Conference PaperPDF Available

Nicholas of Cusa's methodology of the Infinite

Authors:
  • Centre Jean Pepin, CNRS, Paris.

Abstract

During the mid-fifteenth century, Nicholas of Cusa, in his major work Of Learned Ignorance [1], transformed the Aristotelian "potential" and "actual" infinity into a "negative" and "positive" infinity. In order to explain these new features of the infinite, Cusa developed the method of the coïncidentia oppositorum. In the context of what he coined as our "learned ignorance," he established a proportion between what we know and what we do not know. First of all, Cusa's method does not treat the infinite as a logical statement in the way the philosophers of the Middle Ages did. Their logical approach was based on speculations upon the sophisms and paradoxes of the infinite to overcome the gap between language and reality. For example, one of the most influential philosophers of that period, Gregory of Remini, came up with a new logical expression of the infinite as "categorematical" or "syncategorematical" [2]. Secondly, Cusa's perspective on the infinite was not quantitative as was Leibniz' calculus by the end of the seventeenth century [3,4]. Instead of conducting a logical or quantitative analysis, Cusa identified various orders of knowledge to define the infinite. According to his method of the coincidentia oppositorum, the maximum infinite can be identified with the minimum infinite. Cusa thought that geometry was the best science to use in order to get an understanding of the infinite by progressing through the different orders of knowledge. He studied geometrical figures such as lines, triangles and circles, and demonstrated how these figures can also be said to correspond to an infinite line, triangle, or circle. Cusa then applied this model to the world, concluding that the relationship between the finite and infinite figures is analogous to the relationship of the maximum infinite "to all things" [1]. In this presentation, I will examine how Cusa's method to reach the infinite through geometrical analysis provides a unique standpoint for research on mathematical and philosophical infinity and the pursuit of solutions to philosophical, mathematical and theological issues. In showing how Cusa's reasoning in his methodology of the infinite differs from a logical analysis (Gregory of Remini) or calculation (Leibniz) of the infinite, I will be able to underline a new way to manage the infinite. Finally, I will explain how the different fields of geometry, theology, and philosophy interplay with each other to define the infinite.
(for purposes here) "objects". An important component if David Lewis's modal realism is that anything can
coexist with anything, expressed initially in his unqualified principle of Recombination:
(R) For any objects (in any worlds), there is a world that contains any number of duplicates of
those objects.
Consider the following consequence of R:
(RC) For any cardinal number , it is possible that there are at least objects.
In the context of modal realism, RC entails:
(A*) For any cardinal number , there are at least objects.
But this is problematic for Lewis. Consider:
(SoA) There is a set of all objects.
In the context of ZFCU, it follows that (A*) is inconsistent with (SoA). Faced with such inconsistencies,
Lewis opted to abandon (RC) and, hence, Recombination. For, as properties are sets of objects and
propositions are sets of worlds for Lewis, many important properties and propositions will not exist if
there is no set of all objects and, hence, many of the applications of modal realism will fail.
But there is another option here. In a forthcoming paper I develop a modification ZFCU* of ZFCU that
accommodates the existence of "wide" sets, i.e., sets that, like (assuming (A*) and (SoA)) are too big
to have a definite cardinality but which have a definite rank. The key modifications are to Replacement
and Powerset. Say that a set is (mathematically) determinable if it is equipotent to some pure set. We
then our modified Replacement F* applies to sets that are either determinable or for which we have a
replacement mapping that is "bounded above" by rank on .
On the modified version PS* of Powerset, only the determinable subsets of a given set constitute a
further set. The motivation for this modification stems from Cantor's conception of the "absolute infinite",
i.e., the "size" that characterizes non-determinable collections. For Cantor, this "size" is an "absolute
quantitative maximum" that is subject to no mathematically definite increase. Accordingly, given PS*,
Cantor's theorem fails for wide sets. A final axiom further enforces the Cantorian intuition: Only
determinable sets are smaller than some other set. ZFCU* thus yields a rather different, "cylindrical"
picture of the cumulative hierarchy in which there is no mathematically definite increase in its "girth".
(ZFCU* is consistent relative to ZFCU + "There exists an inaccessible cardinal".)
Assuming the set of objects is wide, ZFCU* permits the construction of, even if not the full intuitive
power set of O, infinitely many complex sets of arbitrarily high rank over . The central focus of my
presentation will be to investigate the extent to which Lewis's program–with full Recombination–can be
restored if the modal realist adopts ZFCU*. Secondarily, I will address other implications of ZFCU* in
regard to the nature of the infinite, the structure of the comulative hierarchy, and the possibility of
absolutely general quantification.
Nicholas of Cusa's Methodology of the Infinite
Françoise Monnoyeur-Broitman (Linköping University)
During the mid-fifteenth century, Nicholas of Cusa, in his major work Of Learned Ignorance [1],
