ArticlePDF Available

Abstract

This paper illuminates a variety of issues that speak to the question of whether ‘captivity for conservation’ can be an ethically acceptable goal of the modern zoo. Reflecting on both theoretical disagreements (animal protectionists vs. wildlife conservationists) and practical challenges (the small percentage of endangered species actually exhibited in zoos, disappointing success of reintroduction programs), the paper explains why the ‘Noah’s Ark’ paradigm is being replaced by an alternative ‘integrated approach.’ It explores the changes in the zoo’s core tasks that the new paradigm implies. And it pays special attention to the changes that would have to be made in zoos’ collection policies: connection with in situ projects, emphasizing local species and the local biogeographical region, exchange of animals among zoos and between zoos and wildlife, and a shift towards smaller species. Finally the question will be addressed whether the new paradigm will achieve a morally acceptable balance between animal welfare costs and species conservation benefits.
1 23
Journal of Agricultural and
Environmental Ethics
ISSN 1187-7863
J Agric Environ Ethics
DOI 10.1007/s10806-015-9537-z
Captivity for Conservation? Zoos at a
Crossroads
Jozef Keulartz
1 23
Your article is published under the Creative
Commons Attribution license which allows
users to read, copy, distribute and make
derivative works, as long as the author of
the original work is cited. You may self-
archive this article on your own website, an
institutional repository or funder’s repository
and make it publicly available immediately.
ARTICLES
Captivity for Conservation? Zoos at a Crossroads
Jozef Keulartz
Accepted: 22 February 2015
Ó The Author(s) 2015. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com
Abstract This paper illuminates a variety of issues that speak to the question of
whether ‘captivity for conservation’ can be an ethically acceptable goal of the
modern zoo. Reflecting on both theoretical disagreements (animal protectionists vs.
wildlife conservationists) and practical challenges (the small percentage of endan-
gered species actually exhibited in zoos, disappointing success of reintroduction
programs), the paper explains why the ‘Noah’s Ark’ paradigm is being replaced by
an alternative ‘integrated approach.’ It explores the changes in the zoo’s core tasks
that the new paradigm implies. And it pays special attention to the changes that
would have to be made in zoos’ collection policies: connection with in situ projects,
emphasizing local species and the local biogeographical region, exchange of ani-
mals among zoos and between zoos and wildlife, and a shift towards smaller spe-
cies. Finally the question will be addressed whether the new paradigm will achieve a
morally acceptable balance between animal welfare costs and species conservation
benefits.
Keywords Future zoo Animal welfare Species conservation Metapopulation
management
Introduction
Today, the animal world is under severe attack as a result of two strongly
interconnected global processes. On the one hand, global environmental changes
J. Keulartz (&)
Emeritus Professor of Environmental Philosophy, Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands
e-mail: J.Keulartz@science.ru.nl
J. Keulartz
Wageningen University, Wageningen, The Netherlands
123
J Agric Environ Ethics
DOI 10.1007/s10806-015-9537-z
such as climate change, land use and land cover change, deforestation and
desertification have a disruptive impact on plant and animal life. Entire populations
are being confronted with the alternative to abandon their original habitat or to go
extinct. On the other hand, globalization causes massive dislocations of entire
populations. As trade, travel, transport and tourism boom, the world is becoming
more and more borderless and, by the same token, it is becoming increasingly
vulnerable to invasive species. Since globalization took off, more plants and animals
have become globetrotters than ever before (Keulartz and Swart 2012).
Because animals are constantly on the move worldwide as a result of these global
processes, traditional in situ (place-based) conservation methods seem no longer
sufficient to save threatened species (Sandler 2012). The magnitude of anthro-
pogenic environmental stress from bioinvasion, habitat fragmentation, nitrogen
deposition, biodiversity loss, and, above all, climate change, makes it unavoidable
to replace the hands-off approach that has guided mainstream species conservation
until recently by a more proactive and interventionist strategy.
However, this new strategy has led to manifold conflicts between wildlife
conservationists and animal protectionists (Minteer and Collins 2013). As Michael
Soule
´
has remarked in his presidential address at the third annual meeting of the
Society for Conservation Biology in 1989: ‘Conflicts between animal rights groups
and management agencies are increasing in frequency and cost—the cost being
borne by endangered species and ecosystems as well as by the public that pays for
expensive rescue operations and time-consuming court battles’ (Soule
´
1990, 235).
In his address, Soule
´
claimed that among the many environmental challenges of
the coming decades, ‘the onslaught of alien species’ would be the most
revolutionary. And he foresaw that attempts by conservationists to control
destructive exotics would meet resistance from ‘well-meaning animal welfare
enthusiasts’, who oppose eradication programs that involve techniques such as
hunting and trapping or make use of pesticides such as piscicides, chemical
substances which are poisonous to fish (Keulartz and Van der Weele 2008).
1
Another potential area of conflict between wildlife conservationists and animal
activists concerns managed relocation (also known as assisted colonization or
assisted migration). The human-aided relocation of threatened species may be
required when their historical ranges have become inhospitable due to climate
change or habitat fragmentation and destruction, and when moving on their own to
other regions where environmental conditions are more suitable is impossible.
Relocated animals will inevitable experience chronic stress at all stages of the
process, from capture and captivity to transport and release to novel areas. Such
relocation-induced chronic stress increases the overall vulnerability of the
individuals and, as a result, decreases the probability that the population will
become self-sustaining (Dickens et al. 2010).
1
A famous example of the clash over programs to eradicate invasive species is the controversy about the
feral pigs in Hawaii, between the Nature Conservancy and People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals
(PETA). While conservation biologists have argued that the pigs should be killed and removed because
they threaten Hawaii’s biodiversity, animal activists argued that it is wrong to harm and kill the pigs
because they are sentient animals (Woods and Moriarty 2001).
J. Keulartz
123
Here, I will focus on yet another major battlefield between wildlife conserva-
tionists and animal activists: ex situ conservation through zoos and aquaria. As a
response to the ongoing decline in effectiveness of in situ conservation and the
accompanying loss of biodiversity, zoos began to turn their attention to the
conservation of endangered species and wildlife in the 1970s and 1980s. Captivity
for Conservation became a crucial slogan for the modern zoo. A major milestone in
this development was the Convention on Biodiversity which was signed at the Earth
Summit in Rio de Janeiro in 1992. In the wake of the Earth Summit the first World
Zoo Conservation Strategy was launched in 1993. Its conclusion explicitly stated
that, at a time when species, habitats and ecosystems worldwide are threatened with
extinction, modern zoos must commit to the conservation of species and wildlife.
Caring for our planet’s biological systems is one of the greatest challenges to
humankind. Consequently, conservation is being seen as the central theme of
zoos, and zoos should thus further evolve into conservation centers (WAZA
1993, 3).
In this scheme of things the zoo was envisaged as a kind of Noah’s Ark which owed
its raison d’eˆtre primarily to its contribution to the conservation of species through
breeding and reintroduction programs. As the main institution for ex situ
conservation of wild animal species, the zoo was now confronted head-on with
the potential conflicts between animal protectionists and wildlife conservationists.
In this essay, I will analyze the moral issues at stake in these conflicts over the
zoo with an eye to possibilities to bridge the differences between the conflicting
parties. I will argue that both sides of the controversy may find common ground in
the view that zoos will be morally justifiable only if the costs in terms of animal
welfare and freedom are clearly outweighed by the benefits to species preservation.
Next, I will argue that the Noah’s Ark paradigm does not meet this standard, that it
therefore has lost credibility and has gradually given way to a new paradigm: the
‘integrated approach’ in which the zoo is primarily seen as a conservation park or
center. I will then set out the implications of the new approach for the zoo’s core
tasks and explore the collection policy options that are open to zoos in order to carry
out these tasks in the best possible way. Finally, I will address the question whether
the new paradigm may achieve a morally acceptable balance between animal
welfare costs and species conservation benefits. But in order to understand what is at
stake in the battle over the zoo’s legitimacy and right to existence I will first take a
closer look at the heated philosophical debate between animal ethicists and
environmental ethicists.
The Animal Ethics/Environmental Ethics Debate
The philosophical debate between animal ethicists and environmental ethicist
erupted around 1980 (Hargrove 1992). Before that time it was expected that an
adequate environmental ethics would develop as a natural extension of animal
ethics. Both Peter Singer’s animal liberation theory and Tom Regan’s animal rights
theory denounced traditional morality for its ‘human chauvinism’ and its
Zoos at a Crossroads
123
‘speciesism’. The time seemed ripe for a moral rehabilitation of the rest of animate
nature, and animal ethicists and environmental ethicists were supposed to join
forces in fighting for wildlife preservation. But, as Sagoff (1984) has remarked
somewhat sarcastically, this was a ‘bad marriage’, followed by a ‘quick divorce’.
