ArticlePDF Available

Prostitution, Harm, and Disability: Should Only People With Disabilities Be Allowed to Pay for Sex?

Authors:

Abstract

Thomsen (2015) argues that people with disabilities should be granted an exception to a general prohibition on paying for sex. In this paper, I argue that Thomsen’s definition of disability is too vague to be useful in identifying who should be granted an exception to an overall ban, and that Thomsen’s case for a ban also fails to withstand scrutiny. A more reasonable argument, then, might be that mature individuals should be allowed to decide for themselves (a) what kind of consensual sex they wish to engage in, and (b) in exchange for what.
Prostitution, harm, and disability: Should only
people with disabilities be allowed to pay for sex?
Brian D. Earp
University of Oxford
Abstract
Thomsen (2015) argues that people with disabilities should be granted an exception to a
general prohibition on paying for sex. In this paper, I argue that Thomsen’s definition of
disability is too vague to be useful in identifying who should be granted an exception to
an overall ban, and that Thomsen’s case for a ban also fails to withstand scrutiny. A more
reasonable argument, then, might be that mature individuals should be allowed to decide
for themselves (a) what kind of consensual sex they wish to engage in, and (b) in
exchange for what.
Key words: prostitution, sexual autonomy, prohibition, disability
This is the author’s version of a published e-letter. Please cite as follows:
Earp, B. D. (2015). Prostitution, harm, and disability: Should only people with disabilities be
allowed to pay for sex? Journal of Medical Ethics, 41(6), e-letter. Available at
https://www.academia.edu/13252176/Prostitution_harm_and_disability_Should_only_people_wit
h_disabilities_be_allowed_to_pay_for_sex.
* Note: this e-letter is adapted from a blog post with the same title originally published at the
Journal of Medical Ethics Blog, available here: http://blogs.bmj.com/medical-
ethics/2015/06/17/prostitution-harm-and-disability/. A more formal academic paper drawing on
both pieces is now in press at the Journal of Medical Ethics; please see:
Earp, B. D., & Moen, O. M. (in press). Paying for sex—only for people with disabilities? Journal
of Medical Ethics, in press. Available online ahead of print at
https://www.academia.edu/16276000/Paying_for_sex_only_for_people_with_disabilities.
Introduction
Is prostitution harmful? And if it is harmful, should it be illegal to buy (or sell) sexual services?
And if so, should there ever be any exceptions? What about for people with certain disabilities—
say—who might find it difficult or even impossible to find a sexual partner if they weren’t
allowed to exchange money for sex? Do people have a “right” to sexual fulfillment?
In a recent issue of the Journal of Medical Ethics, Frej Klem Thomsen[1] explores these and
other controversial questions. His focus is on the issue of exceptions—specifically for those with
certain disabilities. According to Thomsen, a person is “relevantly disabled” (for the sake of this
discussion) if and only if:
(1) she has sexual needs, and desires to exercise her sexuality, and
(2) she has an anomalous physical or mental condition that, given her social
circumstances, sufficiently limits her possibilities of exercising her sexuality, including
fulfilling her sexual needs. (p. 455)
There is a lot to say here. First, in order to figure out the merits of making an exception to a
general ban on prostitution (for people with disabilities or for anyone else), we have to start by
deciding what to think about the advisability of such a ban in the first place. For, if we don’t
think that it’s a good idea to begin with, then we can skip all the talk about making exemptions,
and just argue against the overall ban.
But Thomsen doesn’t pursue that route. Instead, he wants to make a case for an exception. So, he
has to try to convince his reader that a general prohibition makes at least some kind of moral
and/or practical sense. How does he go about making this argument?
A case for prohibition?
Thomsen spells it out like this:
(1) Prostitution is bad because it causes harm to prostitutes.
(2) We have reason to avoid harm to persons.
(3) Prohibiting prostitution will reduce harm to prostitutes.
(4) Therefore, we have reason to prohibit prostitution. (p. 453)
Is this a good argument in favor of prohibition?
The harm of prostitution
We can start with the first claim: that prostitution is bad because it causes harm to prostitutes. Is
that a convincing claim?
