
feature reexive pronouns, such as Wash yourself !Reexives are also possible in some swear phrases
(e.g. Fuck yourself ) on a different interpretation, although not with others (e.g. ??Damn yourself !).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
A surprising verb form: The imperative 161
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
expressions can be seen as negative versions of optative phrases such as Long Live the
King!in(19). These connections and overlaps with optatives and injunctives make it
more plausible to accept the (proto-)imperative analysis of VN compounds (see
Progovac 2010c for more details). Section 6.6discusses evolutionary signicance of
swearing.
If indeed such VN compounds were among the rst two-word creations involving
proto-Merge, then it stands to reason that early language would have made use of
what it already had at its disposal: (proto-imperative) verbs. The beginning of the
category verb in human language may have been the (one-word) imperative utter-
ance. The next section introduces data from additional languages, establishing
further crosslinguistic parallels in the structure and use of VN compounds.
6.5Crosslinguistic distribution and parallels
VN compounds are found in a variety of languages, including non-IE, showing
striking parallels in form and imagery, as illustrated in this section.
6.5.1VN compounds in other Slavic languages
In addition to the imperative analysis of Serbian compounds (previous section), the
imperative analysis of VN compounds has also been proposed for other Slavic
languages, including Bulgarian (Andreĭčin 1955) and Macedonian (e.g. Koneski
1954). For Polish, it is sometimes claimed that iis a connecting/linking vowel (e.g.
Ułaszyn 1923). Polish lost the imperative in iby the end of the sixteenth century, and
Mirowicz (1946) advocates a diachronic imperative analysis of VN compounds in
Polish. According to Klemensiewicz, Lehr-Spławiński, and Urbański (1964:2567),
VN compounds in Polish went through several stages, including an imperative stage.
In any event, the diverging analyses of Polish and Serbian compounds simply reect
the fact that the marker i/j is still recognizable as an imperative marker in Serbian, but
no longer in Polish. Once Polish lost the connection with i/j as an imperative marker,
the original proto-Slavic paratactic VN strategy may have been reinterpreted as a
proto-coordination strategy, reanalyzing i/j as a meaningless linker (see Chapter 4for
the progression of syntactic stages from parataxis to (proto-)coordination.)
The following are some examples from Polish, Russian, and Macedonian, featur-
ing the same i/j ending.
(22) Polish (supplied and/or glossed by PawełRutkowski, p.c. 2006)
Chwali-bóg [praise-god] (name)
dusi-grosz [squeeze-penny, miser] (cf. English pinch-penny)
goli-broda [shave-beard, barber]
hulaj-dusza [roister-soul, reveler, rioter]
Kopaj-gród [dig-town] (place name)
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
162 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
łami-strajk [break-strike, strike-breaker]
łami-główka [break-head.
DIM
, puzzle, riddle]
mąci-woda [muddy-water, troublemaker, brawler] (cf. Serbian
muti-voda)
moczy-morda [soak-muzzle, sot, drunkard]
obieży-świat [trot-world, globe-trotter]
pali-woda [burn-water, ibbertigibbet, madcap]
pasi-brzuch [pasture-belly, glutton, lazybones]
pędzi-wiatr [drive-wind, ibbertigibbet, madcap]
rzezi-mieszek [cut-purse, pick-pocket]
wali-góra [topple-mountain, giant of Polish folklore who
could topple mountains]
wierci-pięta [wiggle-heel, dget]
wozi-woda [carry-water, water-carrier]
(23) Russian (Yana Pugach, Maria Babyonyshev, Dina Brun, Natasha
Kondrashova, Asya Pereltsvaig, p.c. 2006)
lomi-golovka [break-head, brain-teaser/puzzle]
sorvi-golova [cut-off head, dare-devil]
perekati-pole [roll-over-eld, tumbleweed]
24
verti-hvostka [wag-tail, a bird]
(24) Macedonian (Olga Mišeska Tomić, p.c. 2006)
gazi-bara [tread-water]
isturi-čorba [stick-out broth, tactless person]
zajdi-sunce [set-sun, sunset]
6.5.2VN compounds in Romance languages
Verb-noun compounds are productive in some Romance languages, including Span-
ish, Italian, and French, which suggests that they might have acquired additional
structure, at least the newly formed ones, and that they conform better to modern
syntactic patterns. However, VN compounds are still marginal in Rumanian, where
they belong to affective and familiar language,and where they are exclusively
epithets applied to persons in a contemptuous fashion, as are the earliest examples in
the other Romance languages(Lloyd 1968:7).
Lloyd claims that Romance VN compounds were originally nicknames, usually
playful and humorous, and that it was only around the twelfth/thirteenth century
that the strategy was extended to names of places, instruments, occupations, plants. It
could be that Romance VN compounds acquired more structure at this juncture in
24
Tumble-weed itself belongs to the VN compound type, as per discussion in Section 6.2.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Crosslinguistic distribution and parallels 163
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
time, distinguishing themselves from the original pattern, still preserved in Germanic
and Slavic languages.
25
Lloyd (1968:20) believes that these compounds spread to
more neutral contexts due to their expressiveness, and also due to the lack of a
competing pattern, i.e. the lack of the English -er compound type (e.g. dish-washer).
According to Lloyd (1968), many of the original VN compounds were used by the
lowest classes of society, were coarse and humorous, and because of that did not enter
the texts and reference books.
Here are some examples from Spanish, Italian, and French.
(25) Spanish (Murray 2004; Eugenia Casielles, p.c. 2012)
calienta-pollas [heat-penises, a tease]
espanta-pájaros [scare-birds, scarecrow]
lame-culos [lick-asses]
lava-manos [wash-hands, bathroom sink]
lava-platos [wash-dishes, dishwasher]
para-brisas [stop-wind, windshield]
para-caídas [stop-falls, parachute]
para-sol [stop-sun, sunshade]
pica-or [peck-ower, hummingbird]
rasca-cielos [scrape-sky, skyscraper]
rompe-cabezas [break-heads, puzzle] (cf. Polish and
Russian)
saca-corchos [extract-corks, corkscrew]
saca-muelas [extract-teeth, hack dentist]
(26) Italian (Hall 1948b: 175-6; Murray 2004)
akkatta-pane [beg-bread, beggar]
akkiappa-kani [catch-dog, dog-catcher]
faci-male [do-evil, evil-doer]
gratta-cielo [scrape-sky, skyscraper]
25
Not only are VN compounds in some Romance languages productive, but they also can be recursive,
and often contain plural nouns inside them (see e.g. Murray 2004; Ferrari 2005). One example of a
recursive Spanish VN compound is limpia-para-brisas wipe-stop-wind, windshield wiper(Murray
2004). In English, only the complex -er counterparts are recursive (e.g. dishwasher user). A recursive V
[VN] combination seems to me to be completely out of reach for English and Serbian VN compounds
(*scare-pick-pocket (one who scares pick-pockets); *dare-spoil-sport (one who dares spoil-sports); *muti-
ispi-čutura (one who confuses drunkards)). Serbian and English VN compounds are neither productive
nor recursive, and are thus likely to be better approximations of the postulated proto-syntactic constructs
(for recursion, see Chapter 4). Italian and French VN compounds also differ from Serbian counterparts
with respect to gender specication, as discussed in Section 6.2. It is also of signicance that the productive,
more recently created, VN compounds in Romance mostly refer to instruments, rather than people,
contrary to what one nds in English and Serbian fossil compounds, as well as in Rumanian, as pointed
out in the text. The idea is that the original creations of this kind targeted people, possibly for ritual insult
purposes (Section 6.6).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
164 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
lava-piatti [wash-plate, dishwasher]
metti-male [put-evil, trouble-maker]
spremi-limoni [squeeze-lemon, lemon-squeezer]
(27) French (some from Nyrop 1908; also Kate Paesani, p.c. 2006)
accroche-coeur [engage-heart, irt]
Boil-eau [drink-water] (name)
cache-col [hide-neck, scarf]
coupe-bourse [cut-purse, pick-pocket]
coupe-gorge [cut-neck, rough neighborhood]
essuie-glace [wipe-windshield, windshield wiper]
grippe-sou [seize-up-penny, skinint]
perce-neige [pierce-snow, snowdrop]
porte-bonheur [carry-happiness, lucky charm]
saute-mouton [jump-sheep, leap-frog]
tire-bouchon [cork-screw]
It is intriguing that the imperative analysis has also been proposed for Romance VN
compounds by many, including Diez (1838); Shulze (1868) (this reference also
consults Sanskrit and Slavic and Germanic families); Darmesteter (1894)(avery
extensive and comprehensive study and defense of the imperative analysis in
Romance); Darmesteter (1934); Prati (1931,1958); Migliorini (1946); Lloyd (1968)
(see the latter reference for an overview of the imperative and non-imperative
approaches to VN compounds). Most historical grammars generally followed Dar-
mesteters imperative analysis (e.g. Meyer-Lübke (1895:21314) and subsequent work;
Adams (1913); de Diego (1914); Rohlfs (1954); while some advocated the third person
singular analysis (e.g. Bolufer 1920:170). The imperative analysis is challenged and
argued against in Meunier (1875); Osthoff (1878) (Osthoff was criticized in Tobler
1886); Tollemache (1945); Heinimann (1949); Hall (1964, also 1948a,b). More recently,
while Floricic (2009) explores an imperative analysis, Ferrari (2005) has argued
against the imperative analysis, in a very thorough study of word formation in Italian
and other languages.
My claim here is that those compounds which approximate proto-syntactic
structures are more likely to exhibit ancient verb forms, including proto-imperative
forms.
26
While preservation of structure in this close manner is by no means
guaranteed or necessary, it is nonetheless possible that this syntactic mold (even
though certainly not specic words) was passed on from generation to generation,
with only minor adjustments to the morphology of the verb form, to best approximate
26
In Romance, the (proto-)imperative analysis may be more appropriate for the original compounds
than for the recently coined, productive compounds referring mostly to instruments.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Crosslinguistic distribution and parallels 165
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
the original compound. It is thus intriguing that so many researchers, working on
diverse languages, converged on a conclusion that VN compounds involve a form that
looks like imperative, even though such an analysis is obviously counterintuitive, un
vero controsenso,as put in Tollemache (1945:181). By embracing the imperative
puzzle, as well as the traditional exocentric characterization of VN compounds, one is
led to seek an explanation in the deep evolutionary past.
6.5.3VN compounds in non-Indo-European languages
VN compounds with comparable morphological make-up, and with comparable
metaphors, can also be found in non-IE languages, as illustrated in this section
with Tashelhit Berber, Twi, and Chinese.
(28) Tashelhit Berber (spoken in Morocco; Dris Soulaimani, p.c. 2007)
slm-aggrn [suck.in-our, buttery]
ssum-izi [suck-y, thrifty person]
ssum-sitan [suck-cow, insect]
(29)Twi
(spoken in Ghana; Kingsley Okai, p.c. 2011)
Atoto-botom [dip-in pocket, pick-pocket]
Kukru-bin [roll feces, beetle]
Nom-mmogya [suck blood, vampire]
Wodi-nii [kill person, killer]
(30) Chinese (Murray 2004; Haiyong Liu, p.c. 2006)
dean-shin [stay-stomach, refreshments]
liing-shyh [lead-affairs, consul]
ua-eel [dig-ear, ear-pick]
It should be noted in this respect that Tashelhit ssum-sitan [suck-cow] in (28)is
closely parallel to Old English burst-cow, which also meant insect,and the drinking
image for a miser drynk-pany [drink-penny] (1) is reminiscent of ssum-izi [suck-y]
in Tashelhit (28). Likewise, Twi kukru-bin [roll feces, beetle] in (29) involves the same
image as English tumble-dung (insect), and there is also a clear parallel between the
Twi word atoto-botom (29) and English pick-pocket.
The following table reveals further parallels in morphological make-up and meta-
phorical expression; many more can be found across the data provided in this
chapter.
(31) English Serbian French Polish Twi
Drink-water Popi-voda Boil-eau
cut-purse seci-kesa coupe-bourse rzezi-mieszek
pick-pocket atoto-botom
cut-throat Koji-vratićcoupe-gorge
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
166 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
lick-pot liži-sahan
Bere-water wozi-woda
Burn-house pali-kuća
wag-tail vrti-rep
pinch-penny grippe-sou dusi-grosz
tumble-dung kukru-bin
According to Lloyd (1968), the original VN compounds described people who were
lazy, useless, careless in dress, idle, contemptible, criminal, stupid, uncultured,
bullies, busybodies, atterers, gluttons, drunkards, gloomy, cheating and swindling,
misers, defective, of contemptuous professions.
27
If these descriptive words were not
available to ancient humans, which is a reasonable assumption to make, then the VN
naming strategy would have increased their expressive power (as well as the insulting
power) enormously. In other words, the ability to use such compounding strategy
successfully would have constituted an enormous expressive advantage over just
using single-word utterances, an advantage which could have been subject to sexual
selection, as discussed in the following section.
6.6VN compounds and sexual selection
My proposal in this chapter is that VN compounds may represent the best fossils we
have for the postulated intransitive, paratactic, two-word grammar stage, which
moreover involves a verb(-like element) acting as a proto-predicate. Not only is the
structure of these compounds rudimentary and unsyntactic in almost every sense of
modern syntactic theory (at structure, no headedness, no subject/object differenti-
ation, no recursion), but this compound strategy specializes for derogatory reference
and insult. Moreover, this strategy clearly illustrates how one can create hundreds of
complex and abstract concepts out of a handful of concrete base words. This alone
would have been enough to demonstrate to the ancient hominins the power of
(proto-)syntax, and to involve them in a possibly cut-throat race toward evolving
the capacity for syntax. This section looks into how creations comparable to VN
compounds would have contributed to the sexual selection of (proto-)syntax.
It is important to point out that I am not saying that this kind of naming/insult
strategy was the only benet of proto-syntax, and the only reason for selecting syntax.
Not at all. There are just so many benets of being able to combine words into larger
meaningful units that it would be trivial and pointless to list them here. What I am
saying is that I have isolated the data that point to just one of these benets, and even
this one alone would have afforded such a signicant concrete advantage that it could
27
Busy-body is probably another VN compound expressing a concept that can hardly be expressed so
succinctly and vividly in any other way.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
VN compounds and sexual selection 167
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
have by itself triggered selection for proto-syntax. The more such factors at work, of
course, the faster and more complete the selection would have been. Chapter 7offers
a concrete scenario which outlines how this process could have involved genes.
VN compounds across languages are typically playful, pejorative, and/or vulgar.
Their expressive potential seems unmatched by any other (nick)naming strategy. As
put in Darmesteter (1934:443), the artistic beauty and richness of VN compounds (in
French) is inexhaustible.
28
Mihajlović(1992) was equally impressed by the VN
compounds in Serbian. He devoted his career to traveling to remote places and
collecting over 500 Serbian place and people names in the form of VN compounds.
He reports that these condensed compositions pack in them frozen fairy tales,
proverbs, and ancient wisdoms and metaphors (1992:89).
According to Progovac and Locke (2009), formation and use of VN compounds
may have been an adaptive way to compete for status and sex in ancient times. Their
successful use would have enhanced relative status rst by derogating existing rivals
and placing prospective rivals on notice; and second by demonstrating verbal skills
and quick-wittedness (see Chapter 7for a hypothetical scenario). Darwin (1874)
identied two distinct kinds of sexual selection: aggressive rivalry and mate choice
(see also Miller 2000), both of which seem relevant for the proposed use of exocentric
compounds. Darwin (1872) also pointed out that strong emotions expressed in
animals are those of lust and hostility, and that they may have been the rst verbal
threats and intimidations uttered by humans (Code 2005:322).
Throughout recorded history, sexually mature males have issued humorous
insults in public (Locke 2009; Locke and Bogin 2006). These verbal duelsare
taken to discharge aggressive dispositions, and provide a way to compete for
status and mating opportunities without risking physical altercations (Marsh
1978;Parks1990). In this respect it is signicant that vulgar VN compounds in
Serbian target males. For example, jebi-vetar [screw-wind, charlatan] is typically
used to describe males. Even those compounds that seemingly describe females
are typically used in reference to males, for a doubly insulting effect (Mihajlović
1992): laj-kučka [bark-bitch, loud and obnoxious person]; lezi-baba [lie-(old.)
woman, loose woman or man].
In fact, it is hard to come up with an alternative explanation for the creation of
hundreds of such brilliant and humorous insults. The vast number of these com-
pounds (reported to have been in the thousands in medieval times) clearly exceeds
what is needed for just survival. Such excess is typically ascribed to sexual selection
forces. According to Miller (2000:369): if language evolved in part through sexual
28
In his own words, at the time of Renaissance, Ronsard introduced [VN compounds] in a new and
original manner as epithets: Jupiter lance-tonnerre, le soleil donne-vie, Hercule porte-massue ...Itwould be
well could French poets again make use in lofty poetry of this class of epithets; for they may attain Homeric
breadth(Darmesteter 1934:443).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
168 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
choice as an ornament or indicator, it should be costly, excessive, luxuriant beyond
the demands.