In 1980, Baird Callicott published a highly polemical article to counter the
widespread view that the existing animal ethics of Singer en Regan were fully
capable of answering all environmental ethical questions. In particular, Callicott
opposed their view that only individual animals have intrinsic value and direct
moral standing, not collective entities such as species or ecosystems. While Singer
believes that we have no duties to species because as such they ‘are not conscious
entities and so do not have interests above and beyond the interests of the individual
animals that are members of the species’ (Singer 1979, 203), Regan holds that ‘the
rights view does not recognize the moral rights of species to anything, including
survival’ (Regan 1983, 359).
According to Callicott, animal ethicists demonstrate their ‘ecological illiteracy’
by pleading for a responsibility to maintain individual animals irrespective of
whether these are tame or wild, rare or common, indigenous or exotic. In line with
Aldo Leopold’s ‘land ethic’, he advocated a holistic approach in which individual
organisms are perceived as parts of the biotic community. Such an approach does
not accord equal moral worth to each and every member of the biotic community;
‘the moral worth of individuals is relative, to be assessed in accordance with the
particular relation of each to the collective entity which Leopold called ‘land’’
(Callicott 1980, 327).
Holmes Rolston, one of the founding fathers of environmental ethics, based his
holistic view on a neo-Darwinian account of the evolutionary history of life on
earth. He writes: ‘In an evolutionary ecosystem it is not mere individuality that
counts; species is also significant because it is a dynamic life form maintained over
time by an informed genetic flow. The individual represents (re-presents) a species
in each new generation. It is a token of a type, and the type is more important than
the token’ (Rolston 1988, 143). It follows that ‘the individual is subordinate to the
species, not the other way around’ (ibid. 149).
Tom Regan responded to these attacks against the animal ethicists’ basic
principle with the accusation that environmental ethicists were committing the
crime of ‘environmental fascism’ by subordinating the rights of individuals to the
interests of the greater whole. ‘Environmental fascism and the rights view are like
oil and water, they don’t mix’ (Regan 1983, 362).
Animal ethicists and environmental ethicists usually not only differ with regard
to the locus of moral concern—individual organisms or greater wholes—they also
tend to use different species concepts (Sandler 2012, 4). Animal ethicists have
generally adopted a conventionalist species concept; they see a species merely as a
category or class with arbitrarily drawn boundary lines that may serve as a
convenient mapping device for theoretical purposes only.
2
Environmental ethicists,
2
According to Dale Jamieson ‘‘the notion of a species is an abstraction; the idea of its welfare is a human
construction. While there is something that it is like to be an animal there is nothing that it is like to be a
species’ (Jamieson 1995, 61).
J. Keulartz
123
on the other hand, generally hold a realistic species concept. Rolston, for instance,
argues that a species is a real historical entity, a ‘dynamic historical lineage’ that can
persist as a discrete, vital pattern over time (Rolston 1988, 151).
3
While it is evident that conflicts between individualistic animal-centered and
holistic species-centered ethicists and activists will increase as conservation
strategies will inevitable become more and more interventionist and hands-on, the
gap between these divergent views simply seems too wide to bridge, even in cases
where advocates of both sides have common cause (Minteer and Collins 2013, 43).
Such seemingly intractable controversies are often not resolvable by recourse to
facts and unlikely to be settled by compromise. They require what Donald Scho
¨
n
and Martin Rein, inspired by John Dewey’s idea of ‘reconstructive thinking’, have
called ‘frame restructuring’, i.e. the attempt to integrate conflicting frames.
As a necessary first step towards such an integration, both sides of the
controversy regarding the moral acceptability of zoos have to develop a ‘double
vision’, namely ‘the ability to act from a frame while cultivating awareness of
alternative frames’’ (Scho
¨
n and Rein 1994, 207). They should learn to ‘squint’ so to
speak in order to see things from both angels simultaneously. Only then will it be
possible to find a morally defensible balance between animal welfare concerns on
the one hand and species conservation commitments on the other.
Balancing Animal Welfare/Rights Against Species Conservation
Most animal rights proponents will resist any attempts at such value balancing.
They consider infringing an individual’s right to freedom for the sake of the
preservation of the species as morally wrong. For Regan any type of captivity or
manipulation of a sentient animal is morally unacceptable, irrespective of the
possibly beneficial consequences for the protection of rare or endangered species.
The rights view’s answer to the question whether zoos are morally defensible, ‘not
surprisingly, is No, they are not’ (Regan 1995, 46).
Utilitarians like Singer, on the other hand, do allow for value balancing and
accept reductions in animal welfare when the survival of entire populations or
species is at stake. A case in point is Singer’s approach to the problem of the South
American cane toad that was introduced to Australia as a method of agricultural pest
control, but became itself a serious pest for native wildlife. Whereas animal rights
groups fiercely opposed the eradication of cane toads because they believe that
killing an animal, unless to end suffering, is always bad, Singer argued that ‘where
killing can be done humanely, and is necessary to preserve endangered species, it
may be defensible.’
4
When Singer was recently asked whether zoos should exist for the sake of species
preservation, he answered as follows, ‘‘I think if a species is likely to become extinct
in the wild and you can capture the animals humanely and recreate the physical and
behavioral conditions, then could release them or their progeny in the wild, then that
3
For a recent contribution to the animal ethics/environmental ethics debate, see McShane (2014).
4
http://www.abc.net.au/environment/articles/2011/01/17/3113142.htm.
Zoos at a Crossroads
123
function of zoos is defensible.’
5
Singer feels, however, that most zoos today fail to
live up to their conservation mission. They tend to confine animals for our
amusement in ways that are contrary to their interests. Even if these zoos do
occasionally preserve an endangered species, ‘what is the point of preserving
animals if they are having miserable lives?’
6
Dale Jamieson, another animal ethicist working in the utilitarian tradition,
7
is
even more skeptical about zoos than Peter Singer. As starting point for his
assessment of the moral defensibility of the zoo, Jamieson claims that keeping
animals in captivity is wrong, unless a case can be made that the benefits outweigh
the moral presumption against depriving animals of liberty. In his classic essay
‘Against Zoos’ from 1985, Jamieson concludes that the supposed benefits of zoos—
amusement, education, scientific research and species preservation—are outweighed
by the moral presumption against keeping animals. Ten years latter, he repeated his
analysis with a strong focus on the modern zoo’s most compelling reason for its
existence, its contribution to species conservation. And again Jamieson’s final
judgment proved unfavorable for the zoo; he considered the benefit of preservation
‘not significant enough to overcome the presumption against depriving an animal of
its liberty’ (Jamieson 1995, 60).
Noah’s Ark in Rough Water
Jamieson’s verdict was, to a considerable extent, shared by an increasing number of
critiques within the zoo-community. The vision of the zoo as a Noah’s Ark started
to shipwreck as the breeding programs ran into some substantial problems. Many of
the animals exhibited in zoos do not belong to groups designated for conservation.
Because the space for all the zoo animals in the world could easily fit within New
York’s 212.7 km
2
borough of Brooklyn (Conway 2011, 4), zoos can only maintain a
limited number of endangered species. This number will even decrease as exhibits
increase in size to meet animal welfare, while zoos are usually also very reluctant to
give up popular animals that are not threatened with extinction. But even if zoos
were to dedicate half their space to breeding programs for the conservation of
endangered species, they would still—according to the most optimistic estimates—
be unable to accommodate more than around 800 of the 7.368 species of vertebrates
that are threatened with extinction according to the 2013 IUCN Red List.
8
Due to
lack of space zoos are increasingly being pressed to separate grain from chaff and
devote more resources to a chosen few. As Leslie Kaufman has strikingly remarked,
breeding endangered animals ‘feels less like Noah building an ark and more like
Schindler making a list’ (Kaufman 2012a).
5
https://www.thedodo.com/peter-singer-on-the-animal-rig-726248280.html.
6
http://www.mkhumanists.org.uk/node/73.
7
Jamieson calls his brand of utilitarianism ‘progressive consequentialism’ (Jamieson and Elliot 2009).
8
The list cites 1140 species of mammals, 1313 species of birds, 847 species of reptiles, 1948 species of
amphibians, and 2110 species of fish.
J. Keulartz
123
Research has shown that zoos currently hold roughly one in seven (15 %)
threatened species of terrestrial vertebrates (Conde et al. 2011).