It does have a certain intuitive appeal, and most people would probably say “yes.” But in another
recent essay (also published in the JME), the philosopher Ole Martin Moen has put forward a
powerful set of arguments that call into question conventional wisdom.[2] According to Moen,
while it is true that prostitution is not a harmless line of work:
(1) it is no more inherently harmful (on balance) than a long list of other occupations
which we do not see fit to ban, but instead choose to regulate; and
(2) most of the harm that does go along with prostitution is actually a consequence of its
being illegal (and otherwise socially stigmatized)—i.e., contingent, external factors that
have little to do with prostitution per se.
Let us take a closer look at Moen’s argument. To do this, we can start by considering one
specific type of harm as an example: the apparently higher rates of physical and mental health
problems among sex workers compared to members of the general population.
As Moen argues, this purported harm of prostitution might be due—at least in part—to the legal
prohibition against the activity, which prevents sex workers from taking certain actions that
would predictably improve their lot. For example: “joining labour unions, organizing their work
in brothels, renting a place where they can work, hiring security agencies, advertising and
forming work contracts (regarding salary, working hours, working conditions, health insurance,
retirement savings, and so on)” ([2], p. 3).
In fact, Moen does a good job of addressing most of the arguments that claim to show that
prostitution is inherently harmful (including in ways that are not just physical, but also more
abstract, symbolic, or moral), by performing a similar analysis for each one. Readers who are
skeptical, of course, can read Moen’s paper themselves, and reach their own conclusions.
Thomsen’s critique
Thomsen actually considers Moen’s argument. Only he doesn’t find it entirely convincing.
Among other issues, his main objection that even if “extrinsic” factors like social stigma and
legal prohibition were responsible for some of the harms associated with prostitution, they
wouldn’t necessarily account for all of the harms associated with prostitution. (As far as I can
tell, Moen doesn’t dispute this claim, but let us set that aside for now.)
To support his position, Thomsen cites an empirical study by a researcher named
Vanwesenbeeck.[3] According to Thomsen, this study showed that “roughly half—but no more
than half—[of] the variance in [certain negative emotional outcomes] experienced by indoor
prostitutes in the Netherlands was explained by external factors including stigma, lack of control
and poor working conditions” ([1], p. 453, emphasis added).
The implication, then, is that the other half of these negative outcomes (for example, emotional
exhaustion) must be due to something intrinsic to prostitution.
Intrinsic vs. extrinsic
There are a few ways to respond to this line of thought. First, there is the problem of non-random
sampling: some people turn to prostitution because of pre-existing issues with addiction or
mental health, and so the arrow of causation is not entirely clear. Second, it seems unlikely that
the study by Vanwesenbeeck measured every possible “external factor” that could be responsible
for the various harms of prostitution, which introduces a further limitation to what we can infer
from these results. But even if it did—so, even if we were justified in saying that “roughly half”
of the variance in (say) emotional exhaustion experienced by this particular sample of Dutch
prostitutes was due to something intrinsic about their selling sex—we would still have to put this
information in context.
What sort of context do I mean? Well, consider the fact that many careers contribute to, e.g.,
emotional exhaustion (and other negative emotional outcomes): just think of the burn-out that
grief and trauma counselors experience, for example, which is probably due to factors that are (at
least in large part) intrinsic to that particular line of work. Or think of the various harms that are
“built in” to any number of jobs, like the dangers of construction work, or professional boxing;
or the job-insecurity of being an actor (unemployed after every show); or the “degrading” nature
of, say, collecting people’s garbage or cleaning out their toilets.
When it comes to these careers, however, no one thinks we should prohibit people from
choosing to pursue them, just on account of the fact that they carry some degree of risk, or are
stigmatized, or are otherwise less than ideal. Instead, we try to think of ways of reducing the
various risks that are involved, and/or we compensate people—usually monetarily—for the
harms and difficulties that do in fact come along with their choice of employment.
None of this is to suggest that the intrinsic harms of prostitution are identical to those in the other
lines of work just mentioned. They may very well be much more problematic. The point is only
that the mere fact that some occupation has intrinsic harms, whatever those turn out to be, is not
sufficient to show (without further argument) that it should therefore be prohibited.
The importance of choice
Note the importance of choice here. My position has to do with people—men, women, intersex,
and transgender people—who freely choose to sell sexual services in exchange for money. If
someone is forced to sell sexual services, that is sexual slavery, not prostitution, and that is a
different matter entirely.