29
In this respect, Franks and Rigby (2005) have performed experiments which found
that males increase their creativity with language not only in the presence of
attractive females, but also in the presence of male competitors. They did not nd
either of these effects with female subjects. Their test phrases involved unusual
combinations of e.g. two nouns (such as book bicycle), and the subjects were asked
to provide possible referents for such noun phrases. As independently established,
the relation interpretation (such as a bicycle for delivering books) is considered by
females to be less creative than property interpretations (such as a book with two
wheels).Their study thus provides evidence that males even today display their
creativity and cognitive skills by using language. As pointed out in e.g. Miller (2000)
and Franks and Rigby (2005:208), human mate selection often involves display of
cognitive traits by creativity in language use. Moreover, creativity is considered to be
highly correlated with intelligence (Miller 2000).
The possibility that sexual selection played a role in evolving syntax is consistent
with the ndings reported in e.g. Ullman (2008) that there is a gender difference
when it comes to language processing (see also Pinker and Ullman 2002), as
discussed in Chapter 7.
6.7Corroborating evidence and testing grounds
As argued in Section 6.3, the simple, paratactic VN compound structure provides a
foundation/scaffolding for building hierarchical -er/-ac compounds in English and
Serbian. Another reason to consider exocentric VN compounds as derivationally
related to their -er/-ac counterparts comes from language acquisition studies, as
pointed out in e.g. Lieber (1992). In addition, Clark, Hecht, and Mulford (1986)
conducted an experiment in which they prompted children to produce novel -er
compounds (see also Clark and Barron 1988). At around three, children consistently
produced VN compounds such as grate-cheeseinstead of cheese-grater,”“rip-
paperinstead of paper-ripper,and bounce-ballinstead of ball-bouncer.
According to the authors, children begin by forming compounds with VN predicate
order, basically from verb phrases (Clark, Hecht, and Mulford 1986:26).
30
This seems
29
As pointed out by a reviewer, there is no reason to believe that there were that many compounds at
the onset of the paratactic stage, and I am certainly not claiming that. The sheer number of these
compounds attests to their enormous creative potential, as well as to the fact that people got very good
at creating them at some point, for some reason.
30
While many have reconstructed SOV as the proto-world word order (e.g. Givón 1979; Newmeyer
2000; see also Aske 1998; Lightfoot 1979; and Section 3.1), according to Miller (1975), the oldest recon-
structible stage of IE (Indo-European) may have been VSO. Miller (1975:32) notes that in IE the productive
compound type was SV, OV, but that VS, VO was archaic and residual. IE also had a marked conjunct
order, with the verb at the beginning (Watkins 1963), another residue of VS order. Lehmann (1969:12f)
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Corroborating evidence and testing grounds 169
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
to indicate that children start with the foundation, before they can build the
suprastructure.
At the next stage, there is a tendency to produce compounds with misplaced afx:
dry-hairer/dryer-hair(cf. the target hair-dryer) and x-biker/xer-bike(cf.
bike-xer). It is only later that children begin to place the noun before the verbal
form, creating the adult NV-er order. At the very least, this nding supports the
proposal that VN compounds are more primary and simpler in structure than their
hierarchical counterparts, as they emerge earlier in language acquisition. Moreover,
the stages and struggles in the acquisition of these compounds reinforce the conclu-
sion that NV-er compounds are built upon the foundation of the paratactic VN
compounds (Section 6.3).
In addition, the imperative in general is among the rst productive verbal forms
used by young children (Bar-Shalom and Snyder 1999). It is conceivable that the
imperative is a paradigm case of an unmarked mood form, and that for that reason it
emerges early, whether in evolution or acquisition. Moreover, as reported in e.g.
Bates et al.(1979), childrens early speech acts are manipulative, expressing wishes
and commands (the typical uses of optative, as per Section 6.4), while the informative
(declarative) speech acts emerge later. The acquisition data are thus consistent with
the view that the grammar behind VN compounds represents an evolutionary
primary, foundational strategy.
In addition to language acquisition, there is some corroborating evidence from
language representation in the brain. It has been reported that swearwords are
processed by the more ancient structures of the brain, suggesting that they them-
selves might be ancient creations. According to e.g. Code (2005:317), swearwords (as
well as some other non-propositional uses of language) might represent fossilized
clues to the evolutionary origins of human communication, given that their process-
ing involves the right hemisphere, basal ganglia, thalamus, and limbic structures.
Basal-limbic structures are phylogentically old and the aspects of human communi-
cation associated with them are considered to be ancient too (e.g. van Lancker and
Cummings 1999; Bradshaw 2001).
31
Moreover, as pointed out in reference to other syntactic fossils, such as small
clauses (Chapter 2) and absolutives/unaccusatives (Chapter 3), neuroimaging experi-
ments can be devised to compare and contrast the processing of VN compounds and
their hierarchical -er counterparts (Progovac 2010b). The prediction of the proposal
claims that these verb-initial compounds are derived from underlying sentences having the order with the
verb preceding the object or subject. Perhaps (proto-)imperatives had a preference for initial verb order,
and the compounds that fossilize such imperatives are verb-initial. Needless to say, resolving this issue is
beyond the scope of this book. But, as pointed out in Section 4.4.5, word order in the two-word proto-
syntax stage was probably not xed.
31
Note also that Tourettes Syndrome, a disorder caused by basal ganglia-limbic connection dysfunc-
tion, is characterized by involuntary production of obscene speech.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
170 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
in this chapter is that the processing of VN compounds involves less syntactic
activation in Brocas areas, and less lateralization in the left hemisphere, but more
reliance on subcortical structures of the brain, and the right hemisphere. This would
especially be the case with the compounds involving swearwords, as per the discus-
sion above. The Appendix returns to this testing opportunity in more detail.
6.8Concluding remarks
In conclusion, the grammar behind VN compounds is an excellent candidate for a
fossil of proto-syntax, involving the simplest possible merger of a verb-like and a
noun-like element. Little about these compounds makes sense except in the light of
evolution. They show rudimentary syntax, defying the most fundamental postulates
of modern morpho-syntax, including headedness and hierarchy. In addition, their
semantics is underspecied, with no differentiation between thematic roles, and
therefore between subjecthood and objecthood. Additionally, these compounds
specialize for derogatory reference, which invokes an explanation in terms of ritual
insult and sexual selection. Adding further to the exotic nature of VN compounds,
their verb surfaces in a (proto-)imperative form in some languages.
These crude compounds, typically exhibiting the most base and basic of vocabu-
lary, can nonetheless express abstract (human) traits not only with astounding
succinctness and vividness, but also with humor and playfulness. Using this kind
of compounding strategy at the dawn of language would have not only augmented
the expressive power of human language enormously (Chapter 7), but it would have
also provided a foundation for further vocabulary and structure building, in keeping
with the main theme of this monograph.
6.9Appendix 1: Additional English VN compounds
As names in English (most are taken from Weekley 1916)
Ben-bow (bend-bow), Bere-water (bear-water), Bran-foot (possibly from brand-foot,
for animals/slaves), Break-speare, Burn-house, Catch-love (love = wolf), Cant-well,
Crake-bone, Cut-bush, Cut-fox, Cut-love (love =wolf), Cut-right, Culle-hare (culle
= kill), Culle-hog (culle = kill), Culle-bolloc (culle = kill), Do-best, Do-bet, Do-little,
Do-well, Doubt-re (from arch. dout”–in charge of furnace), Dread-nought,
Drink-low, Drynk-pany (drink penny), Drink-water, Eat-well, Gather-all, Gather-
cole (coal or cabbage), Gather-good (good = property, wealth), Go-lightly, Hab-good
(from hap=to snatch), Hack-block, Hack-wood, Hate-crist (crist = Christ), Hop
(e)-well (well = stream/pool), Hurl-bat, Kill-buck (place name in the state of New
York), Kis-sack, Lack-land, Lack-love, Love-gold, Love-good (probably good = God;
contrast with Hate-crist), Love-well, Make-joy, Make-mead, Make-peace, Mar-brow,
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Appendix 1: Additional English VN compounds 171
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Mar-wood, Mean-well, Mend-market, Pass-eld, Passe-low (cross-water), Perce-
forest (perce = pierce), Perce-val (pierce-vale), Pers-house (pers = pierce), Pil-beam
(pil=peel, barker of trees), Pinch-back, Porte-rose, Rack-straw (rack = rake), Rid-land
(rid = clear), Rid-wood (rid = clear), Save-all, Scare-devil, Scatter-good (good
= wealth/property), Shake-lady, Shake-lance, Shake-rose, Shak-shaft, Shake-speare,
Shake-staff, Shear-gold (coin-clipper), Shear-lock, Shear-wood, Shave-tail (shave
= shove), Spare-good (good = property, wealth), Spare-water, Spin-garn, Spyll-
payn, Stab-back, Stand-even, Stand-fast, Strangle-man, Swep-stak, Thack-well
(thatcher), Thumb-wood (cf. mar-wood;thumbarchaic for to handle clumsily),
Tickle-penny, Tire-buck (tire = tear), Tread-away, Tread-gold, Tread-well (well
= stream), Trede-water, Trust-god, Tuck-well, Turn-bull, Turn-penny, Turn-pike,
Wage-spere, Wag-horn, Wag-staff, Wag-tail, Wast-all, Win-bow, Win-penny, Win-
rose, Wipe-tail, Wrynge-tail
Online dictionaries of slang; dictionary.com
(It is of note here that for some of these compounds it is not possible to tell if they are
VN or NN compounds.)
fuck-ass (fool), fuck-bag (disgusting person), fuck-ball, fuck-brain, fuck-buddy, fuck-a-
bush, fuck-chop (an imbecile), fuck-head, fuck-dog (dog-fucker), fuck-face, fuck-freak,
screw-ball, shit-ass, shit-bag, shit-bullets (terried person; cf. Serbian Seri-sabljić,
Appendix 2), shit-bird, shit-head, shit-face, shit-stick
6.10 Appendix 2: Additional (mostly coarse) VN compounds as Serbian
people and place names (taken from Mihajlović1992)
Čepi-guz IMP/3SG cork-butt
Češi-guz IMP/3SG scratch-butt
Ćuli-brk IMP/3SG stick-moustache
Deri-gaća IMP rip/tear-underpants
Deri-kučka IMP rip-bitch
Deri-muda IMP rip-balls(place name, a steep hill)
Draži-vaška IMP/3SG tease-louse
Gladi-kur IMP stroke-dick(womanizer)
Gori-guzica IMP burn-butt(person in trouble; cf. Burn-
breeches)
Jebi-baba IMP fuck-old.woman(unselective womanizer)
Jebi-sestra IMP fuck-sister/cousin
Jebi-vetar IMP fuck-wind(charlatan)
Kapi-kur IMP drip-dick(name of a slow spring)
Kosi-noga IMP skew-leg(person who limps)
Kovrlji-guz IMP drag-butt
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
172 Exocentric VN compounds: The best fossils
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Kradi-gaća IMP steal-underpants
Krpi-tur IMP patch-butt(poor person)
Laj-kučka IMP/3SG bark-bitch(loud and obnoxious person)
Lezi-baba IMP/3SG lie-old-woman(loose woman or man)
Lezi-tetka IMP/3SG lie-aunt(loose woman or man)
Liz-guz IMP/3SG lick-butt
Muz-govno IMP/3SG milk-shit
Nabi-guz IMP/3SG shove-butt
Neper-gaća IMP/3SG no-wash-underpants
Peči-govno IMP/3SG burn-shit
Piš-kur IMP/3SG piss-dick
Plači-guz IMP/3SG cry-butt(cf. cry-baby)
Plači-pička IMP cry-cunt(vulgar version of cry-baby)
Plaši-vranac IMP/3SG scare-crow
Poj-kurićIMP/3SG sing-dick(womanizer)
Prdi-kučka IMP/3SG fart-bitch
Prdi-vuk IMP/3SG fart-wolf
Prdi-zec IMP/3SG fart-rabbit
Prti-mud IMP/3SG carry-balls
Puš-kur IMP/3SG smoke-dick
Razbi-dupe IMP/3SG break-butt(steep terrain)
Seri-sabljićIMP/3SG shit-sword
Seri-vuk IMP/3SG shit-wolf
Visi-guz IMP hang-butt
Vuci-guz IMP drag-butt(slow-moving person)
Vuci-klašnja IMP drag-stockings(carelessly dressed person)
Vuci-kuja IMP drag-dog(stray dog)
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Appendix 2173
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
7
The plausibility of natural selection
for syntax
Evolution is the only physical process that can create an eye because it is the only
physical process in which the criterion of being good at seeing can play a causal role
(Pinker and Bloom 1990:710)
7.1Concrete and selectable advantages accrued by each stage
This chapter considers how each new postulated stage of syntax accrues concrete
communicative advantage(s) over the previous stage(s), and how such advantage(s)
would have been subject to natural/sexual selection. More specically, I show how
the progression from one-word stage (no syntax), to paratactic two-slot syntax
(Section 7.2), to hierarchical vP/TP stage (Section 7.3), brings about clear incremental
communicative benets. Section 7.4details one concrete hypothetical scenario for
progressing from one stage to the next, invoking sexual selection. Section 7.5con-
siders how these syntactic stages may t into the timeline of human evolution.
Doubt has been repeatedly expressed regarding the possibility that aspects of
syntax were naturally/sexually selected. Most of the dismissive reactions mention
abstract syntactic postulates such as Subjacency (Chapter 5), or EPP (requirement
that every clause has a subject), pointing to the improbability of such principles being
sexually selected given that even their status in syntax is not clear, let alone their
usefulness to survival. As famously put by Lightfoot (1991:69), Subjacency has many
virtues, but [ ...] itcould not have increased the chances of having fruitful sex.
However, as concluded in this book, phenomena associated with Subjacency are
not the essence of syntax. In fact, islandhood effects are largely unexplained and
poorly understood phenomena in syntax, and their characterization still remains at
the level of observation and description, as discussed at length in Chapter 5. Given the
framework developed in this monograph, it transpires that islandhood is in fact an
epiphenomenon of evolutionary tinkering, that is, an ancient, foundational state of
grammar, which does not sanction Move. To put it slightly differently, islandhood is
the default state of proto-grammars, and only some relatively recent, innovative
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
constructions can override this default state, giving an illusion of Subjacency. On my
approach, which illuminates the issue from a shifted perspective, it is the ability to use
these innovative constructions, and the communicative benets that come with
them, that would have been selected, rather than Subjacency. So, in order to explore
a gradualist approach to syntax, one needs to decompose syntax along dimensions
which are concrete and specic enough for selection to target, and at the same time
consistent with the basic theoretical postulates of syntax. This is the most important
pursuit of this monograph.
Speaking in broad terms, my argument is that (more) complex syntax brings about
adaptive advantages in the following ways. First, it automatizes/streamlines the
expression of various syntactic phenomena, such as transitivity, tense, subordination,
which can otherwise be expressed, but only vaguely and with less speed and precision
(see also Pinker and Bloom 1990, among others). One rather amazing property of
human language is the speed with which we can talk and understand others talking.
The less we have to guess as to what goes with what, and the more we can rely on
subconscious, automatic processes to arrange the basic information, the faster and
more undistracted our speech will be. Syntax does its part by providing that frame
which organizes the information in a reliable and predictable manner.
Second, and related to the advantage identied above, by offering more precision in
expression, more complex syntax allows us to escape the vast vagueness associated with
underspecied proto-grammars and to break away from the here-and-now, as well
as from the prison of pragmatics more generally, enabling the famous displacement
property of human language (see e.g. Hockett 1960). Third, and related to the above, given
that a more complex grammar is much more self-sufcient and much less reliant on
pragmatics,itismuchbetteratexpressingstrange,evennon-existentconcepts,contri-
buting to the capacity for novelty and creativity. Several other properties of language only
emerge in the later stages of syntax, including hierarchy and the capacity for recursion.
The following two sections break down these general advantages into specicones.
7.2From one-word to two-word utterances: Vagueness galore
A progression from one-word to two-word stage, i.e. from no syntax to rudimentary
(paratactic) syntax, would have brought about enormous communicative advantages
to our ancestors. While syntacticians often dismiss any precursors to complex syntax
as irrelevant or even impossible, the argument that I build throughout this mono-
graph is that this simple paratactic syntax is the foundation for any further develop-
ments with syntax, the scaffolding without which it would not have been possible to
reach the complex realm.
1
As such, the emergence of productive two-slot syntax may
1
Jackendoff (1999,2002) also considers that previous stages of evolution, such as Bickertons(1990)
protolanguage, provided a foundation for subsequent stages. Jackendoff and Wittenberg (2014) also
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From one-word to two-word utterances: Vagueness galore 175
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
have been the most dramatic breakthrough in the evolution of human language. In
this section I focus on the advantages of this stage brought to light by the concrete
proposals and fossil evidence discussed in this monograph, but there is no doubt that
there would have been many more advantages of transitioning into a two-word stage.
Consider now some hypothetical examples that can shed light on the communi-
cative possibilities in the one-word stage (1). One should keep in mind that one-word
utterances would continue to be available in the two-word stage as well, as per the
theme of this monograph that the emergence of a new stage preserves the achieve-
ments of the previous stages:
(1) Snake! . . . Gone! . . . You! . . . Out! . . . Eve! . . . Run!