9
Moreover, zoos
even struggle to breed these few species because the populations are usually too
small. As Sarah Long, director of the Population Management Center in Chicago,
has remarked, ‘‘Noah got it all wrong. One or two or even a dozen of each species is
not enough’’ (Kaufman 2012b). Initially, the target of zoo breeding programs was to
maintain 90 % of genetic variability of a species for a period of 200 years (Soule
´
et al. 1986). Because this time frame requires very large numbers of animals per
species, it has been reduced from 200 to 100 years in the mid-1990s. But the
majority of breeding programs do not have sufficient space to meet even this
objective.
However, not only are the success rates of breeding programs disappointing, the
prospects of reintroduction programs are also low, largely because ecological,
social, economic and political aspects were not taken into consideration. Reintro-
duction is a costly business which often diverts attention from other, more cost-
effective options. In captivity, animals risk losing the skills they need to survive in
the wild. Lastly, the ecosystems into which they are eventually released are dynamic
systems which have often undergone dramatic changes in the time span between the
breeding program and the reintroduction, sometimes as a result of anthropogenic
disturbances such as CO
2
emissions and deforestation. A review by Beck (1995)
estimated that only 16 out of 145 reintroduction projects using captive-born animals
were successful. It also showed that most animals for reintroduction do not come
from zoos but from other specialized facilities. Although the situation improved
after the development of the Guidelines for the Placement of Confiscated Animals
(IUCN 2000), the performance of zoos regarding the reintroduction of captive-bred
animals still fell far short of expectations. Instead of a guiding light, reintroduction
proved to be a shooting star, ‘‘providing an eye-catching attraction but not long-term
illumination for conservation’ (Price and Fa 2007, 173).
10
By the turn of the century, Noah’s Ark seemed to have become irretrievably
shipwrecked as the zoo community started to realize the limitations of ex situ (zoo-
based) conservation as a prelude to in situ (field-based) conservation (Lees and
Wilcken 2009). The vision of the zoo as a Noah’s Ark has gradually given way to a
new paradigm, the ‘integrated approach’. This transition becomes apparent when
the first World Zoo Conservation Strategy of 1993 is compared to the new World
Zoo and Aquarium Conservation Strategy of 2005. The first document explicitly
describes reintroduction as the ultimate goal of ex situ conservation. The second
document, on the other hand, recognizes the reintroduction of captive-bred animals
9
Invertebrates are almost absent in zoos (see Collection Policy Options section).
10
Furthermore, many of the successful reintroductions have their own history of struggle and strife.
Take, for example, the Black-footed ferret (McCarthy 2004, 196/7). In 1986, the Black-footed ferret
population had diminished to a mere 18 individuals, but thanks to a captive breeding program, more than
220 now roam the prairie of the US state of Wyoming. The program was not, however, entirely plain
sailing. When the kits were released they were far too blase
´
to make themselves scarce when predators
such as eagles, coyotes and badgers arrived on the scene. The researchers tried to resolve this problem by
building a mock predator. They attached wheels to a stuffed badger, which would win fame as
RoboBadger. The only way the ferrets could escape RoboBadger was to find a burrow. The researchers
then tried to increase the ferrets’ aversion to RoboBadger by firing rubber bands at them.
Zoos at a Crossroads
123
as a useful instrument for the conservation of wildlife, but cautions against high
expectations because of the complexities of returning these animals to the wild
(Price and Fa 2007, 156). It outlines a much broader conservationist role for zoos,
including research, training, education, awareness campaigns and direct support for
in situ projects. In the latest strategy, the primary mission of zoos is to integrate all
these elements with their efforts to protect endangered species and conserve healthy
ecosystems (Mace et al. 2007; Bowkett 2008; Lees and Wilcken 2009). Insofar as
captive-breeding for reintroduction is considered necessary and appropriate, it
should be accomplished as part of such a larger, integrated, holistic program
(Hutchins 2003, 18).
This paradigm shift in the zoo’s mission raises the question whether Jamieson’s
verdict will remain valid that the supposed benefits of the zoo, in particular its
contribution to species conservation, are outweighed by the moral presumption
against keeping animals. Will the integrated approach make it possible to strike a
balance between animal welfare and rights on the one hand and species conservation
on the other that leads to a morally more favorable evaluation of the zoo? To answer
this question, I will proceed in two steps: first I will spell out the implications of the
new paradigm for the zoo’s core tasks; and next I will explore the collection policy
options that are open to zoos in order to perform these tasks optimally.
Implications of the Integrated Approach for the Zoo’s Core Tasks
In this section, I will successively discuss the impact of the integrated approach on
education, awareness and advocacy; financial support and fund-raising; research and
training; and population management.
Education, Awareness and Advocacy
Education in the context of the integrated approach must be fully geared to the
conservation of species and wildlife. With over 700 million visitors a year, zoos
have a unique opportunity to provide for such an education to large numbers of
people (Gusset and Dick 2011). Research on the impact of education on zoo visitors
is still in its infancy (Davey 2006; Falk et al. 2007; Marino et al. 2010), but it seems
that two courses of action are absolutely essential to achieve the desired effect.
First of all, the animals should be shown in an environment which resembles their
natural environment as closely as possible—where they get the best chance to
develop behavior typical of their own species. This will help to prevent stereotypical
behavior, which is a poor advertisement for a zoo and merely undermines the
educational message. The much-desired ‘naturalization’ of zoos is well underway;
nowadays, when zoos are designed, habitat takes precedence over taxonomic group.
But the process runs up against limits. True habitats cover huge expanses of territory
(look at the area covered by tigers). Moreover, it is virtually impossible to create
realistic simulations of some forms of predatory behavior, such as chasing and
killing prey, in captivity. Likewise, in the absence of predators, prey behavior, such
as vigilance, may not be adequately exhibited in captivity (Kreger et al. 1998).
J. Keulartz
123
When Seattle’s Woodland Park Zoo started feeding whole sheep and goats to the big
felids and whole rabbits and chickens to the small felids in the 1970s, many
members of the public were aghast at the sight of flesh being torn from recognizable
carcasses (Hancocks 2001, 249). They are used to it now, but feeding live animals to
the cats is probably a step too far.
Secondly, the visitor must not be overcome by a numbing sense of helplessness.
Awareness alone will not change behavior and it might even prove counter-
productive if visitors are not afforded an opportunity to act (Sterling et al. 2007;
Gwynne 2007). In his 1999 book Beyond Ecophobia, David Sobel contends that we
must allow people to connect with nature and love the Earth before we ask them to
save it. Most people know by now that the natural world is in trouble. When they
hear that yet another ten thousand acres of rainforest were being lost while they
were spending time at the zoo, they may distance themselves from, rather than
connect to, the natural world which is so painful, unless they get a chance to make a
difference—no matter how small.
Congo Gorilla Forest, a project of 2.7 hectares in Bronx Zoo dedicated to wild
animals and habitats from central Africa, offers such a chance. It provides visitors
with an opportunity to make a direct contribution to the conservation of the African
rainforest by allowing them to name the project that will benefit from the three-
dollar supplement on their admission fee. The initiative raises one million dollars a
year for fieldwork (Gwynne 2007). Another good example is the They’re Calling on
You campaign at Melbourne Zoo. Visitors to the gorilla enclosure are asked to
donate their old mobile phones, which are then sent off for recycling. The idea is to
save coltan, an ore that is mined at the expense of the gorillas’ habitat, and to
generate funding for their conservation.
11
Financial Support and Fundraising
This is the simplest way for zoos to assist in situ conservation. Recent research has
shown that zoos do indeed make a financial contribution to this cause. But
investment in conservation by zoos is generally still low. It has been suggested that
zoos devote at least 10 % of their income to in situ conservation (Tribe and Booth
2003). Available data point to \5 % of income being spent on conservation (Fa
et al. 2011). This finding could reinforce the view that the mission of zoos is
primarily ‘window-dressing’.
Various fundraising ideas have recently been circulating. For instance, visitors
could be asked to contribute ‘on-the-spot’ to a project of their choice (as in the case
of the Congo Gorilla Forest project); ‘conservation-contribution’ machines could
be installed so that visitors can donate cash to conserve certain species; groups of
schoolchildren could be asked to adopt projects. In Australia, valued donors are
taken on guided tours behind the scenes. Some feel that the time has come to set
aside a percentage of the admission fee for in situ conservation projects (Conway
2003, 12).
11
http://www.zoo.org.au/get-involved/act-for-wildlife/theyre-calling-on-you.