Now, someone might argue that prostitution is so inherently harmful or degrading, that someone
would only “choose” to exchange sex for money if in reality they were forced by their
circumstances (i.e., extreme poverty).[4] A similar argument has been made about the prospect
of establishing a market for selling kidneys: only people who are pressured (by their
circumstances) to sell their kidneys would end up doing so—the argument runs—so this kind of
vending is not really a free “choice.”
This takes us to yet another recent JME article, by Luke Semrau, entitled, “The Best Argument
Against Kidney Sales Fails.”[5] Semrau points out that there are two types of pressure to tease
apart here: a specific pressure to sell one’s kidney (or to engage in prostitution), which would in
fact be directly coercive—and which could conceivably be relieved by prohibiting the activity in
question—and a more general kind of pressure (i.e., economic insecurity), which, by contrast,
could actually be relieved by any number of activities, including not only selling one’s kidney or
engaging in prostitution, but also other types of employment.
In this latter case, however, prohibiting the activities in question does not actually relieve the
more general pressure. Instead, it may actually compound it—because it would take away
otherwise viable employment options. So, if someone has another way of relieving their poverty
apart from kidney-vending or prostitution (or collecting garbage, or cleaning toilets, or filling out
spreadsheets, or flipping burgers)—but regards one of those options as being preferable to the
alternatives—then it’s hard to see how we could say that they had been specifically pressured
into choosing that career.
Harm and prohibition
All of which is to say the following. Even we if were to grant the first point from Thomsen’s
argument—the one that says that prostitution causes at least some intrinsic harm to prostitutes—
this wouldn’t necessarily mean that we should favor a ban on prostitution. For one thing, if Moen
is right, a ban might actually increase the level of harm to prostitutes, compared against the
alternative policy of not having a ban, and setting up reasonable health and safety regulations,
encouraging de-stigmatization, etc. And for another thing, as Thomsen himself points out, even
if a ban did not have this harmful effect, we might still have other reasons to argue against it.
For example, we might endorse what Thomsen calls the “antipaternalist challenge.” This view
holds that “prohibition constitutes an unjustifiable interference in the freedom of consenting
adults” ([1], p. 454). Peter de Marneffe[6] puts the view like this:
Discretionary control over one’s own sexual activity [is] central to sexual autonomy, [to]
control over one’s body, and so to personal autonomy. … It is important that adults have
the discretion to make personal choices about the kind of sex they engage in with other
adults, even if these choices are unwise. So it is objectionable for the government to
prohibit a person from using her own body and sexuality for prostitution. (quoted in [1], p.
454).
As it happens, I tend to agree with this kind of analysis.[7, 8, 9, 10] Just think: adults are allowed
to have sex with someone they might find otherwise unappealing in exchange for almost
anything they desire except cash: promises of emotional support, the prospect of economic
security, or maybe just a few drinks at the bar. This doesn’t mean that those are good reasons to
engage in sexual intercourse—but it’s up to each of us how we negotiate our needs and desires.
More generally, however, when it comes to prohibition, one has to remember that it is no small
step from (on the one hand) getting one’s ethical analysis in order—in terms of establishing if a
given practice is in fact harmful, and in what particular way—to (on the other hand) determining
what kinds of social and legal changes would best reduce the harm in question, with the least
amount of collateral damage.[11]
To put it simply, prohibition is often a bad idea, even if the targeted activity is harmful.[12]
Back to Thomsen
Thomsen actually appears to agree with this. So, after taking several pages to try to convince us
that prostitution can plausibly be regarded as bad (because it is at least somewhat intrinsically
harmful), and that the best arguments to the contrary are not as strong as they may seem—he
nevertheless concludes that the “case for [actual] prohibition is murkier and weaker than its
proponents sometimes suggest” ([1], p. 455). A mere three sentences later, however, Thomsen
shifts gears rather awkwardly and asks us to go ahead and just “assume for the sake of argument
that the balance of reasons favours a general prohibition of prostitution” (ibid)!
Presumably, this is so that Thomsen can set up his case for the advisability of an exception to an
overall ban. He points to two facts that lay the groundwork for his position:
(1) Many or most persons have a sexuality that generates strong needs for sexual relations,
and
(2) Some disabled persons are partially or entirely incapable of satisfying this need
except through the purchase of sexual services from a prostitute. ([1], p. 455)
Buying sex—for people with disabilities only?