transformed the Aristotelian "potential" and "actual" infinity into a "negative" and "positive" infinity. In order
to explain these new features of the infinite, Cusa developed the method of the coïncidentia oppositorum.
In the context of what he coined as our "learned ignorance," he established a proportion between what
we know and what we do not know. First of all, Cusa's method does not treat the infinite as a logical
statement in the way the philosophers of the Middle Ages did. Their logical approach was based on
speculations upon the sophisms and paradoxes of the infinite to overcome the gap between language and
reality. For example, one of the most influential philosophers of that period, Gregory of Remini, came up
with a new logical expression of the infinite as "categorematical" or "syncategorematical" [2]. Secondly,
Cusa's perspective on the infinite was not quantitative as was Leibniz' calculus by the end of the
seventeenth century [3,4]. Instead of conducting a logical or quantitative analysis, Cusa identified various
orders of knowledge to define the infinite. According to his method of the coincidentia oppositorum, the
maximum infinite can be identified with the minimum infinite. Cusa thought that geometry was the best
science to use in order to get an understanding of the infinite by progressing through the different orders
of knowledge. He studied geometrical figures such as lines, triangles and circles, and demonstrated how
these figures can also be said to correspond to an infinite line, triangle, or circle. Cusa then applied this
model to the world, concluding that the relationship between the finite and infinite figures is analogous to
the relationship of the maximum infinite "to all things" [1].
In this presentation, I will examine how Cusa's method to reach the infinite through geometrical analysis
provides a unique standpoint for research on mathematical and philosophical infinity and the pursuit of
solutions to philosophical, mathematical and theological issues. In showing how Cusa's reasoning in his
methodology of the infinite differs from a logical analysis (Gregory of Remini) or calculation (Leibniz) of
the infinite, I will be able to underline a new way to manage the infinite. Finally, I will explain how the
different fields of geometry, theology, and philosophy interplay with each other to define the infinite.
References.
[1] Nicolaus Cusanus, Of learned Ignorance, Hyperion Press Inc : Wesport, (1954).
[2] Françoise Monnoyeur, Infini des mathematiciens, infini des philosophes, Editions Belin: Paris, 1st
Ed (1992).
[3] Françoise Monnoyeur, Infini des philosophes, infini des astronomes, Editions Belin: Paris, 1st Ed
(1995).
[4] Françoise Monnoyeur, Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (4):527-528 (2010).
An Aristotelian Approach to Infinite Causal Sequences
Tamer Nawar (University of Cambridge)
Aristotle's antipathy to actual infinites (e.g., Physics 206b12-14) and his gnomic remark that nature flees
the infinite (Generation of Animals 715b15-17) are well known. Aristotle is often taken to rule out infinite
κ
κ
κ
κ
O
O
S
A
O
O
History & Philosophy of Infinity: Cambridge, England
http://www.math.uni-hamburg.de/home/loewe/HiPhI/abstracts.html
7 of 14 2015-03-22 14:06
Article
Full-text available
The understanding of matter is a philosophical endeavor. Scientists are interested in finding or building adequate models in order to explain phenomena and find the properties of matter. Models are then tested against experience and when validated lead to the formulation of laws. From a philosophical perspective models are not only tools to understand matter and discover laws of nature, but representations that reveal how we acquire knowledge about nature . The philosophical perspective takes into account that models are representations of an object under the scrutiny of a viewer, and therefore analyzes the interaction between the mind and the object. We focus on two geometrical models created with more than two millennia apart, and consider how they capture natural phenomena. The first model appears in one of Plato's dialogues when the young astronomer Timaeus, in a conversation with Socrates, introduces geometric solids to understand the basic structure of matter and interaction of the primary elements: fire, air, water, and earth. The second geometric model appeared nowadays with the development of electron microscopy and x-ray diffraction and allows physicists to discover the atomic structure of matter. Furthermore, we analyze the value of these geometric models and identify their cognitive function.
Book
Full-text available
L'astronomie se confronte à la réalité d'un cosmos fini ou infini. Au gré des théories astronomiques, physiques, mathématiques, philosophiques ou esthétiques, l'infini s'impose ou disparaît. AVAILABLE AS e-BOOK SINCE 2011
Book
Full-text available
Ce livre éclaire les étapes de la réflexion sur la notion philosophique et mathématique d'infini du XIVe au XIXe siècle. Un infini inaccessible qui n'a cessé de stimuler l'activité des mathématiciens, des théologiens, des philosophes et des artistes. Tous ont mis, à leur manière, leur art à son service, afin de nous permettre de mieux appréhender et transcender le fini. Ce livre éclaire, du xive au xixe siècle, les étapes de la réflexion sur la notion philosophique et mathématique d'infini. AVAILABLE AS e-BOOK SINCE 2011
  • Françoise Monnoyeur
Françoise Monnoyeur, Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (4):527-528 (2010).
Infini des mathematiciens
  • Françoise Monnoyeur
Françoise Monnoyeur, Infini des mathematiciens, infini des philosophes, Editions Belin: Paris, 1st