The string in (1) could mean that a snake has been spotted, and that you should be
gone and out, and that Eve should run, too. Or it could mean that the snake was
spotted, but is now gone, thanks to you, and now Eve should go out and run. Or
maybe you should run to save Eve. There are various other possibilities for (1) as well,
each conveying very different messages. The one-word stage would have been
frustratingly vague, at least from the point of view of the modern person. Still, at
the point when rst words emerged, they would have been a source of joy, a novel
device for display, in addition to being somewhat informative. Darwin (1872) argued
that neophilia, i.e. love of novelty, was an important factor in the diversication and
rapid evolution of e.g. bird song. Primates in general are extremely neophilic, and this
is certainly the case with humans. This clearly has important implications for sexual
selection of language.
On the other hand, the two-word stage, as postulated in Chapters 2to 4, would
have been able to express basic intransitive (absolutive-like) propositions (or predi-
cations) by combining a verb-like and a noun-like category, as illustrated in the
following examples, analyzed here as fossils of this stage:
(2) Come winter, . . . Problem solved.
(3) Pao sneg. Stigla pošta. (Serbian)
fell.
PART
snow arrived.
PART
mail
(4) Ayam makan (Riau Indonesian, Gil 2005)
chicken eat
The chicken is eating.
Somebody is eating the chicken.
(5) rattle-snake, cry-baby, scare-crow, hunch-back
emphasize the layering and preservation of older stages. However, they characterize their stages and
layering differently, as discussed in Section 1.6.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
176 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Early child language also abounds in two-word utterances. Consider the following
hypothetical small clauses used in the two-word stage:
(6) Marie cut. Me go. Eve gone. Snake roll.
Even though two-word grammars are still quite underspecied, the vagueness is
signicantly reduced in comparison to the one-word stage.
2
Here, in the two-word
stage, it is at least clear which verb is associated with which noun, and it is also
typically the case that the referent of the noun is a major participant of the action
specied by the verb, providing evidence of (proto-)predication, as characterized in
Section 3.4.2.
If the proto-words from (6) were not grouped into (small) clauses (7), many more
options for interpretation would be readily available, including the following one,
highly unlikely for (6): Look at Mary. She is cutting me. Go, Eve. The snake is gone.
Roll now.
(7) Marie ...Cut...Me...Go...Eve...Gone . . . Snake . . . Roll . . .
Still, as discussed in the following section, it takes hierarchical syntax, such as vP and
TP layers of structure, to unambiguously distinguish between e.g. subjects and
objects. This is exactly the scenario compatible with the incremental, step-by-step
evolution of syntactic complexity, in response to communicative pressures to reduce
vagueness in the expression of argument structure.
There is one more characteristic that goes hand-in-hand with vagueness and
reliance on context, especially when it comes to distinguishing subjects from objects.
The pragmatic context can easily give a clue as to who is eating what in sentences
such as (4). If we are observing a chicken walking in a yard, then the rst interpret-
ation in (4) would make sense; if we are observing a chicken on a plate, then only the
second interpretation would make sense. However, the syntax of (4) on its own does
not distinguish these possibilities. But notice now that by utilizing the pragmatic
context we catch ourselves expecting the utterances to make pragmatic sense, to be
consistent with how the world is. If so, at the postulated absolutive-like stage, it would
have been hard to express something very strange, or plain impossible, such as a
chicken eating Tom, or an apple eating a chicken. This means that displacement,
understood not only as a shift away from the here-and-now, but also as a shift away
from the realm of probable or possible, would have been much harder to realize with
two-slot grammars, and especially with one-word utterances, as also discussed in the
following section. The property of displacement, understood in this way, would only
2
It is essential to have an appropriate standard of comparison whenever we talk about adaptiveness or
usefulness of syntax; that is, we need to ask the question: more useful or more precise in comparison to
what?Likewise, when one claims that language/syntax is not good for communication, the question is
again: in comparison to what?
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From one-word to two-word utterances: Vagueness galore 177
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
ourish with the hierarchical stage, and it might have in fact been a major driving
force behind the evolution of the hierarchical stage.
However, this two-word stage can already piece together a way to express transi-
tive events. In addition to combining two words into a (small) clause, two-slot
grammars can also paratactically combine two such clauses. This most probably
would have been a later development, and perhaps a different sub-stage in the
paratactic stage in the evolution of syntax, but it is still in essence a paratactic,
symmetric stage. Recall from Chapter 3that the earliest stages of Nicaraguan Sign
Language tend to use sequences of two intransitive clauses when dealing with
multiple animate arguments, such as (9)or(10), in lieu of transitive structures,
such as (8) (Kegl, Senghas, and Coppola 1999:21617; Senghas et al.1997; see also
Aronoff et al.2008 for Al-Sayyid Bedouin Sign Language):
(8) *WOMAN PUSH MAN.
(9) WOMAN PUSHMAN REACT.
(10) WOMAN PUSHMAN FALL.
The paratactic binary grammar above can already express transitivity, but in a
roundabout way, and not as directly and unambiguously as a true transitive sentence
such as (8) would. This is exactly the claim here, that language evolved in the
direction of streamlining and automatizing the expression of certain syntactic phe-
nomena, including transitivity, starting from a stage in which such grammatical
phenomena could be expressed, but only with vagueness/imprecision, and with the
help of context.
One can nd such binary clause fossils in a variety of languages, as discussed in
Chapter 4. Most of them are used to express some temporal or causal relationships
between two clauses.
3
(11) a. Come one, come all.
b. Easy come, easy go.
c. Garbage in, garbage out.
(12) a. Wo dua, wo twa (Twi)
you sow you reap
b. Wo hwehwea, wo hu
you seek you nd
The symmetrically/paratactically attached clauses above (created by the Operation
Conjoin of Chapter 4) are interpreted as linked, but merely by iconic means. The
3
Thanks to Kingsley Okai (p.c. 2011) for the Twi data. See many more examples from other languages in
Section 4.2.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
178 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
event of the rst clause is taken to precede and/or cause the event of the second
clause. This is iconic because it mimics the intended ordering of the two events.
Reversing the order of these clauses would completely change their meaning (e.g.
??
Easy go, easy come;
??
You reap, you sow). In contrast, fully edged hierarchical
counterparts are not subject to this ordering condition (e.g. You will reap (only) if you
sow), as they rely on functional categories and syntax to express their meaning in a
more self-reliant fashion. This iconicity of ordering is also relevant for the precursors
to transitivity, such as (910). There, again, the causing event is placed before the
caused event (as also discussed in Sections 3.4.1and 1.6).
The data discussed in this section illustrate two points. First, unlike one-word
grammars, two-slot paratactic grammars can express, with some consistency, ele-
mentary predication by combining e.g. a verb and a noun, as well as some temporal/
causal relationships between two clauses. The two-slot grammars are thus more
precise and more expressive than one-word grammars, but less precise and less
expressive than hierarchical grammars, suggesting again an incremental increase in
communicative capabilities, exactly the scenario in which evolutionary forces can
operate.
But the communicative/expressive advantages of a two-word stage certainly do not
end here. As shown in Chapter 6, exocentric VN compounds are fossil structures
which specialize for derogatory reference, and which provide evidence of ritual
insult/sexual selection for (simple) syntax (see Progovac and Locke 2009; Progovac
2012). While it is certainly possible to insult somebody by using single words, ones
ability to create stunning insults increases by leaps and bounds if one can combine
two proto-words (see Section 7.4for a detailed evolutionary scenario).
(13) cry-baby, busy-body, turn-coat, kill-joy, pick-pocket, fuck-head
(14) ispi-čutura (drink.up-askdrunkard), guli-koža (peel-skinwho
rips you off), cepi-dlaka (split-hairwho splits hairs), muti-voda
(muddy-watertrouble-maker), jebi-vetar (screw-wind
charlatan), vrti-guz (spin-buttdget); tuži-baba (whine-
old.womantattletale) (Serbian)
The VN compound data taken from a variety of languages make it clear that these
compounds typically combine basic, concrete words, often denoting body parts and
functions, in order to express vivid and memorable abstract concepts. Selecting for the
ability to quickly produce (and interpret) such compounds on the spot would have gone
a long way towardnot only solidifying the capacity to use paratactic two-slot grammars,
the foundation for more complex grammars, but also the capacity for building abstract
vocabulary. As discussed in Section 7.4, sexual selection for the capacity to produce and
interpret such compound insults would have been one of the factors driving the
progression from the one-word stage to the two-word paratactic stage.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From one-word to two-word utterances: Vagueness galore 179
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In sum, having a bunch of single words to refer to individuals or actions without
using syntax (one-word stage) would have already been very useful to our ancestors,
much more useful than not having any words at all, but much less useful than having
two-word grammars, as the latter provide clear and concrete communicative bene-
ts. The next section considers the advantages of transititioning to the stage of
hierarchical syntax.
7.3From the two-word stage to hierarchical syntax: Evolving
transitivity, displacement, and recursion
7.3.1Introductory remarks
If my proposal in this monograph is on the right track, then some of the design
features of human language, such as displacement (see e.g. Hockett 1960; Hockett and
Altmann 1968), emerged through evolutionary tinkering, that is, by gradually evolv-
ing hierarchical grammars (with e.g. vPs and TPs). Such hierarchical grammars offer
enough precision to be able to stand on their own, without much reliance on context,
and thus to describe situations that are distant, non-existent, or that even challenge
common sense. These capabilities increase signicantly in the transition from the
two-word stage to the hierarchical stage, given that in this stage one does not have to
rely much on pragmatic context, which typically connes one to the available and the
observable. Both displacement and recursion would have been very difcult to
express, if possible at all, in the two-word stage, as discussed in this chapter.
My claim is thus that these amazing properties of human language did not just
materialize out of thin air, but that they had to evolve through a painstaking process
of scaffolding and tinkering, with two-word grammars providing the ultimate syn-
tactic foundation. This process was guided by the evolutionary pressures to tinker
with these grammars to be ever more and more expressive, ever more and more
precise, and to be able to communicate more and more kinds of ideas. It must have
taken constant and relentless acts of creativity and novelty on the part of our
ancestors to get us where we are now. And many good hominins, with otherwise
perfectly good genes, had to make room for those who happened to be just a bit better
at this game.
4
7.3.2Grammaticalizing tense
As discussed in Chapter 4, progressing from the paratactic (two-word) stage to the
hierarchical functional category stage may have proceeded through a linker/proto-
conjunction stage, where the linker initially served only to solidify proto-Merge, that
4
More precisely, just a little bit better at whatever the local game with language was, in that particular
location, at that particular time.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
180 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
is, to provide more robust evidence of combinatorial syntax. Perhaps the initial
meaningless linkers occurring between a subject and a predicate of a small clause, or
between two clauses, gradually became tense particles, or subordinators/complement-
izers, enabling more automatic expression of tense/time reference, as well as subor-
dination. Or perhaps tense markers developed from other sources, such as verbs.
Whatever the source, the emergence of the sentential functional projection such as
TP renders more automatic and undistracted the expression of temporal, modal, and
other properties, allowing speakers to break away from the here-and-now more easily
and more efciently. As also shown in Chapter 2, tenseless root small clauses in
modern languages tend to specialize for the here-and-now, and cannot be easily
modied by adverbials such as three years ago,either in Serbian or in English:
(15) a. *Stigla pošta pre tri godine.
arrived mail before three years
b. *Pao sneg pre tri godine.
fell snow before three years
(16) a. *Case closed three years ago.
b. *Me rst three years ago!
This kind of specialization is possible in modern languages when they also exhibit the
alternative TP strategy:
(17)a.Pošta je stigla pre tri godine.
mail
AUX
arrived before three years
b. Sneg je pao pre tri godine.
snow
AUX
fell before three years
(18) a. The case was closed three years ago.
b. I was rst three years ago!
In the literature on evolution, evolving multiple means to the same end is considered
to create the opportunity for the evolution of specialization through the division of
labor (e.g. Carroll 2005), as pointed out in Section 2.2. The retention of these small
clause fossils in the here-and-now contexts can be explained if more complex
grammars do not bring about a tangible advantage in these contexts, i.e. if they are
an overkill in these contexts. An example of a grammatical overkill would be to use
The point is being taken,in lieu of Point taken;or Serbian Sneg je pao(Snow is
fallen) in lieu of Pao sneg.Another more subtle example of a grammatical overkill
would be to use Serbian On me udara!(He me hits), as opposed to the middle On
se udara!,as per the discussion in Section 3.4.2. See also Du Bois (1985) for the
preference to use intransitive underspecied grammars in discourse, as discussed in
Section 3.5.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From the two-word stage to hierarchical syntax 181
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
There are also languages across the world that do not show an obligatory gram-
maticalized TAM (tense/aspect/mood) system, but can optionally express the rele-
vant temporal/modal properties through the use of adverbials (see e.g. Skou, a
Papuan language, and Riau Indonesian (Gil 2014), and Tongan (Churchward
1953).
5
Indeed, according to Gils(2014) study based on a sample of 868 languages,
377 are categorized as having optional TAM marking, while 491 are classied as
having obligatory/grammaticalized TAM marking. This shows that variation in this
respect is not only possible but widely attested. This is again consistent with the
gradualist approach explored here, which postulates only a paratactic, small clause
foundation as the common syntactic core. Beyond the paratactic platform, languages
will diverge with respect to where and what to build on top of this foundation (see
Section 7.5for more discussion).
In various other modern languages, including Russian (e.g. Pesetsky 1982) and
Hebrew (Rothstein 1995), one nds mixed systems, or perhaps we should call them
split systems, on analogy with the split systems attested in case marking, as discussed
in the following section. In these systems the present tense in general remains
unmarked, while the other tenses show obligatory TAM markings:
(19) Ivan veren. (Russian)
Ivan faithful
(20) Ivan byl veren.
Ivan was faithful
The present tense in formal semantics literature is normally characterized as
coincident with the time of the context in which the sentence is produced
(Chierchia and McConnell-Ginet 1990:266). If so, then grammaticalizing present
tense is somewhat superuous, an overkill, as it does not bring about a clear
advantage. Most importantly, this indicates that the TAM system in one single
language can be split/mixed, involving either TPs or TP-less structures, with the
split aligning with communicative considerations. As will be shown in Section 7.3.3,
similar mixed systems exist in the realm of transitivity, the so-called split-ergative
systems.
A hierarchical TP system makes it easier to express claims about the (distant) past,
as well as to make future and counterfactual claims, all hallmarks of displacement.
This is not to say that these notions cannot be expressed without functional categor-
ies and projections, perhaps through the use of loosely adjoined adverbs. This is only
to say that functional projections such as TP facilitate a more automatic, unambigu-
ous, and undistracted way of expressing such notions.
5
See also Section 2.2for Kiparskys(1968) claim about pre-Indo-European in this respect.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
182 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
7.3.3Grammaticalizing transitivity
Breaking away from the here-and-now, and from the prison of pragmatics in general,
which is the essence of displacement, is much easier to achieve with more articulated
grammars. As pointed out above, the two-word stage does not distinguish between
subjects and objects, and it is typically pragmatics that sheds light on the intended
meaning of the sentence in this regard. The same certainly holds of one-word
grammars.So, imagine encountering the following one-word (21) and two-word
(22) utterance sequences in the early stages of language:
(21) Apple ...Eat...Go...Tom.
(22) Appleeat...Go Tom.
These kinds of utterances are much less precise (more vague) than a corresponding
hierarchical sentence such as (23) below, and can receive many interpretations in
addition to the one in (23):
(23) Tom will (go and) eat the apple.
But it is important to point out that the meaning that does not readily come to mind
with respect to (2122) is the one expressed in (24), even though there is nothing in
the form of these utterances that would preclude that interpretation.
6
(24) The apple will (go and) eat Tom.
This suggests that pragmatically odd (or impossible) notions can hardly be expressed
without hierarchical syntax, given that simple underspecied structures are in close
alliance with pragmatics. In this respect, adding a layer of transitivity makes it
possible now to unambiguously make the applethe subject of eating a human
being (24), no matter what the context is, or what common sense tells us.
As discussed in Chapter 3, there is an abundance of fossilsof this two-slot
absolutive-like stage across languages. For example, absolutive-like constructions
characterize nominals, certain middle constructions, as well as certain compounds,
even in nominative-accusative languages. Ergative-absolutive languages exhibit such
absolutive structures in the verbal domain as well, at least in some cases, given that
most of the languages classied as ergative are in fact not purely ergative, but split-
ergative systems.
Certain types of splits in split ergative languages provide a compelling argument
for the claim that transitivity serves to alleviate vagueness. Many split ergative
languages are mixed languages in the sense that they are ergative-absolutive with
6
A reviewer suggests that the reading in (24) should be obtainable even from (21/22). This is something
that can be subjected to psychological testing to determine the statistical likelihood of interpreting (21/22)
as something pragmatically implausible, such as (24).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From the two-word stage to hierarchical syntax 183
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
some types of nominals, such as inanimates, but nominative-accusative with others,
such as animates (e.g. Gair 1970 for Sinhalese, a language spoken in Sri Lanka).
7
Clearly, this kind of split aligns with communicative considerations, as the ambiguity
is much more likely to arise with the animates than with the inanimates. As
Tchekhoff (1973:285) notes in connection to Tongan, a yam cannot eat any more
than a box can dig a hole.