Let me give you an example of what he means. Quoting from another source,[13] he cites the
case of a man who “couldn’t walk and his carer would bring him. You had to lift him out of the
wheelchair and into the Jacuzzi and he was stiff because he didn’t move his arms or legs. He
couldn’t move, could get an erection but that was about it” ([1], p. 455).
Evidently, in exchange for money, someone was willing to have sex with this man under the
stated conditions, and this was helpful for resolving his “needs for sexual relations.” (Note that
Ezio Di Nucci has suggested a very interesting alternative: namely, establishing non-profit
charities whose members would voluntarily provide sexual pleasure to the severely disabled.[14]
For a related story, see the fascinating autobiographical account, “Head Nurses” by William
Peace in Atrium magazine.)[15]
What should we say about a case like this? The first thing to point out is that the man’s disability
didn’t make it so that he physically couldn’t have sex (if that were the case, hiring a prostitute
would not help his situation); instead, the issue was more that he couldn’t find a willing sexual
partnerfor whatever reason.
Now, it seems reasonable to conclude that—in this particular instance—the “reason” had
something to do with his physical disability. In other words, it seems likely that (all else being
equal) relatively few people would desire, as their first choice, to form a sexual relationship with
someone who could not “move his arms or legs” (although I imagine that there are many
exceptions). This is for the simple reason that some, presumably enjoyable, sexual experiences
are only possible if it is the case that one’s partner can make use of his external limbs without
assistance.
But that is a very specific issue—and it glosses over a more general point. And that is that all
sorts of people find it difficult to find a willing sexual partner—or enough willing sexual
partners—to “satisfy” their sexual needs, for a whole range of reasons that have nothing to do
with physical (or mental) disability of the “obvious” kind exemplified by this man. They may
simply be perceived as unattractive. Or they may be shy. Alternatively, they may be very
attractive—and not at all shy—and just have an insatiable sexual appetite. Are all of these people
“disabled” on Thomsen’s account?
Defining disability
It’s hard to tell. On the one hand, Thomsen could define “disability” in a very narrow sense that
captures only the “obvious” cases that everyone would recognize—perhaps typified by the man
in the example. But this would result in an extremely unreliable, and indeed almost absurdly
arbitrary proxy for the “real” underlying issue at stake, which is the difficulty that some people
have in finding a willing sexual partner(s) sufficient to meet their sexual needs without having
recourse to prostitutes.
After all, innumerable people with physical and/or mental disabilities have extremely satisfying
sexual relationships, so the connection between “having a disability” (of some kind) and “being
perceived as sexually unappealing” is so tangential as to be almost offensive.
On the other hand, Thomsen has the option of defining “disability” in a very broad sense—which
is what he does in fact choose to do—which carries its own set of problems. For one thing, it
refers to an extremely vague and amorphous group of people who (to quote from Thomsen’s
definition) have “an anomalous physical or mental condition that, given [their] social
circumstances, sufficiently limits [their] possibilities of exercising [their] sexuality, including
fulfilling [their] sexual needs” ([1], p. 455).
But that could include just about anyone! For one thing, there is the nearly boundless room for
interpretation surrounding most of the key terms in Thomsen’s definition: “anomalous,”
“physical,” “mental,” “condition,” “sufficiently,” and “fulfill.” For example, what is “anomalous”
– ? Statistically rare? How rare? As measured along what dimension? Also, why should the
condition have to be “anomalous” in any event? Isn’t it the (lack of) functional outcome that is
the morally relevant concern here?
Or think about the word “condition” – meaning what? Is shyness (to repeat that example) a
“mental condition” that counts as a disability? And what about “sufficiently”? How shall we
determine the cut-off? In other words, just how “hard” does it have to be to find a willing sexual
partner before one is allowed to register oneself as “sexually disabled,” say, and pick up her
“prostitution exemption” card? And finally—“fulfill.” Wouldn’t, say, most married couples
report that their sexual needs were not “fulfilled” in some relevant way? Indeed, one survey puts
the figure at 57%.[16]
Conclusion
So this doesn’t seem to be the way to go. Either the definition of disability is so narrow as to be
unjustifiably arbitrary as a proxy for the real underlying moral issue, or it’s so broad as to include
almost anyone. Why not—instead—just argue against a general prohibition, and let mature
individuals decide for themselves (a) what kind of consensual sex they wish to engage in, and (b)
in exchange for what.