Zoos at a Crossroads
123
Research and Training
The basic principle of research and training in the context of conservation efforts is:
‘Export expertise rather than repatriate animals’ (Price and Fa 2007, 169). The
tools and technologies developed by zoos are becoming increasingly relevant for
in situ conservation as natural habitats continue to being damaged and destroyed at
the current pace. Habitat loss and habitat fragmentation lead to an ongoing
conversion of what were originally continuous populations to so-called
‘metapopulations’. Metapopulations are collections of subpopulations, that are
spread geographically over patches of habitat. Because these patches are usually
small and because the movement of the animals between these patches is restricted
for lack of connectivity, local extinction of subpopulations is a common event. This
situation asks for metapopulation management, by which one may try to artificially
perform the function of dispersal and recolonization of patches of locally
endangered or extinct species.
With metapopulation management the distinction between classic in situ and ex
situ conservation is gradually breaking down. As the size and genetic diversity of
remaining wildlife populations is progressively declining, these populations are
becoming more and more similar to ex situ populations. Accordingly, zoo-based
expertise in genetic management of small populations of captive animals may be
useful to the conservation of small and declining populations in the wild, whereas
zoo-based skills in animal handling may be helpful in wild-to-wild translocations of
animals from one site to another, to repopulate habitats where species have
extirpated (Hutchins 2003; Hatchwell et al. 2007).
Population Management
Apart from research on management of small populations and wild-to-wild
translocation, zoos can also contribute to metapopulation management through what
has been called ‘integrated species conservation planning’ (IUCN 2014). The new
approach to conservation is increasingly replacing captive-breeding for reintroduc-
tion that has fallen out of favor due to the growing recognition of its limits (Price
and Fa 2007, 173). It refers to the exchange of animals between in situ populations
(in the wild) and ex situ populations (in human care) and has also been termed a
‘hybrid’ (Redford et al. 2012) or ‘pan situ’ approach (Minteer and Collins, in
preparation). On the one hand, captive populations can be used for restocking in
areas with declining populations or for reintroduction in areas where populations
have gone extinct; on the other hand, the demographic and genetic viability of ex
situ populations can be boosted by supplying genetic founders from wildlife
populations (Byers et al. 2013).
Collection Policy Options
In the previous section, I have shown how the paradigm shift in the zoo’s mission
will affect its core tasks. However, in order to fulfill these tasks in an optimal way
J. Keulartz
123
some substantial changes have to be made with respect to the zoo’s collection
policy. In this section, I will discuss some of the most important options that have
been proposed and that have often already been put into practice in one combination
or another: creating a link between the collection and in situ conservation projects;
putting more emphasis on local species and the local biogeographical region;
exchanging animals among ex situ populations and between ex situ and in situ
populations; and replacing big charismatic mammals with smaller species.
Link Between Collection and In Situ Conservation Projects
The species in the collection should match the zoo’s conservation goals. This can be
achieved by the creation of explicit connections between the animals on display and
the in situ projects that are being supported, so that visitors can learn about the
living conditions of the exhibited animals in the wild. This argument returns in
WAZA’s global strategy Building a Future for Wildlife, which also presents a good
example of a link between ex situ and in situ conservation:
Pongoland in Leipzig Zoo has created a link between the ex situ conservation
and breeding of chimpanzees and the attempts at in situ conservation of the
Wild Chimpanzee Foundation (WCF) in Ivory Coast. The zoo is acting as
guarantor for the long-term funding of projects in Tai National Park. Projects
have been set up specifically to raise local awareness of the plight of
chimpanzees, currently an endangered species. Visitors to Leipzig Zoo are
told about the collaborations with the WCF; meantime, the local population is
told about the activities at Leipzig Zoo and the research in Pongoland for the
conservation of the chimpanzee (WAZA 2005, 10).
Another example is the spectacular 11.000 m
2
rainforest at Zurich Zoo. This
exhibition was developed in cooperation with Masoala National Park in Madagascar.
Over the years, a whole string of direct and indirect links were forged between the
Swiss zoo and the Madagascan park. Zurich Zoo provides the funding for small-scale
development projects in communities around the park. These projects have proven
highly successful in winning the support of the villagers and the local government for
the park. Two nurseries have been established nearby to help the local community and
to supply the zoo with seeds. Support was provided for field research in Masoala. The
park was promoted in Madagascar and in Europe as a place of international
importance for the conservation of biodiversity (Hatchwell and Ru
¨
bel 2007).
These kinds of alliances between zoos in developed countries and protected areas
in developing countries are in everyone’s interests: on the one hand, they help zoos
to strengthen the impact of their activities on in situ wildlife conservation; on the
other, they secure long-term funding for protected areas.
Emphasis on Local Species and the Local Biogeographical Region
The link between the collection and in situ conservation projects is easier to make
when more emphasis is put on local species and the local biogeographical region. A
shift in breeding programs for reintroduction from exotic to indigenous species is
Zoos at a Crossroads
123
entirely in keeping with Article 9 of the Convention on Biological Diversity. This
article states that ex situ conservation should take place preferably in the country of
origin of the biological component. Likewise, the International Union for the
Conservation of Nature (IUCN) has recommended that regional zoo associations
work with threatened species in their own biogeographical area (IUCN 2002; Dickie
et al. 2007).
A stronger emphasis on local species and regional problems closer to home is
also important from an educational perspective, given that education should
preferably address problems with direct relevance for the target group. Education
can encourage local involvement and action. ‘If the Giant panda is going to be
saved, the most important audience for educational initiatives is undoubtedly in
China’ (Hutchins 2003, 23).
Exchange of Animals Among Zoos and Between Zoos and Wildlife
Because of limits of space, zoos can only maintain a small fraction of currently
threatened species. To address this problem, zoos have a number of options. They
can reduce the number of species they maintain that are not threatened and
specialize in species that are. ‘Specialization is key to every successful threatened
species propagation program’ (Conway 2011, 5). In addition to specialization zoos
can increase and improve regional and global cooperation. Only very few captive
populations managed in isolation are self-sustaining since population sizes generally
need to be very large to retain 90 % of the genetic diversity over 100 years.
Populations with less than 50 individuals ‘might have a high likelihood to be
managed inadvertently or implicitly for extinction’ (Fa et al. 2011, 271). The
problem of low numbers can be addressed by collaborative management and the
exchange of animals among zoos.
To combat the problem of numbers the interactive exchange of animals between
captive and wild populations in the context metapopulation management is also a
very effective strategy. The integration of in situ and ex situ programs opens the
possibility to simultaneously improve the demographic stability and genetic
diversity of the wild and captive populations of endangered species.
A Shift Towards Smaller Species
But the most effective strategy to combat the problem of limited space is without
any doubt a shift away from the large charismatic mammals towards smaller
species, particularly amphibians, invertebrates and some species of fish, which
occupy less space, are relatively inexpensive to keep, have a high birth rate and are
easy to reintroduce.
12
Several initiatives have already been launched on this front,
12
A recent and also very promising strategy to tackle the problem of limited space concerns the creation
of walkways between enclosures that allow animals greater freedom of movement. Building a network of
trails, in particular top tree trails, gives animals the opportunity to rotate between various interconnected
display and off-display areas. Animals may spend mornings in one area and afternoons in another. This
design strategy was first applied in Philadelphia Zoo, with only 42 acres a relatively small zoo.
http://theconversation.com/zoos-of-the-future-break-down-the-enclosure-walls-26605.
J. Keulartz
123
not least the Amphibian Conservation Action Plan, a partnership involving the
World Association of Zoos and Aquariums (Gewin 2008).
The ever-present collections of charismatic megafauna—lions, tigers, giraffes,
elephants, zebras, bears, hippos, and rhinos—are a poor reflection of the rich
diversity of the animal kingdom. There are around 30 million animal species on this
planet, 1640 of which are mammals. The average American zoo collection features
53 well-known mammals, a ratio of 1:31. The ratio for birds, at 1:98, is less than a
third of this. The ratio for reptiles, at 1:104, is less still. The disproportion becomes
even more alarming when it comes to very small creatures. Amphibians in the
average US zoo are represented in a ratio of only 1:2000. And the ratio for
invertebrates is an incredible one to several million. Over 95 % of all fauna are
small enough to hold in the palm of your hand, but in zoos, they are conspicuous by
their absence (Hancocks 2001, 165).