Consider again some hypothetical examples from the postulated absolutive-like
stage:
(25) Yam eat. Tree cut. Water drink.
(26) Chicken eat. Chicken cut. Boy cut.
While there is little possibility for confusion with (25), where yam,”“tree,and
waterare readily interpreted as objects of the expressed actions, there is often
possibility for confusion with animates (26), as they can both cut and be cut, and they
can both eat and be eaten. Thus, the split in these cases is designed to reduce
vagueness where it is likely to arise, as per the discussion in e.g. Comrie (1989:
12437).
Comrie (1989:130) in fact observes that there are some languages, such as Hua
(spoken in Papua New Guinea), where the occurrence of a special transitivity marker
(e.g. accusative) is conditioned not by any specic rigid cut-off point in the animacy
or deniteness hierarchies, but rather . . . [by] the assessment of likelihood of confu-
sion,which is left to the speaker in the particular context. This is a clear case of
syntax responding to communicative considerations in modern times, which more-
over illustrates exactly the kind of transitional scenario that could have paved the way
toward grammaticalized transitivity. Aissen (2003) looks at a variety of languages
with what she terms differential object marking (DOM),which include ergative/
accusative splits, and concludes that DOM is a compromise between two contradict-
ory principles, Iconicity and Economy. For her, Iconicity is at work when overt case
marking occurs on an object which can easily be confused for a subject, while
Economy simply avoids any case marking.
7
The animacy scale that these processes typically target can be expressed as:
(i) Human > Animate > Inanimate (se e.g. Silverstein 1976; Aissen 2003)
Another dimension along which case marking can split is deniteness (Aissen 2003). As reported in e.g.
Dixon (1994), in the Australian language Dyirbal, pronouns denoting rst and second person adopt the
nominative-accusative pattern, while the rest of the nominals, those lower on the animacy/deniteness
hierarchies, adopt an ergative-absolutive pattern.
There are various other kinds of ergative/accusative splits, including those which are based on aspect.
A discussion of these is outside the scope of this monograph. My goal here is simply to show that there exist
ergative/accusative splits which clearly align with communicative considerations. I am not claiming that all
splits necessarily do.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
184 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Recall from Section 7.3.2that in mixed/split TAM systems, present tense usually
remains unmarked, possibly TP-less, as it is the context in which more complex TP
marking does not bring about a tangible advantage. The same considerations hold in
the realm of transitivity in this case: simpler, vP-less structures are used in those
(typically inanimate) contexts in which more complex vP structures yield no signi-
cant communicative advantage. This ties in well with one of the themes of this book,
that simpler, fossil structures co-exist with more complex structures because they are
more economical, and because there are many situations in which more complex
structures are just an overkill.
The DOM marking discussed above is also found in nominative-accusative lan-
guages. As pointed out in e.g. Comrie (1989:132) and Gil (2014), in languages in which
accusative marking is optional, it typically occurs on animate and/or denite nouns,
but not on inanimates, as illustrated below for Spanish and Serbian:
(27) El hombre vio a la mujer. (Spanish)
the man saw
ACC
the woman
(28) El hombre vio la silla
the man saw the chair
(29) Milan donosi jež-a. (Serbian)
Milan brings hedgehog.
ACC
Milan is bringing a hedgehog.
(30)Milan donosi Jež.
Milan brings hedgehog
Milan is bringing (the magazine called) Jež.
This leaves enough room for the view that the key syntactic properties, including
transitivity and Tense/TP, emerged for communication purposes, and gradually so.
This is not consistent, however, with the view that syntax in all its complexity, arose
only once, as a single event, shortly before the H. sapiensdispersion out of Africa
(e.g. Chomsky 2005; Berwick and Chomsky 2011), as discussed in Section 7.5. Neither
is this consistent with the concomitant view that communicative considerations
cannot have anything to do with (the emergence of) syntax.
A reviewer suggests that the saltationist view mentioned above does not necessarily
exclude the possibility that vP, TP, and CP emerged later through grammaticalization
processes, and that what emerged as a single mutation were the design featuresof
language, such as Merge, Move, recursion. However, as I have argued, these design
features of syntax cannot be there without the functional categories in question. If the
whole package of syntax emerged as one single event, as per saltationist claims, then
this package would have certainly included the functional projections/categories, as
they are the postulates of syntax upon which all the other postulates rest. Take away
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From the two-word stage to hierarchical syntax 185
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
vP, TP, CP, DP, and other functional categories, and you get pretty much what I have
reconstructed here, a precursor to language operating with short (and at) small
clauses, with hardly any syntax to speak of (see Section 1.1for Berwick and
Chomskys2011 view about precursors; also Section 1.6). But, much more import-
antly, one should not be second-guessing what these saltationists might have had in
mind, or what they might have in mind in the future. If somebody is proposing
something, then they should make their proposal fully explicit, as well as under-
standable and vulnerable to verication.
The reviewer further suggests that communicative considerations can play some
role in Chomskys(2010) and Berwick and Chomskys(2011) view as well, even
though their view is that language emerged (in full) to facilitate thought (inner
speech), rather than communication; once this thought system was externalized
(e.g. pronounced), then it could have proved useful for communication as well.
More precisely, according to Berwick and Chomsky (40-1), in the very recent past,
maybe about 75,000 years ago, ...an individual . . . underwent a minor mutation that
provided the operation Merge,which brought about recursive structured thought. It
was at some later stage that the language of thought was connected to the external
speech, quite possibly a task that involves no evolution at all.
However, what I have proposed in this book is not just that once language in its full
complexity arose (for some other purpose), it so happened that it was also useful for
communication. My proposal here and elsewhere is that communication pressures
were the very reason why language evolved. These communication considerations
shaped the very design of human language, and determined each incremental step of
its evolution. Furthermore, on my approach, each new stage relies heavily on the
previous stage, and the innovations it introduces are small and incremental, so that
they can be understood and negotiated by the rest of the community as soon as they
arise. This incremental approach removes any rationale for the claim that language
could not have evolved for communication purposes.
8
Going back to the communicative benets of the vP/TP equipped syntax, it is
useful to recall that, the more vague the expression, the more it relies on the
pragmatic context and on pragmatic plausibility in general, because of our tendency
to seek pragmatic sense. In contrast, more complex language/syntax is better able to
take us away from the concrete and observable in the here-and-now, toward what is
less concrete, and less observable, and ultimately to what is non-existent or plain
8
As for Berwick and Chomsky (2011), one reason for their proposal that syntax and Merge were initially
useful only for thought, but not for communication, has to do with that one person in their evolutionary
scenario who got the language mutation. Their argument is that this one single person would not have had
anybody to communicate with, and that communication could start only much later, after this mutation
was passed down through several generations. This kind of conundrum only arises if you insist that
language/syntax arose as one single event/mutation, but not if you envision an incremental, gradualist
approach, with precursors, as discussed in the preceding and following sections of this chapter.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
186 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
bizarre. While our ability to talk nonsense is clearly not always advantageous, one
would have to concede that it makes it easier to talk about things that do not exist, but
that might have existed, or might exist in the future. It is easier to describe a different
world, and then perhaps to change the world so it ts this new description. Or, if one
is skeptical about displacement being adaptive in this way, there certainly remains the
great potential for using language to amuse and surprise, i.e. for display purposes.
In other words, the evolutionary pressures to proceed to a transitive (hierarchical)
stage would have included the following tangible benets: (i) more precision in the
expression of argument structure; which in turn leads to (ii) capacity for displace-
ment, not only in the sense of temporally/spatially removed (relevant also for TP),
but also removed from the ordinary, common sense, or plausible; which in turn
opens doors to (iii) the capacity to tell amazing and entertaining stories; or just to
(iv) stun and amuse with novel and fantastic claims. Again, it is entirely possible that
those who were just a bit more creative with using language in these ways left more
offspring than the rest, leading to the spread of this capacity. As pointed out in
e.g. Tallerman (2013b: 95), even in modern societies the most eloquent speakers tend
to be granted the highest status, which in turn is correlated with greater reproductive
success (e.g. Locke 2009 and references there). In this respect, Miller (2000:350)
points out that the speaker benets much more from holding the oor, than the
hearer benets from listening.
7.3.4Recursion
As argued in Chapters 2,3, and 4, it is only in the hierarchical stage that true
recursion becomes available, making it possible to embed, repeatedly, e.g. one
point of view within another.
9
Recall that fossil structures, such as tenseless root
small clauses in English (31) and Serbian (32), cannot embed at all, in contrast to full
nite CPs (33,36), which show innite recursion:
(31) *Him worry [me rst]? *Him happy [problem solved]?
(32) *Ja mislim [(da) stigla pošta].
I think (that) arrived mail
(33)Ja mislim [da ti znaš[da je stigla pošta].
I think that you know that AUX arrived mail
As pointed out in Chapter 4, full CP structure, with a designated complementizer, may
be necessary to realize the full (unlimited) recursion potential in the clausal domain.
9
As pointed out in the previous chapters, I adopt the typical, standard characterization of recursion in
linguistics, according to which recursion refers to the ability to repeatedly embed/insert one type of
category (e.g. a CP or a DP), within another category of the same type (for a detailed discussion of this,
see Section 4.4).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From the two-word stage to hierarchical syntax 187
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
AsshownindetailinSection4.4, it is possible to identify, by looking at the three
strategies for syntactic integration, a gradual progression toward achieving unlim-
ited recursion. While parataxis already allows the interpretation of one view
embedded within another (34), and coordination may allow two such levels of
embedding, with some special tinkering (35), it is only subordination, with a
designated functional projection, that can achieve unlimited recursion (36). In
that sense, parataxis and coordination provide excellent precursors to CP recursion
(Bouchard 2013:60 also observes that parataxis is an alternative way of expressing
what subordination does).
(34)a.
?
Marc is a linguist[you know,] [Mary knows].
b. Marc is a linguist[you know it,] [Mary knows it].
(35) Marc is a linguist, [and you know it,] [and Mary knows that].
(36) You know [
CP
that Mary knows [
CP
that Marc is a linguist]].
As pointed out in Chapter 4, it seems that all hierarchical phenomena considered in
this book, including subordination and transitivity, have alternative routes, involving
non-hierarchical, paratactic structures. This is consistent with the proposal in this
book that parataxis provides a precursor, a foundation for building hierarchical
structures.
Going back to the paratactic example in (34), the clauses in it should be
analyzed as occurring next to each other, loosely Conjoined, in the sense of
iteration, rather than true recursion (Kinsella 2009, Section 4.4). The nature of
the semantic link between the clauses will then be gured out pragmatically.
Perhaps one way to implement this distinction is to consider that a specic
functional category, such as CP (36), is processed in a direct, streamlined way by
the specialized syntactic areas in the brain, such as Brocas area. On the other
hand, Conjoin (responsible for parataxis) may be delegated to more general and
more scattered processing strategies, which work quite well when only two ele-
ments are Conjoined, but which are challenged when multiple combinations are
attempted, as is the case with e.g. No come, no money, no shelter,asdiscussed
earlier (see Sections 3.1and 4.4.2).
This is again exactly what evolutionary forces can operate upon: there is already a
precursor to recursion, that is, a precursor to the ability to embed one viewpoint
within another, but it is only good for one or two levels of such embedding.
In contrast, CP subordination, which specializes for this kind of embedding, gives
rise to unlimited recursion. With CP subordination, unlike with coordination or
parataxis, you do not need to gure out and guess what various pieces might or might
not be referring tothe syntax gives you no choice but to interpret each CP as
embedded within the higher CP. It is a fool-proof strategy. This is the sense in which
gradual, step-by-step, evolution should be understood: a new stage does not bring
about something totally new, but something just a bit more streamlined.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
188 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
This also goes a long way toward answering some more general questions that
linguists sometimes pose, as discussed briey in Section 7.3.3. For example, a reviewer
wonders how an innovation gets to be received or interpreted by the rest of the
community. In other words, how do the listeners know that the speaker is using vP
transitivity or CP recursion, if they themselves do not have it (yet)? As proposed in
Chapter 3, transitivity is something that also emerges gradually, step by step, and
there are precursors to it, so that the listeners are prepared to recognize when a more
streamlined expression of transitivity is being presented.
10
As shown above (as well as
in Chapter 4), the same is true for the emergence of CP recursionthe precursors are
already in place, and nothing totally new is being introduced. That is in fact a
powerful argument in favor of the claim that the evolution of language had to
proceed in small increments, so that something that is already available in one
stage can become just a bit more streamlined and unambiguous in the next. While
the issue raised by the reviewer poses a problem for saltationist accounts (see
Footnote 8for the saltationist response to this question), the gradualist approaches
to evolution in general are designed to address exactly these types of concerns.
One also must keep in mind that evolution is not a predestined or predetermined
course of progression to ever higher and brighter realms. It is full of random twists
and turns, and full of attempts and failures (see Section 7.3.5for some discussion). In
other words, it is not that the transitive stage emerges as soon as one person utters a
verb, a subject, and an object in one breath. Many conditions have to be met for a
community of speakers to converge on an innovation like that, and even when all
such conditions are met, it is still up to chance whether the innovation will take hold
or not. But this is also the case with grammaticalization processes that take place in
modern times. Also, as discussed in Chapter 3, there exist different solutions to the
problem of transitivity, not just one perfect solution.
The same goes for CP and other types of recursion. Modern languages that do not
make use of nite subordination have been reported to exist today (see e.g. Dixon
1995 for Dyirbal; Mithun 1984,2010, for various Native American languages; Everett
2005 for Pirahã). As pointed out in Chapter 4, languages like German and Serbian do
not exhibit DP recursion with possessives, of the kind illustrated below for English:
(37) Johns mothers friends kitten
It follows that recursion cannot be the dening property of human language, or an
automatic consequence of Merge, as it is perfectly possible to have coherent gram-
mars which make use of Merge, but which do not show recursion. Moreover, as seen
in the previous sections, it is also possible to have coherent (even if underspecied)
grammars without a vP or TP layer.
10
The use of the term precursorhere is not meant to suggest that this is some kind of unstable
structure awaiting further evolution. These can be perfectly stable and persistent structures by themselves.
They are only seen as precursors from the perspective of transitive structures.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From the two-word stage to hierarchical syntax 189
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Finally, taking into account everything that has been discussed so far, it seems that
what needed to evolve through selection/adaptation when it comes to syntax, was,
rst of all, uency in the paratactic (at) stage (Section 7.2), and then the hierarchical
stage (Sections 7.3.2and 7.3.3), with a vP, TP, or an equivalent functional projection.
These two transitions would have constituted truly signicant breakthroughs in the
evolution of human language. This does not necessarily mean that the addition of yet
another functional layer on top of this, such as CP, had to have involved natural
selection. Once the brain (and language) evolved sufciently to be able to support two
or three levels of hierarchical layering, it may be that after that the third or fourth
layer of structure would have been accommodated with the existing capabilities.
11
The next section discusses this.
7.3.5Historical change vs. language evolution
First of all, it is maintained in e.g. Hurford (1990) and Fitch (2008, and references
cited there) that historical change is relevant for language evolution. Fitch (2008:483)
points out that, for example, the historical loss of tone is relevant for evolutionary
considerations because it proves that such a change is possible in principle. Even if
that were all there is to it, historical change can at least provide corroborating
evidence for specic evolutionary proposals, such as the ones explored in this book.
However, the reviewers wonder how one can distinguish between just historical
change and language evolution regarding the postulated stages of language evolution.
Historical change is typically considered to be a change which has no genetic basis or
consequences. In contrast, language evolution (and evolution in general) is typically
associated with genetic changes and selection. However, these two processes may not
be as disjointed as one typically considers them to be. Let us look at one concrete,
although completely hypothetical, scenario suggesting how this distinction between
historical change and genetic evolution can get blurred.
Suppose we are in a community of speakers of a tone language, which is under-
going a (historical?) change to a non-tone language, i.e., it is losing its tones.
12
I have
chosen to discuss tone here because it has already been discussed in the context of
genetics, and because it seems easier to imagine selection for tone.
13
Still, the same
11
As discussed in the Appendix, several neuro-linguistic studies on syntax found that more hierarchical
layering involves more activation in the brain.
12
Very roughly speaking, tone can be characterized as the use of pitch (high, low, or contours thereof)
to distinguish not only the meaning of words, but also grammatical categories (e.g. Yip 2002). Some
languages, e.g. Bantu, use tone to distinguish tense categories. It is also of relevance here that the historical
change affecting tone typically goes in the direction of tone loss, rather than the development of tone (see
also Fitch 2010:483, quoting Jespersen 1922). One salient example of such change is the recent loss of tone
in Swahili, a Bantu language.
13
For example, the papers by Dediu and Ladd (2007) and Dediu (2008) have reported that there is a
small genetic difference between populations speaking tone languages vs. those speaking non-tone
languages. Their particular take on this is that the new gene variants provide a small bias toward learning
a non-tone language, and against learning a tone language (but see e.g. Diller and Cann 2012 for criticism).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
190 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
logic could apply to any other historical change. For concreteness, let us say that this
community has 1,000 speakers. Suppose now that the large majority of this popula-
tion, say 90%, has a good genetic basis for learning and using tone, that is, for quickly
and effortlessly producing and discriminating the distinctions made by tone. Suppose
next that the rest 10% are still uent and functional speakers, but have something of a
speech impediment, which is observable in their less than optimal use of tone.