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Julian Savulescu, John Danaher, Michael Hauskeller, Daniel Goldberg, and Ole
Martin Moen for feedback on these ideas. This e-letter is lightly adapted from a blog post with
the same title originally published at the Journal of Medical Ethics Blog, available here:
http://blogs.bmj.com/medical-ethics/2015/06/17/prostitution-harm-and-disability/. Although
most of the text is identical to that in the blog post, I have made some minor improvements to the
text in terms of both style and content. Please note that Dr. Moen and I are preparing a formal
academic paper expanding on the ideas presented in this e-letter, and that some passages are
expected to overlap substantially. [Update as of 28 September, 2015: this paper has now been
accepted for publication. Please see Earp, B. D., & Moen, O. M. (in press). Paying for sex—only
for people with disabilities? Journal of Medical Ethics, in press. Available online ahead of print
https://www.academia.edu/16276000/Paying_for_sex_only_for_people_with_disabilities.]
References
[1] Thomsen, F. K. (2015). Prostitution, disability and prohibition. Journal of Medical
Ethics, 41(6), 451-459.
[2] Moen, O. M. (2014). Is prostitution harmful? Journal of Medical Ethics, 40(2), 73-81.
[3] Vanwesenbeeck, I. (2005). Burnout among female indoor sex workers. Archives of Sexual
Behavior, 34(6), 627-639.
[4] Weinberg, J., de Marneffe, P., Demetriou, D., Earp, B. D., Fuller, L., Gauthier, J., Hay, C.,
Marino, P., Pettit, P., & Whisnant, R. (2015). Philosophers on prostitution’s decriminalization.
Daily Nous. Available at http://dailynous.com/2015/08/13/philosophers-on-prostitutions-
decriminalization/.
[5] Semrau, L. (2015). The best argument against kidney sales fails. Journal of Medical
Ethics, 41(6), 443-446.
[6] de Marneffe, P. (2009). Liberalism and prostitution. Oxford University Press.
[7] Vierra, A., & Earp, B. D. (2015). Born this way? How high-tech conversion therapy could
undermine gay rights. The Conversation. Available
at https://www.academia.edu/12055156/Born_this_way_How_high-
tech_conversion_therapy_could_undermine_gay_rights.
[8] Earp, B. D. (in press). Female genital mutilation and male circumcision: Toward an
autonomy-based ethical framework. Medicolegal and Bioethics, in press. Available
at https://www.academia.edu/10270196/Female_genital_mutilation_and_male_circumcision_To
ward_an_autonomy-based_ethical_framework.
[9] Earp, B. D., Sandberg, A., & Savulescu, J. (2014). Brave new love: The threat of high-tech
“conversion” therapy and the bio-oppression of sexual minorities. AJOB Neuroscience, 5(1), 4-
12.
[10] Maslen, H., Earp, B. D., Cohen Kadosh, R., & Savulescu, J. (2014). Brain stimulation for
treatment and enhancement in children: An ethical analysis. Frontiers in Human
Neuroscience, 8(953), 1-5.
[11] Earp, B. D. (2014). Things I have learned (so far) about how to do practical ethics. Practical
Ethics. University of Oxford. Available at http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2014/03/things-
ive-learned-so-far-about-how-to-do-practical-ethics/.
[12] Earp, B. D. (2013). The ethics of infant male circumcision. Journal of Medical Ethics, 39(7),
418-420.
[13] Sanders, T. (2007). The politics of sexual citizenship: commercial sex and
disability. Disability & Society, 22(5), 439-455.
[14] Di Nucci, E. (2011). Sexual rights and disability. Journal of Medical Ethics, 37(3), 158-161.
[15] Peace, W. (2014). Head nurses. Atrium, Winter, 12, 20-22.
[16] National Survey of Marital Strengths. Available at https://www.prepare-
enrich.com/pe_main_site_content/pdf/research/national_survey.pdf.
... Acknowledgements Parts of this essay have been adapted from an informal piece by the first author, entitled, "Prostitution, Harm, and Disability: Should Only People with Disabilities be Allowed to Pay for Sex?," originally posted at the Journal of Medical Ethics Blog, and subsequently published as a short e-letter. 8 A handful of sentences have also been adapted from an interview with the same author for the website Daily Nous. 9 Thanks to Daniel Goldberg for feedback on an earlier draft of this essay. ...