13
Some fear that turning the spotlight on small species will weaken the attraction of
zoos. Zoos need to balance conservation credibility with commercial viability; to
reach the aim of species conservation they need to attract visitors. The focus on
charismatic mammals is considered to be appropriate because these animals are
supposed to act as flagship species or ambassadors that raise public awareness and
support for in situ conservation (Baker 2007, 147; Leader-Williams et al. 2007,
237). However, the assumption that zoos will not attract enough visitors without
large mega-vertebrates is far from uncontroversial. Recent findings even suggest
that small mammal displays yield a higher cost to benefit ratio, in terms of exhibit
popularity per unit cost, than large mammal displays. They also suggest that
imaginative displays of small-bodied species can substantially increase zoo
attendance (Fa et al. 2011, 79).
A case in point is Micropia, the first museum of micro-organisms such as moulds,
yeasts, (micro)algae, bacteria, archaea, and viruses. Micropia, located in Artis Royal
Zoo in the center of Amsterdam, the Netherlands, opened its gates in October 2014.
The museum uses 3D viewers, allowing visitors to see how living microbes move
around, eat and reproduce. It has become a popular venue that has plenty of
interactive displays on offer, including a body scanner which can show you what
types of microbes live on your body, and a Kiss-o-meter which can count the
number of microbes transferred during a kiss.
Towards a New Balance Between Animal Welfare/Rights and Wildlife
Conservation?
Will the integrated approach, if rigorously applied, tip the balance between animal
welfare and species conservation concerns in favor of the zoo? Most animal rights
proponents will deny this possibility because they are opposed to such value
balancing. However, this abolitionist position will lose normative force as the
13
Edward O. Wilson once said that it cannot be stressed enough ‘that, as a whole, invertebrates are more
important than vertebrates for the conservation of ecosystems. If invertebrates were to die out, I fear that
the human race would survive for just a few months’ (Wilson 1987, 345).
Zoos at a Crossroads
123
borderline between in situ and ex situ conservation will more and more be blurred,
i.e. as zoos will increasingly become more like national parks and wildlife reserves
and, vice versa, parks and reserves will take on some of the character of zoos, and
hence be subject to zoo dilemmas. Like zoo populations, wild populations are
increasingly becoming too small to be demographically and genetically viable and
will inevitably go extinct without continuous monitoring and management. In such a
situation abolitionism is tantamount to capitulation to species extinction (Minteer
and Collins 2013).
On the other hand, a focus on smaller species such as reptiles, amphibians and
fish might to some extent address the concerns raised by adherents of the rights
view. After all, Tom Regan’s rights theory does not extend to all animals, but only
to those animals, notably mammals, that can be regarded as subjects-of-a-life
because they have capacities for emotion, memory, belief, desire, intentional action,
self-awareness, as well as conceptual abilities and a sense of the future, including
their own future.
Unlike animal rights advocates, animal welfare proponents generally do allow for
trade-offs between animal welfare and species conservation concerns. But most of
them agree with Dale Jamieson’s verdict that the zoo’s contribution to species
conservation is not significant enough to overcome the presumption against keeping
animals in captivity. They usually also endorse Jamieson’s view that we cannot save
wild nature by bringing it indoors but only by setting aside large tracts of land and
change our present environmentally unfriendly behavior.
14
‘Should zoos breed
animal populations that have no home to return to?’ (Hanson 2002, 171), these
animal ethicists and activists ask.
But, on the other hand, one might ask if it does make any sense to preserve or
create wild lands when there are only few populations left to inhabit these places. As
David Hancocks has remarked, simply setting aside wild lands will not always be
sufficient. He illustrates this with the example of the management plan to save the
Javan tiger that was published in 1980 by the Indonesian government, assisted by
the WWF and the IUCN. ‘It overruled any efforts at captive propagation, relying
solely upon habitat protection. Today the Javan tiger is extinct’ (Hancocks 2001,
175). Moreover, radically altering our present lifestyle might take too long for many
endangered species to survive. All in all, an ethical position that focuses solely on
the preservation of habitat will carry little normative force in a situation where
in situ conservation is no longer sufficient to slow down or stop the current species
extinction rate. Preserving wild lands and saving endangered species need not be
exclusionary, but should be pursued together to effectively meet widespread threats
such as climate change, habitat loss, poaching, invasive species and disease.
Moreover, Jamieson’s unfavorable judgment of the zoo might need to be revised
in light of the paradigm shift towards the integrated approach. Under this approach,
the prospects for the zoo to achieve a morally acceptable balance between animal
welfare costs and species conservation benefits look rather good, provided that the
14
Jamieson even blames zoos for being deeply implicated in causing the problem that they purport to be
addressing; they undermine the case for preserving wild nature by taking more and more animals out of
the wild (Jamieson 1995, 62).
J. Keulartz
123
zoo’s core tasks are all geared to wildlife conservation and the species collection
clearly reflects the zoo’s conservation goals. A shift towards small species, which
generally experience less welfare problems in captivity and fewer behavioral
problems that make return to the wild difficult than large animals, would certainly
tip the scales in favor of the zoo. This also applies to the adoption of integrated
metapopulation management. Interactive exchange of animals between captive and
wild populations will greatly enhance our capacity to sustain the genetic and
demographic viability of both populations. Reductions of animal welfare due to
capture, research, captive breeding and reintroduction will be all the more ethically
justified as the risk of extinction of small and fragmented populations in the wild
will be significantly minimized.
Pie in the sky, critics of the zoo will say—and not without reason. Today, the zoo
is standing at a crossroads—and has to decide if it will fully commit to the new
paradigm and develop into a conservation center or if it will degenerate (further)
into a venue for entertainment that will provoke increasing criticism, not only from
animal protectionist but also from wildlife conservationists.
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License
which permits any use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and
the source are credited.
References
Baker, A. (2007). Animal ambassadors: An analysis of the effectiveness and conservation impact of ex
situ breeding efforts. In A. Zimmermann, M. Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos in the
21st century. Catalysts for conservation (pp. 139–154). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Beck, B. (1995). Reintroduction, zoos, conservation, and animal welfare. In B. Norton, M. Hutchins, E.
Stevens, & T. Maple (Eds.), Ethics on the Ark (pp. 155–163). Washington: Smithsonian Institution
Press.
Bowkett, A. E. (2008). Recent captive-breeding proposals and the return of the Ark concept to global
species conservation. Conservation Biology, 23(3), 773–776.
Byers, O., Lees, C., Wilcken, J., & Schwitzer, C. (2013). The one plan approach: The philosophy and
implementation of CBSG’s approach to integrated species conservation planning. WAZA Magazine,
14, 2–5.
Callicott, J. B. (1980). Animal liberation: A triangular affair. Environmental Ethics, 2, 311–338.
Conde, D. A., Flesness, N., Colchero, F., Jones, O. R., & Scheuerlein, A. (2011). An emerging role of
zoos to conserve biodiversity. Science, 331(6023), 1390–1391.
Conway, W. (2003). The role of zoos in the 21st century. International Zoo Yearbook, 38, 7–13.
Conway, W. (2011). Buying time for wild animals with zoos. Zoo Biology, 30, 1–8.
Davey, G. (2006). Visitor behavior in zoo: A review. Anthrozoos, 19(2), 143–157.
Dickens, M. J., Delehanty, D. J., & Romero, L. M. (2010). Stress: An inevitable component of animal
translocation. Biological Conservation, 143, 1329–1341.
Dickie, L. A., Bonner, J. P., & West, C. (2007). In situ and ex situ conservation: Blurring the boundaries
between zoos and the wild. In A. Zimmermann, M. Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos in
the 21st century. Catalysts for conservation (pp. 220–235). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fa, J. E., Funk, S. M., & O’Connell, D. (2011). Zoo conservation biology. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Falk, J. H., et al. (2007). Why zoos & aquariums matter: Assessing the impact of a visit to a zoo or
aquarium. Silver Spring, MD: Association of Zoos & Aquariums.
Gewin, V. (2008). Riders of a modern-day ark. PLoS Biology, 6(1), 18–21.
Gusset, M., & Dick, G. (2011). The global reach of zoos and aquariums in visitor numbers and
conservation expenditures. Zoo Biology, 30, 566–569.
Zoos at a Crossroads
123
Gwynne, J. A. (2007). Inspiration for conversation: Moving audiences to care. In A. Zimmermann, M.
Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos in the 21st century. Catalysts for conservation (pp.