14
Perhaps they speak in a hard-to-understand monotone. As pointed out to me by
Haiyong Liu (p.c. 2014), in Mandarin Chinese, a tonal language, there is a special
term for good speakers, which has to do with how dramatically they make the tone
distinctions: die dang qi fu (lit. up-down, fall-rise).
Going back to the hypothetical scenario, suppose now that those individuals who
speak in a monotone, or exhibit other imperfections with their use of tone, may not
have inherited all the genetic basis necessary for streamlined processing of tone,
but managed to survive anyway perhaps because they were t in other ways.
Perhaps they were stronger or more attractive than most other people. The reason
why such a high number, 90% of the population, got to have this genetic basis for
tone, presumably gained by natural/sexual selection, would attest to the obsession
that humans seem to have with perfectuse of language, which often trumps other
desirable traits.
But now suppose that tone is lost in this community of speakersa historical
change has occurred. People who are perfect at it no longer hold an advantage over
those who are not. To use the terminology from Deacon (2003) (see Section 7.5.1), the
genetic basis for being good at tone is now masked; that is, it is no longer accessible to
selection processes, because it is no longer observable. This means that the tone-
challenged 10% are no longer at a disadvantage, and that the tone-savvy 90% are no
longer at an advantage. In fact, the opposite may now be true, because those 10% who
managed to survive in spite of being tone-challenged may be more attractive or
healthier people in general. Suppose now that after many, many generations the
pendulum starts to swing in favor of the 10%, and the population now becomes say
70% tone-challenged, losing the genetic basis that was originally selected for tone.
This would essentially constitute a genetic change that is inextricably linked to a
historical change.
But this genetic change is not something that would be readily observable. While
we would observe the historical change, we would not necessarily observe any genetic
change associated with it. And if this new hypothetical generation, which is now only
14
See e.g. Wong et al.(2009) and Nan, Sun, and Peretz (2010) for some discussion of tone and language
disorders, still a largely unexplored topic. The reader should keep in mind that the scenario I am
considering here is purely hypothetical, and is not meant to make any specic claims either about tone
disorders or the consequences of tone loss.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
From the two-word stage to hierarchical syntax 191
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
30% tone-ready, were to acquire tone again (an unlikely scenario), the pendulum may
swing back again. But, crucially, I do not see how one can guarantee that natural
selection, including sexual selection, would not operate in such cases. As Fitch (2008:
522) puts it, language change does not entail a cessation of selection.
This hypothetical example can also help illustrate what I mean in this book by
evolution of syntax via natural selection. It is not some kind of straightforward
progression toward a clearly dened lofty goal, but rather it involves just small and
random local advantages, in competition with a host of other potential advantages,
which can swing back and forth. It is only in hindsight, and only by sifting through
a lot of variation, and a lot of twists and turns, that one can even discern a pattern,
if a pattern emerges at all. Evolution in this sense is as much about loss as it is
about gain.
In this respect, since I already got off track, perhaps one more (hypothetical)
observation is in order. If my reconstruction of proto-syntax is on the right track, and
if there was a paratactic stage in language evolution, perhaps lasting for a prolonged
period of time, then I would say that our ancestors at that point got to be really good
and creative with this paratactic language, including with VN compounding (cry-
baby, rattle-snake), and with AB-AC patterns (Easy come, easy go), which may or
may not have been accompanied by melodies (Sections 2.4. and 4.2). But very few of
us living today seem to be still capable of using language in such creative, poetic ways.
It could be that by going grammatical, and by becoming slaves to a host of tiny
grammatical categories and distinctions, we masked our other great abilities, includ-
ing poetic and possibly musical abilities, which then gradually got diminished, in a
scenario similar to the one described above.
Those few who are still capable of such artistic expression may be considered as
great orators in some cultures, as seems to be the case with skilled Hmong shamans
and preachers, whose productive use of lofty AB AC patterns is highly valued
(Martha Ratliff, p.c. 2013). It is also reported in Maxwell and Hill (2006:25) that
Maya writings have long shown parallelism in structure, but that such parallelism in
modern spoken language only appears in most formal genres, particularly public
prayer (see Section 4.2).
In any event, my proposal is that the stages of syntax, as postulated in this book,
brought about incremental advantages one over the other, the advantages that could
have, in principle, been subject to selection. Not all of them had to be, of course. This
is an open empirical question that nowadays can be subjected to genetic and other
types of testing.
15
15
According to Christiansen and Chater (2008), human genome-wide scans have revealed evidence of
recent positive selection for more than 250 genes (Voight, Kudaravalli, Wen, and Pritchard 2006), making
it possible that there exist genetic adaptations for language.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
192 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
7.4A detailed selection scenario
For the sake of concreteness, this section describes in detail one possible scenario for
how the capacity for the simplest two-word paratactic syntax could have been subject
to selection, the kind of syntax that, according to this book, provided a foundation for
all subsequent structure building. While this book discusses various fossils of this
stage of grammar, and any of them could be used for illustration purposes, VN
exocentric compounds are particularly illustrative in this respect, given that they rely
on the basic, concrete vocabulary to create abstract concepts, and given that they
specialize for naming and derogatory reference (insults), while at the same time clearly
exhibiting the properties of the two-slot paratactic grammar (Chapter 6). The goal of
this section is to envision how the ability to coin such insults on the spot would have
secured survival benets in the ancient times. Needless to say, this is a hypothetical
scenario. But I believe that it is important to get very specic about the details of ones
proposal in order to make sure that the implementation is at least in principle plausible.
The signicance of these compounds is exactly in that they make this particular
selection scenario plausible from the point of view of evolutionary biology.
Imagine, if only for the sake of argument, that we encounter a community of
hominin ancestors, such as perhaps the H. erectus (see Section 7.5), living in a society
of about 100, with approximately equal number of males and females. The adults in
this community do not divide neatly into couples, but rather some males (and
females) mate with multiple partners. This is not a far-fetched scenario, given that
polygamy is practiced even in the modern times, by humans and non-humans alike
(see e.g. Symons 1979). In this kind of situation, if the males with certain proto-syntax
capabilities left more offspring than the other males, consistently, over generations,
then they would have skewed the course of evolution toward the spread of the
mutation(s) responsible for that ability to the rest of the population. As discussed
in Section 7.5.1, the speed of the spread depends on how high the tness of these
individuals was relative to the competitors. According to Stone and Lurquin (2007), if
relative tness is high, the increase of the variant in the population can be fast, taking
just a few dozen of generations for the variant frequency to increase tenfold.
Suppose now that at this point the vast majority of the population are only capable
of one-word utterances (pre-syntactic stage). Moreover, the words they use are basic
and concrete, numbering in dozens, perhaps up to 200 (see the examples in (38) and
(39) as a possible sample). This is the kind of protolanguage that primates such as
Kanzi, a bonobo, seem capable of (see e.g. Savage-Rumbaugh and Lewin 1994).
Anticipating the argument below, most of these words, nouns and verbs, are taken
from the VN compounds discussed in Chapter 6.
16
16
Recall also that Heine and Kutevas(2007) reconstruction of proto-categories based on the theory of
grammaticalization leads to the conclusion that the rst proto-words in the evolution of language were
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
A detailed selection scenario 193
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(38) Verb-like proto-words
break, burn, burst, crack, cry, cut, drag, drink, drip, eat, fart, ll,
fold, fuck, hang, heck, hunch, kill, lick, lie, peck, pierce, pinch,
piss, rattle, rip, roll, run, scatter, scrape, scratch, shake, shit,
shove, skew, sing, sit, smoke, spin, spit, split, stink, stroke,
suck, sulk, tread, tumble, turn, wag, wipe
(39) Noun-like proto-words
ass, baby, back, balls, beard, belly, bird, brain, butt, dung, face,
nger, re, hair, head, heel, leg, mustache, neck, old-woman,
penis, shit, skin, sky, snake, sun, tail, throat, vagina, water,
wind, wolf, wood
Suppose now that an innovation occurs in the community: one or two hominins
begin to merge these proto-words to create insults that succinctly characterize their
rivals in derogatory terms. While it would have no doubt been possible to insult with
single words, in a one-word stage one is severely limited to insults such as:
(40) ass, fart, old.woman, penis, piss, shit, snake, spit, stink, vagina
Now compare this one-word potential for insult with the possibilities that open up in
the paratactic two-slot stage (see Chapter 6for many more examples from a variety of
languages):
17
(41) kill-joy, turn-skin (cf. turn-coat), hunch-back, wag-tail,
tattle-tale, scatter-brain, cut-throat, mar-wood (bad carpenter),
heck-wood, busy-body, cry-baby, break-back, catch-y (plant),
cut-nger (plant), ll-belly (glutton), lick-spit, pinch-back
(miser), shufe-wing (bird), skin-int (miser), spit-re,
swish-tail (bird), tangle-foot (whiskey), tumble-dung (insect), bere-
water (bear-water), crake-bone (crack-bone), drink-water, shave-
tail (shove-tail), wipe-tail, wrynge-tail, fuck-ass, fuck-head, shit-
ass, shit-head
(42) cepi-dlaka split-hair(hair-splitter); guli-kožapeel-skin(who
rips you off); vrti-guz spin-butt(restless person, dget); muti-
voda muddy-water(trouble-maker); jebi-vetar screw-wind
noun-like and verb-like. In this respect as well, VN compounds count as good fossils, and a good starting
point for breaking into paratactic syntax. It is important to clarify here, however, that in this stage one can
only speak of proto-verbs (denoting actions, perhaps proto-imperative forms) and proto-nouns (denoting
static individuals). There is no claim here to the effect that nouns and verbs were distinguished morpho-
logically at this stage.
17
When such combinations are used to name animals or plants, unsurprisingly, they are not insults.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
194 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(charlatan); vuci-guz drag-butt(slow-moving person); gori-
guzica burn-butt(a person in trouble, burn-breeches); kosi-noga
skew-leg(person who limps); lezi-baba lie-old.woman(loose
woman or man); jedi-vek, eat-life(one who constantly annoys);
kljuj-drvo peck-wood(wood-pecker); podvi-rep fold-tail
(one who is crestfallen); čepi-guz cork-butt; češi-guz scratch-
butt;deri-muda rip-balls(place name, a steep hill); gladi-kur
stroke-dick(womanizer); jebi-baba fuck-old.woman
(unselective womanizer); kapi-kur drip-dick(name of a slow
water spring); kovrlji-guz drag-butt;liz-guz lick-butt;nabi-guz
shove-butt;peči-govno burn-shit;piš-kur piss-dick;plači-guz
cry-butt(cf. cry-baby); plači-pička cry-cunt(vulgar version of cry-baby);
poj-kurićsing-dick(womanizer); puš-kur smoke-
dick;razbi-dupe break-butt(steep terrain); seri-vuk shit-wolf;
visi-guz hang-butt
One goes from being able to utter a handful of very predictable and boring insults, to
suddenly having the power to create many more novel insults, abstract, witty, and
often humorous, combinations of words that have never been heard before. You are
suddenly able to capture a trait of a person, or perhaps his essence, with only two
basic proto-words. Maybe you rst stumbled upon one or two combinations like this,
but then you started to actively seek new ones.
According to Progovac and Locke (2009), coining compounds akin to the ones
illustrated above would have been an adaptive way to compete for status and sex in
ancient times. Their successful use would have enhanced relative status rst by
derogating existing rivals and placing prospective rivals on notice, and second by
demonstrating verbal skills and quick-wittedness. Darwin (1874) identied two
distinct kinds of sexual selection, aggressive rivalry and mate choice (see also
Miller 2000), both of which seem relevant for the proposed use of exocentric
compounds.
18
There is no doubt that this ability would have attracted attention.
Insult and ritual insult still do, even in the present times.
It should be noted that considering the simpler stages of grammar helps identify
some potential points of continuity with animal communication abilities. As
observed in e.g. Darwin (1874), the males of almost all the mammal species use
their voices much more during the breeding season, and some are absolutely mute
except at this season. If human language was used for display purposes from the very
start, then there is some continuity there.
19
In addition, compounds used for insult
18
See Section 6.6for Darwins(1872) suggestion that strong emotions expressed in animals are those of
lust and hostility, and that they may have been the rst verbal threats and intimidations uttered by humans.
19
Darwins view in fact was that language evolved gradually through sexual selection, as an instinct to
acquire a particular method of verbal display similar to music (see e.g. Fitch 2010 for recent arguments for
musical protolanguage; see Sections 2.4and 4.2).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
A detailed selection scenario 195
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
often feature swearwords. Code (2005, and references there) provides neurological
evidence that swearwords are separately stored from the other words, using both the
part of the brain where digital language is processed, and the part of the brain which
processes laughing and crying. In that sense, swearwords straddle the boundary
between (animal) calls, which share many properties with laughing and crying, on
the one hand, and digital language, on the other (see e.g. Burling 2005; see also the
Appendix for more discussion on this).
In general, decomposing syntax into evolutionary primitives in this way has an
added bonus in that it can reveal some continuity, some points of contact, between
human language and other animal communication systems. Recall from Section 7.3.2
(also Chapter 2) that the paratactic (two-slot) syntax is tied to the here-and-now, and
does not show displacement or recursion. These properties are also difcult to nd
across animal communication systems.
Let us now go back to the concrete scenario involving VN insults and our hominin
ancestors. Perhaps after a day of gathering and/or hunting, as well as evading
predators, the community would come together for some socializing. The group
would have been thoroughly entertained by the ability to use words in novel and
playful ways. Suppose for concreteness that those few men who could quickly and
efciently coin VN-type compounds on the spot had a preexisting mutation that
makes this task easier for them.
20
They can do it with less effort and with more
buoyancy. If the chances of these compound-savvy men of having fruitful sex was
only 23% higher than for the rest, then it would have taken less than 10,000 years to
spread this mutation to the rest of the population (see Section 7.5.1for some
calculations). As pointed out in e.g. Symons (1979), tribal chiefs are often both gifted
orators and highly polygynous. Consider that the H. erectus species existed for more
than a million and a half years. But notice that this would have allowed enough time
for syntax to evolve even if the paratactic stage emerged with the H. heidelbergensis
species (see Section 3.5).
It is not my intention here to suggest that (paratactic) syntax evolved only, or even
primarily, for insult purposes. My intention is only to show that insults could have
played an important role in solidifying basic syntax. There is no doubt that the ability
to join words would have opened up many other communicative possibilities,
including the accumulation of (complex) vocabulary items. For example, compound
words could now be used to distinguish snakes (e.g. rattle-snake), to name animals
(e.g. swish-tail (bird), tumble-dung (insect)), as well as to describe peoples activities
and issue more specic (less vague) commands:
20
This ability may be attributable not just to one mutation, but perhaps a cluster of mutations, in which
case the selection would have targeted the whole cluster.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
196 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
(43) Kill snake! Eat berry! Cut wolf! Sing baby! Run wolf! Rattle snake!
21
Intriguingly, as discussed at length in Chapter 6, VN compounds across languages
seem to preserve traces of an imperative verb form.
The possibility that sexual selection played some role in evolving syntax is con-
sistent with the ndings reported in e.g. Ullman (2008) that there is a gender
difference when it comes to relying on declarative vs. procedural memory in language
processing (see also Pinker and Ullman 2002).
22
At the same time, as noted in e.g.
Darwin (1874), the law of the equal transmission of characters to both sexes prevails
with mammals, and ensures that characters of all kinds are inherited equally by the
males and females; we might therefore expect that with mankind any characters
gained by the females or by the males, through sexual selection, would commonly be
transferred to the offspring of both sexes. In other words, one would expect any
differences between sexes (sexual dimorphism) to be minor and subtle.
Finally, as Pinker and Bloom (1990) argue persuasively, human language is too
complicated and too specically designed for communication to be a spandrel or a
by-product of some other development.
23
The only way for a complex design such as
human language to evolve is through a sequence of mutations with small effects, and
through intermediate stages, with each stage useful enough and small enough in
triggering natural selection. Based on syntactic theory and linguistic fossils, this
monograph has reconstructed just such concrete intermediate stages of syntax
through which language evolution would have passed, and identied specic com-
municative benets that each stage brought about, sufcient to trigger natural/sexual
selection.
24
21
Interestingly, imperatives themselves can be quite vague. While in modern languages we often
distinguish the noun in Kill wolf as an object of the action, and the nouns in Run wolf! and Cry baby!as
vocatives (thus subjects of the actions), without specic case markings for these categories, these structures
are ambiguous. Rattle snake! could in principle either be a (bizarre) command for a snake to rattle, or a
command for somebody to rattle a snake.
22
It has also been reported by many that the use of cursing and dirty words is more common in males
(e.g. Jay 1980,1995; van Lancker and Cummings 1999), and this is true even in language disorders (Code
1982). As Code observes, such words are used for fundamental expression of deep emotion, including fear,
pain, frustration, as well as for sex and violence.
23
Gould (1987) and Chomsky (2002,2005), among others, have claimed that human language/grammar
can be a by-product of other phenomena, such as the increase in brain size, or general laws of physics.