Article
Full-text available
Thomsen (2015) argues that people with disabilities should be granted an exception to a general prohibition on prostitution. In this response, we argue that Thomsen's call for an exception does not withstand careful scrutiny. The concerns that appear to motivate his argument point instead, we argue, to a case for legalization of prostitution, coupled with sensible health and safety regulations.
... 43 Conversely, as Christine Mason and others have argued, adults should be free to use medical technologies to modify their own bodies and minds, in a process of self-creation, if that is what they truly want. [147][148][149] While I do not suggest that (nontherapeutic) MGA should be banned, necessarily, 85,150,151 it is clear that the current laissez faire attitude toward this practice that is typical of Western societies -and in particular the United States -can no longer be maintained without facing serious objection. FGA and MGA are both highly problematic practices, with far more overlap between them (both physically and symbolically) than is commonly understood: they should not be discussed, therefore, in hermetically-sealed moral discourses. ...
Article
Full-text available
The non-therapeutic alteration of children's genitals is typically discussed in two separate ethical discourses: one for girls, in which such alteration is conventionally referred to as "female genital mutilation" (or FGM), and one for boys, in which it is conventionally referred to as "male circumcision." The former is typically regarded as objectionable or even barbaric; the latter, benign or beneficial. In this paper, however, I call into question the moral and empirical basis for such a distinction, and I argue that it is untenable. As an alternative, I propose an ethical framework for evaluating such alterations that is based upon considerations of bodily autonomy and informed consent, rather than sex or gender.
Article
Full-text available
On August 12th, 2015, the non-governmental human rights organization Amnesty International voted to put forward a policy supporting the "full" decriminalization of prostitution – i.e., both the buying and the selling of sex. The announcement proved controversial, and divided the human rights community as well as those who hold different positions on the question of prohibiting prostitution more generally. In this article, ten philosophers, from ten different universities, representing a wide range of opinion on the issue, spell out some of the key philosophical considerations that play into this contentious debate.
Article
Full-text available
On August 12th, 2015, the non-governmental human rights organization Amnesty International voted to put forward a policy supporting the "full" decriminalization of prostitution – i.e., both the buying and the selling of sex. The announcement proved controversial, and divided the human rights community as well as those who hold different positions on the question of prohibiting prostitution more generally. In this article, ten philosophers, from ten different universities, representing a wide range of opinion on the issue, spell out some of the key philosophical considerations that play into this contentious debate.
Article
Full-text available
The non-therapeutic alteration of children's genitals is typically discussed in two separate ethical discourses: one for girls, in which such alteration is conventionally referred to as "female genital mutilation" (or FGM), and one for boys, in which it is conventionally referred to as "male circumcision." The former is typically regarded as objectionable or even barbaric; the latter, benign or beneficial. In this paper, however, I call into question the moral and empirical basis for such a distinction, and I argue that it is untenable. As an alternative, I propose an ethical framework for evaluating such alterations that is based upon considerations of bodily autonomy and informed consent, rather than sex or gender.
Article
Full-text available
Following the death of 17-year-old Leelah Alcorn, a transgender teen who committed suicide after forced “conversion therapy,” President Barack Obama called for a nationwide ban on psychotherapy aimed at changing sexual orientation or gender identity. The administration argued that because conversion therapy causes substantial psychological harm to minors, it is neither medically nor ethically appropriate. We fully agree with the President and believe that this is a step in the right direction. Of course, in addition to being unsafe as well as ethically unsound, current conversion therapy approaches aren’t actually effective at doing what they claim to do – changing sexual orientation But we also worry that this may be a short-term legislative solution to what is really a conceptual problem. The question we ought to be asking is “what will happen if and when scientists do end up developing safe and effective technologies that can alter sexual orientation?”
Article
Full-text available
Davis (2014) called for “extreme caution” in the use of non-invasive brain stimulation (NIBS) to treat neurological disorders in children, due to gaps in scientific knowledge. We are sympathetic to his position. However, we must also address the ethical implications of applying this technology to minors. Compensatory trade-offs associated with NIBS present a challenge to its use in children, insofar as these trade-offs have the effect of limiting the child’s future options. The distinction between treatment and enhancement has some normative force here. As the intervention moves away from being a treatment toward being an enhancement—and thus toward a more uncertain weighing of the benefits, risks, and costs—considerations of the child’s best interests (as judged by the parents) diminish, and the need to protect the child’s (future) autonomy looms larger. NIBS for enhancement involving trade-offs should therefore be delayed, if possible, until the child reaches a state of maturity and can make an informed, personal decision. NIBS for treatment, by contrast, is permissible insofar as it can be shown to be at least as safe and effective as currently approved treatments, which are themselves justified on a best interests standard.