52–62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hancocks, D. (2001). A different nature. The paradoxical world of zoos and their uncertain future.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Hanson, E. (2002). Animal attractions. Nature on display in American zoos. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Hargrove, E. C. (Ed.). (1992). The animal rights/environmental ethics debate. The environmental
perspective. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Hatchwell, M., & Ru
¨
bel, A. (2007). The Masoala rainforest: A model partnership in support of in situ
conservation in Madagascar. In A. Zimmermann, M. Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos
in the 21st century. Catalysts for conservation (pp. 205–219). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Hatchwell, M., Ru
¨
bel, A., Dickie, L. A., West, C., & Zimmermann, A. (2007). Conclusion: The future of
zoos. In A. Zimmermann, M. Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos in the 21st century.
Catalysts for conservation (pp. 343–360). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hutchins, M. (2003). Zoo and aquarium animal management and conservation: Current trends and future
challenges. International Zoo Yearbook, 38, 14–28.
IUCN. (2000). Guidelines for the placement of confiscated animals. Gland, Switzerland.
IUCN. (2002). Technical guidelines on the management of ex situ populations for conservation. Gland,
Switzerland.
IUCN. (2014). Guidelines on the use of ex situ management for species conservation. Version 2.0. Gland,
Switzerland.
Jamieson, D. (1985). Against zoos. In P. Singer (Ed.), In defense of animals (pp. 108–117). New York:
Basil Blackwell.
Jamieson, D. (1995). Zoos revisited. In B. Norton, M. Hutchins, E. Stevens, & T. Maple (Eds.), Ethics on
the Ark (pp. 52–66). Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press.
Jamieson, D., & Elliot, R. (2009). Progressive consequentialism. Philosophical Perspectives, 23,
241–255.
Kaufman, L. (2012a). To save some species, zoos must let others die. New York Times, May 27.
Kaufman, L. (2012b). Zoos struggle to breed endangered animals. New York Times, July 5.
Keulartz, J., & Swart, J. (2012). Animal flourishing and capabilities in an era of global change. In A.
Thompson & J. Bendik-Keymer (Eds.), Ethical adaptation to climate change (pp. 123–144).
Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Keulartz, J., & Van der Weele, C. (2008). Framing and reframing in invasion biology. Configurations,
16(1), 93–115.
Kreger, M. D., Hutchins, M., & Fascione, N. (1998). Context, ethics, and environmental enrichment in
zoos and aquariums. In D. Shepherdson, et al. (Eds.), Second nature. Environmental enrichment for
captive animals (pp. 59–82). Washington and London: Smithsonian Institution Press.
Leader-Williams, N., Balmford, A., Linkie, M., Mace, G. M., Smith, R. J., Stevenson, M., et al. (2007).
Beyond the ark: conservation biologists’ views of the achievements of zoos in conservation. In A.
Zimmermann, M. Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos in the 21st century. Catalysts for
conservation (pp. 236–254). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lees, C. M., & Wilcken, J. (2009). Sustaining the Ark: The challenges faced by zoos in maintaining
viable population. Zoo Yearbook, 43, 6–18.
Mace, G. M., Balmford, A., Leader-Williams, N., Manica, A., Walter, O., West, C., & Zimmermann, A.
(2007). Measuring conservation success: Assessing zoos’ contribution. In A. Zimmermann, M.
Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos in the 21st century. Catalysts for conservation (pp.
322–342). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Marino, L., Lilienfeld, S. O., Malamud, R., Nobis, N., & Brogliod, R. (2010). Do zoo and aquariums
promote attitude change in visitors? A critical evaluation of the American zoo and aquarium study.
Society and Animals, 18, 126–138.
McCarthy, S. (2004). Becoming a tiger. How baby animals learn to live in the wild. New York: Harper
Perennial.
McShane, K. (2014). Individualist biocentrism vs. Holism revisited. Les Ateliers de l’Ethique/The Ethics
Forum, 9(2), 130–148.
Minteer, B. A., & Collins, J. P. (2013). Ecological ethics in captivity: Balancing values and
responsibilities in zoo and aquarium research under rapid global change. ILAR, 54(1), 41–51.
J. Keulartz
123
Minteer, B. A., & Collins, J. P. From the wild to the walled: Ethical aspects of ‘Pan Situ’ conservation.
In B. Hale, & A. Light (Eds.), Routledge companion to environmental ethics. London: Routledge.
(in preparation).
Price, M. R. S., & Fa, J. E. (2007). Reintroductions from zoos: A conservation guiding light or a shooting
star? In A. Zimmermann, M. Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos in the 21st century.
Catalysts for conservation (pp. 155–177). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Redford, K., Jensen, D., & Breheny, J. (2012). Integrating the captive and the wild. Science, 338,
1157–1158.
Regan, T. (1983). The case for animal rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Regan, T. (1995). Are zoos morally defensible. In B. Norton, M. Hutchins, E. Stevens, & T. Maple (Eds.),
Ethics on the Ark (pp. 38–51). Washington: Smithsonian Institute Press.
Rolston, H. (1988). Environmental ethics. Duties to and values in the natural world. Philadelphia:
Temple University Press.
Sagoff, M. (1984). Animal liberation and environmental ethics: Bad marriage, quick divorce. Osgoode
Hall Law Journal, 22, 297–307.
Sandler, R. L. (2012). The ethics of species. An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Scho
¨
n, D., & Rein, M. (1994). Frame reflection. New York: Basic Books.
Singer, P. (1979). Not for humans only: The place of nonhumans in environmental issues. In K.
E. Goodpaster & K. M. Sayre (Eds.), Ethics and problems of the 21st century (pp. 191–206). Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Soule
´
, M. (1990). The onslaught of alien species, and other challenges in the coming decades.
Conservation Biology, 4(3), 233–239.
Soule
´
, M., Gilpin, M., Conway, W., & Foose, T. (1986). The millenium ark: How long a voyage, how
many staterooms, how many passengers. Zoo Biology, 5, 101–113.
Sterling, E., Lee, J., & Wood, T. (2007). Conservation education in zoos: An emphasis on behavioral
change. In A. Zimmermann, M. Hatchwell, L. Dickie, & C. West (Eds.), Zoos in the 21st century.
Catalysts for conservation (pp. 37–50). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tribe, A., & Booth, R. (2003). Assessing the role of zoos in wildlife conservation. Human Dimensions of
Wildlife, 8, 65–74.
Wilson, E. O. (1987). The little things that run the world (the importance and conservation of
invertebrates). Conservation Biology, 1, 344–346.
Woods, M., & Moriarty, V. (2001). Strangers in a strange land: The problem of exotic species.
Environmental Values, 10, 163–191.
World Association of Zoos and Aquariums (WAZA). (1993). Executive summary of the world zoo
conservation strategy—The role of the zoos and aquaria of the world in global conservation. Gland:
WAZA.
World Association of Zoos and Aquariums (WAZA). (2005). Building a future for wildlife—The world
zoo and aquarium conservation strategy. Gland: WAZA.
Zoos at a Crossroads
123
... The validity of our reliance on in situ conservation is further undermined due to the vulnerability of wild populations in the face of climate change as climatic niche conditions shift (Pritchard et al. 2012;Stralberg et al. 2020). As a result, it has been acknowledged that for wildlife to persist some level of human intervention and management will likely be required, increasingly blurring the distinction between in situ and ex situ conservation Keulartz 2015). ...
... This strong taxonomic bias is criticised as such species are often costlier to maintain, demonstrate poor ex situ reproductive success, require exponentially greater enclosure sizes and raise significant ethical and welfare issues (Balmford et al. 1996;Young 2015). As a result, it has been recommended that zoos and aquariums shift their focus away from large vertebrates towards smaller-bodied species (preferably amphibians, invertebrates and fish), threatened species, native species and consolidate their conservation efforts on fewer species overall (Fa et al. 2014;Keulartz 2015;Palmer et al. 2018). However, as the global zoo and aquarium community has a limited capacity, there are concerns that the removal of popular species could result in reduced visitor attendance, lowering economic viability and consequently in situ conservation investment (Carr 2016;Kawata 2013;Ward et al. 1998;. ...
... However, compared to smaller species, large animals are often costlier to maintain, prove more difficult to breed in captivity, require larger enclosure sizes (Balmford et al. 1996) and raise ethical and welfare issues (Young 2015). As the global zoo community has a limited capacity (IUDZG/IUCN SSC 1993), zoos have been encouraged through conservation objectives to shift their focus towards smaller-bodied species (particularly amphibians, invertebrates and fish), native species, threatened species and specialise on fewer species (Keulartz 2015;Palmer et al. 2018). However, this compositional shift could result in reduced visitor attendance, lowering economic return and consequently in situ conservation investment (Carr 2016;Kawata 2013). ...