Chomskys arguments have to do with his views that syntax is not decomposable into stages, and that there
are no genetic differences among humans when it comes to language abilities (Chomsky 2002:147).
Additionally, Chomsky (2002) considers that natural selection is messy and not properly understood. He
also considers that the evolutionary explanations that invoke natural selection via tinkering can be
symptomatic of the lack of understanding (if you take a look at anything that you dont understand, its
going to look like tinkering(139)), and that when things are properly understood, one realizes that there is
much more order in nature.
24
As pointed out by a reviewer, Pinker and Blooms(1990) approach has been criticized on the account
of the claim that the properties considered to be adaptive in language, such as recursive Merge, are not
complex, and vice versa (see e.g. Pesetsky and Block 1990). My approach shows that, when syntax is
decomposed into plausible evolutionary stages, this criticism dissipates. Interestingly, Pesetsky and Block
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
A detailed selection scenario 197
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The following section considers how these stages might map onto the human line
of descent.
7.5The timeline for the evolution of language
7.5.1Was there enough time?
Many evolutionists have adopted the Baldwin Effect as an evolutionary force,
including Dawkins (1999). Pinker and Bloom (1990); Deacon (1997); and Briscoe
(e.g. 2000) have applied it to language evolution. According to Pinker and Bloom
(1990) this is a process whereby environmentally-induced responses set up selection
pressures for such responses to become innate, triggering conventional Darwinian
evolution (see also Deacon 1997; Hinton and Nowlan 1987).
As pointed out by Depew (2003), there is a variety of shifting and contested
theoretical ideas associated with the Baldwin Effect (see also Longa 2006). What
they all seem to have in common may be just the following: learned behaviors can
affect the direction and rate of evolutionary change by natural selection(Depew
2003:3). This may lead to converting learned behaviors into genetic adaptations, or,
alternatively, it may lead to supporting learned behaviors by related genetic adapta-
tions (Depew 2003:3).
Deacon (2003) considers that masking and unmasking of preadaptationsplays
an important role. As language became more and more essential to successful
reproduction, novel selection pressures unmasked selection on previously neutral
variants and created advantages for certain classes of mutations that might not
otherwise have been favored(9394). At the same time, this innovative tool masked
selection on traits made less vital by being supplementedby the innovative tool,
such as perhaps the inventory and specicity of human calls (94) (see Section 7.3.5for
a hypothetical scenario along these lines). It is important to point out that the process
of unmasking can have highly distributed parallel synergistic consequences, with the
potential to signicantly amplify adaptations(Deacon 2003:956). As Deacon
claries in the postscript to his paper, his approach does not really deviate from
Darwins, given that the unmasking process is comparable to uncovering the so-
called preadaptations, associated with Darwinian evolution, or changes of function
(Godfrey-Smith, Dennett, and Deacon 2003:110).
One example that is often associated with the Baldwin Effect is the emergence of
lactose tolerance among herding populations (but see Depew 2003:26 for the claim
that there is no theory neutral empirical phenomenon that can be named the
(1990:751) challenge Pinker and Bloom to explain why it is adaptive to allow the citys destruction by the
enemybut not the citys sight by the enemy,which, as they say, is not fully acceptable. Ironically,
examples like these turn out to be relevant for evolutionary considerations, even though, of course, at a
much more abstract level, as discussed in Section 3.3.4.1.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
198 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Baldwin Effect.)As discussed in Deacon (1997), in these populations, alleles that
allow infants to digest milk are not shut down immediately after weaning, but instead
remain operative at increasingly deferred points in the life cycle. While this eventu-
ally reduces to classical Darwinian selection, as these alleles are just being discovered
or unmasked by this cultural habit, according to Deacon the emphasis here is on the
causal factor for selection, which is a cultural phenomenon.
Small selective advantages are sufcient for evolutionary change: according to
Haldane (1927), a variant that produces on average 1% more offspring than its
alternative allele would increase in frequency from 0.1%to99.9% of the population
in just over 4,000 generations. As discussed in e.g. Stone and Lurquin (2007), the
speed of natural selection depends on relative tness of a trait/mutation. The time
necessary for a gene variant frequency to change is proportional to the difference in
tness of the variants competing in the population.
As one example, the tness of lactose tolerance is 23% higher in dairy areas. It
took about 5,00010,000 years to reach the current rates of lactose tolerance among
northern Europeans, which is close to 100% in some cases. For sickle cell anemia the
tness of the AS heterozygotes can be 910% greater, because they are clinically
normal, and because they are protected from malaria to some extent. According to
Stone and Lurquin (2007:1045), in this case it took only 2,000 to 3,000 years, or even
less, to reach the equilibrium seen today. Moreover, xations of different genes can
go in parallel, and sexual selection can signicantly speed up any of these processes,
triggering a runaway effect (Fisher 1930; see also Miller 2000 and Hurford 2007).
This suggests that there was enough time to evolve language gradually, in stages,
especially if the tness value for each new stage of language was high. Given the scenario
for the evolution of syntax outlined in this monograph, there would have been at least
two major breakthroughs: (i) the emergence of the paratactic two-word stage out of a
one-word stage (Section 7.2); and (ii) the emergence of hierarchical grammars, with
transitivity and/or TAM marking (Section 7.3).
25
For each progression, one can identify
several concrete communicative advantages, as per the previous sections.
26
7.5.2The timeline
At this point, one wonders if my proposal has anything to say about the timeline for
the evolution of human language. While the proposal as it is now cannot precisely
25
There must have been many more developments and detours, including possibly a proto-conjunction
stage, as discussed in Chapter 4, as well as many transitional stages, which left us with ambivalent
structures, such as middles. Here, I focus only on the major breakthroughs, for which the evidence is the
clearest, and leave the rest for future research.
26
This is also consistent with the idea of punctuated equilibrium, according to which evolutionary
change involves bursts of change that are relatively brief on the geological time scale, followed by long
periods of stasis (Eldredge and Gould 1972; Gould and Eldredge 1977). For example, it is possible that the
paratactic stage was stable for a long time.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The timeline for the evolution of language 199
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
place the stages of proto-syntax in evolutionary time, it is capable, even in this broad
outline, of excluding some hypotheses regarding language evolution, and supporting
others. This indicates that the level of granularity is appropriate, and that future
research along these lines, and at this level of granularity, can certainly shed further
light on this topic.
Consistent with the considerations of this monograph, it is likely, even though
not certain, that the paratactic proto-syntax stage already characterized the
H. heidelbergensis species, the common ancestor of both humans and Neanderthals,
which would place the emergence of the proto-syntactic stage to as far as half million
years ago. In fact, my proposal also cannot exclude the possibility that H. erectus also
had some form of proto-syntax, especially considering that their brain doubled in
size relative to that of the Australopithecus, who lived sometime between 4million
years ago and 2million years ago. The earliest fossil evidence for H. erectus goes back
to 1.8million years ago and the most recent to about 140,000 years ago. It is conceivable
that the capacity for paratactic grammars triggered a speciation event, such as a
transition from H. erectus to H. heidelbergensis (or, if the deeper timeline for language
is correct, a transition from Australopithecus to the hominin species).
27
Clearly, the
pressure to be able to use and memorize innovative language combinations and
abstract vocabulary would have certainly required increasingly more mental capability,
and thus more brain capacity. There was nothing else at that juncture that would have
required as much brain capacity as the paratactic stage of language would have,
accompanied by an increase in vocabulary size (see Section 7.4).
28
According to Deacon (1997), the unusually expanded prefrontal brain regions
(Footnote 27) are an evolutionary response to a sort of virtual input with increased
processing demands, suggesting that language forced the brain to evolve in this
particular way, or at least that it co-evolved with it (see also Diller and Cann 2013).
As put in Darwin (1874:634), a great stride in the development of intellect will have
followed, as soon as the half-art and half-instinct of language came into use; for the
continued use of language will have reacted on the brain and produced an inherited
effect; and this again will have reacted on the improvement of language. . . . The
27
According to Deacon (1997), symbolic language has been accruing from around the time that the
Austrolopithecines were replaced by the hominins, some 2million years ago, when ancestors became
bipedal, freeing up their hands for tool use and gesture, and when brains expanded signicantly. As he
notes, in the australopithecine-hominin transition, our brains did not get bigger proportionately, but,
rather, it was the forebrain, particularly the cerebellum and the cerebral cortex, which ballooned the most.
28
Another potentially relevant observation is that H. erectus was possibly the rst hominin to move out
of Africa, as early as 1.7million years ago, and spread as far as England, Georgia, India, Sri Lanka, China,
and Java. However, as pointed out by McBrearty (2007:140), no genetic mutation enhancing intelligence
was necessary for hominins to migrate out of Africa, given that faunal exchanges between Africa and Asia
have occurred sporadically since the land bridge at Sinai was established 17 million years ago. Finlayson
(2009) also notes that having language in place, or a large brain, is not a necessary prerequisite for
dispersions of this kind to take place.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
200 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
largeness of the brain in man, relatively to his body, compared with the lower
animals, may be attributed in chief part to the early use of some simple form of
languagethat wonderful engine which afxes signs to all sorts of objects and
qualities, and excites trains of thought which would never arise from the mere
impression of the senses . . . [emphasis mine].
Dediu and Levinson (2013) review a number of recent ndings suggesting that at
least H. heidelbergensis had some form of language, based on the comparative
evidence among its descendents: H. sapiens, Denisovans, and Neanderthals, as also
suggested by Finlayson (2009:116) (but see Berwick, Hauser, and Tattersall 2013 for
criticism of this view). According to Dediu and Levinson (2013:10), language as we
know it must then have originated within the ~1million years between H. erectus
and the common ancestor of Neanderthals and us.The most interesting evidence
comes from genetics, and Dediu and Levinson (2013:5) conclude that Neanderthals
and Denisovans had the basic genetic underpinning for recognizably modern
language and speech, but it is possible that modern humans may outstrip them in
some parameters (perhaps range of speech sounds or rapidity of speech, complexity
of syntax, size of vocabularies, or the like).In addition to genetics, Dediu and
Levinson also review evidence from the skeletal morphology, the morphology of the
vocal tract, infant maturation, Brocas area, brain size, cultural artifacts, and con-
clude that all the evidence is consistent with their proposal. According to them, the
H. heidelbergensis species might have even spoken complex languages, comparable
to human languages, which in my framework would imply a hierarchical stage.
Given the considerations in this monograph, it is much more likely that the
hierarchical stage of language evolved only in H. sapiens, after the dispersion from
Africa, or perhaps after a dispersion within Africa, and that H. heidelbergensis, as well
as Neanderthals and Denisovans, only commanded the paratactic stage, that is, two-
slot grammars, as well as one-word protolanguage. But, as it is clearly established in
this monograph, this mereparatactic stage of language has a remarkable commu-
nicative potential. Interestingly, Dediu and Levinson (2013:11) hope that some
combinations of structural features will prove so conservative that they will allow
deep reconstruction.My hope is that this monograph has provided just such a
conservative structural feature which can be used for reconstruction, the two-slot
absolutive-like platform.
On this scenario, the second major breakthrough, the one that brought about
hierarchical grammars, would have originated with H. sapiens. On one view, the
H. sapiens species is taken to have emerged in Africa around 200,000 years ago, and
dispersed out of Africa about 60,000 years ago, to Asia and Europe, where the species
co-existed with Neanderthals for a while (see e.g. Stone and Lurquin 2007). Nean-
derthals are thought to have left Africa much before H. sapiens, and lived in Europe
and Asia since at least 200,000 years ago, dying out about 20,000 years ago. In the
scenario outlined above, Neanderthals would have commanded the paratactic use of
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The timeline for the evolution of language 201
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
grammar, inherited from the common ancestor with the H. sapiens, but would not
have inherited hierarchical grammars from the ancestor, as hierarchical grammars
would have only emerged in the H. sapiens. This of course does not mean that
Neanderthals could not have, independently, evolved layers of grammar on top of
the paratactic foundation, or even musical language (see e.g. Mithen 2006; Section 2.4;
4.2). It only means, under this scenario, that whatever they built on top of the paratactic
two-slot grammars, if anything, was not shared by the common ancestors.
29
However, the stages broadly outlined in this monograph are also consistent with
the less likely possibility that paratactic grammars emerged only at the transition
from the H. heidelbergensis to the H. sapiens species, in which case H. heidelbergensis
(and possibly H. erectus and Australopithecus) would have been stuck in a one-word
stage, with some basic vocabulary but no syntax, or even in a stage without any words
at all. In that case, Neanderthals would not have inherited the paratactic grammar
from the common ancestor, as the common ancestor would not have had one, but,
again, it is possible, if not likely, that they could have developed some form of proto-
syntax on their own. Under this more recent scenario for the evolution of language, it
would be hard to explain why the brains ballooned in the transition from the
Australopithecus to H. erectus, as per previous discussion. But even this recent
scenario would have allowed enough time for syntax to evolve gradually in stages,
as pointed out above.
30
Importantly, there are certain scenarios for the evolution of syntax that are not
consistent with the approach outlined in this monograph. For example, a great
degree of crosslinguistic variation in how different languages build upon the postu-
lated foundational paratactic stage suggests that the hierarchical stage did not emerge
in all its complexity and in a uniform fashion only once (in Africa), but instead
multiple times, and independently, either within Africa, or after the dispersion from
Africa. If it had emerged only once, before H. sapiens spread out, it would be difcult
to explain why there is so much variation across languages of the world in how they
29
Recall that paratactic grammars are characterized not only by compound insults and rudimentary
small clauses, but also by paratactic clause combinations, of the kind:
(i) Easy come, easy go. Come one, come all. You sow, you reap. You seek,
you nd.
For what it is worth, such symmetric, parallel combinations would have been easy to t onto simple
melodies, and to develop musical protolanguage from. As pointed out in Sections 2.4and 4.2, such
paratactic structures rely on prosodic glue to hold them together, and if there was musical protolanguage
at any point in human evolution, then it would have been most useful in this stage.
30
As observed by Maggie Tallerman (p.c. 2014), in this scenario the transitions from one stage to the
next could have been so swift as to become close to saltationist views of the evolution of language. In my
view, what is important for distinguishing the gradualist, incremental approaches from saltationist
approaches is not so much the amount of time that elapsed from having no language to having hierarchical
language, but rather whether or not there were well-dened incremental stages, to provide the scaffolding
without which natural/sexual selection could not have been able to operate.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
202 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
express transitivity (by ergative, accusative, or other means), or in whether or not
they grammaticalize tense/aspect/mood systems, to name just some parameters of
variation. Dediu and Levinson (2013) mention that interbreeding with Neanderthals
or Denisovans, or just the contact with their languages, may have contributed to the
differences among human languages. While this may be possible in principle, a
proposal of this kind would have to be made much more explicit in order to be
evaluable. At present, what my approach can say for sure is that all human languages
have the paratactic grammar as a common denominator, and, if anything, it would
have been this kind of paratactic grammar that was also shared by Neanderthals and
Denisovans, if it was indeed present in their common ancestor, H. heidelbergensis.
What all human languages and constructions undoubtedly have in common is the
paratactic platform, that is, the ability to combine two words or two clauses paratac-
tically, essentially the properties of the postulated at, intransitive, absolutive-like
stage.
31
As pointed out above, all the hierarchical phenomena discussed in this book,
including transitivity and subordination, have alternative routes, as well as pre-
cursors, in parataxis. This is a deep, conservative property of human language that
young children across cultures seem capable of, and that pidgin speakers and second
language learners seem to often resort to. However, as pointed out in Sections 7.2and
7.3, modern languages vary with respect to whether they exhibit grammaticalized
expression of TAM (tense/aspect/mood), recursive clause embedding, and a particu-
lar type of transitivity, all properties of hierarchical syntax. In other words, if
transitivity and TAM emerged only after the dispersion of hominin populations,
we can explain the vast variation across languages in how they choose to express
them, or not. This would in turn mean that the common ancestor with Neanderthals
and Denisovans did not have hierarchical syntax.
The postulations in this monograph, as they stand now, are not capable of
choosing between the uniregional and multiregional hypotheses about human ori-
gins. According to the widely accepted uniregional hypothesis, the Asian and Euro-
pean H. erectus lineages went extinct in all the places into which the species migrated
(see e.g. Stone and Lurquin 2007). In the meantime, H. sapiens evolved only once
from H. erectus in Africa (around 200,000 years ago), where H. erectus also went
extinct. The African H. sapiens populations migrated out of Africa around 50,000 to
60,000 years ago, which would mark the second dispersion out of Africa (Out of
Africa II model). Within this scenario, my approach is consistent with H. sapiens
exhibiting basically only the paratactic grammar before the dispersion to different
geographical locations, as pointed out above. This paratactic grammar would have
31
The use of linkers/proto-conjunctions, as discussed in Chapter 4, may also be common to all or most
languages, and this would be another good topic for further research along these lines. If it turns out that
languages differ signicantly in this respect, this might help situate the stages of language in time more
precisely.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The timeline for the evolution of language 203
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
provided the common platform upon which all languages could build further
complexities, often in diverging directions. Still, the syntactic variation among
languages would be largely constrained by the shared scaffolding that paratactic
(absolutive-like) grammars provide.