Article
Full-text available
This paper breaks a long silence by bringing together two areas of literature that have generally been considered separately: that of sexuality and disability with findings from studies on sex work. Presenting empirical findings from two studies, one with sex workers who work from indoor sex markets and the other with men who buy sex, this paper exposes the existing relationships and practices between men with physical and sensory impairments who seek out commercial sexual services from female sex workers. In the discussion the politics surrounding sexual rights and commercial sex will be addressed. In the context of commercial sex, quality of life issues, complex power dynamics and the common ground between disabled people and sex workers rights are discussed. This paper considers the negative aspects of promoting commercial sex for people with impairments, as well as the positive aspects regarding the wider campaign for sexual citizenship. Finally, I set out recommendations and a new research and policy agenda that investigates the complexities of commercial and facilitated sex.
Article
Full-text available
Our understanding of the neurochemical bases of human love and attachment, as well as of the genetic, epigenetic, hormonal, and experiential factors that conspire to shape an individual’s sexual orientation, is increasing exponentially. This research raises the vexing possibility that we may one day be equipped to modify such variables directly, allowing for the creation of “high-tech” conversion therapies or other suspect interventions. In this paper, we discuss the ethics surrounding such a possibility, and call for the development of legal and procedural safeguards for protecting vulnerable children from the application of such technology. We also consider the more difficult case of voluntary, adult “conversion” and argue that in rare cases, such attempts might be permissible under strict conditions.
Article
Full-text available
Is the non-therapeutic circumcision of infant males morally permissible? The most recent major developments in this long-simmering debate were (a) the 2012 release of a policy statement and technical report on circumcision by the American Academy of Pediatrics (AAP), and (b) the decision of a German court that ritual circumcision is an unconstitutional form of bodily injury. In this editorial I address the AAP's claims as well as evaluate religious motivations more specifically. I suggest that the AAP's "health benefits" arguments are weak, and that religious circumcision is in tension with post-Enlightenment ethical and legal norms--the root of much of the current controversy. I conclude by asking how this tension might begin to be resolved.
Article
Civil libertarians characterize prostitution as a "victimless crime," and argue that it ought to be legalized. Feminist critics counter that prostitution is not victimless, since it harms the people who do it. Civil libertarians respond that most women freely choose to do this work, and that it is paternalistic for the government to limit a person's liberty for her own good. This book argues that although most prostitution is voluntary, paternalistic prostitution laws in some form are nonetheless morally justifiable. If prostitution is commonly harmful in the way that feminist critics maintain, this argument for prostitution laws is not objectionably moralistic and some prostitution laws violate no one's rights. Paternalistic prostitution laws in some form are therefore consistent with the fundamental principles of contemporary liberalism.
Article
Simon Rippon has recently argued against kidney markets on the grounds that introducing the option to vend will result in many people, especially the poor, being subject to harmful pressure to vend. Though compelling, Rippon's argument fails. What he takes to be a single phenomenon-social and legal pressure to vend-is actually two. Only one of these forms of pressure is, by Rippon's own account, harmful. Further, an empirically informed view of the regulated market suggests that this harmful pressure is easily avoided. Thus, the harm that is the lynchpin of Rippon's opposition is neither a necessary feature of the market nor is it likely to play a significant role in its operation.
Article
Criminalisation of prostitution, and minority rights for disabled persons, are important contemporary political issues. The article examines their intersection by analysing the conditions and arguments for making a legal exception for disabled persons to a general prohibition against purchasing sexual services. It explores the badness of prostitution, focusing on and discussing the argument that prostitution harms prostitutes, considers forms of regulation and the arguments for and against with emphasis on a liberty-based objection to prohibition, and finally presents and analyses three arguments for a legal exception, based on sexual rights, beneficence, and luck egalitarianism, respectively. It concludes that although the general case for and against criminalisation is complicated there is a good case for a legal exception.