Thesis
Despite the best efforts of conservation practitioners global biodiversity is continuing to decline. The role of zoos and aquariums in conserving global biodiversity ex situ has become increasingly important as more species become threatened with extinction. As ex situconservation resources are limited, evidence-based decision making is required to identify, and prioritise, the management actions necessary to increase the potential of ex situ conservation efforts. The efficacy of ex situ conservation efforts is currently hindered by 1) entrenched taxonomic biases in collection planning and the prioritisation of large, charismatic vertebrates, 2) the unsustainability of ex situ populations due to limited space availability and management practices, and 3) limited considerations of the potential for ex situ collections to conserve and reintroduce genetic variation into populations using biological samples and advanced reproductive technologies. In this thesis I explore the multifaceted contribution of ex situ collections to global biodiversity conservation. I focus on the importance of standardised, globally shared ex situ records, and their potential to inform collection planning, population sustainability and genetic conservation decision-making.
... For scientists, debates about ethics are conducted through professional communication channels. For example, in the last decade, scientists have debated the ethics of killing feral animals to help threatened species (Olszańska et al., 2016;Wallach et al., 2018;Hayward et al., 2019), containing them within protective fencing (Mallon and Price, 2013;Child et al., 2019), taking threatened species into captivity (Jamieson, 1995;Keulartz, 2015), mixing previously separated populations (Edmands, 2007;Frankham et al., 2011), deliberate hybridization (Todesco et al., 2016;Quilodrán et al., 2020), assisted migration (Albrecht et al., 2013;Ahteensuu and Lehvävirta, 2014), and applying genetic engineering and gene drives to conservation (Piaggio et al., 2017;Kirk et al., 2020;Sandler, 2020) among other issues. However, expert opinion should be just one aspect of the decision-making process. ...
... We assessed preferences for nine conservation interventions (Table 1) following a review of the literature about feasible and innovative conservation strategies currently being applied or proposed in Australia (Jamieson, 1995;Edmands, 2007;Frankham et al., 2011;Albrecht et al., 2013;Mallon and Price, 2013;Ahteensuu and Lehvävirta, 2014;Keulartz, 2015;Olszańska et al., 2016;Todesco et al., 2016;Piaggio et al., 2017;Wallach et al., 2018;Child et al., 2019;Hayward et al., 2019;Kirk et al., 2020;Quilodrán et al., 2020;Sandler, 2020). These interventions fell into two approachesinvasive species control and genetic management. ...
Article
Conservation management is a rapidly evolving field in which scientific innovation and management practice can run ahead of social acceptability, leading to dispute and policy constraints. Here we use best-worst scaling (BWS) to explore the social preferences for two broad areas of threatened species management in Australia as well as support for extinction prevention as a whole. Of the 2430 respondents to an online survey among the Australian general public, 70% stated that extinction should be prevented regardless of the cost, a sentiment not fully reflected in existing policy and legislation. There was strong support for existing measures being taken to protect threatened species from feral animals, including explicit support for the killing of feral animals, but the demographic correlations with the results suggest approval is lower among women and younger respondents. There was a particularly high level of support for moving species to new places, which does not match current capabilities of managers responsible for assisted migration, suggesting messaging about the current limitations needs to be improved, or for resources to overcome them greatly increased. There was less support for genetic interventions than the feral animal control and other land management measures. A small majority of respondents thought it would be better for a species to cope without assistance than invasively alter their genome. This suggests that greater community consultation is desirable before applying genetic management approaches more interventionist than interbreeding subspecies.
... Estimating animal movements using direct observation also has its issues. In order to encourage animals to exhibit their natural behaviours, zoos must create habitats that resemble the animal's natural habitat to aid in the development and maintenance of natural behaviours (Keulartz 2015). Habitats that have varied terrain, feeding and social enrichment should result in the maximum movement, use and exploration of the habitat (Hutchins 2006). ...
... The amount of travelling an animal undertakes on a daily basis is typically related to the distribution of essential resources within their range (Leighty et al. 2009a). Zoos aim to create habitats that resemble the animal's natural range which aids in the development of natural behaviours (Keulartz 2015), including movement rates targeting an increased health status. In the wild, Asian elephants spend 60-80% active hours feeding (Baskaran et al. 2010), and up to 20 hr of their day is spent actively moving (Brockett et al. 1999). ...
... Zoos suddenly realized the need for change within the institution, and began developing more meaningful and effective conservation programs, though the measures for success in this area still often lack consensus. Zoos could no longer stand on the sidelines, claiming to act as "Noah's Ark" by protecting species from the storm of species extinction; the world was changing too quickly and the Zoo Ark didn't have the space necessary to protect all the creatures facing destruction (Keulartz 2015). All zoos could do was buy threatened species some extra time (Conway 2011). ...
Article
Full-text available
Context Zoos are a unique landscape with fascinating connections to the principles of landscape ecology. These ‘zooscapes’ have a focus on managing wild species. Objectives This article examines the multiple scales of zoos as urban green spaces, exhibit landscapes, and resources for resilience. I identify that landscape ecology can inform zoo evolution and note how zoos may provide a novel research site for landscape ecology. Methods I provide a brief history of American zoos and insight into lingering questions within zoos, including their representations of animals and humans. Additionally, I note conceptual overlap between zoo design/function and landscape ecology literature. Results Zoos provide habitat for native species and valued cultural ecosystem services. Zoo exhibits developed a landscape focus as modern landscape ecology emerged in the 1980s. Patches, corridors, and matrices exist within a zoo, and these facilities have value for the genetic support of fragmented populations. Zoos’ strategies for disease management are increasingly relevant for global health. Simultaneously, zoos must exhibit sustainable landscapes, not just ecological simulacrums for threatened species. Conclusions Zoos must promote humanity’s continued coexistence with other species. A landscape view is essential to achieving this goal. Zoos need to model sustainable landscapes of our present and future.
... The pervasiveness of anthropogenic degradation of ecosystems has driven the global loss of biodiversity with more than a quarter of all species assessed by IUCN at risk of extinction [1]. Large-scale, intense conservation efforts, such as animal captivity and species reintroduction, have been put forward to accelerate ecosystem recovery and reduce species declines (e.g., [2][3][4]). Captivity provides a suitable opportunity to care for threatened species [5] and can facilitate reintroduction efforts but many species in captivity suffer from a variety of illnesses and physiological changes that can increase mortality and reduce reproductive success [6,7]. ...
Article
Full-text available
During the ongoing biodiversity crisis, captive conservation and breeding programs offer a refuge for species to persist and provide source populations for reintroduction efforts. Unfortunately, captive animals are at a higher disease risk and reintroduction efforts remain largely unsuccessful. One potential factor in these outcomes is the host microbiota which includes a large diversity and abundance of bacteria, fungi, and viruses that play an essential role in host physiology. Relative to wild populations, the generalized pattern of gut and skin microbiomes in captivity are reduced alpha diversity and they exhibit a significant shift in community composition and/or structure which often correlates with various physiological maladies. Many conditions of captivity (antibiotic exposure, altered diet composition, homogenous environment, increased stress, and altered intraspecific interactions) likely lead to changes in the host-associated microbiome. To minimize the problems arising from captivity, efforts can be taken to manipulate microbial diversity and composition to be comparable with wild populations through methods such as increasing dietary diversity, exposure to natural environmental reservoirs, or probiotics. For individuals destined for reintroduction, these strategies can prime the microbiota to buffer against novel pathogens and changes in diet and improve reintroduction success. The microbiome is a critical component of animal physiology and its role in species conservation should be expanded and included in the repertoire of future management practices.
... Effectively addressing such issues across a sector as taxonomically, culturally, philosophically, and geographically diverse as zoos and aquariums where institutions are routinely judged according to the performance of the least accomplished facilities, will inevitably be a challenge. This is exacerbated by a tendency by many zoo and aquarium professionals to disregard nonexpert opinions on welfare matters as being anthropogenic, subjective, and superficial (see Melfi & Mccormick, 2004;Wolfensohn et al., 2018) and a widespread belief across a range of organisations that animal-related priorities compete with commercial objectives (see Born Free, 2021;Keulartz, 2015;Morino, 2017;PETA, 2021;N. A. Rose & Parsons, 2019;Wolfensohn et al., 2018). ...