Recall that H. erectus traveled out of Africa around 1.7million years ago,
spreading to Europe and Asia, where fossil evidence of the species was found.
The absence of older hominin fossils in Europe and Asia (and in the Americas) is
taken as evidence that H. erectus evolved only once, in Africa. According to the
much less accepted multiregional hypothesis regarding human origins, the local
H. erectus populations in Africa, Asia, and Europe differentiated into H. sapiens
independently, by a process of parallel evolution, as well as some admixture among
the populations (see e.g. Stone and Lurquin 2007).
32
If this hypothesis turns out to
be correct, then, under my approach, one would have to say that H. erectus,prior
to the migrations out of Africa, already commanded the foundational paratactic
grammar, and that the more complex hierarchical grammars emerged separately in
different geographical locations, after the dispersion. On this scenario, the hier-
archical grammars could have emerged much earlier than with the uniregional
hypothesis, given that the dispersion took place much earlier, around 1.7million
years ago. On the other hand, if the uniregional hypothesis is correct, then the
dating of the emergence of hierarchical syntax would be in a more shallow time
frame, sometime around 60,000 years ago, after the second dispersion out of Africa
took place, involving H. sapiens.
33
As discussed in Section 2.5.4, initially, it was reported by Enard et al.(2002) that
FOXP2gene mutation in humans occurred at some point in the last 200,000 years,
which would have neatly coincided with the emergence of hierarchical syntax.
However, it has since been found that the same mutation characterizes Neanderthals
(Krause et al.2007), which pushes the mutation back to at least the common
ancestor, about half a million years ago. This nding was a disappointment to the
adherents to the saltationist view, for whom the initial report by Enard et al. provided
32
As pointed out by Finlayson (2009), the distinctions between H. habilis,H. erectus,H. sapiens, and
other hominins are not as clear-cut as is typically assumed. For example, when it comes to the size of the
brain, while the brains of H. sapiens are certainly larger on average than the brains of H. erectus, Finlayson
(2009:423) points out that the variation within species is so large that some H. erectus individuals were
within the human range. This speaks in favor of the gradualist approach to the evolution of language
and cognition.
33
There may be another possible scenario for the timeline for hierarchical syntax, which would allow
for an earlier timing of hierarchical syntax. Namely, it is possible that hierarchical syntax emerged
independently among different populations in Africa, and that, as these different populations migrated
to different parts of the world, they brought with them these diverse hierarchical grammars. According to
Stringer (2007:17) and Finlayson (2009), there are still many uncertainties about human timeline and
dispersals. Stringer mentions that there might have been an African version of multiregionalism, citing
growing molecular evidence of deep divisions within African populations.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
204 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
encouragement (see Piattelli-Palmarini and Uriagereka 2011 for discussion). Diller
and Cann (2009;2012:171) even propose that the FOXP2mutation should be dated
back to 1.8to 1.9million years ago, approximately the time when Homo (Homo
habilis, H. ergaster, and H. erectus) emerged.
Another type of evidence that has often been invoked in favor of the saltationist
view has to do with the postulation of the Middle to Upper Paleolithic transition/
revolution.Based on archeological ndings, Mellars (2002) and others have initially
suggested that there was a major transition/revolution around 4335,000 BP, char-
acterized by major changes, all reecting shifts in many different dimensions of
human culture and adaptation: new forms and complexity of stone, bone, and other
tools; explosion of explicitly decorative or ornamental items; representational art
carving of animal and human gures; increase in human population densities. To
many this symbolic explosionwas exactly what one would expect from a major
shift in the complexity of language patterns, possibly associated with corresponding
shifts in the neurological structure of the human brain (Mellars 1991:35; Bickerton
1995; Pinker 1995; Mithen 1996). These archeological ndings were often interpreted
to mean that language (or syntax) in its entirety arose at this juncture, through one
single event, such as a mutation (see e.g. Chomsky 2005,2010; Berwick and Chomsky
2011; Tattersall 2010).
However, the recent ndings lead to the conclusion that there was no human
revolution, at least not at this particular juncture (see e.g. McBrearty and Brooks
2000; McBrearty 2007; and Mellars himself 2007:3). According to Mellars (2007:3)
there is now ample evidence . . . that virtually the whole pattern of radical behav-
ioural changes as reected in the archeological record of the classic Middle-to-Upper
Paleolithic transition in Eurasia is due entirely to the replacement of one human
population (that of the Eurasian Neanderthals) by the new, intrusive populations of
biologically and behaviourally modern humans, from an ultimately African source.
Consequently, this archeological situation cannot reect some in situ cultural or
evolutionary processes. According to McBrearty and Brooks (2000) and McBrearty
(2007), a much more gradual and piecemeal pattern of development of new techno-
logical innovations can be documented in Africa.
It should also be pointed out that even if there had been an explosion of cultural
artifacts in the archeological record at this or some other point, it would not have
followed that language or syntax emerged at that point, or that they emerged
suddenly. Denitive conclusions in this regard are especially difcult to draw given
the common assumption among linguists, based on present-day cultures, that it is
possible to have a highly complex language in the absence of any complex culture
(see e.g. Roebroeks and Verpoorte 2009; Tallerman, 2014c; and references there). This
in turn means that a sudden emergence of culture does not imply a sudden emer-
gence of language, which means that this never was a plausible argument for the
saltationist views in the rst place.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
The timeline for the evolution of language 205
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In summary, there are no real obstacles for studying the evolution of language/
syntax within the Darwinian adaptationist framework, along the lines proposed in
this book: there was plenty of evolutionary time to evolve syntax in stages, and each
stage can be shown to accrue concrete and important communicative advantages,
including precision in the expression of e.g. argument structure, as well as the
capacities for insult, displacement, and recursion. In addition, languages of the
world show variation consistent with the postulated stages, and there are fossils of
these stages to be found across languages and constructions. Furthermore, this
reconstruction can serve as a source of possible hypotheses for correlating linguistic
variation with genetic variation.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi
206 The plausibility of natural selection for syntax
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
8
Conclusion
The basic proposal of this monograph is that the capacity for syntax evolved incre-
mentally, in stages, subject to selection pressures. Following an internal reconstruction
of syntax, based on the syntactic theory adopted in Minimalism and its predecessors,
this monograph arrives at the stage of human grammar which had no tense (no Tense
Phrase), and no transitivity (no vP), but only the rudimentary small clause structure
consisting of a verb and just one argument (typically a noun). This proto-grammar
could not differentiate between subjects and objects, and it knew of no Move or
recursion. This is essentially an absolutive-like, binary, two-slot grammar, which can
nonetheless create not only rudimentary small clauses (e.g. Come winter, . . . ), but
also paratactic binary combinations of such clauses (e.g. Come one, come all.). It can
also create some stunning insults in the form of compounds.
The internal reconstruction is based on stripping off the layers of functional
structure typically associated with a modern clause in Minimalism:
(1) CP > TP > vP > SC/VP
[where CP is a Complementizer Phrase, TP a Tense Phrase, vP a transitive (light)
Verb Phrase, VP the basic Verb Phrase, and SC a Small Clause.]
The logic behind the proposed reconstruction is straightforward: while VP/SC can be
composed without a vP or a TP layer, a vP or a TP can only be constructed upon the
foundation of a VP/SC. Moreover, while imposing an additional layer of structure
upon the foundational SC, whether it is a vP, a TP, or both, necessarily results in a
hierarchical construct, the SC itself can be a at, headless, paratactic creation.
Strikingly, as this monograph shows, languages of the world abound in the fossil
structures approximating this paratactic, two-slot, one-argument proto-grammar.
Such fossils are found among nominals, certain exocentric compounds, unaccusa-
tives, root small clauses, absolutive constructions, and absolutive-like constructions
in nominative-accusative languages, as well as among the so-called middles,the
structures that blur the boundary between intransitivity and transitivity, between
passives and actives, and between subjecthood and objecthood. Middles are just one
of several examples of transitional structures discussed in this monograph, which
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
straddle the boundary between stages, providing support for a gradualist approach to
the evolution of syntax.
That one should nd fossils of previous stages in the structures of the more recent
stages is consistent with the recurring theme of this monograph, taking the advent of
each new stage to preserve the achievements of the previous stages. In addition to
fossil structures often being used side by side more complex structures, this mono-
graph also shows that the fossils of proto-syntax are built into the very foundation of
modern syntactic structures. For example, a modern sentence (TP) is built upon the
foundation of the proto-syntactic small clause, as if the building of a modern
sentence retraces its evolutionary steps.
For each postulated major stage of the evolution of syntax, including the absolu-
tive-like two-word stage, and the hierarchical transitive (vP) and TP stages, this
monograph identies clear and concrete communicative benets which would have
driven natural/sexual selection in each case. Not only that, but the level of concrete-
ness and granularity of this proposal makes it possible to seek cross-fertilization
among the (sub)disciplines of syntactic theory, evolutionary biology, neuroscience,
language variation (typology), and even genetics, in pursuit of language origins. This
proposal is also specic enough to be able to shed light on the hominin timeline, as it
is able to discriminate among some competing hypotheses in this regard. One
hypothesis that is not compatible with the ndings in this monograph is that syntax
emerged in all its complexity abruptly, as one single (minor) mutation/event.
By decomposing syntax into its evolutionary primitives, this monograph has
demystied some of the otherwise problematic syntactic postulates, including Sub-
jacency, recasting them in a completely novel light: in the light of evolution. For if
syntax evolved gradually, through stages, this progression had to have left a mark on
the very design of syntax, as well as on the way syntax is processed by the brain. This
monograph thus nds an explanation for certain properties of modern syntax in the
nature of its evolution, as well as outlines very specic neuroimaging experiments
designed to test the proposed hypotheses. If language structure arose in a drawn-out
coevolutionary process in which both brain and language structures would have
exerted selection pressures on one another, then we should expect to nd that
human brains exhibit species-unique modications that tend to tthe unique
processing demands imposed by language learning and use(Deacon 2003:867).
Importantly, the proposals and hypotheses of this monograph are compatible with
the forces of natural/sexual selection, as well as vulnerable to verication not only by
syntactic theory, but also by neuroscience and genetics.
When it comes to genetics, some recent experiments with mice suggest that the
specically human FOXP2mutations are responsible for increased synaptic plasti-
city, as well as for increased dendrite connectivity (Enard et al.2009). While syntactic
theory can help identify proto-structures, and distinguish them from more complex
structures, neuroscience can test if these distinctions are correlated with a different
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
208 Conclusion
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
degree and distribution of brain activation, and genetics can, among other possibil-
ities, shed light on the role of some specic genes in making such connections in the
brain possible (see e.g. Vernes et al.2007; Newbury and Monaco 2010).
Decomposing syntax into its evolutionary primitives is the only way to arrive at
concrete and testable hypotheses about language origins, as it is the only way to forge
synergy among the elds of syntax, neuro-linguistics, and genetics, by also taking
into account the geography of language variation. While each of these elds on its
own may provide glimpses into the origins of human language, any conclusive
account will ultimately have to be both based on a linguistic theory, and synergistic
with the other relevant disciplines.
In sum, there are several components to this proposal that set it apart from the
other approaches to the evolution of language. First, this approach pursues an
internal reconstruction of the stages of grammar based on the syntactic theory
associated with Minimalism, to arrive at very specic, tangible hypotheses. Second,
it provides an abundance of theoretically analyzed living fossilsfor each postulated
stage, drawn from a variety of languages. Third, and most importantly, this approach
shows how these fossils do not just co-exist side by side with more modern structures,
but that they are in fact literally built into the foundation of these more complex
structures. Fourth, the postulated stages, as well as fossils, are at the appropriate level
of granularity to reveal the selection pressures that would have driven the progression
through stages. Fifth, this approach offers a very specic experimental design for
testing the proposed hypotheses. Last but not least, it arrives at a reconstruction
which stands a chance of being meaningfully correlated with the hominin timeline, as
well as with the quickly accruing genetic evidence.
While this monograph provides a comprehensive framework for studying the
evolution of syntax based on a theory of syntax, it is only a framework, a program,
meant to stimulate further research and lead to better proposals. Further evidence
will need to come from (i) additional syntactic fossils from more languages; from
(ii) a better integration of language variation in syntactic theories; from (iii) neuro-
scientic experiments targeting specic hypotheses about language evolution; and
from (iv) the search for correlations between the geography of language variation and
genetics, but with all of these quests mediated by a coherent and comprehensive
evolutionary framework. While various pieces of the puzzle of the origins of human
language are certainly still missing, my hope is that this book has placed enough
pieces into the right spots to make the contour of the solution discernible.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Conclusion 209
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Appendix
Testing grounds: Neuroimaging
CO-AUTHORED WITH NOA OFEN
1Syntax and neuroimaging
Broadly speaking, this Appendix considers how evolutionary considerations can provide a
missing piece of the puzzle to bridge the gap between the theory of syntax and the eld of
neuroscience. According to e.g. Poeppel and Embick (2005), what is needed but missing for
cross-fertilization between the two elds is a theoretical framework of how they should be
related. This monograph suggests that any such framework will have to take into account
evolutionary origins of syntax, especially if syntax co-evolved with the brain. According to
Deacon (2003:867), if language structure arose in a drawn-out coevolutionary process in
which both brain and language structures would have exerted selection pressures on one
another, then we should expect to nd that human brains exhibit species-unique modica-
tions that tend to tthe unique processing demands imposed by language learning and
use . . . Reciprocally, we should expect languages to exhibit structures that optimize limits in
human working memory . . . This gives a rationale for why evolutionary considerations may
be the missing piece of the puzzle.
The same evolutionary considerations also promise to provide the necessary points of
contact between the elds of neuroscience and genetics. The data and analyses in this
monograph are presented in sufcient detail to allow for the formulation of specic hypotheses
based on minimally contrasting structures. The availability of such concrete and testable
hypotheses makes the proposals in this monograph vulnerable to falsication.
As pointed out throughout the monograph, neuroimaging methods involving subtraction or
correlation can provide a fertile testing ground for various specic hypotheses advanced in this
monograph. Roughly speaking, the subtraction neuro-scientic method is designed to com-
pare and contrast how certain inputs are processed in the brain by subtracting the brain image
reecting the processing of one from that of another, isolating the differences between the two.
The correlation method can be roughly characterized as correlating the increase in the stimulus
complexity with the increase in brain activation. Both methods described above can employ
brain-imaging techniques such as functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), which
measures differences in blood oxygenation levels accompanying neuronal activation.
Generally speaking, one can use these methods to determine how proto-syntactic structures
(e.g. root small clauses, middles, exocentric compounds) are processed in comparison to their
more complex hierarchical counterparts, in the hope of isolating neuro-biological correlates of,
for example, TP layering and vP shelling/transitivity. For the reasons discussed below, the
Evolutionary Syntax. First edition. Ljiljana Progovac
#Ljiljana Progovac 2015. Published 2015 by Oxford University Press
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
prediction is that the processing of TPs and transitives with vP shells will show clear lateralization
in the left hemisphere, with extensive activation in certain specic Brocas areas, as well as
possibly in the anterior temporal lobes, while the corresponding proto-structures are expected
to show less lateralization, and less involvement of Brocas areas, but more reliance on both
hemispheres, as well as, possibly, more reliance on the subcortical structures of the brain (see
Progovac 2010b for these hypotheses).
Despite the current impasse, neuro-linguistic research in the domain of syntax has yielded
enough solid results to serve as a springboard for continued search for knowledge in this area.
1
There is growing consensus in the literature that language processing involves a large number
of small but clustered and interconnected modules, as well as that the right hemisphere is also
involved in language processing, more than previously thought (see e.g. Bookheimer 2002;
Embick et al.2000; Friederici, Meyer, and von Cramon 2000; Moro et al.2001; Brennan et al.
2012). More specically, various ndings suggest that syntax itself is not a monolith, but a
complex phenomenon that recruits multiple loci in the brain. In this respect, Moro et al.(2001:
117) point out that syntactic capacities are not implemented in a single area, but rather
constitute an integrated system which involves both left and right neocortical areas, as well
as other portions of the brain, such as the basal ganglia and the cerebellum.Grodzinsky and
Friederici (2006:240) similarly conclude that each subpart of the linguistic system, including
syntax, can be neurologically decomposed into subcomponents.These ndings are consist-
ent with, and expected under, the evolutionary considerations explored in this project.
There are already quite concrete and specicndings about how some syntactic phenomena
are processed. Neuroimaging ndings support the claim that syntactic movement is associated
with increased involvement of the inferior frontal gyrus (IFG). More specically, syntactic
movement is associated with increased activations in the left IFG, clustering around Brocas
areas: Brodmann Areas (BA) 44 and 45, but also BA 46 and 47 (see e.g. Ben-Shachar, Palti, and
Grodzinsky 2004; Constable et al.2004; Friederici et al.2006; Grodzinsky 2010; Grodzinsky
and Friederici 2006; Stromswold et al.1996).
2
The neural investigations mentioned above focus
on the types of movement that involve visible rearrangements of the basic sentential constitu-
ents: the subject, the verb, and the object. For example, Ben-Shachar, Palti, and Grodzinsky
(2004) consider object preposing in topicalization (as in This paper, John dislikes) and
wh-questions (as in Which paper does John dislike?) in Hebrew and conclude that both types
of movement yield comparable activation in a consistent set of brain regions, including left
IFG. According to Grodzinsky and Friederici (2006:244), complexity in these studies can be
measured as the number of moved constituents.
3
1
According to Poeppel and Embick (2005), among others (also Poeppel 2008; Fedorenko and
Kanwisher 2009), current neuro-linguistic research in the domain of syntax presents a case of cross-
sterilization, rather than cross-fertilization. This is because, according to them, no meaningful correlates
have been found, nor are expected to be found, between biological units of neuroscience (e.g. neurons,
dendrites, axons) and the formal syntactic postulates such as Move, Subjacency, Theta-Criterion. The
proposal in this book (also in Progovac 2010b) is that the missing piece needed to bridge the two vastly
different elds is the consideration of the evolution of syntax. This Appendix elaborates on that idea.
2
In addition, syntactic movement poses specic comprehension difculties for aphasic patients
suffering from a lesion in Brocas region (e.g. Caramazza and Zurif 1976; Grodzinsky 2000; Zurif et al.1993).
3
In assessing relative complexity, the literature on this topic typically uses as a starting point what are
referred to as basic, canonical sentences, such as John ran;John dislikes the paper. In contrast, this proposal
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
212 Testing grounds: Neuroimaging
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
There is converging evidence in the literature showing that increased syntactic complex-
ity corresponds to increased neural activation in certain specic areas of the brain (see
e.g. Caplan 2001; Indefrey, Hagoort, et al.2001; Just et al.1996; Pallier, Devauchelle, and
Dehaene 2011; Brennan et al.2012). The experiments performed by Pallier, Devauchelle,
and Dehaene (2011) and Brennan et al.(2012) found a positive correlation between the levels
of hierarchical structure and the degree of activation, even when keeping the number of words
constant. In Pallier, Devauchelle, and Dehaenes experiment, the subjects were exposed to
twelve word strings, but the conditions varied based on whether these twelve words were a
single sentence, two or more shorter sentences, or just random words. The cumulative building
of structure showed correlated accumulation of activation both in IFG areas, and in temporal
lobe areas (e.g. posterior superior temporal sulcus (pSTS)). Most accumulation occurred in the
single sentence condition, and the least accumulation with strings of random words, even
though the accumulation was logarithmic, rather than linear. Brennan et al.(2012) exposed
their subjects to a naturalistic twelve-minute story-telling experiment, in which the subjects
passively listened to a fairy tale. Each word in the story was analyzed for its level of hierarchical
embedding, and the degree of embedding was found to correlate with the amount of activation
in the anterior temporal lobes, as well as in the left posterior temporal lobe, left IFG, and medial
prefrontal cortex.
Section 2of this Appendix considers root small clauses in Serbian and English, in contrast to
their full sentential counterparts. Section 3considers at exocentric compounds in contrast to
their hierarchical counterparts.
2Small clauses vs. full sentences
Recall from Chapters 2and 3that Serbian unaccusative clauses are in productive use in three
syntactic patterns: unaccusative (TP-less) root small clauses with the underlying VS order (1),
TPs with the same V-T-S order (2), and TPs with subject movement, resulting in S-T-V order (3):
(1)a.Stigla pošta.
arrived mail
b. Pala vlada.
collapsed Government
(2)a.Stigla je pošta.
arrived
AUX
mail
b. Pala je vlada.
collapsed
AUX
government
(3)a.Pošta je stigla.
mail
AUX
arrived
b. Vlada je pala.
government
AUX
collapsed
advocates probing below this basiclevel, to the level of proto-syntax, in an attempt to compare the
processing of TPs, some even transitive, with the processing of fossil structures, which are arguably a
product of proto-syntax, still alive in the brain.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Small clauses vs. full sentences 213
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
In Chapters 2and 3, root small clauses such as (1) are analyzed as approximations of proto-
sentences used in a TP-less stage in language evolution, exhibiting paratactic, at structure
assembled by the operation Conjoin. In contrast, the sentences in (2) and (3) are TPs, headed
by the tense auxiliary je, where (2) keeps the underlying VS order, but (3) additionally Moves
the postverbal subject to the specier of TP position.
Given that TPs involve a layer of functional structure on top of the VP layer, the structures
in (2) and (3) are necessarily instances of hierarchical, headed syntax. At the very least, the
sentences in (2) and (3) involve more hierarchical layering than those in (1). According to the
proposed analysis in Chapter 2, the examples above differ incrementally in their syntactic
complexity, with (1) being the simplest, and (3) the most complex, because it involves not only
additional hierarchical structure, but also Move.
4
This analysis can be subjected to neuroimaging testing by applying either the subtraction
method, or the correlation method, as introduced in Section 1. Starting with the contrast
between the two TPs in (2) and (3), and assuming that movement incurs a processing cost, as
established in many references discussed in Section 1, one can expect a difference in brain
activation between these two types of structures. Any additional activation with (3) should thus
reect the neural correlates of syntactic movement of this kind. This nding would thus isolate
the processing strategies which support the operation Move. In other words, the hypothesis is
that sentences such as (3), in comparison to those in (2), will show more left-lateralization and
more activation in purely syntactic areas, including, but not limited to, left Brocas areas.
More relevant to the proto-grammar considerations, one can also compare and contrast the
processing of basic intransitive TPs, such as (2) above, and minimally contrasting TP-less small
clauses in (1), arguably proto-syntactic creations. It is fortunate that these minimally contrast-
ing pairs share the same meaning and vocabulary, differing on the surface only with respect to
the presence vs. absence of the tiny functional word, auxiliary je, whose presence in this context
contributes no difference in meaning. They are both unaccusative intransitive sentences with
VS word order and with their subjects in situ, that is, not moved. Any detected difference in
their processing would thus isolate a neuro-biological correlate of TP layering, or more
generally, an incremental increase in hierarchical layering. Given that functional categories,
including TPs, are postulates of hierarchical syntax, the prediction is that TPs in (2) will show
more activation in the syntactic areas of the brain than their proto-syntactic counterparts in (1).
This would be a prediction associated with subtracting (1)from(2).
5
Employing a correlation
method, such as the one used in Pallier, Devauchelle, and Dehaene (2011)orBrennanet al.(2012),
4
At rst sight, the examples such as (1) can be seen as sentences whose trees have undergone pruning,
to use the metaphor explored in e.g. Friedmann and Grodzinsky (1997). According to the analysis pursued
in this monograph, these sentences are nothing but small clauses (SCs), the most basic (paratactic)
argument/predicate creations, which never were TPs. Instead of adopting the pruning metaphor, which
suggests that we start from the top with the full syntactic tree, and then shed various functional projections,
the view here is that such functional projections are never projected in these structures in the rst place. It
is for that reason that the TP-less proto-structures are expected to show less syntactic activation in e.g.
Brocas areas.
5
Kolk (2006, and several references cited there) has also found that sub-sentential speech in e.g.
German and Dutch, including small clauses, requires less processing time (is processed within a smaller
temporal window), and that it is thus frequently resorted to in agrammatic production as preventive
adaptation.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
214 Testing grounds: Neuroimaging
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
one can contrast blocks of sentences of type (1) with blocks of sentences of type (2) and look for
enhanced activation with type (2) in e.g. the anterior temporal lobe.
While the prediction for subtracting (1) from (2) is clear, it is not completely clear what to
predict for the subtraction of (2) from (1). The question is whether (2) completely subsumes (1),
without a residue, or if there is some activation present in (1) but not in (2). Recall the
argument from Chapters 2and 3that modern nite sentences are built upon the foundation
of small clauses. This analysis is at the heart of the current syntactic theory adopted in
Minimalism, as well as its predecessors. If this is directly reected in the activation in the
brain, then it may be that the subtraction of (2) from (1) will be null. However, it is also possible
that there will be some additional activation in the brain associated with root small clauses, in
which case the subtraction of (2) from (1) may be non-null. This important issue can only begin
to be resolved by performing specic neuroimaging experiments of this kind, which will help
identify further hypotheses to be tested.
If there is a residue in the subtraction of (2)from(1), then the residue may involve
activation in the subcortical regions of the brain, as well as in the right hemisphere. One
reason to hypothesize subcortical/right hemisphere activation comes from the expectation
that the processing of proto-structures, those assembled by the operation Conjoin, would
involve more ancient and more scattered processing strategies, as also discussed in Chapter 2.
Another reason to expect this result comes from the observation that small clause structures
tend to be (semi-)formulaic, as evidenced in many English and Serbian examples (see
Chapters 2and 3). According to e.g. Code (2005)andWray(2002), formulaic speech in
general is processed by the more ancient structures of the brain, showing resilience in the
case of Brocas aphasia.
This is consistent with the recent ndings that language is not solely supported by Brocas
and Wernickes areas of the brain, but also by the primitive subcortical basal ganglia, given
that damage to the basal ganglia can cause serious harm to linguistic processing (see e.g.
Gibson 1996; Lieberman 2000; Ullman 2006). According to Ullman (2006:4801), Brocas
area is part of a larger circuit that involves the basal ganglia. The two parts of the brain are
densely interconnected, and both are implicated in language processing, including in
morphology and syntax. If the proto-syntactic structures (and the operation Conjoin)
postulated in this monograph provide a foundation for the rest of syntax, and if proto-
syntax is processed in part by subcortical structures of the brain, then it is expected that
damage to these areas in the brain would signicantly affect language. To put it another way,
if the foundation is faulty, it will not be able to support the suprastructure. As pointed out in
the previous section, Moro et al.s(2001) study also reveals activation of basal ganglia and the
cerebellum regions in syntactic processing, as well as the involvement of the right hemisphere
(see also Bookheimer 2002; Embick et al., 2000; Friederici, Meyer, and von Cramon 2000). The
hypothesis here is that this is so because modern syntactic structures still rest on the paratactic
foundation assembled by Conjoin, which in turn relies on the more scattered and more ancient
processing strategies.
In conclusion, while the predictions regarding subtracting (2) from (1) are ambivalent (but
testable), the subtraction of (1) from (2) is clearly expected to show increased activation in
Brocas areas, and possibly also in anterior temporal lobes. If so, then neuroimaging experi-
ments in this case can isolate direct neural correlates of utilizing a functional projection (e.g.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Small clauses vs. full sentences 215
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
TP), and with it hierarchy. In addition, due to the highly specic and concrete nature of these
hypotheses, neuroimaging testing in this case has the potential to tease apart movement (the
operation Move) from hierarchical layering, as well as to observe the contribution of each
hierarchical layer, one at a time.
If the theoretical predictions identied in this section get conrmed, the results will yield a
strictly controlled three-way distinction in graded syntactic complexity: rst, at proto-syntax
with no TP overlay and no movement possibilities, exhibiting only the operation Conjoin (1);
second, hierarchical syntax with a basic functional category, TP, but no movement performed,
exhibiting both Conjoin and Merge (2); and third, hierarchical syntax with both the basic
functional category TP and movement, exhibiting not only the operations Conjoin and Merge,
but also Move (3). This continuity of syntactic complexity, if found to correlate as predicted
with brain activation, would provide plausibility for a gradualist approach to the evolution of
syntax, as well as a promising new way of mediating between the elds of syntax and
neuroscience. It is also signicant that this framework can serve as a point of contact, an
intermediary, between the elds of neuro-linguistics and genetics, as discussed in Sections 1.5
and 2.5.4).
One can use the same neuroimaging methods to test the processing of English root small
clauses in (4), in contrast to the full TP counterparts in (5), as per the proposal in Chapter 2.
The small clauses in (4) are expected to show similar properties as Serbian small clauses
discussed above.
(4) Case closed. Problem solved. Point taken. Crisis averted.
Mission accomplished.
(5) The case has been closed. The problem has been solved. The point
has been taken. The crisis has been averted. The mission has been
accomplished.
Even though the clauses in (4) are certainly not exact equivalents of the Serbian unaccusative
small clauses in (1), they do show enough syntactic similarity to warrant a comparison. First,
these are passive-like structures, in which, just as is the case with unaccusatives, the subject is
not the agent. For that reason, passives and unaccusatives often receive a similar treatment in
syntactic theory (see e.g. Marantz 1984; Belletti 1988; Adger 2003).
6
Another similarity is that
both the Serbian data in (1) and the English examples in (4) are rigid small clauses assembled
by the operation Conjoin. As such, they lack the Tense auxiliary verb (and TP), cannot have
their constituents questioned (e.g. *How problem solved?), and cannot embed into other clauses
(e.g. *I think (that) case closed.), as discussed in Chapter 2. Even though the full nite
counterparts of these clauses (5) appear rather wordy, the additions are just functional words
which, in this case, add little, if anything, to the meaning. The predictions regarding these
English data are then comparable to the predictions for Serbian unaccusatives, as outlined
above.
6
While the mainstream syntactic analysis would implicate movement in passive sentences, the
approach explored in this book would suggest that these proto-syntactic passives do not involve move-
ment, given the general rigidity of proto-syntactic structures in this respect (Chapters 24). The results of a
neuroimaging experiment like this can shed light on this matter as well.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
216 Testing grounds: Neuroimaging
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
The general prediction of this proposal is that the distinction between small clause proto-
syntax and hierarchical syntax cuts across a variety of data and even languages, and that one
can isolate this distinction by looking at various minimally contrasting data of this kind across
languages and constructions, including verbal compounds discussed in the following section.
3Flat vs. hierarchical compounds
Neuroimaging experiments can also be devised to compare and contrast the processing of at
proto-syntactic VN compounds (6) and their hierarchical counterparts (7), both in English and
Serbian, based on the analysis in Chapter 6.
(6) pick-pocket, scare-crow, turn-coat, dare-devil, hunch-back,
wag-tail, tattle-tale, kill-joy, cut-purse, spoil-sport, rattle-snake,
catch-word, cry-baby, stink-bug, worry-wart, copy-cat, turn-
table
(7) joy-killer, head-turner, truck-driver, meat-eater, brick-layer,
story-teller, tax-payer, heart-breaker
The at (fossil) characterization of VN compounds, and their association with the operation
Conjoin, predicts that they will exhibit less syntactic activation, and less lateralization in the left
hemisphere, but possibly more reliance on the right hemisphere and the subcortical structures
of the brain, such as basal ganglia, thalamus, and limbic structures, especially the compounds
involving swearwords. As discussed in Chapter 6, VN compounds specialize for derogatory
reference, and many among them are obscene. Code (2005) has provided some neurological
evidence that swearwords are stored separately from other words, as they can remain intact
even when e.g. aphasic patients cannot access the rest of language. According to Code (2005),
the processing of swearwords relies on the right hemisphere of the brain, and on the
subcortical structures, considered to be involved in emotional processing in general.
According to LeDoux (2000:159), while the triune brain and the limbic theory for emotional
processing (e.g. MacLean 1949; Isaacson 1982) may not provide an adequate theory of the
specic brain circuits for emotion, MacLeans original ideas are very interesting in the context
of a general evolutionary explanation of emotion and the brain.
7
In particular, the notion that
emotions involve relatively primitive circuits that are conserved throughout mammalian
evolution seems right on target.
LeDoux (2000:159) further acknowledges that it is possible that cognitive processes involve
other circuits, and that they might function relatively independently of emotional circuits
(LeDoux 2000:159). The VN compounds thus bring together both proto-syntactic structure
assembled by the operation Conjoin and the subcortical underpinnings of swearing, rendering
these compounds of particular relevance for the study of language evolution. The approach to the
evolution of syntax outlined in this monograph provides some postulates which are at the right
level of granularity to help bridge the gap between the elds of syntax and neuroscience. This
approach may also provide an intermediary between genetic considerations and neuro-linguistic
considerations, another important piece of the puzzle for evolutionary considerations.
7
For MacLeans notion of the triune brain, see Section 2.5.5.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
Flat vs. hierarchical compounds 217
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
Acknowledgments
This Appendix is based on an ongoing joint project with neuroscientist Noa Ofen, Institute of
Gerontology/Pediatrics, Wayne State University. The project, titled In Search of Protosyntax
in the Brain,is supported by the 2014 Marilyn Williamson Endowed Distinguished Faculty
Fellowship.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF FINAL, 8/5/2015, SPi
218 Testing grounds: Neuroimaging
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/book/26661 by guest on 16 May 2024
References
Abney, Steven P. (1987). The English Noun Phrase in its Sentential Aspect. Ph.D. Dissertation,
Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA.
Ackema, Peter (1998). The Nonuniform Structure of Dutch N-V Compounds,in Geert Booij
and Jaap van Marle (eds.), Yearbook of Morphology. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Pub-
lishers, 12758.
Adams, Edward L. (1913). Word-Formation in Provençal. New York.
Adams, Valerie (1973). An Introduction to Modern English Word Formation. English Language
Series. London: Longman.
Adger, David (2003). Core Syntax: A Minimalist Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Aikhenvald, Alexandra Y. (2005). Serial verb constructions in typological perspective,in
Alexandra Y. Aikhenvald and R.M.W. Dixon (eds.), Serial Verb Constructions:A Cross-
Linguistic Typology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 168.
Aissen, Judith (2003). Differential object marking: Iconicity vs. economy,Natural Language
and Linguistic Theory 21:43583.
Akmajian, Adrian (1984).