Article
Full-text available
Animal welfare is a growing public concern that has the potential to undermine the social license of zoos and aquariums. The lack of consensus on how animal welfare is defined across such a diverse sector combined with and a widespread belief that commercial priorities such as entertaining visitors conflicts with animal welfare, hinders efforts to effectively address this fundamental issue for the sector. Data derived from an audit of habitats across a major North American wildlife attraction revealed that holistic animal welfare assessments undertaken by animal carers embracing three principal constructs of animal welfare, correlated strongly with visitor perceptions of animal happiness. Visitor assessments of animal happiness also correlated with animal carer assessments of social, behavioural and locomotor opportunities and inversely with the prevalence of stereotypic behaviours, supporting the proposition that folk conceptions of animal welfare are more accurate than may have previously been considered to be the case. However, the holistic animal welfare assessment inversely correlated with assessments of a habitat's capacity to safeguard welfare as determined by the facility's veterinary staff, supporting the proposition that tensions exist between physical and psychological components of captive animal welfare provisioning. This further underlines the importance of clarity on how animal welfare is conceived when developing institutional animal welfare strategies. Finally, the data also showed that both holistic animal welfare assessments and visitor perceptions of animal happiness strongly correlated with the level of enjoyment experienced by visitors, challenging the belief that animal welfare competes with the commercial priorities of zoos and aquariums. The audit supports the case that maintaining high animal welfare is a commercial imperative as well as a moral obligation for zoos and aquariums and underlines the necessity to utilize conceptions of animal welfare that acknowledge the centrality of the affective states of animals in maintaining those standards. A holistic welfare audit of habitats within a large wildlife attraction correlated with visitor perceptions of animal happiness and visitor enjoyment but inversely correlated with a veterinary‐based welfare audit. These findings underline the significance of differing welfare conceptions in establishing institutional animal welfare management priorities and the potential tensions between physical and psychological priorities in captive animal care. Most zoo animal welfare stakeholder groups do not have publicly available animal welfare definitions and those that do, differ from the reported scientific consensus. For wildlife attractions, this ambiguity has the potential to create confusion, misalignment of effort, conflict, and an erosion of trust with the general public. An animal welfare audit undertaken across a large wildlife attraction encompassing a range of stakeholder perspectives and welfare conceptions revealed differing alignments; the performance of habitats from a veterinary management perspective inversely correlated with a holistic animal welfare assessment undertaken by animal care staff utilising a suite of broad‐based criteria, encompassing three principle animal welfare constructs relating to natural living, effective states and health/biological functioning. This holistic assessment correlated with visitor perceptions of animal happiness as well as their enjoyment of those habitats. Visitor assessments of welfare also correlated with animal carer assessments of social, behavioural and locomotor opportunities and with the prevalence of stereotypic behaviours. The findings of this audit support the case that tensions can exist between veterinary and holistic animal welfare‐based priorities in achieving peak captive animal welfare and support the case for a consensus in defining animal welfare centred around the affective states of animals. Finally, the audit suggests folk understandings of animal welfare are more accurate than may have been considered to be the case, and that welfare is important in shaping visitor experiences of wildlife attractions, illustrating the strategic as well as moral importance of animal welfare to wildlife attractions. Most zoo animal welfare stakeholder groups do not have publicly available animal welfare definitions and those that do, differ from the reported scientific consensus. For wildlife attractions, this ambiguity has the potential to create confusion, misalignment of effort, conflict, and an erosion of trust with the general public. An animal welfare audit undertaken across a large wildlife attraction encompassing a range of stakeholder perspectives and welfare conceptions revealed differing alignments; the performance of habitats from a veterinary management perspective inversely correlated with a holistic animal welfare assessment undertaken by animal care staff utilising a suite of broad‐based criteria, encompassing three principle animal welfare constructs relating to natural living, effective states and health/biological functioning. This holistic assessment correlated with visitor perceptions of animal happiness as well as their enjoyment of those habitats. Visitor assessments of welfare also correlated with animal carer assessments of social, behavioural and locomotor opportunities and with the prevalence of stereotypic behaviours. The findings of this audit support the case that tensions can exist between veterinary and holistic animal welfare‐based priorities in achieving peak captive animal welfare and support the case for a consensus in defining animal welfare centred around the affective states of animals. Finally, the audit suggests folk understandings of animal welfare are more accurate than may have been considered to be the case, and that welfare is important in shaping visitor experiences of wildlife attractions, illustrating the strategic as well as moral importance of animal welfare to wildlife attractions.
... Indeed, when context tends to strongly promote respect for animals, thoughtfully designed digital technologies may synergize that moral effect. Some think that, for example, true conservation sanctuaries (Keulartz, 2015) or "intentional communities," in which rescued animals have substantial control over their lives and live amongst humans and other species, may sometimes succeed in appropriate moral edification (Donaldson & Kymlicka, 2015). Lastly, as noted earlier, properly designed and deployed digital technologies might mitigate (though not necessarily abolish) moral prejudices even where context tends to reinforce them (again, this needs empirical study). ...
Article
Full-text available
This paper examines how digital technologies might be used to improve ethical attitudes towards nonhuman animals, by exploring the case study of nonhuman apes kept in modern zoos. The paper describes and employs a socio-ethical framework for undermining anti-ape prejudice advanced by philosopher Edouard Machery which draws on classic anti-racism strategies from the social sciences. We also discuss how digital technologies might be designed and deployed to enable and enhance rather than impede the three anti-prejudice strategies of contact and interaction, enlightenment, and individualization. In doing so, the paper illuminates the broad potential and limitations of digital technology to both harm and benefit animals via its effects on human ethical attitudes. This examination provides guidance for future projects and empirical work on using digital technologies to promote moral respect for a range of nonhuman animals in different settings.
Thesis
Full-text available
Public awareness of nature and environmental issues has grown in the last decades and zoos have successfully followed suit by re-branding themselves as key representatives for conservation. However, considering the fast rate of environmental degradation, in the near future, zoos may become the only place left for wildlife. Some scholars argue that we have entered a new epoch titled the “Anthropocene” that postulates the idea that untouched pristine nature is almost nowhere to be found.1 Many scientists and scholars argue that it is time that we embraced this environmental situation and anticipated the change. 2 Clearly, the impact of urbanization is reaching into the wild, so how can we design for animals in our artificializing world? Using the Manoa School method that argues that every future includes these four, generic, alternatives: growth, discipline, collapse, and transformation3, this dissertation explores possible future animal archetypes by considering multiple possibilities of post zoo design.
Article
Full-text available
The article analyze the reproductive potential of uncastrated domestic cats. The notions of the high reproductive capabilities of the species have been refuted, even with provided resources, shelter and human attention. Space and density are not major stressors in a multi-cat indoor group if a high-protein food and inner freedom of individuals are provided. The established natural patterns in its development and the parallel made between other wild felines and human population are evidence of the evolutionary value and genetic potential of the species, which must be assessed and preserved in time. Specific adaptive behavior in female individuals related to indoor life and possibly a way of self-control of reproduction is described
Article
Full-text available
While holist views such as ecocentrism have considerable intuitive appeal, arguing for the moral considerability of ecological wholes such as ecosystems has turned out to be a very difficult task. In the environmental ethics literature, individualist biocentrists have persuasively argued that individual organisms—but not ecological wholes—are properly regarded as having a good of their own . In this paper, I revisit those arguments and contend that they are fatally flawed. The paper proceeds in five parts. First, I consider some problems brought about by climate change for environmental conservation strategies and argue that these problems give us good pragmatic reasons to want a better account of the welfare of ecological wholes. Second, I describe the theoretical assumptions from normative ethics that form the background of the arguments against holism. Third, I review the arguments given by individualist biocentrists in favour of individualism over holism. Fourth, I review recent work in the philosophy of biology on the units of selection problem, work in medicine on the human biome, and work in evolutionary biology on epigenetics and endogenous viral elements. I show how these developments undermine both the individualist arguments described above as well as the distinction between individuals and wholes as it has been understood by individualists. Finally, I consider five possible theoretical responses to these problems. This paper is available online for free at https://www.erudit.org/en/journals/ateliers/2014-v9-n2-ateliers01522/1026682ar/
Article
The aim of this paper is to highlight how the structure maintained by zoos contributes to inefficiency of the purposes outlined by them, namely: entertainment, education, preservation of species and research opportunity. Recalling the history of those institutions will be shown that the impacts on the lives of animals have always been to deprive them of their liberty, the right to obtain their own food and develop its own social order.
Article
List of Illustrations Preface Acknowledgments 1. Collections as Status 2. The Eighteenth-Century Concept 3. The Nineteenth-Century Phenomenon 4. Romanticists and Modernists 5. Toward New Frontiers 6. Immersed in the Landscape 7. Agents of Conservation 8. Which Way the Future? Epilogue Bibliography Illustration Credits Index